14.127 Behavioral Economics (Lecture 1) Xavier Gabaix February 5, 2003 1 Overview • Instructor: Xavier Gabaix • Time 4-6:45/7pm, with 10 minute break. • Requirements: 3 problem sets and Term paper due September 15, 2004 (meet Xavier in May to talk about it) 2 Some Psychology of Decision Making 2.1 Prospect Theory (Kahneman-Tversky, Econometrica 79) Consider gambles with two outcomes: x with probability p, and y with probability 1-p where x ≥ 0 ≥ y . • Expected utility (EU) theory says that if you start with wealth W then the (EU) value of the gamble is • Prospect theory (PT) says that the (PT) value of the game is where π is a probability weighing function. In standard theory π is linear. • In prospect theory π is concave first and then convex, e.g. • for some β∈ (0 , 1). The figure gives π ( p ) for β = .8 2.1.1 What does the introduction of the weighing function π mean? • π(p) > p for small p. Small probabilities are overweighted, too salient. E.g. people play a lottery. Empirically, poor people and less educated people are more likely to play lottery. Extreme risk aversion. • π(p) < p for p close to 1. Large probabilities are underweight. In applications in economics π(p) = p is often used except for lotteries and insurance 2.1.2 Utility function u • We assume that u ( x ) is increasing in x, convex for loses, concave for gains, and first order concave at 0 that is • A useful parametrization • The graph of u ( x ) for λ = 2 and β = .8 is given below 2.1.3 Meaning - Fourfold pattern of risk aversion u • Risk aversion in the domain of likely gains • Risk seeking in the domain of unlikely gains • Risk seeking in the domain of likely losses • Risk aversion in the domain of unlikely losses 2.1.4 How robust are the results? • Very robust: loss aversion at the reference point, λ>1 • Robust: convexity of u for x < 0 • Slightly robust: underweighting and overweighting of probabilities π ( p ) ≷ p 2.1.5 In applications we often use a simplified PT (prospect theory) and 2.1.6 Second order risk aversion of EU • Consider a gamble x +σ and x -σ with 50 : 50 chances. • Question: what risk premium πwould people pay to avoid the small risk σ ? • We will show that as σ → 0 this premium is O (σ2 ). This is called second order risk aversion. • In fact we will show that for twice continuously differentiable utilities: where ρ is the curvature of u at 0 that is • The risk premium π makes the agent with utility function u indifferent between • Assume that u is twice differentiable and take a look at the Taylor expansion of the above equality for small σ. . or • Since π(σ ) is much smaller than σ , so the claimed approximation is true. Formally, conjecture the approximation, verify it, and use the implicit function theorem to obtain uniqueness of the function π defined implicitly be the above approximate equation. 2.1.7 First order risk aversion of PT • Consider same gamble as for EU. • We will show that in PT, as σ→0, the risk premium π is of the order of σ when reference wealth x = 0. This is called the first order risk aversion. • Let’s compute π for u (x) = xα for x ≥ 0 and u (x) =-λ|x|α for x ≤ 0. • The premium π at x = 0 satisfies or where k is defined appropriately. 2.1.8 Calibration 1 • Take CES, utility , i.e. a constant elasticity of substitution, • Gamble 1 $50,000 with probability 1/2 $100,000 with probability 1/2 • Gamble 2. $ x for sure. • Typical x that makes people indifferent belongs to (60k, 75k) (though some people are risk loving and ask for higher x. • Note the relation between x and the elasticity of substitution γ: x 70k 63k58k 54k 51.9k 51.2k γ 1 3 5 10 20 30 Right γ seems to be between 1 and 10. • Evidence on financial markets calls for γ bigger than 10. This is the equity premium puzzle. 2.1.9 Calibration 2 • Gamble 1 $10.5 with probability ½ $-10 with probability ½ • Gamble 2. Get $0 for sure. • If someone prefers Gamble 2, she or he satisfies Here, π = $.5 and σ = $10.25. We know that in EU And thus with CES utility forces large γ as the wealth W is larger than 105 easily. 2.1.10 Calibration Conclusions • In PT we have π* = kσ. For γ = 2, and σ= $.25 the risk premium is π* = kσ= $.5 while in EU π* = $.001. • If we want to fit an EU parameter γto a PT agent we get and this explodes as σ → 0. • If someone is averse to 50-50 lose $100/gain g for all wealth levels then he or she will turn down 50-50 lose L /gain G in the table L\g $101 $105 $110 $125 $400 $400 $420 $550 $1,250 $800 $800 $1,050 $2,090 ∞ $1000 $1,010 $1,570 ∞ ∞ $2000 $2,320 ∞ ∞ ∞ $10,000 ∞ ∞ ∞ ∞ 2.2 What does it mean? • EU is still good for modelling. • Even behavioral economist stick to it when they are not interested in risk taking behavior, but in fairness for example. • The reason is that EU is nice, simple, and parsimonious. 2.2.1 Two extensions of PT • Both outcomes, x and y , are positive, 0 < x < y .Then, Why not ? Because it becomes self-contradictory when x = y and we stick to K-T calibration that putsπ(.5) < .5 . • Continuous gambles, distribution f (x) EU gives: PT gives: