Jan. 21, 2112 A note to PSAC colleagues: This is a work-in-progress that remains incomplete in a few sections, as indicated. If you are not already familiar with Elizabeth Anderson's work on educational equity, you might want to read this paper strategically. Start with the abstract and then go immediately to pp. 11-18, where I discuss her method. And then you could read the sections entitled: Introduction, Anderson's Imperative, and Philosophers or Gekkos, as I will be concentrating on this material. Appendix I is rather interesting as well. Thanks for your interest, and I look forward to our discussion. (The usual caveats and requests apply; please do not circulate this incomplete draft without my permission.) Yours, Anna Marie Working Title. “Justice and School Finance: Is There a Radical Egalitarian Future Hidden Within Anderson‘s Imperative?” Anna Marie Smith Abstract “Justice and School Finance: Is There a Radical Egalitarian Future Hidden Within Anderson‘s Imperative?” An exploration of the tension between two major political philosophy approaches to education equity: “adequacy” — in which justice requires the provision of a threshold level of educational opportunity for all — and “equality” — in which the standard requires limitations on the gap between the best off and the worst off. The discussion is centered on the adequacy approach of Elizabeth Anderson. I begin by showing that her 2010 book, The Imperative of Integration, not only constitutes a compelling call for racial desegregation but also reproduces the author’s earlier endorsement of the adequacy approach. Moreover, Anderson continues to set the threshold level of educational opportunity at a very high level. I outline her diagnosis of racial segregation as a major 1 cause of racial inequality, and summarize her argument for a moral obligation for racial integration, paying particularly close attention to her proposals for school reform. (Along the way, I also point out that as a “real world” theorist, Anderson has missed out on an opportunity to engage with an important development in school finance economics, namely weighted student funding.) Further, I demonstrate that Anderson is implicitly endorsing a compound standard, one in which barriers to educational opportunity related to both i) racial segregation and ii) race-neutral wealth differences would be addressed. Then I offer a critical assessment of the validity of her “real world” proposals; I construct an imaginary state in which her reforms are successfully established and probe the implications for justice. My assessment pays attention to two complementary dimensions: empirical changes to life chances, especially for the least advantaged; and the legal empowerment of the least advantaged. I argue that Anderson would establish a state constitutional right to education, and that the provision would be framed in adequacy terms. I argue that we can appreciate the significance of Anderson’s educational entitlement by taking the Supreme Court’s 1973 decision, San Antonio v. Rodriguez, fully into account. However, I also show that the outcomes for Anderson's thought experiment cannot be predicted in advance, and that the criticisms of the radical egalitarians, Brighouse and Swift, may have merit in the end. 2 Introduction. In an era in which fiscal austerity is considered an unassailable ideal and raceconscious integrationist policy is regarded as an anachronism, the post-Brown era’s remarkable reduction in the achievement gap serves as an invaluable touchstone. Desegregation, school finance reform, the first rounds of the redistributive Elementary and Secondary Education Act grants from the federal government, and, more broadly, the War on Poverty investments in poverty assistance and health care delivered substantial results. Previously, low-income and African-American pupils attended poorly resourced schools and turned in academic performances that were much more modest than that for their higher-income and White counterparts. As the schools serving the least advantaged students were enormously improved, the gaps in schools spending and access to qualified teachers reached historic lows in the mid- to late-1970s. As a direct result, the black-white achievement gap was halved between 1970 and the mid-1980s; it reached historic lows in 1988. With retrenchment at the federal and state levels, however, these gaps began to rise again in the 1980s, while the Supreme Court’s abandonment of desegregation permitted school segregation to climb from the early 1990s to the present. Today, the schools with majority black student bodies are more segregated and less resourced than ever before. International standardized test results suggest that the United States has a much higher achievement gap for pupils from different socio-economic backgrounds than any other OECD country. Comparative data on school spending suggest that the United States has more inequality in school spending than its European and Asian counterparts, and that these inequalities are closely related to the average socio-economic conditions of the schools’ students. [D-H 18-19, 11-12, 12] There is a strong consensus among education experts that teacher quality constitutes one of the most important “inputs” where pupil achievement is concerned. [d-h *] In an ideal society, each and every student would have a highly skilled and fully certified teacher, regardless of his or her socioeconomic background. In our real world conditions, the best teachers command the highest salaries; by the same token, the schools spending the least on teacher salaries are overwhelmingly populated by the lowest-performing teachers. [d-h pg *]1 On the whole, the wealthiest school districts in the United States have budgets that are nearly ten times larger than that for the poorest. [d-h, 12] The high spending districts typically have much more qualified and skilled teachers, curricula oriented towards higher-level thinking instead of rote learning, a richer array of course offerings, up-to-date libraries and computers, and smaller class sizes.[dh 22] The adequacy-equality debate among political philosophers dealing with distributive justice and educational opportunity is a prominent element in the contemporary literature. Adequacy theorists, such as Amartya Sen, [*] Martha 3 Nussbaum, [*] and Elizabeth Anderson [*], [see also Amy Gutmann, DE, esp. 136-139] argue that the individual has a claim to a threshold level of goods that are functionally related to her basic capabilities in order to live a human life worthy of respect. As exercises in “real world” philosophy, adequacy arguments about justice take into account contemporary conditions, including the scarcity of resources and the imperfect cognitive and normative orientations of the human subject. Adequacy theorists argue that the individual has a right to a decent level of educational opportunity since basic capabilities — such as individual flourishing; the ability to earn a living wage in the labor market; the ability to command the respect of one’s peers; and the ability to participate freely and meaningfully in civil society, democratic deliberation, and the political process — require access to a threshold level of school-based learning. [MN exception*] Egalitarian theorists, such as Rawls[fn] and Brighouse and Swift,[fn] share with the adequacy theorists the valuing of these practices, and the assumption that schoolbased learning is indispensable to them. However, they give priority to the least advantaged and they therefore argue that the introduction of a threshold entitlement to adequate public schooling in “real world” conditions would be ultimately selfdefeating. The adequacy approach leaves the most advantaged free to accumulate disproportionate shares of income and wealth, and to convert them into scarce educational goods, such as hoarded shares [Tilly in Anderson*] of public educational goods, private tutoring, and private schooling. Egalitarians would concede that as long as the adequacy theorists set their thresholds at levels above the current conditions of the least advantaged, the latter would benefit from the adequacy entitlement in the form of enhanced individual flourishing. However, in market societies featuring a “natural liberty”-style labor market — that is, where status discrimination is prohibited such that careers are open to talents, and the most desirable positions are distributed by meritocratic competition [Rawls, TJ, 57] —education also has a positional good dimension. The value of my educational credentials is relative to the quantity and quality of the credentials held by my future competitors for scarce places in higher education institutions and the most desirable positions. In a competitive and individualistic society in which cross-class solidarity is rare, and even the well-intentioned members of the upper strata grasp that they are locked within a prisoner’s dilemma, the long-term impact of the provision of a decent adequacy entitlement to education cannot be determined in advance. Adequacy theorists do not hold that justice requires the limitation of inequality. However, they do not prohibit the adoption of egalitarian policies, that is, the reforms that could reduce the gap between the most advantaged and the least advantaged, through the political process. Perhaps the enhancement of the educational opportunities for the least advantaged will facilitate their political mobilization; over the long term, this “real 4 world” society might see the formation of formidable radical social movements and the gradual adoption of egalitarian policies as a result. On the other hand, however, Brighouse and Swift predict that the most advantaged will react to the enhancement of the educational entitlements among the least advantaged by engaging in an educational “arms war.” As the least advantaged enjoy more and richer educational opportunities, the most advantaged parents invest in private goods such as tutoring and private schooling for their children to preserve their competitive superiority.[BS*] As the level of educational opportunity enjoyed by the most advantaged is ratcheted up, the positional dimension of the adequacy-level public schooling received by the least advantaged will diminish accordingly. In this paper, I intend to contribute four new elements to this well-established debate. First, Brighouse and Swift tend to neglect the potential political mobilization effect that Anderson’s rich adequacy entitlement could have among the least advantaged. By the same token, Brighouse and Swift downplay the tactics used by the most advantaged parents within the public system to hoard educational resources. It is certainly true that by focusing exclusively on a small set of private market goods, tutoring and private schooling, their argument is all the more concise, elegant, and applicable to virtually any market society. In the American context, however, a comprehensive study of the positional educational benefits that are effectively purchased by middle- and upper-class parents for the exclusive use of their children has to address these hoarding practices and the governmental structures that facilitate and incentivize them. Second, a comprehensive review of Anderson’s position on educational entitlement is greatly complicated by the fact that she also insists upon the racial desegregation of neighborhoods and schools. Brighouse and Swift have not fully responded to Anderson’s arguments about the duties of wealthy whites with respect to racial integration. With her publication of a new book on this subject, The Imperative of Integration,2 we have the opportunity to consider their debate in fresh terms. Third, reading Imperative in tandem with Anderson’s earlier political philosophy articles [*] reveals that Anderson’s “real world” reforms should entail two key elements in school finance economics. In an earlier article, [*] she calls for fiscal neutrality. Under this regime, each local school district in a given state would be able to access an equal share of the state’s total property base for the generation of educational tax revenues. Valuing the expression of local educational preferences, she requires the state school finance system to permit voters in each district to choose how much they wish to be taxed, and the fiscal neutrality system would guarantee that their chosen level of school taxation effort would determine the degree to which the local district budgets would be lifted above her threshold. Anderson does not, however, explicitly integrate fiscal neutrality into her Imperative. I demonstrate that even if her racial integration reforms were fully implemented, her standard of fairness could not be achieved without fiscal 5 neutrality. At the same time, it should be noted that Anderson does not address another recent development in school finance economics, namely the weighted student approach. Under these terms, school budgetary needs reflect both the size of the student body, and the individual characteristics of the pupils. Using coefficients calculated to reflect the additional costs of adequately educating pupils with disabilities, pupils coming from low-income households, and English language learners, weighted student formulae permit a much more fine-tuned approach to the fair distribution of educational spending than the traditional per-pupil budgetary methods. I argue that Anderson should supplement the integrationist policies that she endorses in Imperative with weighted student funding requirements as well. In sum, the strongest reconstruction of Anderson’s arguments requires a compound standard: a high level of threshold entitlement; racial integration; optional egalitarian statutory reforms to limit inequality; permissible supplements within and outside the public system; fiscal neutrality; and weighted student funding. Fourth, the Anderson versus Brighouse and Swift debate has been conducted largely in the terms proper to their “real world” political philosophy genre. There are remarkable parallels, however, between their arguments and major constitutional debates that are being conducted in the United States’ federal and state courts. By demonstrating the continuities with San Antonio v. Rodriguez (411 U.S. 1 (1973)), Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School District No. 1 (551 U.S. 701 (2007)), and the right to education cases in the state courts, we can gain a fresh perspective on the constitutional doctrine and underline the legal significance of the philosophers’ adequacy-equality debate. In the first section of this paper, I will present Anderson’s argument for racial integration through local zoning reforms and race conscious school policies. Given the jurisdictional issues that would play an important role in her “real world” scenario, I locate her reforms within a hypothetical state, Andersonia, that is located inside the contemporary federal structure of the United States. I provide an account for my supplementation of her integrationist adequacy approach with the fiscal neutrality and weighted student funding regimes. Then I examine the ways in which the least advantaged would benefit from her reforms — postponing, for the moment, the competitive responses of the most advantaged. I show that she would endorse a new constitution for Andersonia in which there would be an explicit state constitutional right to education, specified in sufficientarian terms and defined with reference to college readiness, a very rich threshold standard. By contrasting the Andersonian constitutional right to education with our existing federal doctrine, under the holdings in San Antonio v. Rodriguez (411 U.S. 1 (1973)), I show that Anderson’s constitutional provision would represent a significant step towards the constitutional empowerment for the least advantaged. My discussion of Rodriguez is also valuable insofar as it brings to light the Supreme Court’s framing of the whole issue of local school budget 6 autonomy. Sracic’s close reading of the decision and the archival materials reveals the way in which the Rodriguez majority situated the questions pertaining to local control within the terms established by the Cold War approach to liberty rights.[*fn Sracic] The holdings, and the Court’s Cold War framing, underline the extent to which the hoarding of public school resources by the most advantaged are deeply entrenched in the American civic ethos. Having fully established Anderson’s reforms, I then weigh their strengths and weaknesses. I critically review the evidence that Anderson herself relies upon — especially the ethnographic studies of housing integration projects and research on the validity of Allison’s “contact theory” — that suggest positive outcomes. I then introduce several other dimensions that produce indeterminate or negative outcomes: empirical evidence from Berkeley High School presented by Noguera and Wing, and, on a more hypothetical level, the implications for justice in Andersonia of above-threshold spending in some local districts, the political mobilization of the least advantaged, defection on the part of the parents who send their children to private school, and defection on the part of the Andersonians who move out of state. In the concluding section, I contrast the implicit emphasis in Anderson’s work on jurisdictional reform issues to the emergence of a cosmopolitan school of normative political theory. Both types of work should be valued insofar as they explore the extent to which the most advantaged have a duty to interrogate the naturalism of given political boundaries and to adopt a more critical understanding of the spatial and associational limits of our moral obligations. Anderson’s Imperative. Anderson’s Imperative of Integration is a powerful and ultimately persuasive indictment of racial segregation in contemporary American society, and a compelling call for integrative reforms. Marshaling a wealth of empirical data, including the fruits of state-of-the-art research in the areas of demography, the housing preferences of blacks and whites, and public opinion, Anderson argues that racial segregation is unjust in that it embodies unjust social relations, is caused by unjust social relations, or reproduces further unjust social relations. Although she readily concedes that racial inequality is overdetermined, Anderson convincingly demonstrates that segregation is a “principal cause” of racial inequality. [*] Through racial segregation, blacks are disproportionately represented among low-income Americans and deprived of the opportunity to join powerful political coalitions that control the distribution of public and private resources. Access to social networks, mentors, and cultural capital is extremely constrained for blacks who reside in the most segregated and low income housing developments. 7 Anderson’s remarks about racial segregation and the maldistribution of public goods, especially quality public schools, are particularly riveting. Of all racial and ethnic groups, African-Americans are the most likely to reside in segregated neighborhoods. The 2000 Census data suggest that about half of the United States’ black population lives in “hypersegregated” census tracts.[26] Jim Crow segregation in the public K-12 schools was significantly reduced between 1960 and 1990, thanks to the impact of the Brown v. Board of Education decision in 1954 (347 U.S. 483 (1954)) and subsequent federal regulation and conditional federal school spending. [fn: ESEA, cite to Rosenberg*] However, the Supreme Court has deconstitutionalized racial segregation since that time.[Chermerinsky*] From the 1970s onwards, the Supreme Court has diminished the authority of the federal district courts to maintain desegregation orders where de jure violations have been established, and it has consistently refused to address racial segregation in districts where intentional racial discrimination on the part of government actors had never been proven. [case cites, Milliken to Jenkins] Today, advocates and federal regulators rarely charge schools districts with committing de jure violations. Nevertheless, the segregation tide turned once again in the early 1990s. Since that time, de facto segregation on the ground has actually become much more widespread and pronounced. In 2005-06, the typical black student attended a school that was 52 percent black, 30 percent white, 14 percent Latino, and 4 percent Asian or Native American.[26] In New York, Michigan, Illinois, and California, segregation is even more extreme. There, the typical black student attended a school in which whites were a small minority: white students made up less than one quarter of the whole student body.[26] Multiple studies have confirmed that the black-white achievement gap is largest in the states with the most highly segregated schools, and smallest in the states with the most integrated schools.[120] Teachers overwhelmingly prefer to teach in the public schools with white majority or highly integrated student bodies. Segregated schools tend to be staffed by the least experienced teachers, and their inexperience has been linked to the black-white gap in educational achievement.[39, 121] Blacks attending integrated schools tend to do better than their counterparts in segregated schools.[121] Although the peer effect is not well understood, educational experts estimate that pupils gain a great deal from their exposure to higher achieving and economically better pupils.[121] The peer effect dimension problematizes the earlier studies that purported to show that busing black children into white majority schools delivered few positive results in terms of the black-white achievement gap. Intra-school segregation through tracking and the discriminatory use of disciplinary exclusion can nullify the potential benefits from racial integration.[121] Substantial gains in scholarly achievement, by contrast, were made by low income blacks drawn from segregated communities who received scholarships to attend elite private academies.[122] Other studies demonstrate that the benefits of integration for disadvantaged blacks can extend throughout the life course. They found that after 8 controlling for family background, economic resources, and educational status, the blacks who attended integrated schools were less likely to be incarcerated, and more likely to earn a high school diploma.[122] Among the black students attending white majority colleges, the ones who were educated in integrated high schools earned higher grades than their black peers with diplomas from segregated high schools.[122] Segregation in the public schools goes hand in hand with residential segregation. The quality and reputation of the local school has a direct impact on the value of the homes located within its catchment area. Conversely, because the school districts’ pupil catchment zones reflect neighborhood divisions, and because blacks tend to live in segregated neighborhoods, we end up with segregated student bodies in the public schools. The heavy hand of federal governmental responsibility for segregative residential outcomes has already been well established where the New Deal and postwar eras are concerned. [fed role: public housing, mortgage lending, highway funding, etc. Massey and Denton, Oliver and Shapiro* ] The role of the local and state governments in producing residential segregation should be emphasized as well. Local governments have several tools at their disposal to safeguard the concentration of wealthy families in a particular area such that they can take the form of a selfperpetuating exclusionary enclave and obtain legal ratification for their self-dealing. Technically, all local governments are “creatures of the state”; in the end, the state bears legal responsibility for their actions. The state, however, typically endows its local governments with tremendous autonomy. The state permits the local governments that serve particularly wealthy constituents to use zoning regulations freely to defend and promote wealth-based exclusion. These local governments may, for example, require their home owners to maintain minimum lot sizes, setbacks, and expensive amenities; prohibit public housing, trailer parks, and mixed-income rental housing developments; and restrict the construction of multifamily residential cooperatives or condominiums. As a supplement to Anderson’s account, we could note that advocates for racial equality have challenged this type of zoning in federal court, but have not prevailed. In Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Development Corporation (429 U.S. 252 (1977)), low-income blacks and a non-profit housing developer argued that because blacks are overwhelmingly concentrated among the poor, a local government violated their equal protections rights when it refused to grant the developer permission to construct a mixed-income housing development, and to carry out its multiracial and class-integrated vision of resident recruitment. The Supreme Court held that the complainants had not proven racially discriminatory intent or purpose on the part of the local government officials. By merely demonstrating that blacks would be disproportionately harmed by the zoning decision, they had not met the burden of establishing an equal protection violation, namely the showing that a discriminatory intent or purpose was a motivating factor in the local government’s zoning decision. 9 Tucked away in the details of Anderson’s exacting and comprehensive review of the latest social science findings on racial residential segregation is a damning piece of evidence that deserves especially close inspection. The phenomenon of municipal fragmentation involves the deliberate drawing and re-drawing of local government boundaries. It is, in sum, an extremely complex legal maneuver that requires the explicit approval of the gubernatorial and state legislative branches and extensive bureaucratic adjustments on the part of several state agencies. While municipal fragmentation constitutes a micro-level reform in sheer spatial terms, it is exquisitely fine-tuned for the purpose of capturing arbitrary advantage. Through municipal fragmentation, an opportunity-hoarding elite can promote its interests in residential capital gains and the monopolization of high quality public school resources to an extreme degree. Anderson notes that municipal fragmentation is not distributed evenly across the country. Nor is it a random trend that pops up here and there without leaving any observable patterns in its wake. On the contrary. Municipal fragmentation in the United States is “particularly intense near cities with high black populations.” [39] Behind every type of “white flight” from the “threat” of a black residential presence — whether it’s a white mass movement to the suburbs as a whole, white flocking to specific white dominated enclaves within the suburbs, or white “resettlement” in the gentrified and Disney-fied section of the urban core — is a governmental actor facilitating white opportunity hoarding. Anderson quite reasonably concludes that “there is reason to believe that whites have used race-based municipal boundary drawing in conjunction with classexclusionary zoning to exclude blacks.”[39] Racial integration, through the dismantling of de jure segregative laws and integration on the spatial, informal, and social levels, brings with it significant benefits and Anderson argues that they are morally significant. Clearly, blacks benefit from the more equal distribution of public and private goods and the reduction of racial stigma. Whites also benefit insofar as racial integration brings about important political effects. Democratic procedures and the whole civic culture can be deeply transformed by racial integration. It can introduce, for example, more thoughtful jury deliberation. It may be necessary for a jury member to understand the socio-cultural context behind a series of actions performed by the accused, and yet such understanding might be quite rare outside a particular disadvantaged group. A democratic society gains from the pluralistic epistemic advantage that can be produced by a racially integrated jury; legitimate questions are more likely to be raised about the evidence produced by the state prosecutor during the deliberations. Racial integration can also enhance democratic accountability. With the empowerment of traditionally excluded black citizens, their voices and specific demands can be amplified in public fora, and they can themselves enjoy a more egalitarian opportunity to run for office. [pgs *] Anderson’s concrete public policy proposals follow logically from her structural diagnosis and moral argument. She endorses racial affirmative action as one of the 10 important tools for achieving racial integration. This is a forward-looking “plus system” procedure that values the integration of a critical mass of blacks within elite institutions, including colleges and professional schools, government contracting, and private business subsidy programs, in order to promote interracial cooperation, attack racial stigma, produce multiculturally sensitive elite decision-makers, and foster vibrant democratic exchange. Black participants in her affirmative action programs would earn inclusion on the basis of their achievement of a minimum standard of individual merit. Crucially, she would nest racial affirmative action programs within a whole system of reforms designed to dismantle segregation and discrimination and encourage racial integration. Many of her proposed reforms would simply involve the active enforcement of existing laws and policies, such as the prohibition of racial discrimination in housing and employment and the dilution of black voting power. Others would redefine existing regulations in more radical terms; she would establish, for example, disproportionate impact standards and openly race conscious integrative plans to produce diverse voting districts. In full opposition against a recent Supreme Court decision, Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School District No. 1 (551 U.S. 701 (2007)), she explicitly calls for deliberately desegregative pupil assignment programs in K-12 public schools to achieve integrated student bodies. Rejecting Arlington Heights, she would prohibit exclusionary zoning and offer housing vouchers to blacks that would subsidize their entry into white middle class neighborhoods. [72, 118-120, 189] Alert to the fact that blacks are vastly overrepresented within the lower income brackets, and that ostensibly economic forms of exclusion often have a disproportionate impact on African-Americans, she also endorses race-neutral policies, such as the prohibition of class-segregative zoning regulations that are necessary for the eradication of de facto racial segregation. [71-3, 189] Moreover, she calls for full participation of members of virtually every social group on terms of equality, cooperation, and mutual respect in all domains of civil society. Anderson rules out, in this sense, reparations and black nationalist separatism. Her vision of racial integration does not, however, extend as far as assimilation. While she endorses the formation of a shared national identity that would serve as the normative basis for public reason, she explicitly rejects the homogenizing vision of the communitarians and republicans who would discourage the formation of particularistic ethnic affiliations altogether.[*] Equity and School Funding Issues Anderson’s “real world” theory is designed to deal with human subjects as we find them today, in our imperfect conditions of scarcity and limited social cooperation. The human subjects who populate a “real world” theory should exhibit the sorts of 11 preference formation and cognitive processes that are familiar to us in the present.[3-4] She nevertheless points out that this does not mean that “real world” theory must take the feasibility of reforms into account as it defines our moral duties.[190-91] It does not matter, for example, to the political philosopher who correctly identifies racial segregation as a form of injustice whether the whites who benefit enormously from segregation would respond to anti-racist criticism positively or stubbornly refuse to give up their racial privilege. It is the moral duty of the individual to do what she can to promote the justice of social arrangements. [148-9, cf. Rawls, natural duty, c.o. section of TJ] Further, it is just to expect that each individual will bear her fair share of the costs of the reforms necessary for progress. [149] The testing of a “real world” philosophical argument, then, is genre specific. The moral validity of a reform proposal generated out of a “real world” argument does not rest on its prospects for implementation in the immediate context. What the “real world” philosopher aims to do is to propose just institutions that would “block, work around, or cancel out our motivational and cognitive deficiencies, […] harness our nonmoral motives to moral ends, […] make up for each other’s limitations by pooling our knowledge and wills.” [4] A sound “real world” theory, then offers an accurate account of our biases and blindspots, identifies the ways in which they have sedimented into unjust social structures, and designs institutions that would encourage these still-flawed subjects to engage in morally better practices. [4] If possible, the reforms proposed by a “real world” theory are put to the test in actual living experiments. Their validity is proven if we find that “they solve the problems for which they were devised, settle people’s reasonable complaints, and offer a way of life that people find superior to what they had before.”[6] Given this framing, the scope of a “real world” theory’s moral claims is limited to the historical configuration to which they are addressed. It is a moral duty of great urgency to promote racial integration in the United States today, given the ways that segregation has been caused by racial injustice, embodies racial injustice, and promotes further racial injustice. At another place and time, however, demographic concentrations by race could be much less closely linked to injustice in these three respects; Anderson’s theory would be less relevant to that world, but its historic specificity has no bearing on its validity for this world. Where a full-blown living experiment is not possible, we can glean evidence about the effects of the theory’s reforms from scholarly observations of existing institutions and plausible hypothetical models. Obviously, the further we get from the comprehensive living experiment, our conclusions become all the more speculative. To test the claims of “real world” theory, we usually have to make educated guesses, preferably on the basis of psychological and sociological research, and well established normative arguments, about the ways in which the various fragments would work together as a whole. 12 In this discussion, then, I will set up an imaginary scenario that combines the following features: it retains our current conditions where individual behavior, structural inequality, and scarcity are concerned, but it suspends feasibility concerns where Anderson’s proposed reforms are concerned. In a state named Andersonia, a democratic social movement that strongly favors racial and economic justice becomes extraordinarily popular and influential. The vast majority of Andersonia’s residents strongly endorse the founding of their state, complete with its own constitution. The constitution requires the adoption of highly interventionary state policies designed to entitle its resident children with the right to an adequate education, [*fn Rebell etc on state cons and edn rts] and the desegregation, in racial and economic terms, of the state’s neighborhoods and public schools. There is a historic convergence in preferences among voters from all walks of life; the coalition in support of the founding and integrative reforms even includes several wealthy whites. The depth of this consensus is such that the preferences of a majority of Andersonians remain secure even in the difficult transitional years as the reforms are first introduced. In the face of the inevitable implementation problems, they enthusiastically choose to stay the course. What outcomes would the founding of Andersonia produce? Would the Andersonian reforms benefit the least advantaged? Would they encourage already advantaged wealthy whites who are bent on the narrow pursuit of their interests, sometimes at great cost to the least advantaged, to examine their behavior critically and adopt attitudes and practices more conducive to social cooperation and the promotion of a non-discriminatory and non-exploitative conception of the public good? For the purposes of this article, I will concentrate on one policy issue that is central to distributive justice, namely the fair distribution of educational opportunity. First, I will round out Anderson’s reform vision by adding the fiscal neutrality scheme that she has endorsed elsewhere, and I will demonstrate how it complements and promotes the integrative vision that she constructs in her Imperative. In her 2007 article, “Fair Opportunity in Education,” Anderson offers a defense of a scheme that would distribute educational goods, in the context of a liberal democratic “real world” society, according to a robust adequacy standard. [Elizabeth Anderson, "Fair Opportunity in Education: A Democratic Equality Perspective," Ethics 117 (July 2007): 595-622.] She would integrate K-12 schools to encourage interracial communication and the production of culturally competent graduates. From Anderson’s perspective, "much of the critical learning that elites need to undertake is grounded in intergroup peer interactions out of class, not in formal in-class discussion or class assignments." [614] Only a public school system that thoroughly grasps the fact that pupils from highly diverse backgrounds bear valuable social funds of knowledge and ensures that pupils from the most advantaged families are brought into close contact with their less fortunate peers in virtually every classroom and 13 extracurricular activity can deliver the kind of collaborative education necessary for the production of culturally competent democratic citizens. [ibid, passim] For Anderson, public investment in higher education would have to be justified in terms resembling the Rawlsian difference principle. Extraordinary public investments in elite education are permissible but only as long as these programs are operated fairly, and the resulting surplus ultimately benefits the worst off. Successful applicants in higher education admission competitions would have to demonstrate, in addition to basic scholarly merit, strong public service records and the multicultural competence skills honed in fully integrated K-12 classrooms.[*ethics]3 Moreover, children from the most disadvantaged families would not be treated with a “sink or swim” attitude by the integrated schools. Teachers and principals would be tasked with providing appropriate support services to deliver genuinely fair equality of opportunity, such as special tutoring for the children of parents with low levels of education who typically arrive at kindergarten with modest vocabularies and poor communication skills.[ethics, imperative*] It is crucial, in this sense, that Anderson both redefines merit to include multicultural competence as well as traditional scholarly achievement, and only permits merit-based competitions for scarce publicly subsidized educational opportunities at the college admissions phase in the life course. Anderson clearly establishes that the state and school district could not satisfy her integrative requirements by merely producing demographically integrated student bodies in each school. The school must bring individuals from diverse social groups together on terms of equality, rather than domination and subordination.[ethics 612, note 31] Anderson would therefore have to require equality of resources between the schools, and she would have to prohibit all forms of “tracking” within each school. Each and every pupil, regardless of their parents’ educational achievements and socioeconomic background, would have to be meaningfully provided with the resources necessary for the preparation of a successful college admission application. For example, an Andersonian high school would not have distinct Basic and Advanced Placement tracks through which racial and socioeconomic segregation lines could creep back into the school’s hidden curriculum. [Noguera and Wing] Even if consistent and across-the-board integration required the teaching of multi-level classes, teachers would simply have to redesign their lesson plans accordingly. [Intl Schools, NYC] Technically, we could say that Anderson envisions the endowment of each pupil with a right to a college-preparation level of public educational resources, regardless of her socio-economic background and her parents’ educational level. [note: children with learning disabilities: individually tailored standard, according to the degree of their personal potential; cite to case] Parents who observe the failures that are all too common in our public schools today, such as class- and race-based segregation, vast intra-district, intra-state, and inter-state differences in school quality, the assignment of 14 unqualified teachers to non-elite classes, the mis-diagnosis of under-performing children as disabled, the abuse of suspension and expulsion procedures to artificially boost a school’s test scores, and so on, [darling-hammond] would be empowered in Andersonia to sue the district and the state for violating their child’s right to a decent education. In Imperative, Anderson remarks that justice requires more than the redistribution of tax revenues from the most advantaged neighborhoods to the least advantaged, since it entails the dismantling of residential segregation altogether.[186] We could not, however, rely solely upon the production of racially- and economically-integrated neighborhoods to satisfy Anderson’s standards. It is highly likely that we would still be confronted by significant mismatches between local pupil needs and local resources. Anderson implicitly anticipates this problem by building up a compound approach to educational equity in “Fair Opportunity.” There she calls for all of the following: 1) the desegregation of the schools, and the integration of all public school classroom environments ; [ibid.] 2) the integration of neighborhoods through the prohibition of class-exclusionary zoning laws, the rigorous enforcement of housing discrimination laws, mandatory mixed-class housing requirements for private developers, and so on; [ibid.] and 3) a state-wide fiscal neutrality formula for the calculation of local school board revenues, along the lines proposed by Coons, Sugarman, and Clune.[618, fn 41] To explain the significance of this compound standard, we have to review each element in the school finance matrix. Anderson implicitly retains the existing structure of school finance in which the local district’s contribution to the school budget makes up about 42 percent of the total, while the state contribution takes care of 50 percent and the federal government makes up the remaining 8 percent. [g and d*] In our hypothetical, we will assume that the state and federal contributions would be fairly calculated according to an equitable needsbased formula. In the United States today, the local school tax contribution is the product of the value of the taxable property located in the district, and the local school tax rate chosen and ratified by the local voters in school board elections.4 Under the original fiscal neutrality scheme designed by Coons et. al., the local school board would be free to set tax rate, according to the educational preferences of the local voters. Intrastate transfers between school boards would be made to ensure that each school district taxing itself at a given rate would be able to raise a roughly equal amount of tax revenues, regardless of the actual value of the taxable property.[Coons *] For the most part, school taxes are levied upon residential property located in the district. In some cases, the state also permits the local school district to impose school taxes upon local commercial and industrial property owners as well. Given the richness and egalitarian character of Anderson’s adequacy standard, she would have to introduce a few friendly amendments to the Coons et. al. formula. Where Coons et. al. propose to leave federal and state school spending untouched, Anderson would want to guarantee that these 15 distributions would be fairly calculated. At the local level, she would also impose a mandatory minimum school tax rate such that no district could choose to make such a low effort that it could not possibly deliver a decent level of educational opportunity. At first glance, it might appear that Andersonia would not preserve the tripartite school finance system. Would not Andersonia replace the local, state, and federal contributions with a simpler state and federal system? Historically, the local contribution has introduced a tremendous degree of inequity into the school finance system. The state-wide coalition for race- and class- integration in Andersonia would surely be a strong proponent of school equity. Would not the retention of local differences in school spending be an anachronism? It is important to recognize in this respect that Anderson permits parents to channel supplements above and beyond the threshold level to their own children. These can be delivered through three mechanisms: an above-threshold local taxation effort; parental purchase of tutoring for children remaining within the public school system; and parental purchase of private schooling for their children. I will return to a discussion of the latter two supplements, the ones that involve the private market in educational goods, below. Anderson anticipates, however, that some local groups of parents will have such extraordinarily strong preferences for above-threshold public school quality that they are willing to make a financial sacrifice to secure this outcome for their children and their local cohort, and she values their liberty to make this choice. [ethics 618] Within Andersonia, there would be some school districts that would have above-threshold budgets, reflecting the formation of local majorities willing to make extraordinary local school tax efforts. Inspired by a social movement within the state, Philosophia, many of the taxpayers wishing to make additional school tax efforts claim that they value the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake, and anticipate that the pupils attending the above-threshold public schools will have experience enhanced individual flourishing as a result. They predict that the Philosophia schools will produce many more musicians, poets, and classicists, than the threshold schools, for example. By retaining the tripartite school finance structure, in which contributions come from local sources, as well as the state and federal governments, Andersonia would guarantee the liberty of local taxpayers to produce above-threshold educational opportunity in their neighborhood schools. It may also appear that the fiscal neutrality formula, in all its complexity, would become superannuated in Andersonia. Once the state achieved a reasonable degree of residential integration, each district would include more or less the same amount of taxable residential property. Since each district would be ordered to calculate its minimum tax effort on a per pupil basis, each district choosing to make a threshold effort should end up with the same amount of per pupil revenue. Only the Philosophia districts would have different per pupil revenues at their disposal, and their higher revenues will reflect important liberty interests and will not have unjust consequences. 16 Fiscal neutrality would nevertheless be needed in Andersonia for several reasons. Local districts have traditionally made use of some parcels of non-residential property, such as mines, as part of their school tax base, and they are not evenly distributed across the state. In addition, Andersonia would adopt the weighted student finance approach that has earned overwhelming bipartisan support. [*] Instead of using a simple per pupil method for calculating a threshold amount of school revenue, weighted student formulae attend to both the total number of pupils and the representation, within that student body, of special needs children: English-language learners, children with disabilities, and pupils from very low income families. Children who are learning English or who have learning disabilities fare best in small classes taught by specially trained teachers. Some pupils with disabilities require additional aides and nurses. A single pupil from a very low-income family also faces, on average, difficult challenges at school. It is highly likely that her parents have relatively modest vocabulary and mathematical skills, and that her base knowledge and academic expectations are more limited than that of her more fortunate counterparts. Again, this is a special needs pupil whose motivation and achievement typically requires access to smaller classes; highly qualified and experienced teachers; after-school tutoring; support from school nurses, social workers, career counselors, and so on. Studies also suggest that pupils engage in a great deal of peer-to-peer teaching and learning. For this reason, experts agree that achievement gains in the schools with the largest concentrations of children who qualify for reduced or free lunches within their student bodies can only be delivered with above-average spending on teachers and support service personnel. Under the “weighted student” approach, co-efficients larger than 1 are assigned to each category of special needs pupils. Where a school has an extraordinary concentration of low income pupils, their co-efficient is adjusted upward.5 In addition, cost-of-living differences can play an important role in the teaching market. If we establish the national average in the cost-of-living index as 100, Los Angeles-Long Beach California has a score of 136.4. The scores for Brooklyn, New York; Tupelo, Mississippi; and Detroit, Michigan are 181.7, 88.1, and 99.4, respectively. [United States. Department of Commerce. Statistical Abstract. Table 728. Cost of Living Index, Selected Urban Areas, Annual Average: 2010.] A dollar in teacher salary expenditure goes further in Tupelo and Detroit than it does in Brooklyn; New York City has to spend a great deal more than any other city simply to hire and retain averageperforming teachers. Experts also agree that of all the inputs, the provision of qualified and experienced teachers outranks the others where student achievement is concerned, that the more qualified and experienced teachers command the greatest salaries. In Andersonia, we should have a rough equality in residential property value, and we should not see too much variation in the representation of low income pupils either by district or by school. However, it is unlikely that we will have perfectly even 17 distributions of pupils with disabilities and English-language-learners across the state’s districts. Further, we might see some districts that have an above-average cost-of-living and yet lack a corresponding above-average endowment in taxable property. Once we calculate the fair threshold level of revenues needed by each district, using weighted student finance methods and cost-of-living adjustments, there will be some districts with significant mismatches between the school revenues needed to provide a threshold level of educational entitlement and local taxable property value. If we want to preserve the liberty rights and fairness of Anderson’s general theory, these morally arbitrary elements will have to be smoothed out. The districts that would generate more local revenues, if they chose a threshold tax effort, than they needed to deliver to a threshold educational opportunity to their local pupils would have to pay the surplus into a redistributive state fund. Those moneys would be paid out to the districts in which student needs outstrip local school tax revenues, assuming a threshold tax effort. This fiscal neutrality scheme would guarantee that the only differences in educational opportunity across districts would reflect the local voters’ preferences for education spending and school tax effort. No district would be allowed to fall below the revenues needed to deliver a needs-based threshold level of entitlement. Among the districts that chose to make an extra school taxation effort, their supplemental revenues would reflect the degree of their extra effort. If, for example, fifty districts choose to make a 125% school tax effort, then they would end up with school revenues that are 125 % above the minimum, regardless of the value of local taxable property, and in terms that are weighted to reflect their actual populations of special needs pupils and adjusted to reflect local cost-of-living. Andersonia: Gains for the least advantaged? If we set aside, for the moment, the responses of the individuals who do not belong to the least advantaged social sectors to Andersonia’s policies, it is immediately evident that the least advantaged residing in the state would gain significantly from the reforms. My claim in this regard has two distinct elements. First, the least advantaged would benefit materially. Second, they would be endowed, under Anderson’s reforms, with an enforceable state constitutional entitlement. Under the existing federal constitutional doctrine, this entitlement would be highly significant. The data strongly suggest that many of the least advantaged schoolchildren in the United States are receiving a below-adequacy level of educational opportunity, and that there are unjust differences in the distribution of public school resources closely connected to wealth, income, race, and state residence. Two of the proxies used by educational experts to measure educational opportunity are student outcomes and resource inputs. International data indicate not only that United States’ public school students are not keeping pace with their counterparts in the OECD countries, but that 18 American whites and Asian-Americans earn average scores that are well above the OECD average, while the ones for Latino/a and African-Americans fall an equal distance below that mark. [d-h 11. On the 2003 PISA (Program for International Student Assessment) in reading, for example, the average score for white American pupils was 525. OECD pupils scored 483 on average, while the scores for Hispanics and blacks were 453 and 429 respectively. Ibid.] There is tremendous interstate variation in proficiency standards and student achievement. (see Appendix I) In sixteen states, the proficiency rate was below 35 percent in Grade Four mathematics in 2005. Two of those states, Mississippi and New Mexico, failed to bring 20 percent of their pupils up to the national proficiency level. Moreover, there is a gap of about twenty percent between the highest and lowest states where the proficiency standard is concerned. The publicly circulated data, however, suggest much better levels of achievement. The state governments are permitted, as part of their extraordinary autonomy in educational affairs, to set their own proficiency standards. In forty-eight states, the proficiency level has been set at such a low level that their schools appear to be performing well. In three states, Mississippi, Alabama, and Tennessee, the national proficiency standard was more than three times stricter than the state standard. Mississippi ranked 79 percent of its students as proficient or better, under its own testing standards, while only 18 percent achieved a proficiency score or higher on the national test. The consensus in the scholarly literature is that a highly qualified and skilled teacher is one of the most important inputs where student achievement is concerned. [dh] This is not to say that the socio-economic conditions of the student body are irrelevant. Children who enjoy good housing, stable and loving caregiving, basic health care, eat a decent diet, and have their hearing and eyesight tested and adjusted as necessary are much more oriented towards success at school than their less fortunate counterparts. [bolder is better: ladd, Rothstein et al*] Much of the governmental reforms necessary to secure or at least bolster these pre-conditions, however, fall under the jurisdiction of other agencies. In addition, studies have also found that even the children who are dealing with deficiencies in the school “surround” can improve their academic performance if they are brought into a good teacher’s classroom [d-h, cfe II, nj case] If we assume that the school district is competently managed, any significant change in revenue will be translated into corresponding decisions about teachers’ hiring, promotion, and salary. Moreover, strong teacher preferences — all things being equal, teachers overwhelmingly prefer positions in the schools and classrooms in which white, wealthy, and high scoring students are in the majority — place even greater fiscal pressure on the districts serving struggling students. One recent study found that the salary increase needed to retain high quality teachers in schools serving the disadvantaged could be greater than 50 percent. [Ladd and Loeb, in Allen and Reich, 6] To hire the most qualified and most experienced teachers, school districts must offer 19 above-average salaries; by the same token, the districts that can afford to pay only the lowest salaries must settle for the least qualified teachers with very little experience or none whatsoever. [Ladd and Loeb, in Allen and Reich,5- 6 [chnge pg with galleys]] Using simple per pupil spending data, Moser and Rubenstein found that there was some improvement in intrastate spending equity across districts between 1992 and 1995. [Michele Moser and Ross Rubenstein, “The Equality of Public School District Funding in the United States: A National Status Report,” Public Administration Review, 62: 1 (Jan./Feb. 2002): 63-72.] They also show that the states in which the state contribution made up the greatest proportion of district revenues — as opposed to the property-value oriented local contribution — generally provided a more equitable distribution of resources across their districts. Across the country, the state school finance schemes remain heavily biased in favor of property-wealthy districts; once again, this finding is especially significant given the fact that federal contributions make up only eight percent of school public spending. [*] A federal government report found that in thirty-seven states, there was a positive relationship between school spending and local income in the 1991-92 school year. [HI, one district, not included] [GAO, see below] The disparity remained even after adjustments were made to reflect the cost-ofliving and students’ educational needs. On average, wealthy school districts were able to spend 24 percent more on a simple per pupil basis. In calculating the contributions to local districts from the state budget, state governments were targeting additional funds to poor districts. Although these state contributions diminished the local property-value based inequalities, they did not eliminate them altogether. [United States. School Finance: State Efforts to Reduce Funding Gaps Between Poor and Wealth Districts. (Washington, D.C., 1997).) (see also Duncan, Greg and Murnane, Richard. Whither Opportunity: Rising Inequality, Schools, and Children’s Life Chances, New York: Russell Sage, 2011.)] Taking a longer view, Ladd and Loeb estimate that intrastate variation across districts in spending has been “reduced substantially in the past 40 years, largely as a result of school finance reform and property tax reform.” [5, Allen and Reich, chng pg galley, see also Corcoran and Evans, Loeb Handbook * more detail] Even with these improvements, intrastate variation, as well as intradistrict and intraschool inequities remain salient. [*Corcoran and Evans] Meanwhile, significant interstate differences also impede the achievement of educational equity. Ladd and Loeb note that the differences in K-12 public education spending across the states are larger than the variations across the districts within each state. [5, ibid.] Rodriguez: Is There a Federal Right to Education? 20 State constitutions can have entirely redundant provisions; if the state equal protection doctrine is defined by the state court as having essentially the same meaning as the federal doctrine, then it does not contribute to the legal empowerment of the least advantaged. Of course, the state court cannot offer an interpretation of the state constitution that would purport to permit the state to infringe upon federally guaranteed rights. However, in some cases, such as the right of same-sex couples to enter into a legal marriage, some state courts have interpreted their state constitutions generously, thereby endowing their residents with more robust rights than they would have if they had to rely upon the federal constitution alone.(ref. to Mass decision) To examine whether Andersonia’s right to education would substantially empower the least advantaged individuals residing in the state, we must compare this provision to the existing federal doctrine. The claim that justice requires the delivery of an adequate level of educational opportunity to pupil, regardless of the value of the taxable property located in that pupil’s district, formed the core of the plaintiff’s case in San Antonio v. Rodriguez (411 U.S. 1 (1973)). A group of parents with children attending public schools in the Edgewood Independent School District in San Antonio, Texas sued the state of Texas in district court in 1968. Their lawyers argued that the state education financing system violated their equal protection rights and their fundamental substantive due process right to education. The Supreme Court's Rodriguez decision was handed down in 1973. The Court held, in a 5-4 split, that the federal constitution does not include a fundamental right to education; that although there were great inequities in Texas’s school funding system, the system’s division of children according to the property wealth of their districts did not constitute a suspect classification; that the system therefore had to be reviewed under the Court’s most deferential rational basis standard; and that because the system promoted the permissible objective of local budgetary control, and was reasonably tailored to achieve that purpose, it was not unconstitutional. At the time of trial, Texas’s schools received the lion’s share of their funds from state and local sources; these contributions made up roughly fifty and forty percent of their revenues, respectively. Federal grants moneys were distributed in a heavily redistributive manner, but at ten percent of the total, they could not make that much of a difference. (J. Marshall, dissenting, Rodriguez, 73, 76.) Edgewood, an inner-city district with a total enrollment of 22,000 students, contained very little commercial or industrial property. The value of a typical residential home in the district was quite modest.6 Edgewood had the lowest median family income and the lowest assessed property value per pupil in the entire San Antonio area: $4,686 and $ 5,960 respectively. The local Edgewood voters had nevertheless imposed an extraordinary school tax effort upon themselves. Their school tax rate of $ 1.05 per $ 100 of assessed property was the highest in the area that year. Even with this extraordinary effort, however, the local homeowners were only able to produce a modest amount of funds. Expressed on a 21 simple per pupil basis, the local portion of Edgewood’s funds amounted to $ 26. The state contributed $ 222 per pupil. Federal funds of $ 108 accounted for more than 30 percent of the total, $356 per pupil. (pg *) The plaintiffs argued that the Texas legislature was essentially forcing the Edgewood district to rely very heavily on its local sources of revenue for its school funding. Given the modest value of the local taxable property, the Texas scheme effectively trapped the Edgewood pupils — that is to say, the children obliged by the socioeconomic circumstances of their parents to remain within the public school system — within schools that were grossly unequal in resources when compared to their counterparts in other Texas neighborhoods. Eventually, when these pupils graduated from their inferior high school, they would nevertheless have to compete with the more advantaged members of their cohort for scarce higher education resources, employment opportunities, and political clout. The plaintiffs tried to emphasize the positional disadvantage of the Edgewood pupils by drawing the attention of the federal court to the Alamo Heights school budget. Alamo Heights was an affluent San Antonio area district.7 There, the median family income was $ 8,001, and the assessed property value per pupil was more than $49,000. The local voters had endorsed a much less severe school tax rate of $ 0.85, but because the value of the district’s taxable property was relatively high, Alamo Heights was nevertheless able to collect $ 333 per pupil for spending on its own schools. The state contributed $ 225 per pupil, for a local-state subtotal of $ 558 per pupil. The state allocation formula emphasized each district’s teacher salaries; because the teachers in Alamo Heights had more years of experience and more advanced degrees than their counterparts in Edgewood, the state paid Alamo Heights a substantially higher grant on a per pupil basis.(Note 35 at 14) Additional federal funds of $ 36 rounded out the total for Alamo Heights school revenues to $ 594 per pupil. (pg *) Statewide research found a correlation of 0.973 between the market value of taxable property per pupil and the sum total of state and local revenues per pupil. [Rodriguez, J. Marshall, dissenting, Note 11, at 75.] The funding differences, argued the plaintiffs, were having a devastating impact on educational quality. In Edgewood, almost half of the teachers were not fully certified; many were teaching in the schools even though they held only the minimal “emergency” permit. Only 15 percent of the teachers had obtained a master’s degree in education. The Alamo Heights schools, by contrast, boasted a teacher certification rate of almost 90 percent. Thirty percent of their teachers held a master’s degree. [51 PSr?*] Throughout the decision, the Rodriguez Court expressed its strong skepticism about the existence of a causal linkage between low education spending 22 and the deprivation of educational opportunity. [23-4, 42-3, Note 56 at 24, and Note 86 at 43.] Granting for the sake of argument some causal linkage, the Court distinguished Rodriguez from previous cases in which it had struck down laws that effectively discriminated against the poor.8 The plaintiffs had failed to show that the classification effectively deployed by the Texas legislature through its school finance scheme closely resembled the indigent classification that had commanded enhanced review. It was possible, the majority reasoned, that some middle-class pupils resided in low property value districts. Moreover, the previous cases involved an “absolute deprivation of a meaningful opportunity to enjoy [some desired benefit.]” [20] The Court held that even if the relatively quality of their education suffered as a consequence of their districts’ relatively lower budgets, “the Equal Protection Clause does not require absolute equality or precisely equal advantages.”[24] It pointed to its “historic dedication to public education,” and acknowledged the “importance of the [educational] service performed by the State.” [30] It nevertheless held that there was no fundamental right to education explicitly or implicitly contained within the federal constitution.[35] The plaintiffs had argued, in part, that the federal courts ought to recognize education as a fundamental right, and that they should, therefore, review the Texas school funding statute under its most searching type of inquiry, because access to educational opportunity is an indispensable precondition for the effective exercise of the First Amendment liberties and the federally protected right to vote. On this reasoning, the plaintiffs reasoned, the right to education was both implicit in the federal constitution and deserved fundamental status. [35] The Court’s reply to this argument was devastating: the constitution does not grant the individual a right to exercise “the most effective speech or the most informed electoral choice.” [36] Persuasive speech and intelligent voting may be desirable goals in themselves, “but they are not values to be implemented by judicial intrusion into otherwise legitimate state activities.”[36] Under the present system, the Court reasoned, every child in Texas enjoyed the opportunity to “acquire the basic minimal skills necessary for the enjoyment of rights of speech and of full participation in the political process.”[37] Applying the deferential rational basis review to the statute, the Rodriguez Court held that the Texas school finance system furthered a permissible governmental objective and employed means that are rationally related to that purpose. The statute preserved and promoted the “local sharing of responsibility for public education.”[49] The localism of the Texas’s education revenue 23 collection system, the Court wrote, had three specific merits. The system encouraged local voters to keep watch over school expenditures, and permitted experimentation in school policy. Because local school board voters could see their preferences for educational effort translated directly into school spending that would benefit their own children, the system also had the virtue of enhancing parental liberty rights. The Texas system, stated the Court, gave the state’s parents “the freedom to devote more money to the education of one’s children.”[49] Rephrased in political philosophy terms, the Supreme Court decided that parental partiality towards one’s own children is not only permissible but constitutes the basis for an important liberty interest of parents, and that the most advantaged parents of Alamo Heights ought to be free to express their partiality by exchanging material wealth for desirable educational opportunities and by channeling those goods exclusively towards their own children. Beyond its dicta applauding Texas for the provision of a minimal education to all children, the Court is silent on the obligation of the Alamo Heights parents to make countervailing material contributions to support Edgewood’s public schools. The Court implicitly affirms the fact that these transfers undermine the positional value of the public share held by less fortunate children and yet endorses them at the same time. Moreover, the Court is holding that the most advantaged parents should not have to exit the public school system altogether, by sending their children to private schools or purchasing tutoring services, in order to give material expression to their partiality. For the Court, the right to participate in a public school system that is exquisitely designed as a vehicle for the delivery of these transfers and the realization of educational advantage for the most advantaged children is integral to the parental liberty interest. There is substantial archival evidence, discovered by Sracic,[*] that the Rodriguez Court took great care to include this reference to parental partiality and the intra-familial reproduction of material advantage through wealth-biased public school finance schemes. Justice Lewis F. Powell, Jr., the author of the Rodriguez decision, had served several terms on the Richmond School Board and the Virginia Board of Education before he was appointed to the Supreme Court by President Richard Nixon in 1972. [Sracic, 64-5] Powell shared his concerns about the case with his clerks after the three-judge court conducted a trial and handed down a decision in favor of the plaintiffs. If the plaintiffs’ prevailed before the Supreme Court, Powell he asked his clerks, would the victory send the entire country down a slippery slope, from the impositions of mandatory intra-state equality standards to interstate equality rules as well? By extension, would this development introduce centralized control and the federalization of the traditional state and local prerogatives over the public schools? [66, 71 *note fed Dept of Edn not estab until 24 Carter, then seen as the poster child of excess federal power by the right etc] Echoing a belief that was arguably predominant among experts at the time, [*note: Coleman rept] Powell did not endorse the idea that there was a linkage between school finance and the quality of educational opportunity. [67] It was not until the early 1990s that substantial bipartisan support was achieved for the proposition that well-managed school systems serving school children from modest economic backgrounds can be significantly improved through increased investments, especially where the hiring of qualified and dedicated teachers and the organization of small-sized classes in the earliest grades are concerned. [rebell] Powell was also worried that a redistribution of resources would hurt some of the urban districts serving low-income students that had gained access to relatively rich taxable property. Because the school finance methodology used in the case was so crude — its simple per pupil basis made no adjustments for the high salaries needed by the high cost-of-living urban districts to attract even moderately qualified teachers, and it absolutely failed to build in student needs-based weightings for the education of low-income children, pupils with disabilities, or English-languagelearners — Powell could logically conclude that a win for Edgewood’s Latinos could come at the cost of the low-income whites and blacks who were already struggling in their urban schools.[67-8, 71, 97] The historical documents also suggest, however, that Powell brought a Cold War interpretive horizon to the case. In the late 1950s, he traveled to Moscow on a tour organized by the American Bar Association. Upon his return, he wrote a report on the Soviet education system and became a passionate champion of the American education system as a vehicle for the promotion of individual liberty. [66] The specter of communism had already been raised at trial by the State of Texas. Pat Bailey, Assistant Attorney General, questioned at least two witnesses during the deposition phase about the linkage between “socialism” and the egalitarian school finance schemes that they supported.[53] Bailey mischaracterized the plaintiffs’ preferred remedy as absolute equality at trial. The plaintiffs had actually endorsed a Coons et. al.-style system of fiscal neutrality that permitted each district to select its school tax rate without state interference. Bailey claimed that “they [the plaintiffs] want the same amount spent on every child; this is socialized education.”[58] His position was supported by Ralph Langley, the counsel for North East Independent School District. Like many other property-rich districts, North East Independent was anxious that its school budgets would be trimmed if the plaintiffs prevailed; the trial court permitted North East Independent and several other property-rich districts to participate in the case as amicus curiae. Langley injected a further note of urgency. He stated before the trial court that the plaintiffs were seeking absolute equality in education, and that if their principle 25 were taken to its logical extreme, the state would have to eliminate interdistrict inequalities in school spending. Langley further speculated that if the plaintiffs’ (alleged) principle of absolute equality became the federal standard, then the state might be ordered in turn by the federal government to dismantle its private schools.[59] During oral arguments, Chief Justice Warren Burger returned to these themes. He posed a rhetorical question for the plaintiff’s attorney: why should one state have better schools than another? The lawyer conceded that the principle of school equality across the nation might be an attractive one when considered as a “moral argument.” The Chief Justice sprang the trap: the plaintiffs’ “argument would apply with equal force whether you call it ‘moral grounds’ or ‘totalitarian philosophy.’” [J. Burger, oral arg., Rod., quoted in Sracic, 89] Later, in conference, Judge Harry Blackmun said that it would be “safer” if the Supreme Court left the states alone to deal with school finance issues. He further speculated that a Court mandate for equality in educational opportunity “would be another step towards big government.” [J HB, quoted in Sracic, 96] The tradition of granting local governments control over the schools in the United States dates back to the colonial and revolutionary period; Jefferson regarded the operation of a local school as an essential dimension of the ward’s responsibilities, and envisioned merit-based scholarships for the higher education of freeborn boys from low-income families. [*] For Powell, however, local control meant more than an entirely salutary community involvement in curricular matters; local control meant that the defense of liberty, American-style. Freedom, from this viewpoint, requires that the most advantaged taxpaying parents should enjoy the governmental ratification of their desire to settle in income-segregated communities like Alamo Heights. Moreover, the fulfillment of their liberty interests also requires the state government to furnish public school finance mechanisms designed to serve their self-regarding interests. During conference deliberations with the other Justices, Powell wrote a note to himself, “To hold that wealth is suspect … is a communist doctrine but it is not even accepted (except in a limited sense) in socialist countries.” [J LP, quoted in Sracic, 96] The state’s finetuned public school finance scheme must ensure that at least a significant part of the family’s school taxes could be used for the elevation of the positional standing of the children of the most advantaged parents. Given the Cold War framework that Powell brought to the case, this was a strictly either/or question; the defense of liberty rights adequate to the “free world” required the decisive defeat of the Rodriguez plaintiffs’ arguments across the board.[fn /j lp : ltr to clerk PS 112*] The Rodriguez holdings are widely regarded as virtually unassailable, at least for the foreseeable future. [fn*] Under Rodriguez, there is no fundamental right 26 to education; there may not be a federal right to education at all. If there is a right to education, it is not itself important enough to command an elevated level of judicial scrutiny in the federal courts, and it endows the individual with an entitlement to a very low level of adequate resources, such as bare literacy. The federal government, through Congressional spending, may choose to offer conditional education grants to the states, but there is no requirement for it to do so. With Rodriguez, the Court closes the door to the federal courts for children residing in property-poor districts who seek fair equality of educational opportunity in comparison to the more fortunate members of their cohort in their state’s property-wealthy districts. The same is true for plaintiffs who might want to make equal protection claims related to interstate inequalities in educational opportunity. From a federal constitutional perspective, the decision by the state to provide a single dollar in public education spending remains entirely a state prerogative. If the state does opt to provide a public education system, it must do so without committing de jure forms of racial and gender discrimination.(Brown, VMI, CR Act, Title IX) But it is not at all clear that if a state decided to abandon the project of public education altogether, aggrieved children and their parents could turn to the federal constitution for legal support. In the United States, the right to education is explicitly established only in the state constitutions.[ref] The public interest litigation relating to the state educational entitlements has proven to be a complex, expensive, and state-specific process in which morally arbitrary variables, such as the political composition of the state court, play far too great a role. [ref: Reed] Where low-income plaintiffs have enjoyed some success in suing the state for failure to provide an equitable or adequate education, in violation of their state rights, there has been some decrease in intra-state inequalities across districts.[Labb and Loeb, 5, chg pg galleys; Moser and Rubenstein 64, Reed, pg *; Walters, P., In Search etc *] Enforcement has varied according to even more intractable and morally arbitrary factors, such as the political configurations in the executive and legislative branches of state government and fiscal conditions.[Walters, P.] Considered in this light, Anderson’s reforms would represent a significant improvement in the educational opportunities for the least advantaged Andersonians in constitutional terms. Lacking a federal right to a meaningful level of threshold educational opportunity, they would value their enforceable entitlement under Andersonia’s constitution all the more. Allison’s Contact Theory and the Enhanced Resources of the Least Advantaged So far, we have set aside the responses of the individuals who do not belong to the least advantaged social sectors to the Andersonian reforms. Once we introduce their reactions, however, the outcomes cannot be predicted with perfect 27 certainty. On the positive side of the ledger, we have the accounts, ones that are noted by Anderson herself, of salutary outcomes from integrated housing experiments and the evidence suggesting the validity of Allison’s “contact theory.” ** Gautreaux ** housing voucher experiment: positive outcomes; ** Allison contact theory ** “under conditions of equality” condition; relying upon psych and soc research fn ** hostile groups can become more cooperative if brought into contact under conditions of equality >> Anderson assumes that there would be more communication and understanding between most advan and least advan ** least advantaged benefit in immediate sense from enhanced educational opportunities; segregation gives them potential access to enlarged social networks, improvement in socio-cultural capital, etc. Berkeley High School: The Retention of Race-Based Tracking in a Progressive School District ** Noguera and Wing ** stubbornness of segregation even in Berkeley, CA Philosophers or Gekkos*? The Long-term Effects of Permitting AboveThreshold Local Tax Efforts [*ref. to film: Wall Street, Gordon Gekko, played by Michael Douglas] Across Andersonia, the formation of the Philosophia districts would have significant effects. Some of the Philosophia voters would be genuinely motivated by the prospect of enhanced individual flourishing for the local schoolchildren; they sincerely look forward to the possibility that their district will produce more philosophers, ballet dancers, sculptors, medieval historians, and chess players as a result. Anderson herself would not see the emergence of a few Philosophia-dominant school boards within the state of Andersonia as a moral problem. Assuming a reasonable level of school management competence, it is likely that the pupils graduating from the especially well-financed public schools in the Philosophia districts will have access to an abovethreshold level of educational opportunity. Anderson would point out that this outcome would not be discriminatory, and that the least advantaged would benefit in the end from the resulting enhancement of the goods and services that they receive. 28 [ethics, pg*] The statewide principle of fair equality of opportunity, requiring the provision to pupils who are coming from disadvantaged families of compensatory supports, such as counseling, tutoring, after-school programs, school nursing, eye and hearing tests and follow-up treatment, free meals, casework, and, in severe cases of need, public housing and poverty assistance benefits, and so on, [*] would apply in the Philosophia districts as well. Pupils from all walks of life would receive a decent chance to thrive and achieve in the Philosophia district’s above-threshold schools. State-wide, there should be a tremendous reduction in the previous relationship between school achievement and factors such as race and parental income. Andersonia should outpace the other states where the achievement of a more demographically balanced representation of African-Americans and students from low-income families among the state’s public school high flyers is concerned. Andersonia’s best students would achieve their top results largely because of their above average levels of talent and effort, rather than morally arbitrary characteristics. During the first few market cycles, we would probably see a significant trend towards similarly balanced representations within the top-tier student groups within the Philosophia districts as well. Moreover, Anderson would expect that all of the top performing students graduating from the state’s high schools would be endowed with greater multicultural and cross-class sensitivity, thanks to the integrated nature of their classes, schools, and neighborhoods. Crucially, she further assumes that the zoning and school policies would inculcate the formation of an elite youth cohort that is more disposed to engage in socially useful careers than their counterparts in other states.[fn ethics 9] She believes that the imposition of social justice-oriented service requirements upon the applicants for admission to higher education institutions would complement integrative policies. Together, these reforms are supposed to encourage the formation of a highly cooperative and integrated elite whose members seek fulfillment through careers oriented toward the delivery of socially useful services to the least advantaged in a multiculturally sensitive manner. For example, she assumes that the best and brightest graduates from her reformed higher education institutions would be much more likely to aspire to careers as general practitioner doctors in public clinics rather than as hedge fund managers. [fn ethics] She concludes that it is just for the state to support these high flyers’ education since the least advantaged would ultimately benefit from their enjoyment of advanced educational opportunities. We should also note that the members of the Philosophia movement might be fairly diverse, at least at the time of the state’s founding. School finance data, such as the evidence related to the Rodriguez case, suggest that many of the voters residing in lowincome and majority Latino/African American school districts in the United States strongly value education. Like the residents of Edgewood, they are willing to make above-average school taxation efforts.[rod, pg *] 29 Because they are subjects in a “real world” case, however, we should expect the residents of the state of Andersonia to exhibit the rationality that is already familiar to us. Like their counterparts in other states, each individual in Andersonia normally prefers more primary social goods, like income and wealth, rather than less. The typical Andersonian has a coherent set of preferences between the options that are open to her. She ranks these options according to her anticipated returns from each one. More generally, she adopts the rational plan of life with reference to two major factors. First, she favors the plans that are most likely to render the greatest possible enhancement of her well-being return. Second, she gives high points to the ones that seem to be feasible and are most likely to be successfully executed. [Rawls, TJ, 123-4] In “real world” conditions, an individual endowed with a greater share of resources will take the good of herself and her family into account first and foremost. If she possesses a superior share of resources in comparison to her counterpart in a market exchange, for example, she will seek to establish a superior bargaining position over others.[JAF, 7] Based on her knowledge and beliefs, her desires and interests, the array of options available to her, and her anticipation of returns from each one, she makes decisions in order to maximize gains and minimize losses. [JAF 81] On an aggregate level, when economic and social inequalities become significant in a “real world” society, they will tend to give rise to political inequality in turn. [JAF, 131] The bases of political power are information, educated skills and intellectual capacities, property, and the ability to engage in strategic cooperation necessary for the formation of relatively stable interest groups. The individuals who accumulate superior shares in these bases of power are overwhelmingly disposed towards the formation of elite factions. These factions promote their members’ interests by gaining “control over the machinery of State, [and] enact[ing] a system of law and property that ensures their dominant position in the economy as a whole.” [Rawls, JAF, 131] To satisfy Anderson’s feasibility requirement, I will assume that the majority of the individuals belonging to the most advantaged socio-economic group sincerely endorse their state’s integrative approach to neighborhood zoning and schools. However, since they are rational actors, in the sense specified above, they seek the accumulation of goods over several market cycles. Under more ideal circumstances, they would be both rational and reasonable; they would be “ready to propose, or to acknowledge when proposed by others, the principles needed to specify what can be seen by all as fair terms of cooperation.”(Rawls, JAF, 6-7) They would accept that they would be bound by these fair terms, even when it meant that they would have to forgo the pursuit of their own gains, as long as their counterparts honored them as well. (ibid, 7) It is rational, however, to refuse to engage in these reasonable practices when the individual finds herself placed in a society structured by unjust institutions that are so basic that they cannot be avoided. A society with insufficiently regulated market institutions — in this case, a society that lacks upper salary caps, a robust capital gains 30 tax, and a 100 percent estate tax — would have an unjust basic structure. In this context, it is rational for the individuals endowed with above-average shares in the bases of power to take advantage of their situation.(ibid.) The most advantaged in Andersonia would appreciate the fact that their state’s intervention in the market is limited to the guarantee of an adequate level of basic goods necessary for the realization of core capabilities, and that the well-educated, hard-working and talented individuals who performed the work most valued in the labor market would be offered the greatest salaries. There would be no limits to salary inequality, as long as a living wage was established as the state minimum pay rate. Andersonia would lack a robust capital gains tax and it would not have a 100% estate tax. These checks on inequality would not be unconstitutional; theoretically, a majority of voters could press successfully for their adoption through the normal political process. It would not, however, be rational for the most advantaged to support these market interventions; almost all of them would exploit their superior bases of power to block any reforms of this nature. As each young adult enters the labor market, her position with respect to educational achievement — relative to the other members of her cohort — will determine her entry salary level and life-long earning prospects. Assuming an open social system in which careers are open to talents, the salary rewards will be greatest for those holding the credentials commanding the highest value in the labor market. Still deeply motivated by a selfish desire to accumulate income and wealth over each market cycle, the ambitious parents of talented children would undoubtedly strive to position their children in the most favorable manner in order to promote the cross-generational formation of family wealth. Andersonian policy will not, in all likelihood, be oriented towards the decrease in inequality or even the preservation of the existing levels of inequality. Morally arbitrary contingencies will change the distribution of assets from that established at the state’s founding. [Rawls TJ 62-3, on the system of natural liberty] The pupils fortunate enough to be born into a family residing in a Philosophia district will have much better life chances than the members of their cohort in other districts who have similar endowments of natural talent and come from comparable family backgrounds, where income, wealth, and parental education are concerned. They will be more likely to finish high school, gain admission to college, command higher salaries, and accumulate capital that can be passed along to their children, thanks to their enrollment in a Philosophia district school system. If it suited their tactical needs, the Philosophia parents might pay lip service to ideals such as individual flourishing and public service-oriented careers. For the most part, they would do so insincerely, since, in a non-ideal society like Andersonia, it is rational to mimic reasonableness while actually prioritizing acquisitive rationality. [Rawls, JAF, 7] Perhaps a few Philosophia parents would deviate from market values and encourage their children to grow up to become poets, knowing that they can 31 always fall back on Andersonia’s guaranteed minimum income. It is inevitable, as well, that a certain proportion of children in virtually every district will rebel against their parents and pursue lifestyles through which they will express values bearing very little relationship to their parents’ beliefs. In most of the Philosophia families, however, parents will encourage their children to take full advantage of the above-threshold educational opportunities available to them and to prepare themselves for the competitive pursuit of careers in which income and wealth accumulation will be given priority over public service for its own sake. Some parents will do so out of a frankly expressed ambition for to get ahead. Others will be more ambivalent, but will grasp that their children will be placed by the insufficiently regulated market institutions in a prisoner’s dilemma. Since they cannot rely upon others to engage in social cooperation on fair terms, they will have to urge their children to compete to win in order to hedge against their getting squeezed out in college admissions, hiring decisions, promotions, and all the other major competitions related to material gains. Andersonia's mandatory integration of neighborhoods and schools would ensure that there would be a significant degree of fair equality of opportunity in at least the first market cycle in the Philosophia districts. If we divided all the schoolchildren in the state according to different levels of native talent, on a scale of 1 to 10, with 10 being highest, integration would reduce the differences in life chances among the children belonging to each native-talent rank, regardless of race, parental income, and parental education.10 Outside Andersonia, bright and eager black children from rank 8 who come from low income families would have much more modest chances of success in school and in the labor market as an adult than her white counterparts in rank 8 from high income families.[Rawls, TJ, 63, etc.] Within Andersonia, mandatory integration would lift up the conditions of the worst off. In each integrated neighborhood, the political power of parents from all races and walks of life would be pooled together. White middle-class and wealthy parents would not tolerate failing schools and would press for the delivery of threshold-level educational opportunity, and their less fortunate neighbors would benefit since they would be enrolling their children in the same schools. Indeed, because classes, extra-curricular activities, schools, and districts would have roughly the same degree of integration, there would be an enhancement in the equal distribution of parental political power and local tax bases across the states. The least advantaged residing in districts across the state would also enjoy the peer teaching/learning effects from mixing with more advantaged pupils in their classes and schools as well. Given the fact that the vast majority of the parents in Andersonia are pro-integration, the most advantaged parents would willingly share their inside information on college preparation and career choices with their less advantaged neighbors. In the first instance, then, the least advantaged residing in every single district benefit absolutely from the introduction of threshold-level educational opportunity, 32 especially insofar as Anderson has set her threshold at such a rich level. Because integration, in the first moment, delivers some degree of equalization, the least advantaged also benefit in a relative sense. Inequality was greater before the reforms; the lifting of the least advantaged to the high threshold level immediately diminishes the gap between the best- and worst-off. The positional value of their education is enhanced for the moment, as the least advantaged eagerly seize upon their enhanced share and become more competitive in the college and job markets. The progress towards the equal distribution of educational resources achieved by Andersonia in its founding moment may not be sustained, however, over subsequent market cycles. Once we control for native-talent ranking, we would probably find that in the state-wide markets for college places and job market positions, the Philosophia graduates would outperform their counterparts. As a result, the relative value of a threshold entitlement would decline. The long term implications would be indeterminate. We might see, for example, the emergence of a formidable social movement for radical egalitarian reforms. Perhaps the least advantaged in the threshold and Philosophia districts will find inspiration for further social change in their state’s integrationist discourse. Moreover, Anderson clearly endorses the integration of democratic and pluralist ideals into the school curriculum. Instead of a narrow vocational orientation, her reformed schools would integrate teaching designed to promote the “virtues, knowledge, and skills necessary for political participation.” [Gutmann, dem edn, 287.] Going well beyond a “3Rs” approach, and rejecting rote learning designed to improve standardized test scores, Andersonian schools would have age-appropriate and effective lessons on racial nondiscrimination, multicultural history, problem-solving and communication in complex social settings, respect for others, responsible deliberation on controversial subjects, and liberal democratic constitutional principles — including free speech, religious toleration and freedom of conscience, due process, and equal protection. [ibid., 287- 309] Through their improved educations, the least advantaged would, in all likelihood, become more articulate, more knowledgeable about market competition, and more politically savvy. They could also become more capable at grasping their relative disadvantage, recognizing their collective interests in solidarity, and organizing community members to engage in mass protest. If Andersonia could preserve its reformed public school system long enough — against the inevitable forces of resistance and backlash — to bring an entire rising generation of the least advantaged through the greatly enhanced K-12 schools, and to train a whole new cohort of diverse elite professionals in scholarship-supported higher education institutions, and if a substantial proportion of these upwardly mobile individuals could be persuaded to adopt and maintain commitments to integrationist political values, then Andersonia might give rise to a progressive vanguard and a 33 significant radical egalitarian social movement.11 That radical democratic vanguard might be able to recruit a significant number of the more advantaged blacks and at least a handful of middle-class and wealthy whites as well. [linked fate and black voting across class divisions; wealthy CT voters voting against pocketbook interests] Moreover, the whole field of expectations among the least advantaged, especially lowand moderate-income blacks, would be transformed by the successful introduction of the Andersonian reforms. It is highly likely that they will exhibit considerably more optimism regarding their future prospects for upward mobility and political efficacy in this context. [McAdam, Pol Process, 108-110] The original demands for eliminating racial inequities came from African-American thinkers, leaders, and ordinary community members; the founding of Andersonia and the formation of a cross-class and cross-racial consensus firmly endorsing integration would probably be regarded by many blacks as a tremendously inspiring and redemptive achievement. Measured against previous anti-racist reforms, such as the desegregation of public schools in the South in the latter half of the twentieth century, the strong commitment of the state’s central institutions to integration would be remarkable. Instead empty promises, delay, and vicious backlash, Andersonia would offer African-Americans and their white liberal allies a historic model of responsiveness and commitment. Political science research has demonstrated the enormous potential of a new social entitlement to encourage civic-minded volunteerism and voting participation among the beneficiaries. [Mettler, GI Bill] Andersonia might see the rise of a whole new generation of thoughtful voters, critical recipients of media messages, eloquent spokespersons, and public interest-oriented lawyers, politicians, and judges eager to enhance democratic empowerment and to diminish socio-economic inequalities across the board. Alternatively, Andersonians might also witness the weakening of solidarity and democratic mobilization among the least advantaged. To begin with, traditional communities would be disrupted by the widespread experience of resettlement under the exigencies of integration. To the extent that the mass mobilization of the least advantaged depends upon spatial concentration, the very re-location processes required under integration could weaken previous kinship, church, and neighborhood ties. There is always the chance for new friendships and social networks to emerge in the integrated neighborhoods, especially insofar as we assume that good faith efforts are the norm in Andersonia, but the building up of the kind of trust that is indispensable to political organizing takes a great deal of time. [Lo in Morris, Aldon D. and Mueller, Frontiers, 237-812] The least advantaged whites would lose, as a result of Andersonian integration, much of the symbolic returns that they reaped under white supremacy and de facto segregation, regardless of their own individual beliefs. [roediger] Their response to the state’s founding would be a particularly acute concern for Andersonia’s political leaders. 34 Moreover, the rise of meritocratic selection effects [see Arneson] could introduce tensions among the least advantaged. The rank 9 and 10 students from the least advantaged families could seize upon their supplemental educational inputs, succeed in winning places in prestigious higher education programs, and, heavily seduced by the promise of substantial material gains, devote themselves to lucrative careers. This pattern would be particularly noticeable among the cadre of high talent but least advantaged students residing in the Philosophia districts. As they take up their elite positions after racking up outstanding scholarly achievements, it is entirely possible that they will rationalize their superior salaries and accumulations of wealth as deserved rewards, and that they will choose not to align themselves politically with radical egalitarian social movements. Instead of more solidarity among the least advantaged in favor of egalitarianism, we could end up with the accelerating fragmentation of this social group in which the narcissism of small differences becomes the rule.[failure of blacks’ cross-class solidarity in voting data; on fragmentation of working class between skilled and unskilled, see Marx, Capital; on symbolic capital and social fragmentation: Bourdieu] As for the most advantaged residing in the Philosophia districts, they would be disproportionately represented within the freshmen classes in higher education institutions and the high salary and high prestige careers. The demand for residential rentals and real estate in the Philosophia districts would rapidly become so intense that upward pressure would be placed on the cost-of-living. Perhaps most of the least advantaged residing within the Philosophia districts would already be settled in publicly subsidized housing, but the ones trying to make ends meet in unregulated apartments would be driven out by skyrocketing rents. The least advantaged families from other districts would find it extremely difficult to find affordable housing in any Philosophia district. Even with the progress towards racial integration within Andersonia’s elite, there would definitely be more strains upon the solidarity between class fractions. The prosperous Andersonians would readily find ways to transfer their extraordinary wealth to their children in turn, thereby placing them in the most advantageous positions. The members of the elite already holding residential property in a Philosophia district would seek to enrich their holdings through renovations and the appropriation of contiguous properties. The most advantaged residing outside Philosophia would be first in line when one of the super-hot Philosophia properties goes on the market, and they would use their deep pockets to defeat the other buyers. Over several market cycles, it is likely that native-talent rank would become a less important factor in Andersonia’s higher education and career markets. Rank 6 Philosophia graduates could begin to outperform the students residing in threshold districts belonging to ranks 8 and 9, for example. Resentment and cynicism would become widespread. Students of color from moderate income families residing outside Philosophia may be particularly disillusioned and alienated. Their parents had 35 probably built up high expectations at the time of the state’s founding, given the fact that they were about to enjoy substantial improvements in their local neighborhoods and schools. They had eagerly looked forward to a time in which their children would live in a safe neighborhood and would graduate with a meaningful high school diploma. Surely their young graduates would prosper as a result. The promises made at the founding, however, would go unfulfilled over the long term. The relative value of the threshold district high school diploma increasingly diminishes over time, and these graduates lose out in competition after competition. The young adults stuck in this position would feel cheated: they had played by the rules and put in the required effort, but now their diploma is grossly insufficient. Places in higher education institutions are extremely difficult for them to obtain, and they cannot find anything better than a minimum wage job. Perhaps these do receive better services at the local health clinic than they did before, and perhaps they do benefit indirectly from enhanced output in Andersonia’s economy. Nevertheless, as the division of labor and socio-economic inequality are intensified, alienation becomes an increasing concern. [see Rawls, TJ, 92] Some of the least advantaged from threshold districts will voluntarily “drop out” of mainstream society; falling back on the entitlement a minimum standard of living, they will deliberately pursue life plans as creative writers, artists, and musicians that emphasize flourishing for its own sake, as opposed to upward mobility. Nevertheless, many will feel cheated out of a decent chance to succeed and to make their own mark in the competitive races that the dominant Andersonian culture values the most. It is entirely possible that for many of Andersonia’s most talented and hardworking high school students, their mandatory participation in integrated schools and neighborhoods, and the pre-college public service programs will foster a lifelong prioritization of the needs of the least advantaged. Others, however, will cynically reframe the Andersonian ideals.13 Rubbing shoulders with least advantaged and less talented pupils in school and public service placements will strike them as little more than two more mandatory credential-gathering exercises. They will bring an acutely competitive attitude to their public service placement, seeking out the positions most valued by college admissions officers and supervisors known for their eloquent recommendation letters. Parental knowledge and ambition will lead to the formation of informal markets, as the keenest pass along their insider’s information and hoard the best public service experiences for kin and close friends. The insider parents’ cohort would be somewhat diverse, thanks to Andersonia’s integrated character, but parental education will trump all other factors where success in the competitive race to secure the best college admissions dossier is concerned. In a few unusual cases, a parent will have extraordinary capital holdings but a low level of education; she will readily make up for her deficit by hiring a college admissions consultant to tutor herself and her teenager in college preparation and admission dossier building techniques. It is possible 36 that over time, the spirit of fairness and community solidarity that had animated the Andersonia’s founding generation will be hollowed out from within, as integrationist and sufficientarian ideals are corrupted and market rationality predominates. The First Defectors: Private Tutoring, Private Schools, and More Ratcheting Up ** Brighouse and Swift : the decline in value of an adequacy level of educational opportunity as the most advantaged opt out of the public-only model, by purchasing private tutoring or paying private school tuitions ** Anderson: explicitly permits these supplements ; least advan benefit, against leveling down, liberty interest (choice) ** the liberty argument in Rodriguez : but is there a parental liberty interest in the freedom to purchase educational advantage for one’s children, including Brighouse and Swift, for their part, have argued convincingly that the parental liberty interest in partiality towards one’s own children only extends as far as the expression of love and the provision of personal caregiving. The accident of being born into a wealthy family is, of course, a matter of pure chance and fairness prohibits morally arbitrary advantage. The securing of educational opportunities, without regard to merit or effort, but simply by virtue of one’s family ties, cannot be defended. In light of the harm to others, namely the deflation of positional educational value for the least advantaged children, Brighouse and Swift conclude that material transfers and purchases of educational advantage should be distinguished from the emotional and caregiving bond that ideally develops between parent and child.[*] The right of an adult to parent — to raise a child regardless of one’s marital status and income bracket, and to participate in a bond that is ideally centered upon a profoundly emotional experience and extensive provision of caregiving — constitutes a very substantial liberty interest. Governmental interference in this dimension of parenting should be kept to an absolute minimum; intervention should only occur, for example, where there is proven abuse and neglect. [*] Material intergenerational transfers and the purchase of educational advantage for one’s personal favorites, by contrast, are properly understood as falling outside the category of parental liberty. They belong, instead, under the rubric of a relatively minor liberty, namely “freedom of contract.” As such, justice requires their close regulation and strict limitation, along the same lines as the imposition, in a society well-ordered by justice as fairness, of progressive income taxation schemes, the minimum wage requirements, maximum pay ceilings, rigorous trade union standards, one hundred percent estate taxes, the provision of a social minimum and generous social security entitlements, regulations designed to ensure that the finance sector prioritizes the needs of the least advantaged, and so on. 37 --------------------- The Other Defectors: Moving Out of State The Gautreaux case that Anderson relies upon raises an interesting question about the problems that arise when integrative policies are scaled up, from a single neighborhood located within a national housing market, to a state-wide integrative program. If some middle-class homeowners in one of the Chicago neighborhoods deeply resented the arrival of a low-income voucher-holder from the public housing project, they could always sell their homes and move into an alternative neighborhood with zoning bylaws designed to establish and maintain an environment catering exclusively to the well-off. It might be somewhat burdensome for them, but as long as the receiving neighborhood is not too far away, the emigrants will not be greatly troubled by the move. If we take integrative policies to a statewide scale, by contrast, we are more likely to find much deeper attachments to the region on the part of the well-off, and much more resentment about the burdens that they would have to assume in order to exit the desegregated state. A few members of the white wealthy elite within Andersonia will resent the integration policies a great deal and will seek to exit. A small number will reside in Andersonia’s areas that lie close to the state’s border. Perhaps they will regard the contiguous state’s policies as more amenable to their ambitions and values; they should be able to find new homes in nearby gated communities located only a few miles away, just across the state border. For other well-off Andersonians, however, exit from the state will mean tremendous relocation costs, in social, emotional, and material terms. Meanwhile, Andersonia will suffer from the out-of-state emigration; they will be paying taxes into the coffers of a different state, contributing their social and cultural capital to non-Andersonian communities, and investing in local business ventures elsewhere. Within Andersonia itself, a disgruntled elite minority could do a great deal of damage. Wealthy whites who bitterly resented the loss of their traditional privilege could turn to the federal courts for relief. In Masters of the Universe v. Andersonia, [*ref novel TW] a group of wealthy white parents file suit against their state in federal court, on the grounds that the Andersonian policies violate, among other things, their equal protection rights by engaging in race-conscious pupil assignment policies. The recent decision, Parents Involved, [Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School District No. 1 (551 U.S. 701 (2007)] provides us with some indications as to the outcome in Masters of the Universe. The Parents Involved Court struck down two much less ambitious 38 race conscious and integrative pupil placement scheme — single district programs that left residential segregation untouched — as a violation of the Fourteenth Amendment. The integrative schemes had been implemented on a voluntary basis by democratically elected school boards in Seattle and Louisville, and the school boards amply demonstrated at trial that they did so out of sincere interests in promoting desegregation. The Supreme Court nevertheless refused to give “local control” its due. [fn In a sense, the Court was obliged to show its hand much more forcefully in PICS than in Rodriguez. A decision in favor of Texas could be defended on the basis of the separation of powers doctrine. Harking back to its embrace of judicial minimalism in economic affairs, one that originated during the New Deal era, [Ackerman] the Rodriguez Court could claim that its rejection of the plaintiffs’ arguments stemmed largely from its constitutional obligation to defer to the legislature in matters pertaining to economic regulation. Indeed, the Rodriguez decision consistently champions federalism and counsels the plaintiffs to seek a remedy through their participation in the political system. [see, eg decision, pg *] Where Rodriguez merely permits a state legislature to retain its existing school finance law, PICS brushes aside the decisions of two democratically elected bodies, the school boards, and strikes down their legislation.] As the Attorney General of Andersonia prepares to defend her state’s brave reforms, she would certainly not be able to turn to Rodriguez for constitutional fortification. Because the Andersonian reforms do not enjoy nation-wide support —given the tremendous and intractable interstate variations in educational opportunity at present, it is reasonable to assume that a national consensus in favor of Andersonia would be lacking — it is highly likely that there would be some legislative response at the federal level. With or without the President’s blessing, anti-Andersonians in Congress could rally enough votes to adopt federal measures to block the reforms. It could tinker with ESEA Title I funding and other federal education spending to deprive Andersonia of federal grants, for example. [The model here is DOMA in response to s-s marriage initiatives at the state level.] Andersonia’s most serious political opponent would be the right-wing social movements based in the other states. Hopefully, Ku Klux Klan-style white supremacists would not suddenly enjoy a surge in credibility as a backlash emerges in the other states. It is entirely likely, however, that skilled leadership on the part of libertarians, neoliberals, and moral conservatives outside Andersonia would lead to the enormous expansion in their groups and organizations and the overnight cultivation of tremendous popular passions against Andersonia through well-staged rallies, town-hall meetings, religious gatherings and other media events. In these conditions, popular fears would be whipped up against big government, the rigorous regulation of the housing market, and the loss of parental liberty. In fact, there are ample historical cases in which similar calls for “the preservation of traditional ways of life,” “local control” 39 and “fiscal responsibility”, as well as analogous denunciations of “Robin Hood”-style redistributions, became overwhelmingly popular in response to equitable reforms. We could look, for example, at the aftermath of the Brown decision in the Southern states, [Rosenberg, What Brown Should Have Said,] or at California’s adoption of Proposition 13, the state constitutional amendment limiting property taxes, in the wake of the Serrano litigation.[ picus, walters In Search, et. al,] [*again, the state responses to ss marriage demonstrate the ways in which federalism facilitates the anticipation of progressive reforms by right-wing movements even in the jurisdictions that are contiguous to, but legally distinct from, the ones in which the demonized reforms are actually achieved.] The backlash in the other states could block Andersonian reforms there, or, even worse, reduce voters’ support for the public school system even further. The least advantaged resident in those other states could end up worse off as a result. Conclusion Value of Anderson’s attention to local government autonomy and the ways in which the most advantaged whites have successfully exploited jurisdictional differences to hoard public education resources and facilitate race- and class-based segregation. Remains true even if outcomes are indeterminate. Holding the conditions of the most advantaged constant, the least advantaged in her “real world” setting, Andersonia do experience a significant enhancement, materially and constitutionally, with respect to educational opportunity. Once we introduce the competitive responses of the most advantaged, the situation becomes quite complex. The enhancement of educational opportunity certainly provides the least advantaged with the means to enjoy enhanced individual flourishing, regardless. But, as Brighouse and Swift would point out, the most advantaged would utilize their competitive market rationality to assess the threat posed by the adequacy and integrationist reforms. They would seek to monopolize residential placements within the districts that are permitted above-threshold local contributions to public school budgets, such that there would be tremendous pressure on Andersonia as it struggles to maintain its commitment to residential integration. There is a chance that the least advantaged will turn their enhanced educations into political tools as they engage in mass mobilization in favor of egalitarian reforms. If they manage to recruit enough middle-class blacks, and at least a handful of middle-class and wealthy whites, they might prevail in the political process and successfully introduce egalitarian distributive policies. However, we might see tremendous alienation among the least advantaged as the positional value of a threshold public high school diploma 40 plummets, and the talented students who enjoy tremendous upward mobility thanks to Andersonia’s public education investments may not maintain a profoundly unselfish commitment to cross-class and multiracial solidarity. The ideological force of market rationality may ultimately lead to the hollowing out of Andersonia’s founding principles, such that ambitious parents and students turn Anderson’s integrative and public service experiences into credential gathering exercises to be negotiated with the cynicism of the typical scheming gamer. Defection: two types: wealthy parents who purchase private educational goods: tutoring, places in private schools; and those who exit state altogether. Long-term implications. Cosmopolitan pol phil – Rawls, Laws; Pogge; Held; Sen; Nussbaum; Shue; Singer; Young; R. Miller; etc. – question the given-ness of our obligations to aid only our fellow countrymen and women; demand answers to difficult questions about our duties towards the needy residing in foreign countries. Why should nation-state borders be accepted as meaningful limits to our moral duty to give assistance to those in need ? Taking the nation-state bounded character of our obligations is to accept moral arbitrariness, given the strategic, geo-political nature of their formation. Attention to North-South problematic should not, however, cause those of us holding citizenship status in developed countries to neglect our moral duties to the least advantaged residing within our countries’ territories. Here, too, justice requires the questioning of the given-ness of political boundaries and the ways in which federal systems can facilitate hoarding, exclusion, and exploitation on the part of the most advantaged. Cf. Patrick Le Gales, governance, regional and local, under conditions of globalization and inequality. Virtues of Anderson’s proposals; encourage us to reflect further [see Walzer on associational justice] on the complex interface between spatial governance, and educational equity. 41 Appendix I. States Plotted According to NAEP and State Proficiency Scores, 2005. Source: Liu 2006. Notes. “NAEP” is the National Assessment of Educational Progress, an independent, non-governmental, and widely respected national testing agency. States fall into the upper left quadrant, like Mississippi, have low state standards and low performing student bodies. About seventy-seven percent of their fourth grade math pupils are ranked as “proficient” in the state test, but only eighteen percent achieve proficiency or better on the NAEP. States in the upper right quadrant, like Kansas, also have low standards, but a greater percentage of their students are achieving proficiency or better on the NAEP. 42 States in the lower left quadrant, like New Mexico, have high standards and low performing student bodies, while states in the lower right quadrant, like Wyoming and Massachusetts, have high standards and high proficiency rates. Only two states, Wyoming and Massachusetts, use state proficiency standards that are actually stricter than that for NAEP. =========================== 43 Appendix II. Weighted Student Formula, CFE III. In one state school funding case, Campaign for Fiscal Equity, the state’s highest court found in 2003 * that the state had violated the adequacy education rights of one class of students, namely the children attending public schools in New York City. In its decision, it gave the state legislature * months to adopt a new school funding scheme that would bring up the NYC schools to an adequacy level, defined by the court as the level of educational opportunity necessary for high school graduates such that they could make thoughtful decisions in casting their votes and participate productively on juries. [dir quote and cite *] Although the Court recognized that the state legislature’s $9.4 billion capital improvement program would cure the constitutional deficiencies in the NYC schools’ physical plant, it further determined that it failed to meet their deadline where the implementation of a plan to rectify the NYC schools’ core operating expenses. Ultimately, the Court imposed a remedy in which the state would have to guarantee the expenditure of $1.93 billion from state and local sources combined, in addition to the existing spending levels, representing a 30 percent increase. To integrate student needs-oriented adjustments into a simple per pupil formula, the Court accepted the following model. 44 Notes. 1 We can get a glimpse of the inequitable distribution of educational opportunity in American public schools by looking at differences in teacher salary expenditures. In a ground-breaking 2011 study conducted by the US Department of Education, the evidence suggested remarkably high and widespread levels of inequity. (U.S. Department of Education, Comparability of State and Local Expenditures Among Schools Within Districts, Washington, D. C., November, 2011.) Because the study looked solely at intra-district differences, the impact of cost-of-living on teacher salaries was not a factor. However, the study did control for grade level. It defined “higher-poverty schools” as those with a poverty rate (based on student eligibility for free or subsidized lunches) above the district average while “lower-poverty schools” had a rate that fell below the district average. It focused exclusively on state and local spending on teachers’ salaries, since federal contributions are heavily redistributive, by the very design of the 1965 ESEA. Looking at the budgets of more than six thousand districts, the study found that more than one third of the higher-poverty schools in the sample had more meager per pupil teacher salary expenditures than the lower-poverty schools in their own districts. (Ibid., X-xii) In one quarter of the higherpoverty schools, the personnel expenditures were more than ten percent below the average for the lower-poverty schools.(Ibid., 23) When the study focuses exclusively upon teachers’ salaries, the inequitable differences between the budgets of the higher-poverty and lower-poverty schools become even more pronounced by several percentage points. (Ibid., passim.) 2 Elizabeth Anderson, The Imperative of Integration. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2010. In Imperative, Anderson also makes it clear that the recruitment of a “critical mass” of traditionally under-represented minorities would be guaranteed by her affirmative action initiative as well. See also Grutter on critical mass. 3 4 In a few extremely large metropolitan areas, like New York City, there are no special school taxes per se; the city’s education department must compete with the other local agencies for its piece of the general local government tax revenues. The overwhelming majority of school districts, however, raise single-purpose school taxes by imposing a fee upon local property owners. In one case, CFE III, the Court used the co-efficients of 1.2 for pupils with limited English proficiency. A pupil coming from a disadvantaged economic background was assigned a co-efficient of 1.35. The co-efficient for pupils with disabilities participating in special education programs was 2.1. However, no provision was made for the concentration of low-income pupils within a single school. The assignment of these co-efficients was enormously controversial; the plaintiffs argued that the co-efficients, and other accounting decisions, led to the Court’s underestimation of the remedial spending by a factor of 2.6. See Appendix II. 5 6 [fn Edgewood had a predominantly Mexican-American population; about 90 percent of the students in Edgewood schools were Mexican-American, while another 6 percent were African-American. [*] However, the plaintiffs’ legal 45 team decided to frame their equal protection complaint on the basis of wealth, rather than ethnicity. Their complaint targeted the statewide school funding scheme, and several districts contained substantial numbers of low-income whites and middle-income Latinos. Further, the Mexican-American residents had moved into the Edgewood district in substantial numbers long after its boundaries were drawn; the original architects of the district boundaries were clearly not motivated by discriminatory intentions. The Court had already signaled the importance of the distinction between de jure and de facto segregation in 1971 in Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenberg Board of Education (402 U.S. 1 (1971)). Under Berger’s leadership, and with Nixon’s Court appointments, the Court was turning away from the aggressive desegregation standards that the Warren Court had established in its 1968 decision, Green v. County School Board of New Kent County (391 U.S. 430 (1968)). Later in its 1973 term, the Court handed down Keyes v. School District No. 1 (413 U.S. 189 (1973)), in which it decided that even if a school board had engaged in intentional segregation in one part of its district, it might be able to escape a district-wide remedy if it could show that it had not engaged in intentional discrimination outside that one area. In Milliken v. Bradley (418 U.S. 717 (1974)), decided in 1974, the Court vacated a multi-district remedy on the grounds that the plaintiffs had only demonstrated that Detroit’s inner city school district had engaged in a de jure form of racial segregation. It prohibited the federal district court from imposing supervision and control over the majority white suburban school boards because the plaintiffs had failed to show that they had intentionally engaged in equal protection violations as well. It was not clear, however, that the Court was also ready to abandon the gains that the Warren Court had made with respect to the suspect character of wealth-based classifications. See, for example, Shapiro v. Thompson (394 U.S. 618 (1969) (striking down residency requirements in state AFDC law), and Frank Michelman, "The Supreme Court, 1968 Term: On Protecting the Poor Through the Fourteenth Amendment," Harvard Law Review, 83: 1 (1969-70): 7-282. The plaintiffs’ lawyers were particularly inspired by a federal appellate court decision, Hobson v. Hansen (269 F. Supp. 401 (D.D.C. 1967), aff'd sub. nom. Smuck v. Hobson, 408 F. 2d 175 (D.C. Cir. 1969), that had struck down racially and economically discriminatory forms of intra-district segregation, biased intra-school spending patterns, and educational tracking in the capitol’s public school system. See Paul A. Sracic, San Antonio V. Rodriguez and the Pursuit of Equal Education, Lawrence: University of Kansas, 2006, especially 225.] 7 Alamo Heights had a predominantly white Anglo school population; once again, the plaintiffs decided not to emphasize an ethnicity-oriented equal protection complaint. See, for example, Douglas v. California (372 U.S. 353 (1963)) (deciding that a state must provide counsel to an indigent defendant facing criminal charges on first appeal.) 8 9 Anderson shares with Rawls the insight that inequalities of natural endowment are undeserved; the naturally talented have a right to own their intellectual assets, but they have a moral obligation towards the least advantaged. Anderson frames that obligation in terms of the guarantee of threshold entitlements and integrated neighborhoods and schools. For his part, Rawls does so in terms of the fair equality of opportunity and difference principles. [see, e.g. Rawls, TJ, 86-93.] Moreover, it is not clear that Anderson would endorse a fully-fledged version of the Rawlsian principle of fair value of equal political liberties. [tj 197-200; j af 148-50] 10 [effort: not a straightforward variable that predicts meritocratic outcomes, given the fact that excellent teachers in very well organized schools can coax stronger efforts out of many of the pupils who appear to be disengaged; See Rawls, TJ,89 *,also Jencks ** 46 11 For arguments and evidence about the ways in which the enhancement of education among the least advantaged facilitates the formation of democratic social movements, see McAdam, Political Process, 108-116. 12 Clarence Y.H. Lo, “Communities of Challengers in Social Movement Theory,” 224-47. 13 On the force of market ideology in the insidious commodification of critical discourse , see Adorno **. 47