Chapter Thirty-Three Law and Economics Effects of Laws Property right assignments affect – asset, income and wealth distributions; e.g. nationalized vs. privately owned industry. Effects of Laws Property right assignments affect – asset, income and wealth distributions; e.g. nationalized vs. privately owned industry. – resource allocations; e.g. the tragedy of the commons e.g. patents encourage research. Effects of Laws Punishments affect – incentives for illegal behavior; e.g. high speeding fines can reduce the amount of speeding. Effects of Laws Punishments affect – incentives for illegal behavior; e.g. high speeding fines can reduce the amount of speeding. – asset, income and wealth distributions; e.g. jail time results in lost income. Crime and Punishment x is the quantity of an illegal activity produced by an individual. C(x) is the production cost. B(x) is the benefit. Gain is B(x) - C(x). What is the rational choice of x? Crime and Punishment max B ( x ) C ( x ). x0 First-order condition is B ( x ) C ( x ). Notice that marginal costs matter more than do total costs. Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), low MC B ( x ) C ( x ) x* x Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), higher, but same MC C(x), low MC B ( x ) C ( x ) x* x No change to illegal activity level. Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), low MC B ( x ) C ( x ) x* x Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), high MC C(x), low MC B ( x ) C ( x ) x* x Higher marginal costs deter crime. Crime and Punishment Detection of a criminal is uncertain. e is police effort. (e) is detection probability; (e) = 0 if e = 0 (e) as e . Crime and Punishment Given e, the criminal’s problem is max B ( x ) ( e )C ( x ). x0 Crime and Punishment Given e, the criminal’s problem is max B ( x ) ( e )C ( x ). x0 First-order condition is B ( x ) ( e )C ( x ). Crime and Punishment Given e, the criminal’s problem is max B ( x ) ( e )C ( x ). x0 First-order condition is B ( x ) ( e )C ( x ). e low (e) low marg. cost. High e high (e) high marg. cost. Low Crime and Punishment B(x) el eh MC ( eh )C ( x ) MC ( el )C ( x ) B ( x ) ( e )C ( x ) x* x Higher police effort deters crime. Crime and Punishment Higher fines and larger police effort both raise marginal production costs of illegal activity. Which is better for society -- higher fines, or more police effort? Crime and Punishment Higher fines and larger police effort both raise marginal production costs of illegal activity. Which is better for society -- higher fines, or more police effort? Police effort consumes resources; higher fines do not. Better to fine heavily. Liability Law An injurer, IN, and a victim, V. x is effort by IN to avoid injuring V. cIN(x) is IN’s cost of effort x; cIN(x) as x . L(x) is V’s loss when IN’s effort is x; L(x) as x . Liability Law Society wishes to minimize total cost; i.e. min c ( x ) L( x ). x IN Liability Law Society wishes to minimize total cost; i.e. min c ( x ) L( x ). x Social IN optimality requires cIN ( x*) L ( x*). I.e. IN’s private marginal cost of effort equals marginal benefit of her extra effort. Liability Law Liability rules: – no liability rule – strict liability rule – negligence rule. Which is best? Liability Law No Liability Rule: IN faces only private cost, cIN(x). Hence chooses effort level x 0. No liability results in suboptimal low care level and excessive injury. Liability Law Full Liability Rule: IN faces private cost and V’s costs, cIN(x) + L(x). Hence chooses the socially optimal effort level x * where cIN ( x*) L ( x*). Liability Law Rule: IN is liable for V’s loss if and only if care effort level x x~, a legally determined effort level. Negligence Liability Law Rule: IN is liable for V’s loss if and only if care effort level x x~, a legally determined effort level. ~ x *, the What if the court sets x socially optimal effort level? Negligence Liability Law x x * full liability for IN; hence she chooses x x*. So Liability Law x x * full liability for IN; hence she chooses x x*. And x x * no liability for IN; hence she chooses x x*. So Liability Law x x * full liability for IN; hence she chooses x x*. And x x * no liability for IN; hence she chooses x x*. I.e. the negligence rule is socially optimal when x~ x*. So Liability Law Both full liability and negligence rules are socially optimal, but full liability fully insures V always, and the negligence rule fully insures V only if IN’s care effort level x x *. Liability Law Both full liability and negligence rules are socially optimal, but full liability fully insures V always, and the negligence rule fully insures V only if IN’s care effort level x x *. Victims prefer full liability; injurers prefer the negligence rule. Bilateral Accidents V and IN can each exert effort to avoid a loss. cV(xV) and cIN(xIN). Loss is L(xV,xIN). Society wishes to min cV ( xV ) cIN ( xIN ) L( xV , xIN ). xV , xIN Bilateral Accidents Society wishes to min cV ( xV ) cIN ( xIN ) L( xV , xIN ). xV , xIN Social optimality requires V’s MC of effort = MB of his effort IN’s MC of effort = MB of her effort. I.e. * * * cV ( xV ) L( xV , xIN ) / xV * * * cIN ( xIN ) L( xV , xIN ) / xIN Bilateral Accidents No Liability: Both V and IN face only their private effort costs, not the full social costs of their actions. Bilateral Accidents No Liability: Both V and IN face only their private effort costs, not the full social costs of their actions. Hence V and IN both provide too little effort. No liability is socially suboptimal. Bilateral Accidents Full Liability: V is fully compensated for all injury costs. Bilateral Accidents Full Liability: V is fully compensated for all injury costs. Hence V chooses xV 0. Full liability is socially suboptimal in bilateral accidents. Bilateral Accidents Strict Division of Losses: IN must pay a fixed fraction, f, of loss caused. IN minimizes cIN ( xIN ) f L ( xV , xIN ). IN chooses effort xIN satisfying cIN ( xIN ) f L( xV , xIN ) / xIN . Bilateral Accidents IN satisfying chooses effort xIN cIN ( xIN ) f L( xV , xIN ) / xIN . Optimality requires cIN ( x*IN ) L( x*V , x*IN ) / xIN Since f < 1, IN chooses less than the * optimal effort level; xIN xIN . Bilateral Accidents IN satisfying chooses effort xIN cIN ( xIN ) f L( xV , xIN ) / xIN . Optimality requires cIN ( x*IN ) L( x*V , x*IN ) / xIN Since f < 1, IN chooses less than the * optimal effort level; xIN xIN . Strict division of losses is a socially suboptimal liability rule. Bilateral Accidents Negligence Rule: IN is fully liable for loss only if her effort level x x~ , a legally determined effort level. Social optimality requires V and IN to choose effort levels xV x*V and xIN x*IN , where * * * cV ( xV ) L( xV , xIN ) / xV * * * and cIN ( xIN ) L( xV , xIN ) / xIN . Bilateral Accidents * Suppose V chooses xV xV . Then IN is fully liable and wishes to * min cIN ( xIN ) L( xV , xIN ). xIN I.e. IN chooses xIN x*IN . Bilateral Accidents * Now suppose IN chooses xIN xIN . Then V wishes to * min cV ( xV ) L( xV , xIN ). xV I.e. V chooses xV x*V . Bilateral Accidents * Now suppose IN chooses xIN xIN . Then V wishes to * min cV ( xV ) L( xV , xIN ). xV V chooses xV x*V . The Nash equilibrium of the negligence rule game is the socially optimal outcome. I.e. Bilateral Accidents Strict Liability with Defense of Contributory Negligence Rule: IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level x~ . Bilateral Accidents IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level x~ . * ~ If society chooses x xV and V * chooses xV xV , then IN is fully liable, so her best reply is xIN x*IN . Bilateral Accidents IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level x~ . * ~ If society chooses x xV and V * chooses xV xV , then IN is fully liable, so her best reply is xIN x*IN . * If IN chooses xIN xIN , then V’s best reply is xV x*V . Bilateral Accidents IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level x~ . * ~ If society chooses x xV and V * chooses xV xV , then IN is fully liable, so her best reply is xIN x*IN . * If IN chooses xIN xIN , then V’s best reply is xV x*V . I.e. the rule causes a socially optimal Nash equilibrium. Bilateral Accidents Notes: – socially optimal liability rules do not generally fully compensate the victim. – socially optimal accident deterrence is distinct from optimal accident compensation. Treble Damages & Antitrust Law The Sherman and Clayton Acts allow an agent damaged by price-fixing to sue and recover treble damages. How does such a penalty affect the behavior of a price-fixing cartel? Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Assume firms collude to form a cartel with a constant marginal production cost, c. Market demand is x ( p ). Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Assume firms collude to form a cartel with a constant marginal production cost, c. Market demand is x ( p ). Cartel’s goal is max ( p ) ( p c ) x ( p ). p Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Assume firms collude to form a cartel with a constant marginal production cost, c. Market demand is x ( p ). Cartel’s goal is max ( p c ) x ( p ). Solution is p p p m x m x ( p m ). Treble Damages & Antitrust Law fixing price at p results in damages D( p ) to a victim V. V’s probability of winning suit against the cartel is . If V wins, the cartel must pay D( p ). Suppose Treble Damages & Antitrust Law fixing price at p results in damages D( p ) to a victim V. V’s probability of winning suit against the cartel is . If V wins, the cartel must pay D( p ). Cartel’s problem is now max ( p c ) x ( p ) D( p ). Suppose p Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Cartel’s problem is now max ( p c ) x ( p ) D( p ). p Solution is not generally the same as for the original problem max ( p c ) x ( p ). p So generally cartel behavior is affected by the penalty. Treble Damages & Antitrust Law case -- suppose D( p ) is the cartel’s profit. The cartel’s goal is Special max ( p c ) x ( p ) D( p ) (1 )( p c ) x ( p ). p Treble Damages & Antitrust Law case -- suppose D( p ) is the cartel’s profit. The cartel’s goal is Special max ( p c ) x ( p ) D( p ) (1 )( p c ) x ( p ). p Maximizing after-penalty profit requires maximizing before-penalty profit. Treble Damages & Antitrust Law case -- suppose D( p ) is the cartel’s profit. The cartel’s goal is Special max ( p c ) x ( p ) D( p ) (1 )( p c ) x ( p ). p Maximizing after-penalty profit requires maximizing before-penalty profit. The cartel’s behavior is unaffected by the penalty. Treble Damages & Antitrust Law What if consumers can seek to be damaged? Treble Damages & Antitrust Law What if consumers can seek to be damaged? Suppose consumer utility is quasilinear; u( x ) m px . Consumer can win damages D ( p c ) x . So consumer’s goal is max u( x ) m px ( p c ) x . x Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Consumer’s goal is max u( x ) m px ( p c ) x . I.e. x max u( x ) m [ p ( p c ) ]x . x Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Consumer’s goal is max u( x ) m px ( p c ) x . I.e. x p ( p c ) ]x . max u( x ) m [ x effective price, p Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Consumer’s goal is max u( x ) m [ p ( p c ) ]x . x effective price, p Since consumer’s action depends upon the effective price, rewrite the cartel’s problem as max ( p c ) x ( p ). p Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Consumer’s goal is max u( x ) m [ p ( p c ) ]x . x effective price, p Since consumer’s action depends upon the effective price, rewrite the cartel’s problem as max ( p c ) x ( p ). p Solution is the same m as the original problem; p p . Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Solution is the same as the original m problem; p p . p* is the price paid by buyers. Then m pm p * p p * ( p * c ). Treble Damages & Antitrust Law Solution is the same as the original m problem; p p . p* is the price paid by buyers. Then m p p * ( p * c ). So m m p c m ( p c ) m p* p p . 1 1 Treble Damages & Antitrust Law m m p c m ( p c ) m p* p p . 1 1 m cartel’s price p* p , the price set in the absence of damage penalties. But the effective price to both consumers and the cartel is the same as in the no damages case. The