Judicial Courts CRT Kritik Index .............................................................................................................................................................. 1 1NC Judicial Courts CRT Kritik ............................................................................................................... 2 Aff is Shallow: Anti-colonialism is key ................................................................................................... 6 Perm Answers: CRT is Best Starting Point ............................................................................................. 7 Link: Starting Point Analysis ................................................................................................................ 12 Link: Government Judicial Action ....................................................................................................... 16 Link: Civil Society/Patriarchy .............................................................................................................. 23 Impacts ................................................................................................................................................ 27 Case Neg.................................................................................................................................................. 30 No solvency: Courts and government fail the people ........................................................................ 31 No Solvency: Courts racist .................................................................................................................. 33 No solvency: Social racism .................................................................................................................. 35 No solvency: US Support for Israel ..................................................................................................... 37 No solvency: Patriarchy....................................................................................................................... 38 No solvency: Middle East Womyns' Rights -- Arab Experience Unique ............................................. 40 CRT Alt Solvency...................................................................................................................................... 41 Decision rules for the K ........................................................................................................................... 47 Language Critique ................................................................................................................................... 49 AFF ANSWERS: ........................................................................................................................................ 52 A2: Courts bad for topic areas ............................................................................................................ 53 A2: CRT takes out case solvency ......................................................................................................... 57 AT: CRT framework good ................................................................................................................... 62 1NC Judicial Courts CRT Kritik Judicial branch supports the rise of the imperial presidency through the executive branches creation of secret laws through the manipulation of the court system Adler, Aug 13 (David Adler is the director of the Andrus Center for Public Policy at Boise State University where he holds appointment as the Cecil D. Andrus professor of public affairs. He serves as an adjunct professor of law in the University of Idaho’s College of Law, where he teaches courses on the Constitution and the Supreme Court. “Secret executive law upheld by courts violates Constitution.” Aug 1, 2013 http://www.idahostatesman.com/2013/08/01/2682709/secret-executive-law-upheldby.html#storylink=cpy) At the time of the American Revolution the principle of the rule of law was focused on the subordination of the executive to legal prescriptions. The founders, who were keen students of history, had culled from their readings the lesson that kings and despots and tyrants had defied efforts to rein in their powers. In a historic act, culminating in decisions made in the Constitutional Convention, the presidency was made subject to the limits of the Constitution. Executive transparency and accountability were ascendant. With some exceptions, that trajectory survived well into the 20th century, but the rise of the imperial presidency has proven to be prologue to another perilous era: executive branch creation of secret law. Since 9/11, the administrations of George W. Bush and Barrack Obama have hidden from public view legal memos prepared by the Office of Legal Counsel that have purported to supply the legal justifications for a range of executive branch initiatives: preventive war, extraordinary rendition, warrantless surveillance, termination of the Geneva Convention, defense of interrogations methods widely condemned as torture and, most recently, targeted killings and the use of exigent letters. Scholarly analyses of OLC memos that were leaked or subsequently released during the latter years of the Bush administration have shredded the reasoning employed by attorneys in that office. Worse than the impoverished and indefensible reasoning, however, is the fact that the Obama administration has refused to release the memos so that they could be scrutinized publicly. If matters could be made worse, they have been made worse — by the judiciary. In the past several years, federal court rulings have granted summary judgment to the Department of Justice, sustaining its claims of the need for secrecy. It’s one thing to withhold on national security grounds certain policy decisions that require secrecy, but it’s quite a different matter to insulate the OLC memos that might disclose advocacy of the desire to violate statutes and treaties, which is what several of the memos have done Unchecked executive power justified the conflation of the INS into the department of homeland security, the creation of the Patriot act and justifies the ongoing Federal abuses such as the labeling of immigrants as well as civilians as terrorist Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) The legal position of Arabs and Muslims has especially declined since the exceptionally speedy passage of the Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to [*729] Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism (USA Patriot Act), n96 which subjects noncitizens to guilt by association, ideological exclusion, unilateral executive detention, and racial profiling. Aliens are deportable for innocent association, without any proof that they supported terrorist activity. n98 Noncitizens are now subject to the resurrection of ideological exclusion, that is that they will be denied a visa on the basis of pure speech if they are seen as endorsing or espousing terroristic activity or persuading others to support activity or a group. n99 Aliens can be detained without any hearing or showing that they pose a threat to national security or are a flight risk. The defendant in a normal criminal proceeding can be held without bail only if he is a danger to the community or a flight risk. n100 Aliens can now be held not only during the proceeding which can take years, but also afterwards, indefinitely, even if the proceeding says they should not be removed from the country!! n101 Rules that effect citizens and noncitizens alike include the authorization of secret searches and wiretaps without any probable cause as would normally be required by the Fourth Amendment. n102 Unchecked governmental power leads to an ongoing declaration of war against Islam and radical dissidents creating a perpetual cycle of retaliatory warfare. Churchill 03 Professor of American Indian Studies at the University of Colorado/Boulde,r Ward, Some people push Back: On the Justice of Roosting Chickens: Reflections on the Consequences of U.S. Imperial Arrogance and Criminality, Published by AK Press in 2003 That desperate circumstances generate desperate responses is no mysterious or irrational principle, of the sort motivating fanatics. Less is it one peculiar to Islam. Indeed, even the FBI's investigative reports on the combat teams' activities during the months leading up to September 11 make it clear that the members were not fundamentalist Muslims. Rather, it's pretty obvious at this point that they were secular activists – soldiers, really – who, while undoubtedly enjoying cordial relations with the clerics of their countries, were motivated far more by the grisly realities of the U.S. war against them than by a set of religious beliefs. And still less were they/their acts "insane." Insanity is a condition readily associable with the very American idea that one – or one's country – holds what amounts to a "divine right" to commit genocide, and thus to forever do so with impunity. The term might also be reasonably applied to anyone suffering genocide without attempting in some material way to bring the process to a halt. Sanity itself, in this frame of reference, might be defined by a willingness to try and destroy the perpetrators and/or the sources of their ability to commit their crimes. (Shall we now discuss the US "strategic bombing campaign" against Germany during World War II, and the mental health of those involved in it?) Which takes us to official characterizations of the combat teams as an embodiment of "evil." Evil – for those inclined to embrace the banality of such a concept – was perfectly incarnated in that malignant toad known as Madeline Albright, squatting in her studio chair like Jaba the Hutt, blandly spewing the news that she'd imposed a collective death sentence upon the unoffending youth of Iraq. Evil was to be heard in that great American hero "Stormin' Norman" Schwartzkopf's utterly dehumanizing dismissal of their systematic torture and annihilation as mere "collateral damage." Evil, moreover, is a term appropriate to describing the mentality of a public that finds such perspectives and the policies attending them acceptable, or even momentarily tolerable. Had it not been for these evils, the counterattacks of September 11 would never have occurred. And unless "the world is rid of such evil," to lift a line from George Junior, September 11 may well end up looking like a lark. There is no reason, after all, to believe that the teams deployed in the assaults on the WTC and the Pentagon were the only such, that the others are composed of "Arabic-looking individuals" – America's indiscriminately lethal arrogance and psychotic sense of selfentitlement have long since given the great majority of the world's peoples ample cause to be at war with it –or that they are in any way dependent upon the seizure of civilian airliners to complete their missions. To the contrary, there is every reason to expect that there are many other teams in place, tasked to employ altogether different tactics in executing operational plans at least as well-crafted as those evident on September 11, and very well equipped for their jobs. This is to say that, since the assaults on the WTC and Pentagon were act of war – not "terrorist incidents" – they must be understood as components in a much broader strategy designed to achieve specific results. From this, it can only be adduced that there are plenty of other components ready to go, and that they will be used, should this become necessary in the eyes of the strategists. It also seems a safe bet that each component is calibrated to inflict damage at a level incrementally higher than the one before (during the 1960s, the Johnson administration employed a similar policy against Vietnam, referred to as "escalation"). Since implementation of the overall plan began with the WTC/Pentagon assaults, it takes no rocket scientist to decipher what is likely to happen next, should the U.S. attempt a response of the inexcusable variety to which it has long entitled itself. The Alternative is to reject the Aff’s usage of Federal power in favor of Judicial Checks and Balances. Only by raising public support can the courts achieve its goal in protecting the rights of citizens and minorities in a Post 9/11 world Fisher 05 Louis, Congressional Research Service, Judicial Review of the War Power, Presidential Studies Quarterly Center for the Study of the Presidency, September 2005) The shock of 9/11 initially produced a compliant judiciary, willing to defer to executive initiatives and judgments. The executive branch continued to flex its muscles, insisting that it had the constitutional authority to detain hundreds of individuals in Guantanamo Bay and hold them indefinitely until the government decided it was time for their release. President Bush, on November 13, 2001, issued a military order authorizing the creation of military tribunals to try noncitizens who had given assistance to al Qaeda. He claimed that he had authority to designate U.S. citizens "enemy combatants" and hold them for years without giving them access to an attorney, charging them with a crime, or bringing them before a court for trial. These sweeping assertions of presidential power finally led to the Supreme Court's decisions on June 28, 2004. Writing for the plurality in Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, Justice Sandra Day O'Connor rejected the government's position that separation of powers principles "mandate a heavily circumscribed role for the courts." A state of war, she said, "is not a blank check for the President when it comes to the rights of the Nation's citizens."145 This judicial rhetoric was not matched by the issuance of clear standards from the Court, either in this case or Rasul v. Bush (Fisher 2005b, 210-49). Lower courts were therefore largely on their own in scrutinizing the administration's claims for presidential power. On January 19, 2005, District Judge Richard J. Leon ruled that the foreigners imprisoned at Guanranamo had no legal way of challenging their detentions in federal court. 146 Other district judges, however, sharply rejected the legal arguments put forth by the Justice Department. On January 31, District Judge Joyce Hens Green ruled that the special tribunals created in Guantanamo to satisfy the Supreme Court's decision were unconstitutional by denying due process to the detainees who sought to challenge their classificacion. 147 In another setback for the administration, on February 28 a district judge in South Carolina held that the government must release Jose Padilla, a U.S. citizen who President Bush had designated as an enemy combatant, within forty-five days unless the government charged him with a crime. 148 Padilla had been held incommunicado for almost three years. The sharp disagreements between Judges Silberman and Tatel in the D.C. Circuit underscore the rift that still exists among federal "judges on war power issues and the political question doctrine. Contrary to the general impression that war power disputes present delicate political issues beyond the scope of judicial scrutiny, courts have generally regarded the exercise of war powers by the political departments as subject to independent judicial scrutiny. Throughout the past two centuries, federal courts accepted and decided a broad range of issues involving military operations. Most of those lawsuits were brought by private individuals who expected their legal claims to be settled on the legal and constitutional merits. While courts often acknowledge the president's broad discretionary powers in foreign policy and military actions, they usually do so after interpreting what Congress has authorized by statute. Even at the height of judicial unwillingness to reach the constitutional merits of the Vietnam War, the courts looked for some form of congressional approval or at least ratification of presidential war initiatives. They also intimated, repeatedly, that absent such a support (express or implicit) the decisions they reached might have turned against the president. Public pressure has affected judicial rulings on the war power. As the Korean and Vietnam Wars continued and popular support diminished, the courts appeared to be responsive to public opinion. District Judge Pine and the Supreme Court were aware of the sharp public disapproval of President Truman's broad claims of executive power. Sentencing of Vietnam War resisters seemed to decline in severity as public opinion turned against the war (Kritzer 1977, 1979; Graebner 1973-74). Although courts often decide war power disputes involving private citizens and private corporations, they are much more reluctant to decide cases brought by members of Congress. It is not enough for a dozen or so lawmakers to initiate a lawsuit. Unless there is evidence of a clear and resolute conflict between the political branches, and unless Congress as an institution is prepared to confront the president, the judiciary is likely to dismiss the case on various grounds. Lawsuits involving war power boundary disputes between the political branches will be addressed only if perfectly "ripe" for judicial resolution. When Congress decides to press a war power issue in the courts, it must do so as a body and after taking votes in opposition to presidential actions. The protection of individual rights and liberties depends now, as it did two centuries ago, on a vigorous system of checks and balances. In no area of federal power is that constraint more crucial than the decision to go to war. Without judicial and legislative controls, this part of presidential power shades into the monarchy that the Framers thought they had put behind them. A restoration of judicial and legislative checks depends on an understanding that the concentration of war power in the presidency is unhealthy for constitutional liberty, the country, and the world. Aff is Shallow: Anti-colonialism is key Colonialism is the Problem, not war powers allocation. The impact they are describing and the racism they pin-point—the narratives of Presidential War Power they tell— are not about Executive authority as much as they are about colonialism as a whole. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) Frantz Fanon, a central figure in the Algerian Revolution of 1952 to 1961, held that colonialism is violence in its pure form. n187 Kwame Nkrumah of Ghana held that the "raison d'etre of colonialism is the thorough exploitation of the subject peoples and territories." n188 Bert [*380] J. Thomas, the editor of the volume of essays I relied upon for my discussion here, asserts: "Pan-Africanism is a coherent theory, which has as its aim the complete destruction of all phases of colonialism and their consequences." n189 John Henrik Clarke in the preface to the Thomas book states that the essays deal with "the African world struggle and the search for an ideology of liberation." n190 The search for an ideology of liberation by and for people of color, in the domestic and international spheres, is a complex, continuing task. European imperialism led to the colonization of the Americas, Africa and Asia. n191 In aid of colonialism, the Portuguese began the European slave trade from Africa over five centuries ago. Colonialisms begat racisms. n192 Frantz Fanon found that racism had become an ideology in the colonial milieu. "Metropolitan scholars, particularly anthropologists, keep this racism alive, since they are prone to write that "before the advent of colonialism, [the native's] history was one which was dominated by barbarism." n193 De-colonization involved and involves not only access to state power in the former European colonies, but the colonized's rejection of internalized racism. n194 This, Frantz Fanon and Albert Memmi n195 posit, is necessarily a violent, painful process. n196 As anti-subordination legal theorists and activists located in the United States, we live in, and with, the legacies of colonial projects. As American lawyers and law teachers of color, we do well to examine the life work of Charles Hamilton Houston and William Henry Hastie. n197 CRT is not focused on one race—that’s another net benefit for the critique. Their advocacy talks about a number of races, but each instance there is a primary focus on one particular group. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) As noted, the LatCrit movement is the best-organized form of race-conscious critical legal thought. The choice to organize as critical race theorists, however, as opposed to as Latina/o, or Asian American, or Native American, or Black critical legal theorists, is a different stance. n140 The distinction is an important one. CRT centers critical theory and race, racisms, and law, rather than a particular racial identity category. CRT can and should learn much from LatCrit, and vice versa. CRT's "first-decade learning curve" framed the start-up of, and served as the "point of departure" for, LatCrit as an organized legal intellectual movement. n141 LatCrit's learning curve, especially its sophisticated [*372] organizing methods and level of theoretical ambition, can be a starting point for a renewed CRT movement. n142 Perm Answers: CRT is Best Starting Point CRT is the best starting point. CRT attacks the Oppressor head on instead of reforming its legal doctrine Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) Charles Houston and William Hastie developed and put into practice the philosophy of legal education that the Howard University School of Law used to educate Thurgood Marshall and most of his NAACP legal staff and volunteer lawyer colleagues. Houston, Hastie, and Marshall led and trained the cadre of lawyers who eradicated the formal law of American apartheid using the judicial process. "Dean" Houston n110 is further acknowledged as the architect of the NAACP's litigation strategy that culminated in 1954 in the Brown v. Board of Education decision. n111 Theirs is a justly celebrated achievement. Houston and Hastie's philosophy of race-conscious community organizing as it philosophy may perhaps be a n113 starting point for progressive forms of racial solidarity. related to their litigation work, however, is less well-known. I submit it is also crucial. n112 This Genna Rae McNeil's summation of Houston's life work applies to both Houston and Hastie: Houston engaged in planned litigation campaigns with what Brazilian social theorist Paulo Freire has described as critical consciousness. This critical consciousness incorporated both understanding and rejecting the oppressor's ideology and explanations, rejecting the oppressor's models and behavioral traits, identifying the system (or aspects of the system) that was the cause of oppressive conditions, and approaching transformation of the system (or those aspects of the system) as a collective endeavor, the strategies of which were to be developed through dialogue across class lines... . A critical consciousness also prompted Houston to extract from his legal training those aspects of the judicial process likely to have the greatest impact on the black struggle. n114 Critical Race theorists should start with an inward focus. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) As critical race theorists, I see our collective project as understanding our own condition--meaning that of the communities of color in the United States from which we come and their relations with each other--in all its multidimensional complexity. n176 This allows us to establish the ideological content of our fight, to know what we want in our condition. This is clearly a race-conscious "we." I further define the collective project of CRT as understanding the principles of white, male, and straight supremacy as they operated and operate in the modern world-system n177 and within the international legal order. n178 Black and white binary doesn’t address non-black minority issues Delgado & Stefancic 12 professor and research professor of law at the Seattle University School of Law (Richard and Jean, Critical Race Theory: An Introduction New York U Press. NY, 2012 Pg76-77) The black and white binary is said to operate in everyday culture as well. Imagine that a group of liberal television executives says to each other, “Let’s have minority sitcom.” The group is well meaning, but their thoughts immediately go to a program whose central characters are a black family. Later, on second thought, they might add an Asian maid or a Latino teenager who is a friend of one of the family’s children. But the essential framework for the program is apt to revolve around African American problems, in-jokes, and situations. Similarly, history text books may devote considerable space to the tremendously significant issue of slavery but overlook or devote scant treatment to the intense persecution of Chinese in California and elsewhere. Many may also ignore the equally important role of Conquest and the wars with Mexico and Spain in shaping Latino history. Even rare would be a book that discusses the recent wave of intense anti- Muslim suspicion that gripped the country in the years following 9/11. Each minority group has been racialized in its own unique way Delgado & Stefancic 12 professor and research professor of law at the Seattle University School of Law (Richard and Jean, Critical Race Theory: An Introduction New York U Press. NY, 2012 Pg77) Regardless of what one thinks about exceptionalism, critics of the black-white binary do make at least one valid point. The differential racialization thesis, mentioned earlier in this book and embraced by most contemporary students of race, maintains that each disfavored group in this country has been racialized in its own individual way and according to the needs of the majority group at particular times in its history. Few blacks will be yelled at and accused of being foreigners or of destroying the automobile industry. Few will be told that if they don’t like it here, they should go home. Few will be ridiculed on account of their unpronounceable last names or singsong accent. Few will have a vigilante, police officer, teacher, or social worker demand to see their papers, passport, or green card. Few will be asked if they are terrorists. By the same token, few Asian-looking people will be accused of being welfare leeches or having too many children out of wedlock. Black-white binary marginalizes nonblack minority groups Delgado & Stefancic 12 professor and research professor of law at the Seattle University School of Law (Richard and Jean, Critical Race Theory: An Introduction New York U Press. NY, 2012 Pg78) Long preoccupied with issues of identity, American society prefers to place its citizens into boxes based on physical attributes and culture. No science supports this practice; it is simply a matter of habit and convenience. Like other paradigms, the black-white one allows people to simply and make sense of a complex reality. And, of course, it is helpful in looking at the historical and ongoing relationship between balck and white Americans. The risk is that nonblack minority groups, not fitting into the dominant society’s idea of race in America, become marginalized, invisible, foreign, unAmerican. Black white binary destroys coalition building Delgado & Stefancic 12 professor and research professor of law at the Seattle University School of Law (Richard and Jean, Critical Race Theory: An Introduction New York U Press. NY, 2012 Pg78-79) The black-white- or any other – binary paradigm of race not only simplifies analysis dangerously, presenting racial progress as a linear progression; it can end up injuring the very group, for example, blacks, that one places at the center of discussion. It weakens solidarity, reduces opportunities for coalition, deprives a group of the benefits of the other’s experiences, makes it excessively dependent on the approval of the white establishment, and sets it up for ultimate disappointment . Consider some of the ways this can happen . The history of minorities in the United States shows that while one group is gaining ground, another is often losing it. For example, in 1846 the United States waged a blood thirsty war against Mexico in which it seized about one half of that nation’s land. Later, Anglo lawyers and land hungry settlers colluded with courts and local authorities to deprive the Mexicans who chose to remain in the conquered territory of their lands, which were guaranteed by the peace treaty. Yet, only a few years later, the North gallantly fought an equally bloody war against the South, ostensibly to free the slaves. During Reconstruction, slavery was abolished and important legislation enacted for the benefit of the newly freed blacks. Yet at the very same time, Congress was passing the despised Indian Appropriation Act, providing that no Indian nation would be an independent entity capable of entering into a treaty with the United States. To make matters worse, a few years later, the Dawes Acr broke up land the tribes held in common, resulting in the loss of almost two-thirds of all Indian land. And in 1882 Congress passed the Chinese Exclusion Act; earlier California had make it a crime to employ Chinese workers. Binary thinking hinders progress for all minority groups Delgado & Stefancic 12 professor and research professor of law at the Seattle University School of Law (Richard and Jean, Critical Race Theory: An Introduction New York U Press. NY, 2012 Pg79-80) Binary thinking, which focuses on just two groups, usually whites and one other, can thus conceal the checker board of racial progress and retrenchment and hide the way dominant society often casts minority groups against one another to the detriment of all. In the years following the Civil War, southern plantation owners urged replacing their former slaves with Chinese labor. Congress acquiesced. And immediately after the Civil War, the army recruited newly freed slaves to serve as Buffalo Soldiers putting down Indian rebellions in the West. Consider, as well, Justice Harlan’s dissent in Plessy v. Ferguson, reproduced in part in chapter 2 of this book, which sharply rebuked segregation for blacks but supported his point by disparaging the Chinese, who did have the right to ride with whites. In more recent times, during California’s Proposition 187 campaign, proponents for this anti-immigrant measure sought black votes by depicting Mexican immigrants as newcomers who took black jobs. And in recent years, antiimmigration forces whip up public sentiment against Muslims among minority and bluecollar communities by appealing to patriotism. Binary thinking can cause minority groups to id with whites at the expense of other groups Delgado & Stefancic 12 professor and research professor of law at the Seattle University School of Law (Richard and Jean, Critical Race Theory: An Introduction New York U Press. NY, 2012 Pg 80) In addition to pitting one minority group against another, binary thinking can induce a minority group to identify with whites in exaggerated fashion at the expense of other groups. For example, early in one state’s history, Asian sought to be declared white so that they could attend school for whites and not have to go to the ones with blacks. And in the Southwest, early litigators for Mexican American pursued an “other white” policy, arguing that segregation of Mexican American was illegal because local law only countenanced segregation against blacks. Community-betterment organizations like the League of United American Citizens reacted to rampant discrimination against their members by insisting that society treat Latinos as whites. Any kind of binary can cause minority groups to fall into repetitive suppressing ruse in which whites select token groups Delgado & Stefancic 12 professor and research professor of law at the Seattle University School of Law (Richard and Jean, Critical Race Theory: An Introduction New York U Press. NY, 2012 Pg 81-82) Anglocentric standards of beauty divide Mexican and black communities, enabling those who most closely conform to the Euro-American ideal to gain jobs and social acceptance and, sometimes, to look down on their darker skinned brothers and sisters. Similar, “box checking” allows those of white or near-white appearance to gain the benefits of affirmative action without suffering the costs of being thought of and treated as black or brown. Black-white or any other kind of binary thinking can also cause a minority group to go along with a recurring ploy in which Caucasians select a particular group – usually a small, nonthreatening one – to serve as tokens and overseers of the others. Minorities who fall into this trap hope to gain status, while whites can tell themselves that they are not racists because they have employed a certain number of suitably grateful minorities as supervisors, assistant deans, and directors of human relations. Finally, dichotomus thinking and exceptionalism impair the ability of groups to form coalitions. For example, neither the NAACP nor any other predominantly African American organization filed an amicus brief challenging Japanese internment in the World War II case of Korematsu v. United States. As mentioned earlier, a politically moderate litigation organization of Latinos distanced itself from other minority groups and even from darker skinned Latinos by pursuing an “other white” strategy during the middle years of the twentieth century. And in Northern California, Asians, Mexican Americans, and blacks have been at loggerheads over admission to the prestigious Lowell High School and the University of California at Berkeley. Will minority groups learn to put aside narrow nationalism and binary thinking and work together to confront the forces that suppress them all? It would seem that they have much to gain, but old patterns of thought die hard. If contextualism and critical theory teach anything, it is that we rarely challenge our own preconceptions, privileges, and the standpoint from which we reason. Link: Starting Point Analysis When focused on pedagogy of oppression, they are talking about a situation involving racism and immigration. Muslims and others are being treated as criminal outsiders, even as citizens. This is a terrible reality, but we still need to think about the context we use to approach this form of racism. Our argument is that implementing a CRT Praxis and examining anti-blackness and Lat Crit are the best starting points to discuss racism in terms of immigration and criminality. Woods 09 teaches criminology at Sonoma State University in northern California, Tyron "The Plantation Society, circa 2008: Discussing Immigration through the Lens of Criminology," Radical Teacher Number 84, Spring 2009) In this reflection on my teaching, I wish to share the problems I have encountered in teaching criminology students about immigration in general and the politics of immigration in particular. I suggest that these challenges are in many ways indicative of the general need for educators in the academy to do more in re-evaluating how we teach and learn about power. There is much about my experience that will be familiar to other radical teachers who attempt to confront complex social issues in the classroom at a historical juncture when such matters are more commonly reduced to individual failures (e.g., as prejudice, criminality, immorality). At the same time, I argue that my experience reveals an uncommon insight, one largely missing from progressive or radical discourse on immigration. Namely, what my criminology students have shown me is that anti-immigrant discourse is fundamentally reliant upon criminological tropes widely distributed throughout the society. These tropes are so basic to our society that while it took teaching criminology for me to recognize it as such, it certainly did not take learning criminology for my students to apprehend the immigration issue in criminological terms. Students come to my classroom well-versed in the prevailing misperceptions of immigrants as “criminals.” Rather than simply meeting this discourse of criminality on its own terms, my teaching implicates it in the legacy of white supremacy which, as I will explain below, is its condition of possibility. Despite the historic variation in immigration policy, the criminological underpinnings remain constant.2 During the period of nativism in the 1950s, immigrants from Latin America were charged with disrupting the job market and displacing “American” labor. This argument led to “Operation Wetback,” the infamous policy of mass deportation of Mexican immigrants (along with many Mexican-Americans). Although “stealing jobs” never really disappears from the discourse, the 1990s anti-immigrant resurgence, especially in California, took the form of “resource depletors”: immigrants and their children were represented as depleting scarce fiscal and natural resources. 3 As with welfare recipients, ex-prisoners, or even the poor generally, immigrants are disqualified through a discourse that holds a rule-breaker as morally deficient, socially inferior, and unworthy of civic inclusion. This moral discourse is racialized and owes its deep roots to Europe’s imperial project. “Resource depletor” is a more expansive formulation of “job stealer,” and both are simply different ways of saying “thief”—a criminal of the most basic kind. In the present day, this criminological discourse occurs amidst an important divergence between crime and immigration. Since the 1990s, immigration to the United States—both documented and undocumented—has reached historic highs, and yet rates of violent crime and property crime have declined sharply over the same period, with the violent crime rate reaching historic lows.4 This divergence is mirrored in the basic contradiction of contemporary criminal justice policy: since the 1970s, the overall crime rate has declined while the rate of incarceration and prison-building has increased dramatically. In other words, much as there is a fundamental structural disconnect between crime and incarceration, the evidence shows that immigration does not contribute to increased rates of crime. 5 Despite the post-9/11 conflation of terrorism (crime) with immigration, immigrants are far less likely to commit crimes than are the native-born. If the politics of immigration nonetheless continue to live through a more fundamental politics of criminality, then we need to understand the basic properties of criminological discourse as it prepares the ground on which people are encouraged to see the presence of (certain) immigrants in the United States as illegitimate. As I will argue, there is no way of getting at the essential components of criminology (as discursive practice and as indispensable appendage to the massive state apparatus of control that is the criminal justice system) without a sustained examination of black existence in the modern Western world, and of slavery in particular. Consequently—and I believe this point is most salient for the overall intervention that Radical Teacher offers with this special issue—the basic characteristics of black positionality provide the fundamental parameters for understanding key issues in immigration today.6 U.S. society has a despotic approach to the “criminal” because it has always maintained despotic relations with its black subjects. As Toni Morrison’s quotation in the epigraph suggests, black (non-) existence serves as the metaphorical and structural scaffolding, largely occluded from view, which sustains the animated debates about immigration. It is only within this larger structural context that my students’ perspectives make sense. By the same token, the context threatens to rob them of their moral courage, of their humanity. Criminology students, regardless of race and ethnicity, and more so than students in any other major, know that so-called “white-collar” criminals are responsible for the majority of the harm caused by criminal behavior in this country. Since it is a basic feature of the curriculum in the department, the students are exposed to the facts that show that immigrants or gang members or drug addicts, or any of the other “usual suspects” of the criminal justice system, do not warrant the obsessive fear with which society tends to regard them. And yet they are immersed in a society, a field of study, and a career path that encourages them to disregard these facts. What are the components of this ethical evasion and how can an educator productively disrupt this process of social formation, literally the making of police officers, prison administrators, probation officers, juvenile counselors, and the everyday citizen amenable to “law and order” rhetoric and policy? To better relate my experiences with these questions, I should say more about the contexts in which I work. I currently teach in the Department of Criminology and Criminal Justice Studies at Sonoma State University in northern California. Most of my students are white, from working to lowermiddle class economic backgrounds in rural or suburban northern and central counties of the state. There are small numbers of Mexicano/Chicano students, followed much further behind by Asian Americans and Native Americans; statistically speaking, blacks are only an occasional presence in my classrooms. The criminology major also tends to attract somewhat more men than women (though not as disproportionately as masculinist stereotypes of criminal justice professions might cause one to expect). Additionally, most of my students are headed into careers in various law enforcement agencies, come from law enforcement families, or are already working in the criminal justice system in some capacity. The “typical” student in my classroom, I would argue, has much in common with the main subjects of U.S. civil society. He is white, but comes from areas in which Mexicanos/Chicanos—immigrants, migrants, and long-time residents/citizens—are the largest minority group (and a majority in many places). Although generally speaking Mexicanos/Chicanos are more likely to be integrated into white spaces than blacks, my typical student’s geography remains well-segregated. Mexicano/Chicano and African American communities thrive throughout the state’s Central Valley, but they largely exist along the internal margins of a dominant paternalistic Anglo social structure.7 My typical student, therefore, is accustomed to seeing and even interacting with people of color—principally people of Mexican origins—but largely through relations that reproduce social distance, rather than bridge it. Rural segregation is mirrored in the small cities that border the heavily populated San Francisco Bay Area, such as Santa Rosa near where my institution is located. The immediate historical context here is the process by which the rural communities of California have emerged from three decades of a radically changing political economy whereby agriculturerelated industries have been superseded by the prison industrial complex.8 The ascendancy of the prison industry in rural California is a manifestation of the massive political, economic, and social shifts attending the transition from welfare to warfare state.9 Capital flight, deindustrialization, and state restructuring produced surpluses in land, capital, labor, and state capacity—the antidote to which became, in part, a dramatic prison building frenzy and social policy of mass incarceration. Prisons became the simplistic answer to a series of complex questions. The state’s job is no longer to provide for the common well-being of its citizens; it has restructured itself away from this capacity, and in a period of permanent crisis, through the mechanics of domestic militarism, presents its social necessity in terms of an impossible mandate: the war on crime in its proliferating forms (drugs, gangs, terrorism, immigration). To put it another way, in terms of social position, the typical criminology major in my classroom is the product of a socio-political geography in which “law and order,” replete with its constitutive racial imaginings, continues to acutely inform their self-identities, albeit with a nagging sense that somehow the “good guys” are losing their grip. Sometimes this shadow manifests in my students as cynicism or bitterness, but often it gets mobilized into a penchant for punishment. They exorcise the economic anxieties that have been such an insidious part of the landscape of their lives by means of racialized antagonisms that they articulate in criminological terms (as in: if you do the crime, be ready to do the time!). The most illuminating discussions about immigration take place in my Criminology seminar. This course is a core class in the major, and generally when it is taught by criminologists, the focus is on the gamut of theories in the discipline about why people do crime and how best to punish and prevent offenders. I find this pedagogy a good formula for making a very bad problem (the prison industrial complex) much worse, but not for much else. 10 As a teacher of students embarking upon careers devoted to controlling the liberty of criminalized Others, I find myself struggling to come up with ways to teach about the problems criminology takes as its objects of study (“crime,” violence, “deviance,” policing, incapacitation), while simultaneously providing students with a “coherent framework” through which to interrogate the very power that criminology (and each one of my students) most takes for granted: the right to seize the freedom of another human being in the first place. To put it more succinctly, criminology empowers us to judge the Other. What I want to do in my Criminology seminar, on the other hand, is to teach about power. Before we even get to what criminology has to say for itself, therefore, we spend almost two months building a context in which to situate our study of criminological theories. 11 We discuss the rise of capitalism and Enlightenment moral theory, the expansion of Europe through imprisonment and the convict trade. The centerpiece of this history, however, is an analysis of slavery. What was it and what role did it play in the genealogy of criminal justice? 12 We discuss W.E.B. DuBois’ analysis of the social relations necessary for slavery to function. 13 DuBois develops a lesson about power that is basic for conscious people: dominance succeeds only through division. If a small handful of white people owned all of the slaves and most of the land—in other words, held the wealth in the society—how could they possibly hope to maintain their control without the assistance of all of the other whites (the majority)? The slave owners needed overseers, bounty hunters, and slave patrols to police their plantations. As DuBois points out, however, it made no rational sense for the average, landless white worker to go along with the slave system since it was precisely slavery that was keeping him impoverished. In short, most whites had more in common with the African slaves—in terms of poverty, self-determination, material security—than they had with the wealthy planters. From where we sit today, it seems a matter of course that the white workers would identify with other whites, even though the owners were their oppressors too, and not with blacks, but it is important for students today to understand that this division had to be created and reproduced on a daily basis. As DuBois (and historian David Roediger much later) observed, the white worker was paid off with the “wages of whiteness”: in the face of continued immiseration and landlessness, he could take solace in the comfort that he was white.14 I find that this story is actually a poignant one for today’s college students, most of whom have all come up in a post-civil rights era in which slavery is recognized as a tragic evil in our nation’s past. The problem, of course, is that we continue to endure slavery’s aftermath, both culturally and in terms of society’s structures: the criminal justice system evinces this legacy perhaps more than any other institutional setting.15 Moreover, racism not only thrives today, but conventional narrow understandings of it betray an implicit faith in the system’s capacity to be reformed and an unwillingness to face the evidence that white supremacy and state violence are two sides of the same coin. 16 I discussed with my students how the fact that the criminal justice system served as the lynchpin on which slavery was remade as a contemporary legal institution meant that we need to pay closer attention to the social relations of slavery. Who were the police of the slave society? Who’s playing the role of the white workers today? Who are the slave patrols, the overseers, the bounty hunters, the slave trading merchants? The point is not to reduce one to the other, to argue that imprisonment today is slavery. Instead, we discuss two principal lessons of slavery for the study of criminology. First, that white supremacy is a hierarchy in which all groups are pitted against each other in competition to distance themselves from blackness, at the bottom, and to get close to whiteness on top. In other words, the social system of white supremacy creates an anti-black world that captures all races within its binary logic: in such a context, racial identity is indexed by two polar realities, one embodying value (whiteness) and the opposite embodying value’s absence (blackness). A second principal lesson of slavery for the study of contemporary criminology is that the function of policing historically has been to contain the political desires of the white worker by binding him to the state. It is not surprising, then, that the slave patrols were the first official organized police force in this nation’s history. As DuBois noted, the white worker was kept from seeing himself in the black worker because he was bound to the planters and repelled from the slaves and even from the mass of white laborers because “they constituted the police patrol [that] could ride with the planters and now and then exercise unlimited force upon recalcitrant or runaway slaves.”17 In class, we discussed how the act of policing entails an unconscious identification with the state and against the objects of police action. When the state is white supremacist, then policing too becomes an act of identification with (and desire for) whiteness. While many of my students were able to process the implications of this history, to recognize both the error and the injustice of the “wages of whiteness,” they saw it mostly as rhetoric or analogy (as in, today is like yesterday in these ways . . .), rather than as a descriptive analysis of what is currently. When I attempted to ground this historical lesson about power into the context of their own lives with the example of immigration, they vigorously resisted, swiftly condemning “illegal” immigration. For example, I asked them, how does the current immigration debate illustrate the historical example of the white worker and the “wages of whiteness”? I brought up the case of California’s anti-immigrant Proposition 187 (which occurred before many of my students had reached kindergarten) and how it won support from a significant number of black and Latino voters. 18 Was this not an example of how white supremacy and racial capitalism work, in this case encouraging oppressed workers and people of color to police themselves by demonizing immigrants and thereby distracting attention from the true source of their oppression? And what about those white workers again, how did they cast their lots this time? The students were quick to defend their position against immigrants. One senior (who has since gone on to a career as an agent with the California Department of Alcohol Beverage Control: “we carry guns,” she told me in response to my query, why?) became particularly agitated. She talked about her father who has owned a landscaping business in Sonoma County for a long time. She said: “My dad is being undercut by immigrants who don’t have proper licensing because they’re undocumented and therefore can charge much less than he does.” She was angry. Is this student’s story a specific illustration of the general failure of this country’s immigration policies? It is, in part. We cannot verify any of the asserted facts, of course, but discursively this student’s story communicates the time-worn theme of the immigrant as “job-stealer,” and therefore implicitly as “thief.” Although the student appeared to understand the concept of the “wages of whiteness” intellectually, when it came to her life, her unconscious emotional investment in white supremacy (understood criminologically) won out and the immigrant was blamed for her father’s declining fortunes. Her viewpoint found ample support among her classmates. When I remind them of the requirements of a capitalist system, of how competition for finite resources like jobs comes about, and of how the increasing hardships and economic anxieties that their own families are enduring today are only extended by transferring the problem onto other struggling workers, they respond simply: “but they broke the law by coming here.” This point, . The tradition of Western liberalism, in which the rational, self-interested, autonomous individual subject is seen as the primary agent of history and thus as existing ontologically prior to the social structures of this history, is deeply ensconced in the U.S. academy across its disciplines. Western liberalism is also racialized at its core, lending the emotional investment in individualism a greater urgency given our racially stratified world. In short, it is not that the students are insensitive to the hardships faced by immigrants, but sensitivity is not the same as a structural analysis of individual behavior: “But they shouldn’t have come that way,” as if undocumented immigration is merely a matter of preference; “They should try to make things better in their country,” as if an individual can resolve historical contradictions on their own; and, “It’s wrong that they’re treated unfairly, but they don’t make an effort either, they need to meet us halfway,” as if the schisms of racial capitalism were actually problems of diplomacy and good-will. What are these emotional investments? As Marlia Banning observed in an earlier issue of Radical Teacher, “there are no obvious pedagogical solutions that address the emotional attachment to political beliefs.” 19 I concur—and I wish to build on, yet depart slightly from, this insight. In the symbolic economy of anti-immigrant discourse, the immigrant is not even a primary figure. The central criminological trope in the anti-immigrant discourse— illegals—and the converse promoted by immigrant supporters—no human being is “illegal”—are both part of a larger deception. The formulation of the immigrant as a thief draws upon the idea of a fraudulent person. But an immigrant is not a fraudulent person; rather, he is a person who, according to anti-immigrant discourse, has committed fraud by attempting to pass as a citizen, or more accurately, given the historical conflation of whiteness and citizen, as a legalized resident. To be a fraudulent person, on the other hand, is to be caught impersonating a human being. There is only one such position in the anti-black world and it belongs to the black. As DuBois once put it, blacks are constructed not as people with problems, but rather as “a problem people.” 20 Slave codes in the southern United States demanded that slaves receive clothing, food, and lodging sufficient to their basic needs. Slaves, although dead to civil rights and responsibilities—social death—are reduced to nothing but the physical body, unprotected against mutilation or torture.21 The functioning of social death is, again, premised on the context itself as anti-black. The post-Emancipation era of the Black Codes, convict leasing, and lynching ensured that blackness meant social death not by virtue of enslavement, but instead as a product of criminality and imprisonment. Blackness remains to this day the essential marker of criminality and deviance. 22 Black existence and its signifier “criminal,” then, serve a central metaphorical and structural purpose for a white supremacist bourgeois society. In the contemporary debates on immigration, it provides the menacing content for the construct “criminal” that gives the anti-immigrant position its purchase in mainstream society. To put it differently, we as educators cannot effectively undo the racism of anti-immigrant discourse without also challenging the anti-blackness of crime and punishment. In concrete terms, moreover, we need to recall the destruction of the black community base, the deindustrialization of the political economy, dismantling of the welfare state, and the installment of the prison industrial complex. These processes collectively produced a black population available on a massive scale for social transfer to the living death of prison cages. These dislocations and debasements were the conditions of possibility for the political economy that draws immigrants to this country, while at the same time, the institutionalization of the (vanquished) black liberation movement serves as the prerequisite for the very struggles against the exploitation of immigrant labor that have, rightfully, gained momentum today.23 In other words, there would be no immigrant labor to speak of if the black liberation movement had not been systematically destroyed, and, ironically, that very same social movement history would not otherwise be available to other oppressed groups to learn and benefit from. Needless to say, I have not been at all successful in realizing this kind of analysis with my students. In much of its practice, criminology is an exercise in bad faith in that it encourages students to flee a displeasing truth for a more comforting lie. The criminological discourse on immigration is an expression of bad faith as well. My students live this lie in their own ways. Although they know that “crime” is far more complex and messy than a simple case of immorality, the fact that the United States has the largest prison population in the world, both in total numbers and per capita, eighty percent of whom are people of color, and that Immigration and Customs Enforcement (ICE) holds some 23,000 people in immigration jails on a given day and about 200,000 annually, does not, in any sincere way, trouble them much.24 At some level in their consciousness, perhaps they know that people (immigrant and non-immigrant alike) do not have what they need to survive in this These are tough ethical problems for young people emerging from a context in which their futures are mortgaged ever more by the racial state’s commitment to the needs of capital. My society, and that in their capacities as law enforcers, they are not making things better for these millions of people. students also know all too well from their own backgrounds in hardworking and increasingly abandoned communities that power and wealth concentrate in the hands of a very select few at the expense of people like themselves. They might recognize, should they dare to admit it, that when they fight on behalf of the state, whether it is in patrol cars, along catwalks or borderlines, or in foreign military escapades, they win only dimmer futures not only for the people of color they apprehend, but also for themselves . The question of ethics, in these ways, lurks throughout the dialectics of race and class in the prison regime that shapes immigration policy. I honestly do not know how to proceed, pedagogically, in this context. Is a Freireian pedagogy possible within an anti-black world? What would it look like to correspond with these students across our differences in social positioning and emotional attachments, as a pedagogy of self-awakening?25 James Baldwin, as always, assesses the challenge with clarity: “One may see that the history, which is now indivisible from oneself, has been full of errors and excesses; but this is not the same thing as seeing that, for millions of people, this history—oneself—has been nothing but an intolerable yoke, a stinking prison, a shrieking grave. ”26 Teaching about immigration within criminology shows me that black-brown-white remain insoluble antagonisms. I remain open to what the answers may be, and, in the interim, try to act ethically myself in confronting the anti-blackness of both criminology and much of the discourse on immigration. Link: Government Judicial Action Courts have unconsciously without remorse gutted the meaning of the Reconstruction Amendments and abandoned laws meant to protect newly freed blacks in order to appease whites Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) Prior to the civil rights movement at the midpoint of last century, whiteness—as critical-race-scholar Cheryl Harris wrote—was a valuable form of property recognized and enshrined by law as a normative civic and legal ideal.44 Not possessing whiteness meant denial of the freedom to immigrate, naturalize, enjoy full citizenship, exercise the right to vote, choose one’s profession, or control one’s labor.45 Not having whiteness infringed upon one’s rights to buy, sell and enjoy property; to marry and form families; to give witness in a court of law and to maintain physical safety and bodily integrity. 46 During this time, the United States was what sociologists Michael Omi and Howard Winant call a “racial dictatorship.”47 The passage of the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth Amendments, along with Reconstruction-era civil-rights statutes, provided a brief respite from the racial-dictatorship era following the Civil War. This respite, a result of an interest convergence 48 in maintaining Republican Party influence in the South, was cut short by the Hayes–Tilden Compromise of 1877, which ushered in the post-Reconstruction era with a vengeance.49 The post-Reconstruction era, with its devolution of state-based federalism accompanied by the withdrawal of federal troops from the South, left no significant federal support in place to enforce the rights of formerly enslaved people.50 In Derrick Bell’s terms, the Hayes–Tilden Compromise represented the ultimate racial compromise: allowing disparate groups of whites to settle their political differences over the involuntary sacrifice of Blacks.51 In the racial-dictatorship era, unreconstructed white normativity 52 prevailed and legislatures passed laws that were clearly “race-d” to disadvantage peoples of color under the auspice of “states-rights”-based federalism.53The courts in the racial-dictatorship era provided little relief. Indeed, courts eviscerated the meaning of the Reconstruction Amendments and civilrights statutes by using seemingly neutral strategies to disenfranchise peoples of color in lockstep with sociopolitical forces that sought to restore the South’s honor. Courts perpetuated racial subordination Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) Second, courts concocted self-serving racially contingent legal distinctions to preserve racial hierarchy. Drawing upon the detailed Critical Legal Studies critique of binary oppositions in legal doctrine, 61 pre-civil-rights-era courts relied on such distinctions to preserve racial hierarchy. Historically, civil rights had a very different meaning than they have today. Then, “civil rights” referred to the economic rights of a small-business owner, such as in Yick Wo v. Hopkins, more than they did to the constitutional right of equal access to public amenities.62 To the nineteenth-century judges hearing cases of African Americans who sought access to restaurants and theaters, neither constitutional amendments nor civil-rights statutes covered the rights of plaintiffs if they involved “social rights” rather than “civil rights.”63 Thus, judges evoked the social-versus-civil-rights distinction as a way to deny the reach of the post-Reconstruction amendments and legislation. In similar fashion, courts articulated publicprivate64 and make-find65 distinctions to perpetuate racial subordination. Courts failed to address the issue of white supremacy within law and society and undo its effects Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) Following World War II, the second reconstruction or mid-twentieth-century civil-rights movement ushered in liberal legal reforms designed to eradicate explicit discrimination imposed on racial grounds. In this civil-rights era, Congress, state legislatures, and the courts strove to enact “equality before the law,” through vehicles such as Brown v. Board of Education74 and its progeny (which struck down de jure segregation), the Civil Rights Act of 1964,75 the Voting Rights Act of 1965,76 and the Immigration Act of 1965.77 Not only did Brown leave untouched everything other than formal inequality, but the Court’s colorblindness principle scrupulously failed to capture the law’s long-running complicity with white supremacy and equally failed to undo its effects. As established previously, the law’s complicity with For all their forward advances, these reforms, enacted at the height of Cold War McCarthyism, provided only formal equality: process-based equality of opportunity, as opposed to a substantive definition of what equality requires in material terms racism was sometimes of the obvious sort, 78 In this sense, de jure equality served the aim of racial redemption, as this Article calls it. but more often its complicity was doctrinally encoded in its self-serving legal rationales, distinctions, and foundational principles. In this sense, formal discrimination’s elimination failed to address the synergy between law and society that helped accumulate and compound centuries of white power and privilege using neutral means. It did not address the subtle, yet well understood, racially coded call-and-response interplay between the courts and the public. Elimination of formal inequalities primarily served to improve the courts’ and society’s own self-perceptions, and ironically, the value of whiteness—a whiteness redeemed by the enlightenment of formal equality. Courts attention on de jure equality focused as a tool for white racial redemption, it did not address the collaboration between society and law that helped perpetuate centuries of white privilege Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) In this sense, de jure equality served the aim of racial redemption, as this Article calls it. but more often its complicity was doctrinally encoded in its self-serving legal rationales, distinctions, and foundational principles. In this sense, formal discrimination’s elimination failed to address the synergy between law and society that helped accumulate and compound centuries of white power and privilege using neutral means. It did not address the subtle, yet well understood, racially coded calland-response interplay between the courts and the public. Elimination of formal inequalities primarily served to improve the courts’ and society’s own self-perceptions, and ironically, the value of whiteness—a whiteness redeemed by the enlightenment of formal equality. In an attempt to redeem the white race reputation, The Supreme Court struck down pro segregation initiatives yet allowed for the active resistance of desegregation in the form of the Southern manifesto. Appearing to be neutral while still preserving white supremacy. Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) Here, redemption is used mainly in a property sense, while secondarily in a quasi-religious sense—a process through which whiteness is decoupled from its problematic association with white supremacy in the civil-rights era and beyond. Thus, in order to repair the damages to the reputational and property value of whiteness caused by complicity with racism, society and its institutions needed to redeem themselves from Jim Crow segregation, indigenous dispossession, racialized labor exploitation, and a centuries-long covenant with white supremacy. The Warren Court brilliantly effectuated the repudiatory aspect of racial redemption, in per curiam after per curiam order striking down segregation in various contexts without written opinion, much like Lady MacBeth in her futile attempts to wash the blood of complicity from her hands.80 In its desire to cater to white preferences for desegregation,81 courts merely invited the active resistance of the South—and later the North—to comply with Brown. Meanwhile, anti-desegregation courts and communities deployed massive resistance in the form of the Southern Manifesto, the Parker doctrine, pupil-placement programs, so-called freedom-of-choice plans, and other ingenious “neutral” tactics to preserve white supremacy’s old forms and habits.82 Warren Burger Court despite being famous for establishing Civil Rights Acts and Voting act still maintained systematic racial power through the redemption of whiteness Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) The elevation of Warren Burger to Chief Justice of the Supreme Court in 1969 furthered the racialredemptive project and aided the transformation to a new form of white supremacy under formal equality. Despite the obvious four-hundred-year legacy of white supremacy which helped structure American society just as plainly as capitalism, gender-difference, or technology, the law during this time was primarily concerned with developing “limiting principles” in response to the genie of equality that had been let out of the bottle. First, in the controversial Milliken v. Bradley decision, the Court applied “local control” as a variant of the nineteenth-century states-rights rationale in an attempt to explain why Brown permitted residential segregation, white flight, and monopolistic control of educational resources.83 Next, the Court in Washington v. Davis imposed an intent requirement upon plaintiffs who sought to claim racial discrimination using the Equal Protection Clause;84 a difficult requirement to prove in a world of multiple causation and implicit biases. The Court in Arlington Heights further complicated matters by requiring a showing of proximate cause to the intent doctrine in order for the plaintiff to prevail in an Equal Protection disparate-impact case.85 Finally, in Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education, the Court erected a firewall between legal and societal discrimination (de jure versus de facto) in this affirmative-action-in-employment case, ironically reminiscent of the social-versus-civil-rights distinction from Plessy (and accompanying rationale that “stateways cannot change folkways”).86 In Wygant, Justice Powell adjudged societal discrimination to be “too amorphous” to impose a race-conscious remedy.87 Contrary to the grand narrative of legal liberalism that dominates United States imagination, the Warren and Burger Courts from 1953–1986 represented a “land bridge” (rather than representing a rupture, or marked departure, from an earlier era of racial dictatorship) over which the Rehnquist Court could pass from a pre-civilrights to a post-civil-rights era, while transforming and maintaining systematic racial power through the redemption of whiteness and the return to a state of racial innocence. In the 1980s-90s Post Civil Rights era Chief Justice of Supreme court advocated for segregation and prioritized rights of whites supposedly injured by civil rights Legislation pushing for a principle of colorblindness to be implemented in court proceedings. Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) William Rehnquist’s 1986 elevation to Chief Justice of the Supreme Court ushered in a new phase of post-civil-rights-era jurisprudence. Prior to his appointment to the highest court, Rehnquist pursued a career advocating segregation.88 The Reagan–Bush prioritization of civil rights as rights of white men injured by civil-rights legislation was aligned with the judicial retreat from and transformation of civil rights under Rehnquist.89 The Court ingeniously deployed the Warren-era principle of colorblindness to interpret white supremacy’s victims and beneficiaries. Using this approach, the Court’s 1989 cases heralded a new order. In City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., the Court restated the de facto–de jure distinction as the societal-identifiable distinction.90 The 1989 term also saw the burden-shifting controversy in Price Waterhouse,91 the relaxation of the defendant’s evidentiary burdens in Wards Cove,92 and the re-emergence of the make-find distinction in the Patterson case which interpreted the “make and enforce contracts” language in section 1981 cases of the 1866 Civil Rights Act.93 Even though Congress rebuked the 1989 Court in the 1991 Civil Rights Act, Congress’s first repudiatory attempt, the Kennedy–Hawkins Civil Rights Act of 1990 failed.94 The Kennedy–Hawkins bill passed both the House and the Senate, but President George H.W. Bush vetoed it. The Senate’s veto override failed by just one vote.95asserting that hidden “quotas” in the bill would require firms to enact racial balancing to avoid claims of disparate-impact discrimination.96 We are now in an era where the idea of civil rights is turned on its head. Conversations arguing against racism are now perceived as “racist” placing whites as an innocent victim of reverse discrimination. Modern U.S. Courts aided in this white supremacist era under the guise of colorblindness and offer no remedy for minorities. Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) By the time of the 1995 Adarand Constructors v. Pena case,97 the project of redeeming whiteness was so complete that mentioning “innocent white victims” as documented by Tom Ross’s analysis of affirmative-action jurisprudence98—was no longer necessary to justify striking an affirmative-action plan. Instead, the Court decided Adarand in the race-neutral doctrinal terms of “skepticism,” “consistency,” and “congruence.”99 The Court declared all racial classifications suspect “irrespective of the race of the burdened or benefited group.”100 Thus, innocent whiteness operated as a background assumption, signaling a return to the full reputational value of whiteness that is able to stand in moral equivalency to blackness and other forms of colored other-ness. It was with this reformulation of the meaning of equality, victimhood, and discrimination that the Court transformed the Fourteenth Amendment’s understanding of equality from an anticaste principle to an antidifferentiation principle.101 In the post-racial world of moral equivalence, racial classifications operate as racial discriminations. Johnnie Cochran, who “played the race card” in the O. J. Simpson trial, was as notorious and as morally culpable as the “n-word”-spouting police officer Mark Fuhrman.102 Affirmative action is the moral equivalent to Jim Crow segregation, and ballot initiatives to ban affirmative action are presented and passed as “civil rights initiatives” in states with an overwhelming white majority of registered voters.103 Barack Obama’s “dollar bill” comment is as morally culpable as Geraldine Ferraro’s diminishing comment that Obama’s rapid ascent was due only to his race.104mention of race is taboo, and making a racist comment is rendered the equivalent to making a critique of racism. We have arrived at the post-civil-rights era, where the idea of civil rights is turned on its head, where equality principles are rearticulated to exercise continued privilege—racial and otherwise—and where critiques of racism are rendered morally equivalent to racism itself. Privilege is again naturalized, asserted boldly as fact, with all of its social Darwinian overtones clearly ringing through. Recent Supreme Court decision in 2007 Parent Involved case make it extremely difficult and rare for plaintiffs to prevail in discrimination lawsuits Cho 09 Professor of Law, DePaul University College of Law (Sumi, "Post-Racialism." Iowa Law Review. vol. 94, 2009) The recent Supreme Court decision in the Parents Involved case reveals the newest judicial mechanisms created to preserve racial hierarchy while rearticulating subordination as equality, and deploying failure-of-proof rationales.105 Such failure-of-proof approaches by the Court focus on raising evidentiary burdens using enhanced causation and plaintiff-unfriendly burden shifting, thereby making it increasingly difficult and extremely rare for plaintiffs to prevail in discrimination lawsuits, while at the same time making it appear as though racial discrimination is either declining or that racial remedies to redress discrimination are unconstitutional .106 The Parents Involved case also sets forth familiar limiting principles for racial remedies: de facto versus de jure discrimination, “no private constitutional rights” revived, narrow tailoring and social justice efficiency arguments, and individual-group rights distinctions.107The Parents Involved case also sets forth familiar limiting principles for racial remedies: de facto versus de jure discrimination, “no private constitutional rights” revived, narrow tailoring and social justice efficiency arguments, and individual-group rights distinctions.107illustrates the problem of industry capture of the judiciary. The Supreme Court’s racial jurisprudence would lead one to believe that racial classifications are so toxic that, like chemotherapy, they should be utilized only when absolutely necessary and, even then, must be used as sparingly as possible. Strict scrutiny’s imperative as applied to racial classifications is clearly reflected in the twoprong test: compelling interest and narrow tailoring.108 The compelling-interest prong seems to have gotten somewhat of a “pass” in recent litigation involving education, permitting “forward looking,” more indeterminate (and less coherent), interest-convergence majority-serving rationales for race-conscious remedies as seen in Grutter v. Bollinger.109 From Bakke to Grutter, the real focus in racial jurisprudence has been on “narrow tailoring”; both cultural and legal proscriptions of effective racial remedies are subject to the invocation of the limiting principle of “narrow tailoring.”110 Although understood as a win for affirmative-action proponents, Grutter achieved the unstated, forwardlooking nongoal of “critical mass.”111 As long as racial balancing is not effective or explicit and diversity is pursued in a nonhistorically contingent manner, with a hegemonically supported postmodern view of what is diverse,112 the Court seems to suggest that it will hold its nose and permit diversity as a compelling interest.113 Judicial courts sustains Executive’s unconstitutional laws Adler, Aug 13 (David Adler is the director of the Andrus Center for Public Policy at Boise State University where he holds appointment as the Cecil D. Andrus professor of public affairs. He serves as an adjunct professor of law in the University of Idaho’s College of Law, where he teaches courses on the Constitution and the Supreme Court. “Secret executive law upheld by courts violates Constitution.” Aug 1, 2013 http://www.idahostatesman.com/2013/08/01/2682709/secret-executive-law-upheldby.html#storylink=cpy) The American people are entitled to an explanation of the legal and constitutional rationales advanced by the DOJ in defense of administration policies. If the executive branch refuses to disclose the decisions it has made, and the reasoning undergirding those decisions, and the judiciary sustains that secrecy the result is the creation of secret law by the executive branch. That pattern inflicts great violence on our constitutional order. Indeed, it diminishes the rule of law when the citizenry is deprived of the opportunity to decide for itself whether governmental programs and policies adhere to the Constitution. Important cases pending in the federal courts, one seeking disclosure of the OLC memos justifying President Obama’s claim of authority to order “targeted killings,” and the other seeking release of the memo defending the FBI’s resort to “exigent letters” to access phone data, afford the courts an opportunity to stem the tide of executive branch lawmaking and restore a semblance of transparency and accountability. The Alice-in-Wonderland nature of recent federal court rulings that have failed to find a defensible legal basis for shrouding the OLC Memos in secrecy has introduced a novel and threatening theory into our jurisprudence: if the executive believes a legal memo should be kept secret, it will be kept secret. When the nation was confronted in 1974 in U.S. v. Nixon — the Watergate tapes case — with President Richard Nixon’s claim of an absolute executive privilege to withhold information from the judiciary, the Supreme Court, in an opinion written by Chief Justice Warren Burger, denounced the claim of absolutism as foreign to our constitutional jurisprudence. Our system rests on checks and balances, fundamental principle that our judges should remember. Detainees get no relief from U.S. District Courts Barclay and Nauziunas, July 13 National Public radio reporters (Eliza and Jessica, “ Why Doctors Oppose Force-Feeding Guantanamo Hunger Strikers” July 11,2013, http://www.npr.org/blogs/thesalt/2013/07/10/200751527/why-doctors-opposeforce-feeding-guantanamo-hunger-strikers) Some of the hunger strikers' lawyers, including those representing Jihad Dhiab, a Syrian who was cleared for release in 2009 but remains in captivity, have petitioned the court to stop the force-feeding, particularly during Ramadan.While U.S. District Judge Gladys Kessler said Monday in a four-page opinion that "force-feedings are a painful, humiliating and degrading process," she dismissed Dhiab's petition because she said her court "lacks jurisdiction" over Guantanamo "and therefore does not have the authority to grant the relief."According to the Miami Herald, the Pentagon says that during the monthlong Ramadan fast, medical personnel will only feed hunger strikers after sunset and before dawn. Race plays a major determinant in judicial proceedings, it decides who gets a public trial and who gets sent to Gitmo, U.S. citizens have less rights than European foreigners Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) It is interesting to look at the disparate legal treatment of these men. Lindh, captured in Afghanistan, got a public trial, whereas hundreds of foreign born Arabs and Muslims, also captured there, are being held in incommunicado detention in Guantanamo Bay, Cuba. n128 The President issued a military order that Al Qaeda members and other noncitizens could be tried in military tribunals or commissions without appeal to civilian courts, an action which has been heavily criticized by various scholars, n129 as well as our allies. n130 At least two federal courts have denied habeas petitions filed by lawyers representing some of the detainees, refusing to assert jurisdiction over the cases. n131 [*733] There may be approximately 650 suspects from 43 countries in Cuba, and officials are preparing accommodations for up to 2000 inmates. n132 Some scholars and government officials have suggested that detention and prosecution of captured suspects should not even be governed by international law. n133 Harvard law professor Alan Dershowitz and others have argued that such persons could be tortured without violating any laws binding the U.S. n134 Padilla, also known as Abdullah al-Muhajir, is a former Chicago Latin Kings gang member who converted to Islam. n135 He was picked up by authorities as he returned from Pakistan and was allegedly planning to set off a dirty bomb containing radioactive materials. n136 He is now being held in incommunicado detention in a U.S. military prison as an "enemy combatant," without access to counsel or any court-military or civilian, and may never be tried. n137 In December 2002, U.S. District Court for the Southern District of New York judge Michael Mukasey issued a 102 page opinion affirming Padilla's right to consult counsel, but the government continues to resist the court's order. n138 Another U.S. citizen, Yaser Hamdi, born in Louisiana of Saudi descent, who was captured by Northern Alliance in Afghanistan, is also being held as an enemy combatant, after being discovered among the Guantanamo prisoners. n139 The U.S. government in both the Padilla and Hamdi cases is resisting petitions for habeas corpus and saying that courts should just accept the President's determinations as to their status. n140 Ironically, putting U.S. citizens under military jurisdiction without access to legal counsel places them in a legal limbo where they have less rights than foreigners Reid or Moussaoui. n141 In October 2002, Reid ultimately pleaded [*734] guilty and was sentenced to life imprisonment by Judge William G. Young of the U.S. District Court in Boston. n142 Judicial courts refuses to stop force feeding detainees Perez and Lawrence, July 13 CNN reporters Natalia Perez, and Chris Lawrence “U.S. rejects call to stop force-feedings at Guantanamo for Ramadan” Wed, July 10, 2013 CNN http://www.cnn.com/2013/07/03/us/guantanamolawsuit) (CNN) -- The U.S. government on Wednesday refused to stop force-feeding prisoners at the U.S. detention facility at Guantanamo Bay, Cuba, during Ramadan. In court papers rejecting a petition by detainees, the United States said the feedings provide "essential nutrition and medical care" and do not interfere with the detainees' religious fasting during Ramadan, the holy month that begins on the evening of July 8. The tube-feedings will take place in the early morning and late evening to help detainees comply with Ramadan restrictions, said Navy Capt. Robert Durand, spokesman for the detention facility. Shaker Aamer, Ahmed Belbacha, Nabil Hadjarab and Abu Wa'el Dhiab filed a lawsuit Sunday arguing that the feedings violate the Ramadan daily fast from dawn to sunset. U.S. District Judge Gladys Kessler had set a deadline of noon Wednesday for the government to respond.Lt. Col Todd Breasseale, a Pentagon spokesman, said the military has changed force-feeding times at Guantanamo during Ramadan for years, but doing so "is an accommodation, not a right."Of the 166 prisoners at Guantanamo, 106 are on hunger strike, Breasseale said.In its court filing, the U.S. Justice Department also denied claims that it was giving the drug Reglan to the detainees. Link: Civil Society/Patriarchy Civil Society is the Masculine Sphere and is Exclusionary Pateman 88 Reader in Government at the University of Sydney, Australia (Carole. (1988) The Sexual Contract, 1977 London: Routledge.(p. 11) Women have no part in the original contract, buy they are not left behind in the state of nature—that would defeat the purpose of the sexual contract! Women are incorporated into a sphere that both is and is not civil society. The private sphere is part of civil society but is separated from the ‘civil’ sphere. The antinomy private/public is another expression of natural/civil and women/men. The private, womanly sphere (natural) and the public, masculine sphere (civil) are opposed but gain their meaning from each other, and meaning of the civil freedom of public life is through into relief when counterposed to the natural subjection that characterizes the private realm (Locke misleads by presenting the contrast in patriarchal terms as between paternal and political power). What it means to be an ‘individual’, a maker of contracts and civilly free, is revealed by the subjection of women within the private sphere. Legalistically Contractarian Societies are Linked to Men’s Freedom and Women’s Subjugation Pateman 88 Reader in Government at the University of Sydney, Australia (Carole. (1988) The Sexual Contract, 1977 London: Routledge.(p. 8) Men’s domination over women, and the right of men to enjoy equal sexual access to women, is at issue in the making of the original pact. The social contract is a story of freedom; the sexual contract is a story of subjection. The original contract constitutes both freedom and domination. Men’s freedom and women’s subjection are created through the original contract—and the character of civil freedom cannot be understood without missing half of the story that reveals how men’s patriarchal right over women is established through contract. Civil Freedom is not universal. Civil freedom is a masculine attribute and depends upon patriarchal right. The sons overturn paternal rule not merely to gain their liberty but to secure women for themselves. Their success in this endeavor is chronicled in the story of the sexual contract. The original pact is a sexual as well as a social contract: it is sexual in the sense of partriarchal—that is; the contract established men’s political right over women—and also sexual in the sense of establishing orderly access by men to women’s bodies. The original contract creates what I shall call, following Adrienne Rich, ‘the law of male sex-right’ Contract is far from being opposed to patriarchy; contract is the means through which modern patriarchy is constituted. The Judiciary’s Historical Decisions Have Upheld Sexist Legislation Pateman 88 Reader in Government at the University of Sydney, Australia (Carole. (1988) The Sexual Contract, 1977 London: Routledge.(p. 139) Sometimes wives have simply been excluded from employment; for example, women were compelled to resign from the Australian public service upon marriage from 1902 until 1966, and the ban was not lifted in the State of Victoria until as recently as 1973. More generally, women’s employment has been restricted by ‘protection’ due to those who lack ownership of the property in their persons. One of the best known examples is the judgement [sic] in the case Muller v. Oregon in the United States in 1908, in a period of great conflict over freedom of contract. In 1905 (in Lochner v. New York), the Supreme Court ruled that a law limiting the work of male bakers to eight hours per day was unconstitutional. In Muller v. Oregon the Court ruled that it was permissible to restrict the working hours of women workers. The Court’s reasoning harks back to the story of the sexual contract; the argument appeals to man’s strength, woman’s physical structure and child-bearing function and her dependance [sic] on man. The Court maintained that although ‘limitations upon personal and contractual rights may be removed by legislation, there is that in [woman’s] disposition and habits of life which will operate against a full assertion of [civil] right’s. Woman is ‘properly placed in a class by herself, and legislation designed for her protection may be sustained, even when like legislation is not necessary for men and could not be sustained’. Patriarchy Gives the Mere Appearance of Freedom in Liberal States Pateman 88 Reader in Government at the University of Sydney, Australia (Carole. (1988) The Sexual Contract, 1977 London: Routledge.(p. 187-188) Contemporary feminists (especially in the United States) often conclude that the only alternative to the patriarchal construction of sexuality is to eliminate sexual difference, to render masculinity and femininity politically irrelevant. At first sight, the complete elimination of status and its replacement by contract appears to signal the final defeat of patriarchy and the law of male sex-right. The realization of the promise of contract as freedom appears to be in sight, and the patriarchal construction of men and women, masculinity and femininity, appears to be breaking down. Feminists have campaigned for, and won, legal reforms that are couched in what how usually called ‘gender neutral’ terms. Such reforms can mean that women’s civil rights are safeguarded, but this approach to reform can also lead to curious results when for example, attempts are made to incorporate pregnancy into legislation that applies indifferently to men or women. Odd things happen to women when the assumption is made that the only alternative to the patriarchal construction of sexual difference is the ostensibly sex-neutral ‘individual’. The final victory of contract over status is not the end of patriarchy, but the consolidation of the modern form. The story of sexual contract tells how contract is the medium through which patriarchal right is created and upheld. For marriage to be become merely a contract of sexual-use—or, more accurately, for sexual relations to take the form of universal prostitution—would mark the political defeat of women as women. When contract and the individual hold full sway under the flag of civil freedom, women are left with no alternative but to (try to) become replicas of men. In the victory hold full sway under the flag of civil freedom, women are left with no alternative but to (try to) become replicas of men. In the victory of contract, the patriarchal construction of sexual difference as mastery and subjection remains intact but repressed. Only if the construction is intact can the ‘individual’ have meaning and offer the promise of freedoms to both women and men so that they know to what they must aspire. Only if the construction is repressed can women have such an aspiration. Heterosexual relations do not inevitably take the form of mastery and subjection, but free relations are impossible within the patriarchal opposition between contract and status, masculinity and femininity. The feminist dream is continuously subverted by entanglement with contract. Irrespective of Social Change, the Contract System of Law Continues to Disenfranchise Women Pateman 88 Reader in Government at the University of Sydney, Australia (Carole. (1988) The Sexual Contract, 1977 London: Routledge.(pp. 6-7) In the natural condition ‘all men are born free’ and are equal to each other; they are ‘individuals’. This presupposition of contract doctrine generates a profound problem: how in such a condition can the government of one man by another ever be legitimate; how can political right exist? Only one answer is possible without denying the initial assumption of freedom and equality. The relationship must arise through agreement and, for reasons which I shall explore in Chapter 3, contract is seen as the paradigm of free agreement. But women are not born free; women have no natural freedom. The classic pictures of the state of nature also contain an order of subjection—between men and women. With the exception of Hobbes, the classic theorists claim that women naturally lack the attributes and capacities of ‘individuals’. Sexual difference is political difference; sexual difference is the difference between freedom and subjection. Women are not party to the original contract through which men transform their natural freedom into the security of civil freedom. Women are the subject of the contract. The (sexual) contract is the vehicle through which men transform their natural right over women into the security of civil patriarchal right. But if women have no part in the original contract, if they can have no part, why do the classic social contract theorists (again with the exception of Hobbes) make marriage and the marriage contract part of the natural condition? How can beings who lack the capacities to make contracts nevertheless be suppose always to enter into this contract? Why, moreover, do all the classic theorists (including Hobbes) insist that, in civil society, women not only can but must enter into the marriage contract? The construction of the difference between the sexes as the difference between freedom and subjection is not merely central to a famous political story. The structure of our society and our everyday lives incorporates the patriarchal conception of sexual difference. I shall show how the exclusion of women from the central category of the ‘individual has been given social and legal expression and how the exclusion has structured the contracts with which I am concerned. Despite many recent legal reforms and wider changes in the social position of women, we still do not have the same civil standing as men, yet this central political fact about our societies has rarely entered into contemporary discussions of contract theory and practice of contract. Husbands no longer enjoy the extensive right over their wives that they possessed in the mid-nineteenth century when wives had legal standing of property. A2-Foucault-Biopower/Discipline, Civil State and Law Represent the Structure of Domination in Modern Patriarchy Pateman 88 Reader in Government at the University of Sydney, Australia (Carole. (1988) The Sexual Contract, 1977 London: Routledge.(p. 16) Attention to the subordination constituted by original contract, and by contract more generally, is itself another possible source of misunderstanding. Michel Foucault’s influential studies might suggest that the story of the sexual contract will generate a view of power and domination that remains stuck in an old juridical formulation ‘centered on nothing more than the statement of the law and the operation of taboos’. Certainly, law and contract, and obedience and contract, go hand in hand, but it does not follow that contract is concerned only with law and not also, in Foucault’s terminology, with discipline, normalization and control. In the History of Sexuality Foucault remarks that ‘beginning in the eighteenth century, [new power mechanisms] took charge of men’s existence, mend as living bodies’. But beginning in the seventeenth century, when stories of the original contract were first told, a new mechanism of subordination and discipline enable men to take charge of women’s bodies and women’s lives. The original contract (is said to have) brought a modern form of law into existence, and the actual contracts entered into in everyday life form a specifically modern method of creating local power relations within sexuality, marriage, and employment. The civil state and law and (patriarchal) discipline are not two forms of power but dimensions of the complex, multifaceted structure of domination in modern patriarchy. Impacts Racial profiling of Arabs and Muslims effects anyone who can be socially constructed as an Arab/Muslim Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) There were early reports that some Blacks and Latinos welcomed the law enforcement targeting of Arabs and Muslims. n85 When I heard that comment, it reminded me that I preferred that my sons not be mistaken for Arabs when flying. On the other hand, I also realized that increased racial profiling of Arabs and Muslims has not meant that the long term racial profiling of African Americans has stopped. It merely means that my sons may be doubly profiled depending on the context. At the airport, they may be regarded as Arab terrorists, while at the taxi stand or ATM machine, they may be regarded as Black criminals. n86 [*728]After September 11, Muslims and Arabs and people who look like them have been under siege. n87 Over 1000 incidents of hate crimes were reported by February 2002. n88 Even President Bush's Arab secret service agent was removed from an American Airlines plane. n89 Of five people who were killed, including a Sikh Indian, a Pakistani Muslim, an Egyptian Coptic Christian, and an Indian Hindu, n90 none of them was a Muslim Arab, but all were socially constructed as such. Arabs and Muslims are being De-Americanized Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) According to Bill Hing, Arabs and Muslims, whether citizens or not, are literally and figuratively being de-Americanized, which is "a twisted brand of xenophobia that is not simply hatred of foreigners, but also hatred of those who may not be foreigners but whom the vigilantes would prefer being removed from the country anyway." n93 A member of the U.S. Civil Rights Commission has even said that in the event of another terrorist attack, the American government might consider interning Arab Americans, n94 reminiscent of the treatment of 120,000 Japanese and Japanese Americans in World War II. n95 Aliens, non-citizens, citizens EVERYONE are now subjected to series of civil rights violations including indefinite detention and secret searches without probable cause Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) The legal position of Arabs and Muslims has especially declined since the exceptionally speedy passage of the Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to [*729] Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism (USA Patriot Act), n96 which subjects noncitizens to guilt by association, ideological exclusion, unilateral executive detention, and racial profiling. n97 Aliens are deportable for innocent association, without any proof that they supported terrorist activity. n98 Noncitizens are now subject to the resurrection of ideological exclusion, that is that they will be denied a visa on the basis of pure speech if they are seen as endorsing or espousing terroristic activity or persuading others to support activity or a group. n99 Aliens can be detained without any hearing or showing that they pose a threat to national security or are a flight risk. The defendant in a normal criminal proceeding can be held without bail only if he is a danger to the community or a flight risk. n100 Aliens can now be held not only during the proceeding which can take years, but also afterwards, indefinitely, even if the proceeding says they should not be removed from the country!! n101 Rules that effect citizens and noncitizens alike include the authorization of secret searches and wiretaps without any probable cause as would normally be required by the Fourth Amendment. n102 America headed toward fascism under the guise of national security. Massive violations against constitutional rights happening now Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) Under the USA Patriot Act, over 1000 people were held for weeks or months with no charges in mass preventive detention. n103 They did not have access to lawyers and, in many cases, their families were not told where they were. n104 Some people were held as material witnesses, i.e. they might have information. Even they have been treated harshly. n105 Some have challenged that detention in court. While federal judges have found that the use of material witness warrants to detain individuals for potential testimony before a grand jury is unlawful, n106 other judges have held the opposite. n107 According to Jerry Kang,[we] should not be surprised if courts determine that national security in the face of terrorism is-in the lingo of constitutional law- a 'compelling interest' and that rude forms of racial profiling, notwithstanding its over and under- [*730] inclusiveness, are 'narrowly tailored' to furthering that interest. It would be foolish to think that the courts will necessarily save us from the excesses of the more political branches. n108 Racial profiling destroys the public’s trust towards law enforcement Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) In November 2001, the Bush Justice Department said it would interview some 5000 young men, solely based on age, date of arrival, and country of origin. Virtually all were Arabs or Muslims. n112 Some police departments refused to assist the federal government as they believed the policy constituted racial profiling. n113 They knew that law enforcement works best if it positively involves the community rather than terrorizes it. n114 Needless to say, the affected groups have been outraged by the targeting. n115 Some months later, the Justice Department announced it would interview 3000 additional men from countries with an Al Qaeda presence. n116When the Justice Department announced the Absconder Apprehension Initiative in February 2002, they decided to prioritize [*731] the deportation of 6000 aliens out of the 300,000 foreigners who remained in the country after being ordered deported. Needless to say, these men were from Arab countries. n117In April 2002, the Justice Department announced that it would put into effect a provision from IIRIRA, which gives the police the authority to enforce immigration laws. n118 This was controversial not only in immigrant communities, but with police concerned about racial profiling. "'We've spent decades establishing trust . . . with our very diverse communities,' says a San Diego spokesman. 'If there is an immigration emergency tied to criminal activity, of course we'll assist. But if it is simply an immigration violation . . . we will not be involved.'" n119 Immigrants are no longer welcomed as contributors and are now perceived as potential terrorists Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) In March 2003, the INS was dissolved and folded into the new Department of Homeland Security along with 21 other federal agencies. The implications are ominous, as one commentator has stated. "Placing all of the INS's functions into a department focused primarily on national security suggests that the United States no longer views immigrants as welcome contributors, but as potential threats viewed through a terrorist lens." n146At the time of this writing, it is alleged that the U.S. government has drafted in secret Patriot II, the Domestic Security Enhancement Act of 2003. n147 The proposed law would authorize secret arrests, overturning the federal court decision requiring the government to release the names of all those detained since September 11. n148 Additionally, the law would permit the U.S. to extradite even American citizens for trial to countries with which we do not have extradition treaties, such as Saudi Arabia, Syria and Libya, which are well known for torture. n149 International and current U.S. law prohibit sending a person to a country where there is likelihood of torture. n150 [*735] Constituting a new level of invasion of privacy, a proposed Terrorist Identification database would authorize the collection of DNA of any suspect and of all noncitizens suspected of having an association with a "terrorist organization." n151 The most extraordinary proposal would possibly strip Americans of citizenship as a form of punishment for giving material support to terrorist groups. n152 Case Neg No solvency: Courts and government fail the people Restricting power won’t solve, checks and balances are already at work. Courts legitimize presidential powers. Durden 13, pseudonym for a group of editors at financial website Zero Hedge (Tyler, “You now Have to Assume Everything is Being Collected” Phil's Stock World blog, http://www.philstockworld.com) Every company involved denied the most sensational assertion in the Prism documents: that the NSA pulled data 'directly from the servers' of Microsoft, Yahoo, Google, Facebook, AOL and more.But PRISM is a filter on what the government is really storing Prism, as its name suggests, helps narrow and focus the stream.In that way, Prism helps justify specific, potentially personal searches.But it's the broader operation on the Internet fiber optics cables that actually captures the data. 'I'm much more frightened and concerned about real-time monitoring on the Internet backbone,' said Wolf Ruzicka, CEO of EastBanc Technologies, a Washington software company. 'I cannot think of anything, outside of a face-to-face conversation, that they could not have access to.' Whether the government has that power and whether it uses Prism this way remains a closely guarded secret. Obama defends the 'intrusion' the only way we would expect:'You can't have 100 percent security and also then have 100 percent privacy and zero inconvenience,'And it's no surprise the President continued the eavesdropping 'You can't expect a president to not use a legal tool that Congress has given him to protect the country. So, Congress has given him the tool. The president's using it.And the courts are saying 'The way you're using it is OK.' That's checks and balances at work. 'But in conclusion: Schneier, the author and security expert, said it doesn't really matter how Prism works, technically. Just assume the government collects everything, he said. He said it doesn't matter what the government and the companies say, either. It's spycraft, after all. 'Everyone is playing word games,' he said. 'No one is telling the truth.' Government Courts have made it difficult for citizens to fight back Apuzzo, June 13 Pulitzer Prize-winning investigative reporter for The Associated Press in Washington, Matt, Denver Post, June 7, 2013, “ What you should know about the NSA phone data program," http://www.denverpost.com/nationworld/ci_23408127/what-you-should-know-about-nsaphone-data) People have sued. But challenging the legality of secret wiretaps is difficult because, in order to sue, you have to know you've been wiretapped. In 2006, for instance, a federal judge in Detroit declared the NSA warrantless wiretapping program unconstitutional. But the ruling was overturned when an appeals court that said the plaintiffs civil rights groups, lawyers and scholars didn't have the authority to sue because they couldn't prove they were wiretapped.Court challenges have also run up against the government's ability to torpedo lawsuits that could jeopardize state secrets.The recent release of the classified court document is sure to trigger a new lawsuit in the name of Verizon customers whose records were seized. But now that the surveillance program is under the supervision of the FISA court and a warrant was issued, a court challenge is more difficult.Suing Verizon would also be difficult. A lawsuit against AT&T failed because Congress granted telecommunications companies retroactive immunity for cooperating with warrantless surveillance. In this instance, Verizon was under a court order to provide the records to the government, making a lawsuit against the company challenging. Congress and courts already oversee surveillance program and deem it legal Drezner June 13 professor of international politics at the Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy at Tufts University (Daniel W., Foreign Policy Online, June 7, 2013, “3 unoriginal thoughts on the NSA revelations," http://drezner.foreignpolicy.com/posts/2013/06/07/ three_unoriginal_thoughts_on_the_nsa_revelations) While on its surface, this order -- which authorized the secretive National Security Agency to collect data on phone calls placed by Verizon customers for a period of three months -- seems blatantly illegal, the reality is that Congress has been enabling and legalizing such surveillance for years.... Rather than challenging the administration's authority to secretly interpret and enact laws, however, Congress instead twice authorized them to keep everything a secret. Last year, Ron Wyden, a Democrat on the Senate Intelligence Committee, tried to prohibit secret legal rulings. He got voted down[8]. That same year Senator Jeff Merkley, also a Democrat, added his own amendment to the renewal of the 2008 wiretapping law. His amendment was voted down[9] by a strong margin in both parties. The administration's response[10] is that the program is legal and is overseen by both Congress and the courts. They also gesture towards, but don't really identify, 'numerous inaccuracies' in the reports. Seeking government oversight will not solve Drezner June 13 professor of international politics at the Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy at Tufts University (Daniel W., Foreign Policy Online, June 7, 2013, “3 unoriginal thoughts on the NSA revelations," http://drezner.foreignpolicy.com/posts/2013/06/07/ three_unoriginal_thoughts_on_the_nsa_revelations) It speaks to a systemic acceptance of this kind of surveillance across the law and the Congress and the oversight courts. It means this is not the action of an overzealous NSA or even an overzealous administration but the consequences of a broad redefinition of the government's domestic surveillance powers -- one that has managed to stick across both the Bush and Obama administrations, and one that will thus be that much harder to uproot. This explains the congressional reaction to yesterday's news stories, which overwhelmingly defended NSA activities. Surely, now that this is public, however, this will change, right? I don't think so. If you dig into the latest New York Times/CBS poll[12], you find pretty robust support for President Barack Obama's counterterrorism policies. So you have a policy that the executive, legislative, and judicial branches have all signed off on, with support from the American people. That doesn't make the policy the right one -- but it does make it legitimate. No Solvency: Courts racist U.S. Supreme Court Justices has deprived natural born American Citizens of their rights without due process of the law off the basis of race Saxton 13 University of Sheffield, School of Law, Graduate Student James, "Korematsu v United States; a basic judgement analysis in light of Hart's legal positivism, Finnis' natural law, and Critical Race Theory " 2013, http://www.academia.edu/1512275/ Korematsu_v_United_States_a_basic_judgement_analysis_in_light_of_Harts_legal_positivism_Finnis_n atural_law_and_Critical_Race_Theory) The most obvious point to raise in light of Korematsu at this point would be the involvement of the US Constitution, especially in light of the Ninth and Fifth Amendment, which concerns the rights of US citizens to be protected from the deprivation of "life, liberty and property, without due process of law" and that manipulation of the constitution cannot discharge these rights. For the purposes of the rule of recognition, the authority of the Constitution would make these valid rules under the legal system. Hart also contended with Austin's "command theory" by proposing his theory on the "variety" of laws, that there should be a distinction between primary rules; rules that apply directly to those bound by the rules, and secondary rules; rules that govern the creation or extinction of the rules themselves. In terms of primary and secondary rules, these amendments offer direct protection to its subjects, binding the legal system to provide adequate protocol when such deprivation occurs. Here we find an interesting feature, as the rule contains elements of both primary and secondary rules, yet both are to be applied simultaneously. Yet Justice Black insists that the curfew was necessary, "… because we could not reject the finding of the military authorities that it was impossible to bring about an immediate segregation of the disloyal from the loyal…" Justice Frankfurter also comments that he could, "… find nothing in the Constitution which denies to Congress the power to enforce such a valid military order." So both Black and Frankfurter approve of the idea that the Fifth Amendment can forgo restricted application. Does this mean that there is a flaw in Hart's theory, or can primary and secondary rules run together and Black and Frankfurter simply applied the law erroneously? I would prefer the latter view, because given this situation where the Fifth Amendment has dual purpose to both the citizens and the state; Black and Frankfurter by their own volition decided to exclude it from relevance altogether as "it was impossible" to apply its secondary function of due process to those of Japanese ancestry. Supreme Court violated the unalienable rights of U.S citizens by taking away the liberty of Japanese-Americans Saxton 13 University of Sheffield, School of Law, Graduate Student James, "Korematsu v United States; a basic judgement analysis in light of Hart's legal positivism, Finnis' natural law, and Critical Race Theory " 2013, http://www.academia.edu/1512275/ Korematsu_v_United_States_a_basic_judgement_analysis_in_light_of_Harts_legal_positivism_Finnis_n atural_law_and_Critical_Race_Theory) Nonetheless in light of this principle of “unalienable rights” we have a prima facie case that the decision in Korematsu successfully alienated the rights of en entire minority group by withdrawing their liberty. As the movement developed, Thomas Aquinas proposed that natural law provides the backdrop for positive law; man-made law.1 As a result, the rule of “lex iniusta non est lex”, or as 1 Aquinas, T, Summa Theologia, I-II, Question 91, in The Treatise on Law, (R.J Henle, trans. And ed., University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, 1993), pp 148-184 interpreted, “... no human laws are of any validity, if contrary to the law of nature.”2 On application of this logic, Mr. Korematsu was correct in not submitting to Execution Order 9066, as it did not conform to the natural rights provided by the US Constitution. In furtherance to this, Justice Roberts submitted that the Order coupled with Proclamation No. 4, made Mr. Korematsu “... subject to two conflicting laws and was not bound, in order to escape violation of one of the other, to surrender his liberty for any period.”3 Justice Murphy also commented that the exclusion of Japanese-Americans “goes over the very brink of constitutional power ”4. Both these attitudes would sit well with natural theorists, as they bear in mind the principles of lex iniusta non est lex and constitutionally conferred natural rights. American institutions are inherently racist and unaware of their racism this is why Minority rights have been infringed on and continue to be today Saxton 13 University of Sheffield, School of Law, Graduate Student James, "Korematsu v United States; a basic judgement analysis in light of Hart's legal positivism, Finnis' natural law, and Critical Race Theory " 2013, http://www.academia.edu/1512275/ Korematsu_v_United_States_a_basic_judgement_analysis_in_light_of_Harts_legal_positivism_Finnis_n atural_law_and_Critical_Race_Theory) One of the fundamental CRT beliefs is that racism is a built in part of the American lifestyle.5 This thought is complimented in Lawrence’s theory of “unconscious racism ”, as stated above; this is when racial matters are present in a situation although not unanimously recognised.6 In Korematsu, Black took the approach that the principle to be decided was if a minority’s rights can be outweighed by public necessity; noting that racial antagonism never can.7 This is a perfect example of unconscious racism, deduced since the public necessity was brought about by the war against Japan; the racial antagonism towards Japanese-Americans was a foregone conclusion. Gardum comments that when a norm regarding equality is adopted, it has “extreme indirect-horizontal effect”8 suggesting Black’s judgement would not sit well with the race-crits. 2 Blackstone, W, Commentaries on the Laws of England, (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1765-1769) Toyosaburo Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 233 (1944) 4 Toyosaburo Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 233 (1944) 5 Bell, Faces at the Bottom of the Well: the Permanence of Racism, 1992 6 Lawrence, The Id, the Ego and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism, 39, Stanford Law Review 317 (1987) 7 Toyosaburo Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 216 (1944) 8 Gardum, S, Where the (state) action is, 2006, I.J.C.L 760-779, 776 3 No solvency: Social racism Orientalism rampant throughout the media and other aspects of society they leave untouched Ali 12, J.D., University of California, Berkeley (Yaser, August, 2012 “Shariah and Citizenship - How Islamophobia Is Creating a Second-Class Citizenry in America,” 100 Calif. L. Rev. 1027) Nowhere were these stereotypes memorialized more vividly than in Hollywood, as cultural productions tend to replicate and render more explicit the dominant paradigms in society. n55 Jack Shaheen, author of Reel Bad Arabs: How Hollywood Vilifies a People, conducted a comprehensive review of Arab dehumanization in over 900 films; he described the popular stereotype of Arabs: From 1896 until today, filmmakers have collectively indicted all Arabs as public enemy #1 - brutal, heartless, uncivilized religious fanatics and money-mad cultural "others" bent on terrorizing civilized Westerners, especially Christians and Jews ... . Arabs are brute murderers, sleazy rapists, religious fanatics, oil-rich dimwits, and abusers of women. n56 Shaheen argued that viewers internalized these stereotypes through constant repetition. n57 He explained this process by use of a powerful Arabic proverb, "Al tikrar biallem il hmar. By repetition even the donkey learns." n58 Not surprisingly, out of over 900 feature films he reviewed, only a handful depicted Arabs as the protagonist. n59 Each of the remaining films brandished stereotypical depictions of Arab men as notorious villains and womanizing sheikhs, while Arab women were either hypersexualized, scantily clad belly dancers or weak and oppressed objects draped in black robes and desperately seeking liberation by Western heroes. n60 Legal and legislative change not enough. The deep-seated racism they are talking about will resurface in other ways. Bell 92, Professor of Law at NYU, (Derrick, Faces at the Bottom of the Well. The Permanence of Racism. p. 97) Erika began with a series of statements all too familiar to me: That the litigation and legislation based on the belief in eventual racial justice have always been dependent on the ability of believers both to remain faithful to the creed of racial equality and to reject the contrary message of discrimination. That, despite our best efforts to control or eliminate it, oppression on the basis of race returns time after time--in different guises, but it always returns. That all the formal or aspirational structure in the world can't mask the racial reality of the last three centuries. Oppressive forces do not vanish when criticized. After their advocacy and the restriction of war powers, the original forces of racism and brutality will still exist and will still divide communities. Spivak 04, Prof. Humanities Columbia U, (Gayatri, “Righting Wrongs” South Atlantic Quarterly 103.2/3, p.523-581) This narrative demonstrates that when the human rights commissions, local, national, or international, right state terrorism, police brutality, or gender violence in such regions, the punishing victory is won in relatively remote courts of law. Catharine A. MacKinnon describes this well: "The loftiest legal abstracts . . . are born . . . amid the intercourse of particular groups, in the presumptive ease of the deciding classes, through the trauma of specific atrocities, at the expense of the silent and excluded, as a victory (usually compromised, often pyrrhic) for the powerless."77 In the aftermath of victory, unless there is constant vigilance (a "pressure" that is itself a species of terror), the very forces of terror, brutality, or violence that suffer a public defeat, often come back to divide and oppress the community even further. If the community fights back, it does so by the old rules of violence. The dispensation of justice, the righting of wrongs, the restoration of human rights, is reduced to a pattern of abyssal revenge and/or, at best, a spirit of litigious blackmail, if the group that has been helped has a strong connection to the regional human rights agencies or commissions (the dominant pressure groups described as "below), which is by no means always the case. Legal awareness seminars, altogether salutary in themselves, can exacerbate the problem without the painstaking foundational pedagogy which prepares the subject of rights from childhood and from within a disenfranchised culture of responsibility. And, if we get away from such remote areas, human rights dependency can be particularly vicious in their neocolonial consequences if it is the state that is the agency of terror and the Euro-U.S. that is the savior. No solvency: US Support for Israel Conflict with the Muslim world is not just excessive use of Presidential power. The US feeds anti-Americanism in a number of ways, many which will continue to exist after the affirmative. US support for Israel, for example, may make some clash inevitable. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) This anger derives partly from the American government's long-standing support for Israel and tolerance military aid to Israel n169 is well-known and well-understood in the Islamic world. This knowledge is a significant element in non-Israeli Middle Eastern and Muslim opposition in the region and elsewhere to America's foreign policy. n170 The New York Amsterdam News recently had a rather telling headline about the war: "Young, Black, and Dead." n171 of Israel's repression of the Palestinian movement for national liberation. n168 While little-known here, American No solvency: Patriarchy No solvency. War Powers Issues require confronting the patriarchy for any hope of institutional change. Warren & Cady 94 chair of the Philosophy department at Macalester College and Professor of Philosophy and Department Chair at Hamline University Karen J. and Duane L., Hypatia vol. 9, no. 2 (Spring 1994) Indiana University Press Conceptually, a feminist perspective suggests that patriarchal conceptual frameworks and the behavior they give rise to, are what sanction, maintain, and perpetuate “isms of domination” –sexism, racism, classism, warism, naturism and the coercive power-over institutions and practices necessary to maintain these “isms.” If this is correct, then no account of peace is adequate which does not reveal patriarchal conceptual frameworks; they underlie and sustain war and conflict resolution strategies. (Examples of why we think this is correct are laced throughout the remainder of the paper.) One glaring example of how the dominant cultural outlook manifests this oppressive conceptual framework is seen in macho, polarized, dichotomized attitudes toward war and peace. Pacifists are dismissed as naïve, soft wimps; warriors are realistic, hard heroes. War and peace are seen as opposites. In fact few individual warists or pacifists live up to these exaggerated extremes. This suggests a reconceptualization of values along a continuum which allows degrees of pacifism and degrees of justification for war (Cady 1989). Feminist philosophers regard conceptual considerations to be at the core of peace issues because many of the other womenpeace connections can be explained theoretically with an analysis of patriarchal conceptual frameworks in place. The evidence for the existence of such conceptual connections comes from such a wide variety of sources: empirical data and history; art; literature, and religion; politics, ethics, and epistemology; language and science. Although we cannot discuss all of these sources here, we do consider several. They are evidence of woman-peace connections that, in turn, help to establish the nature and significance of the conceptual connections. Discourse of “Nationality” backfires. Isolating groups and emphasizing nationality in the eyes of the law will actually reify those categories and allow for a hardening of national norms. Hall 04 associate professor of education and anthropology at the University of Pennsylvania Kathleen D., “BEING HERE AND BEING THERE: FIELDWORK ENCOUNTERS AND ETHNOGRAPHIC DISCOVERIES,” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, September, #595, 80-90 Legal discourse constitutes minority statuses in efforts to determine who belongs to a nation and to protect the rights of those who do. These forms of political discourse designate minority status on ethnic reductionist terms--terms that assume a homology between a community and a culture. These essentialist constructs, in contradictory fashion, provide the basis for challenging discrimination while defining the boundaries of national belonging in racial terms. Yet processes of social incorporation are not shaped only within the designation of legal statuses and the provision of particular rights. They are founded upon and informed by visions of national unity--visions that provide the rationale for different types of integration efforts. What is assumed to preserve the social fabric of a nation or, contrastively, to tear it apart? and How are cultural differences imagined to contribute to either of these social ends? No solvency: Middle East Womyns' Rights -- Arab Experience Unique Arab women discrimination is unique from other minority groups Saloom 05, Attorney, Atlanta, GA, J.D. graduate, University of Georgia School of Law; M.A., Middle Eastern Studies, University of Chicago (Rachel “I Know You Are, But What Am I? Arab-American Experiences Through the Critical Race Theory Lens." Hamline Journal of Public Law & Policy, 27 Hamline J. Pub. L. & Pol'y 55) Third world women as a group or category are automatically and necessarily defined as religious (read "not progressive"), family-oriented (read "traditional"), legal minors (read "they-are-still-notconscious-of-their-rights"), illiterate (read "ignorant"), domestic (read "backward"), and [*74] sometimes revolutionary (read "their-country-is-in-a-state-of-war-and-they-must-fight!"). n84 This mentality exists toward women who live in Arab countries; moreover, this way of thinking becomes engrained in American society. Thus, Arab-American women are then viewed through this lens of inferiority. One scholar argues "there is a tendency, first, to establish the essential otherness of Middle Eastern women by juxtaposing Western and Middle Eastern cultures and images of Occidental women with Oriental women." n85 Arab-American women are viewed as the "other" and as inherently different from white women. n86 Arab-American women are also thought to be more foreign and exotic than many other minorities. n87 This extra [*75] element of foreignness distinguishes Arab-American women experience from some other minority groups. n88 CRT Alt Solvency Critical Legal Studies breaks down social barriers and acts as a social revolutionary tool for creating change in law and practical actions Unger 83 Professor of law at Harvard Law School, Roberto, The Critical Legal Studies Movement, June, http://www.jstor.org/stable/1341032) The transformative activity carried out in these different settings may be understood as a distinctive and perhaps even exemplary reaction to a specific historical circumstance. To grasp what exactly the reaction exemplifies, we need to re- member a few elementary aspects of the situation. One such aspect is the disruption of the imagined mechanism, and the disappearance of the real occasions, of revolutionary transformation. The conventional concept of revolution combines at a minimum the notion of basic if not total change in the formative context of routine social life with the idea of more or less widespread participation in the remaking of a social order that the state has temporarily ceased to con- trol. In the ruling traditions of historical and critical social the only clear alternative to the endless reproduction of society through reformist tinkering or to its slow and obscure remaking through the accumulation of an enormous number of largely unrelated decisions and conflicts. In this inherited picture, the core mechanism of revolution is the alliance of a counterelite with an oppressed mass. In the advanced Western theory and in the vulgar beliefs that these traditions have inspired, revolution appears as the best hope of real social change, countries, however, with their forms of mass-party politics, their extreme segmentation of the work force, and their more or less shared language of a culture that combines attributes of the high and the popular, the simple hierarchical contrasts that this mechanism presupposes have been irremediably con- fused. Moreover, the textbook cases of modern revolution almost invariably have depended upon the occurrence of a narrow range of enabling conditions besides the existence of a well-defined and relentlessly expressed social hierarchy. One of these favorable circumstances was the paralysis of the re- pressive and coordinating apparatus of the state in the wake of war and occupation. Another was the influence of the transformative commitments of those who seized government in the course of a national struggle against a brutal tyranny. But wars in our own historical circumstance must be either too limited or too terrible to have this enabling effect, and As the mechanisms and occasions of revolution disappear, we seem to be left with nothing but the petty squabbles of routine politics. A second feature of the larger situation is the brutal tyrannies do not exist in the industrialized West. strange co- existence, in the rich North Atlantic countries, of constant revolution in the sphere of personal relations with repetition and drift in the struggle over the the meanings and intentions of this cultural-revolutionary practice. It may be enough to remember here that it wants to free the practical and passionate relations among people from the constraining effect of some background plan of social division and hierarchy and to recombine the experiences and opportunities associated with different social or gender categories. To the extent that it becomes cut off from the practical or imaginative contest over institutional structure, as it has in the career of the uses of governmental power and the institutional structure of society. I suggested earlier a view of advanced Western societies, this cultural-revolutionary practice undergoes a perversion: the un- happy search for gratification and self-fulfillment takes precedence over all other modes of subjectivity or solidarity. A third characteristic of our historical circumstance is the nature of the gap between the homogeneous social space of citizens and property holders depicted by classical liberal the- ory and the real nature of social life. The whole of society appears in fact as a vast array of overlapping but nevertheless discrepant sets of prerogatives . These prerogatives, only partly defined by the law, establish a system of social stations. Each place in the system is defined simultaneously by its relation to all the other places and by the degree and character of its access to the favors of governmental power. These favors include both the direct or indirect distribution of material resources and the making of legal rules that turn transitory advantages into vested rights. Each place in the scheme of social stations serves as a haven within which a distinctive form of life can flourish. Politics, narrowly understood as the contest over the control of the state, are largely played out as a struggle among more or less fragmentary interest groups. This process, however, does not express the underlying char- acter of society. Instead, it helps explain why society, as a relatively quiescent division of labor, should be so different from politics. This is truly a new ancien regime. Its great historical accomplishment is to have extended to the masses of ordinary working men and women the experience of right- holding, at least of holding rights that are not just steps in a chain of personal dependence. Its most striking defect is to have fallen short: not to have developed rightholding into active empowerment over the terms of social life and not to have overcome the disparity between the organization of pol- itics, as a contest among fragmentary, crisscrossing interest groups and parties of opinion, and the organization of society, as a system of fixed divisions and hierarchies that makes the individual the captive of a more or less rigidly defined station within a more or less stabilized division of labor. A movement able to act transformatively in the circum- stance I have described must reject the false dilqmmas of conservative reform or textbook revolution. It must find ways to override the contrast between the politics of personal rela- tions and the politics of the large-scale institutional structure. It must take advantage of the highly segmented character of social life - its fragmentation into hierarchically ordered cit- adels of prerogative - in order to experiment with forms of social life capable of overcoming the very oppositions - be- tween rightholding and empowerment or between the quality of grand politics and the reality of practical social experience - that this segmentation helps strengthen. Our movement exemplifies, very incipiently and imperfectly, one such mode of activity, with the distinguishing opportunities and constraints that come from working through the medium of legal thought and practice. A group acts in one of the institutional havens or social stations of the system of prerogatives. In its corner of the social world, it pioneers in types of association and action that serve as countermodels to the dominant scheme of social life and that, appropriately revised, can be extended to other aspects of social life. Targeting whiteness is crucial, we accomplish that critique through our starting point. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) Every generation of race-conscious revolutionary has had to grapple with the knowledge, the philosophy, the ideology of the white oppressor. n179 The "theories as developed by White western thinkers are a product of their values and environment, like all other political thinkers." n180 National and international political structures and organizations reflect the theories of those who created them. Working for change requires a supple grasp of the history of theory as it relates to the creation of specific political structures, organizations, and their political and organizational development over time. For anti-subordination legal theorists, n181 it further requires a particular focus on change [*379] over time in the law of subordination and the changing ideologies of subordination that mutually shape how social power is distributed. n182 Applying Critical Race Theory the US imperialism through a Post-colonial emphasis can target the same problems addressed by the aff. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) Moreover, given current American imperial overstretch, n7 the idea of a clash of civilizations merits rigid scrutiny by American anti-racist activist intellectuals. n8 We are fortunate that we can draw on an established African American tradition of critique that links domestic and global racism. n9 [*353] The following Speech n10 was the opening presentation at the 2003 Critical Race Theory Workshop (CRTW). n11 I wrote and gave it as a response to my panel's title: Race-Consciousness: Progressive Tool or Outmoded Instrument? n12 I wrote this preface later to give readers who have not participated in the movement or read the Critical Race Theory (CRT) literature some context. n13 The preface also extrapolates some of the ideas that were implicit in the Speech as given. In the Speech, I sought both to re-examine the life work of Houston and Hastie through the lens of a leftist Black Nationalism, and to give a reading of contemporary world events through that same lens. I later realized that the Speech itself was an exercise in progressive race consciousness. Whether is defined. n16 race consciousness is a progressive tool, of course, depends on how it n14 Some critical race theorists are questioning the efficacy of race consciousness n15 to our collective anti- subordination project. I understand that the 2003 CRTW organizers had this internal critique in mind when they named the first panel. n17 Nevertheless, deconstructing American race consciousness was always part of CRT's work. n18 My argument in this Article is not that all race consciousness is progressive. n19 Rather, I argue that since a progressive variety can be identified, race consciousness as such is not an outmoded instrument. n20 I submit that anti-colonial, anti-subordination race consciousness remains a progressive tool. I denominate n21 this post-colonial race consciousness. n22 I contend, fundamentally, that CRT and its theoretical progeny build on a progressive history of race consciousness. This tradition centers on work for justice and equality both domestically and internationally. n23 We should spotlight this illuminating tradition in CRT. It can inspire us for our present and future anti-subordination work. n24 Black anti-colonial thought can solve even if application is necessary Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) Black anti-colonial thought affected the American "race relations" discipline. Berkeley's Robert Blauner introduced the internal colonialism model, drawing upon "minority ideologists," into the sociological literature in 1969. While the "fit" of this model to the African American "case" was limited, in 1970, Joan Moore showed that it comported well with the Mexican American "case" in the Southwest. n71 [*361] The intellectual history of Black Nationalism and Pan-Africanism, and a history of the effects of Black anti-colonial thought in intellectual life and on racial order and power in the Black Atlantic, both remain to be written. n72 CRT Best Approach to Nationalism. Extend the nationalism link argument. CRT and decoloniality can solve all of the case without risks the reinscription of an American nationalism. They critique nationalism as “security” and we celebrate it as Pan-Africanism. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) A tradition of scholarship n88 grounds Black critical social thought n89 and anti-subordination work. n90 About thirty years ago, historian Vincent Harding, a founder of the Institute of the Black World, n91 discussed the question of vocation for Black scholars. n92 Harding urged Black intellectuals to speak truth as a fundamental requisite [*364] for collective survival in a racist society. The Black scholar's "calling," he said, was "to speak truth to our people, to speak truth about our people, to speak truth about our enemy--all in order to free the mind, so that Black men, women and children may build beyond the banal, dangerous chaos of the American spirit, towards a new time." n93 Harding stressed the importance of understanding clearly the conditions facing Black communities. n94 Harding noted that colonized peoples cannot be studied in isolation from their colonizers. n95 He thus urged: "we must produce and encourage precise, carefully documented studies of the educational, political, economic, military, and cultural systems of White oppression." n96 Finally, Harding noted that "becoming personally involved in the concrete, active struggle for liberation, entering deeply into its life, and opening our own lives to its risks, is, of course, the most unrespectable aspect of the vocation." n97 Black Nationalism is a complex political and intellectual tradition. n98 Marcus Garvey's social thought represented the emergence of [*365] a racial nationalism that asserted racial identity and pride. Garvey, however, remained within a liberal capitalist frame by affiliating himself with Booker T. Washington's ideology. n99 Socialist and anti-imperialist components were added to Black Nationalism with the formation of the African Blood Brotherhood, the "first Afro-American Pan-Africanist socialist organization in the United States." In the 1920s, several Brotherhood members joined the earliest American communist parties. n100 Socialist Hubert Harrison and communist Harold Cruse broke with the Socialist and Communist parties in the First and Second World Wars based on of critiques of White left racism. Harrison then edited a radical newspaper The Voice. n101 Cruse became a leading theorist of racial nationalism in the Black Power period. n102 In the 1960s, following Malcolm X's assassination, the Black Panther Party, which emerged in Oakland, California, the League of Revolutionary Black Workers of Detroit, Michigan, the Revolutionary Action Movement, and the Black Workers Congress all combined revolutionary Black Nationalism with socialist internationalism. n103 CRT's progressive internationalism builds upon these traditions of Black critical social thought. n104 [*366] Pan-Africanism is a political and intellectual "nationalist" movement that goes beyond the borders of the United States. n105 It is related to, and can be seen as an internationalist variety of, Black Nationalism. n106 PanAfricanism has roots in the African diaspora and Africa. It was a major force in the twentieth-century de-colonization movement on the African continent. n107 Scholars of the American civil rights movement are increasingly acknowledging an international dimension. n108 Pan-Africanism, it appears, also played a role in the twentieth-century American Black freedom struggle. n109 CRT with an anti-colonial emphasis is the best way to solve the case. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) I submit, first, that rigorous critique of how White supremacy and White privilege were, and are ordered , n120 in local, national, regional, and international law and legal institutions was and remains a key CRT task. n121 Second, this critical project must be informed by analyses of the relation of gender, sexuality, and class formations to racial formations, and how these constitute each other. Our readings and analyses should in turn inform CRT praxis. n122 Third, a further query was posed not long ago that applies to all CRT legal scholars: "How do we, as legal scholars, collectively sustain and carry forward in a progressive way the outsider experiment in critical jurisprudence as a form of anti-subordination struggle?" n123 Answering these questions is a collective project for the CRT movement. n124 F. Post-Colonial Race Consciousness, or De-Colonization, as a CRT Emphasis In view of the debate on Black critical legal thought that emerged in LatCrit, I sought in my speech to show that a closer reading of the "White over Black" n125 paradigm of race, examining specifically Pan-Africanism, makes clear that the Black, APA, Latina/o and Native American postcolonial/critical legal theory projects are not so far apart as they may first appear. n126 Post-colonial race consciousness is progressive and internationalist. n127 A "Pan-African" frame n128 for Houston and Hastie's work, and therefore the Brown decision, gives us a new perspective on their life work. When one understands racism as integral to the colonial milieu and as produced to support colonial power relations, their legal struggle [*370] and the movement against American apartheid can be seen as part of a broader global justice movement against colonialism. n129 A race conscious left internationalism - in other words post-colonial race consciousness - can help all those who identify as and with CRT to understand the work that remains before us: (a) to eradicate colonialism's legacies, and (b) to theorize and fight back against the global race/gender/sexuality power machine. n130 Global Critical Race Feminism has already moved in this direction with its incorporation of postcolonial theory. n131 CRT should follow suit. Centering de-colonization as an analytical focus in critical legal studies on race, races, and racisms will require organization. n132 Postcolonial theory has not focused adequately on U.S. law n133 and legal culture, and their internationalization, n134 as an object of critique. De-colonization may be a theoretical basis for international solidarity in both the domestic U.S. and international "race" and racial justice contexts. n135 CRT: The Aff cannot solve. Selective democracy is the problem, not war powers Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) A long time ago, in a land far away, the army of a city-state invaded another country. The city-state from which the army came prided itself on its democratic ideals. The occupying army treated the inhabitants of the invaded country as invaders usually do--poorly. n147A citizen of the occupied country asked: "what about democracy and the rule of law?" n148 An officer in the army replied: "For us there is the law of democracy; for you, there is the law of empire." n149 In 1989, Derrick Bell said that the "traditional way of doing legal scholarship doesn't do justice to our experience... . We need new ways of addressing a situation many of us feel is abominable. But minorities who are trying to blaze new trails in legal academia are meeting opposition and silencing." n150 In 1988, Mari Matsuda wrote to encourage "specific action to end the apartheid in legal knowledge... Human beings learn and grow through interaction with difference, not by reproducing what they already know[.] ... A system of legal education that ignores outsiders' perspectives artificially restricts and stultifies the scholarly imagination." n151 CRT has been defined as using the tools of critical theory in the task of dismantling racial hierarchies in the United States. n152 At the closing plenary of the Fall 1997 Conference on Critical Race Theory, Francisco Valdes proposed "post-reconstruction vision as jurisprudential method." Harlon Dalton rephrased the proposal, posing it as a question: "What would heaven on earth look like?" n153 This moment represented another move from mapping, or critique, of existing subordination, to becoming the architects of a post-subordination world. [*374] Since then, CRT as a self-organized legal intellectual movement has been dormant; until now. n154 I hope this workshop marks the renewal of CRT as a self-organized movement. In developing my remarks for today, I spent some time reading about the critical social thought and life work of Pan-African and other revolutionaries, and also that of Charles Hamilton Houston and William Henry Hastie. n155 With Derrick Bell, I share Jeremiah's lament: "The summer is past, the harvest is ended, and we are not saved." n156 The winter of our discontent has indeed been long. Viewing the treatment of Muslims through a Lens of Racism is Critical to solutions Ibrahim 09 civil rights attorney with the lawfirm of Hadsell Stormer Keeny Richardson & Renick. She is also an alumna of the UCLA School of Law Critical Race Studies Program (Nagwa, The Origins of Muslim Racialization in U.S. Law, 7 UCLA J. ISLAMIC & NEAR E.L. 121, 121 (2008/09) Understanding the mistreatment of Muslims in the United States and abroad as a form of racism, and not only as religious discrimination, is important, not just in terms of appropriately capturing what is really happening to Muslims and Muslim-looking peoples, but because it also significantly changes and expands the legal remedies available both under international law and U.S. antidiscrimination laws. n96 Decision rules for the K Vote negative for insurgency Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) CRT praxis takes many forms. As within the broader left, there is a debate about the varieties of, and the relationship of, activism to theorizing. n137 In my view, it includes scholarship, teaching, writing, cause lawyering, public service, and personal participation in political and social movements within and outside legal academia. n138 Finally, it includes organizing ourselves for the CRT workshops and conferences. The major priority of black intellectuals should be the creation or reactivation of institutional networks that promote high quality critical habits primarily for the purpose of black insurgency. An intelligentsia without institutionalized critical consciousness is blind, and critical consciousness severed from collective insurgency is empty. The central task of postmodern black intellectuals is to stimulate, hasten and enable alternative perceptions and practices by dislodging prevailing discourses and powers. This can be done only by intense intellectual work and engaged insurgent practice. n139 Insurgency tackles the aff’s problem much more effectively without the risk of cooption. Torok 04 CUNY Law Graduate and PhD candidate in ethnic studies, Berkeley (John Hayakawa, Howard Law Journal, Fall, 2004 Doctoral Candidate, Department of Ethnic Studies, University of California, Berkeley. J.D. 1991 C.U.N.Y. Law School. 48 How. L.J. 351, “Freedom Now! - Race Consciousness and the Work of De-Colonization Today.”) I now quote two quite well-known activist lawyers, from statements they each gave at their respective criminal trials. In October 1953, Fidel Castro, while on trial for armed insurrection against the U.S.-supported Batista regime in Cuba, said: "The right of rebellion against tyranny, Honorable Judges, has been recognized from the most ancient times to the present day by men of all creeds, ideas and doctrines." He went on to cite authorities, including the American Declaration of Independence, for this proposition. n157In April 1964, while on trial for sabotage and conspiracy to overthrow the South African government, Nelson Mandela spoke about the reasons for the formation of Umkonto we Sizwe, the military wing of the African National Congress (ANC). Mandela said: I, and the others who started the organization, did so for two reasons. Firstly, we believed that as a result of Government policy, violence by the African people had become inevitable, and that unless responsible leadership was given to canalize and control the feelings of our people, there would be outbreaks of terrorism which would produce an intensity of bitterness and hostility between the various races of this country which is not produced even by war. Secondly, we felt that without violence there would be no way open to the African people to succeed in their struggle against the principle of White supremacy. All lawful modes of expressing opposition to this principle had been closed by legislation, and we were placed [*375] in a position in which we had either to accept a permanent state of inferiority, or to defy the Government. We chose to defy the law. n158 Engagement in critical race praxis solves Wing 03 Bessie Dutton Murray Distinguished Professor of Law at the University of Iowa College of Law (Adrien, "Civil Rights in the Post 911 World: Critical Race Praxis, Coalition Building, and the War on Terrorism." Louisiana Law Review, 63 La. L. Rev. 717, Spring 2003) Another tenet that Critical Race Theorists espouse involves the necessity to engage in praxis, the combining of theory and practice. n153 According to Eric Yamamoto, "critical race praxis focuses on developing and then translating critical theoretical insights about race, culture, and law into operational ideas and language for antisubordination practice and, in turn, rethinking theory in light of new practice experience." n154 Sumi Cho and Robert Westley have [*736] called for synergism, an "interaction of agents or conditions that produces a combined effect that is greater than the sum of the individual effects. We envision a mode of synergistic movement theorizing that contains both substantive and methodological commitments . . . Such a project is necessarily collaborative, requiring information and insights gleaned from movements in order to formulate discursive strategies that must ultimately be tested in the context of actual struggle." n155 My own explanation for the need for praxis is based upon the historical realities of many minorities. "Since many of us come from disenfranchised communities of color, we feel compelled to 'look to the bottom,' n156 to involve ourselves in the development of solutions to our people's problems. We can not afford to adopt the classic, detached, ivory tower model of scholarship when so many are suffering, sometimes in our own extended families. We do not believe in praxis instead of theory, but that both are essential to our people's literal and figurative future." n157 Praxis can take many forms ranging from counseling a client, filing a brief, making a speech, doing op-ed pieces, writing popular press books, appearing on talk shows, serving on boards, testifying before Congress, supporting/attacking federal judicial nominees, or working officially or pro bono with various public interest, governmental, or international organizations. Language Critique Language takes forms in different ways, ways that cannot be manipulated to perform a certain task. It’s an artifact that is deeply soaked in meaning through contexts. Manipulating, more so policy wise, in time of conflict, creates a language that isn’t language. Johnson, ‘11 (Toni A.M. Johnson, “Beyond Accommodation: The legacy of feminist critique and the search for justice”, Vol 1, No 1 (2011), http://journals.kent.ac.uk/index.php/feministsatlaw/article/view/17/61 LE) Throughout her works Cornell posits justice as an ideal, as aspiration, as inherently elusive and always ‘to come’. The nature of Cornell’s exploration ties these ‘possibilities’ of justice to questions of judging and judgment, to equality and the law, to the impact of Lacanian psychoanalytic theory, to the place of women in the symbolic as compared to the imaginary and to the nature and composition of language. The critical response and critical reflections on language found in deconstruction have informed her political position and profoundly influenced her revisionary legal projects.6 For Cornell language is far from neutral. It is influenced by and invested in multiple cultural and contextual referents.7 Furthermore, language perpetuates new cycles of meaning, whereby meaning is neither static nor containable. As Susan Williams has written, ‘language is a social artifact, created, in part by the language we use to describe it...the interpretation that is an inevitable aspect of knowledge formation is deeply permeated by the cultural values and concepts encoded in the language through which that knowledge is expressed’.8 When this system of language production is viewed in the context of the legal system it becomes apparent that the linguistic system upon which law rests, a system that brings us influential definitions of ‘justice’, ‘liberty’, and ‘equality’, is deeply invested and entrenched in the linguistic precedents, histories and contexts via which meaning is given. Thus, the possibility of the legal system providing a way of contesting ‘encoded’ language would seem, if not impossible, certainly challenging. Deconstructing the gendered view in language is the only way to create a new model of language in the legal sphere. Law needs to protect language. Johnson 11 Lecturer in Law, University of Leicester, UK (Toni A.M., “Beyond Accommodation: The legacy of feminist critique and the search for justice”, Vol 1, No 1 (2011), http://journals.kent.ac.uk/index.php/feministsatlaw/article/view/17/61) In Beyond Accommodation, Cornell takes up this challenge by addressing this linguistic bind. Drawing on Derrida, Lacan and Levinas, she explores the nature and language of law. She considers the way the legal system has both gained and continues to gain from and function via that empowered status through the oppression and exclusion of alterity/the Other. Cornell specifically addresses the position of women’s engagement with law and language, considering how it constructs women, and the social violence that is caused by the linguistic exclusivity of those constructions. Cornell’s turn to deconstruction is an exploration of the way in which women are positioned within language and consequently within law. It is her intent to deconstruct the linguistic foundations of that order and acknowledge the necessity of exposing that order if any notion of justice or ethical response to the Other is to bear legitimacy. Cornell’s call to deconstruct gender, as part of a response to engaging with justice in Beyond Accommodation, The Imaginary Domain and At The Heart of Freedom, continues to provide key insights for a radical and transformatory politics. Cornell notes ‘it is time to deconstruct the gendered opposition that pervades western reason, and so to reinvent the model of the legal subject’. Cornell’s project in the Imaginary Domain and At the Heart of Freedom is an engaging attempt in how to manifest this new legal subject.10 The ‘imaginary domain’ is not just about addressing the position of women within the symbolic and within the imaginary. Cornell’s project is much wider in terms of the way in which it seeks to touch the very foundations of gender for both men and women and their status as bearing legal personhood. Cornell’s vision of an alternate legal system, as developed through the imaginary domain, feminism and deconstruction, provides a new way of thinking about personhood. She writes: Our emancipation from state-imposed sexual choices and from their reinforcement by the basic institutions of society demands much greater social equality than we have now...When all persons have this right to the imaginary domain, states can no longer force women to play the role of primary caretaker in families, either directly by law or indirectly by the manipulation of social institutions.11 Cornell’s development of the ‘imaginary domain’, deployed as a psychological space in which to reimagine personal understandings of gender and sexuality, and bearing the protection of law, was a revolutionary reimagining of legal personhood. Within the conceptual framework of the ‘imaginary domain’, law is the social mechanism that protects the version of ‘private’ life envisaged by the individual. Law does not determine the form of the imaginary domain, but protects the individual’s right to it and the conditions in which that private life can be lived out. Furthermore, the conceptual framework of the imaginary domain has at its heart a concept of ‘freedom’ rather than formal equality. For Cornell, the freedom to orient ourselves as individuals, to create our own visions and versions of ‘the good life’, is at the heart of the imaginary domain. Subsequently, the freedom to become a person is dependent on the minimum conditions of individuation; namely, the conditions necessary in order to ‘transform ourselves into the individuated beings we think of as persons’.12 Cornell’s use of ‘freedom’ rather than ‘equality’ is part of a critique of formal equality provisions that she claims are based on an aspiration to particular positions of privilege. Cornell argues that these positions of privilege are normative and delimited constructs of identity that stifle the imaginary possibility of those who occupy them and those who wish to ascend to them. Critical discourse should view language as a social practice. Specifically, language should not re-conceptualize the LGBTQ community. The imaginary claim allows for more conceptualization, giving legal claims and rights to validate the worth and selfesteem in individuals. Johnson 11 Lecturer in Law, University of Leicester, UK (Toni A.M., “Beyond Accommodation: The legacy of feminist critique and the search for justice”, Vol 1, No 1 (2011), http://journals.kent.ac.uk/index.php/feministsatlaw/article/view/17/61) The emphasis on the ability of individuals to shape their own lives outside of and unhindered by legislative constructs of appropriate familial formations encouraged me to take advantage of the theoretical premise of the imaginary domain in order to re conceptualize the position of lesbian and gay refugees and the contexts from which they had fled. Relying on the freedom associated with the imaginary domain provided a theoretical site to rethink and reframe identity within the legal structure of the Refugee Convention. In lieu of taking a more radical position that would call for a practice of no border regulation and the rendering of law as moot, I instead relied on a new language of law. This reliance upon a new theory of legalism on which the right to legal personhood turned, a legal personhood that called for freedom rather than equality was intrinsically shaped by Cornell’s ‘imaginary domain’ Cornell’s version of intimate relationships has been significant for LGBT refugees, particularly in its engagement with and response to sexuality’s boundedness within nationalist politics and identity politics. Her version of ‘freedom’ is able to assert itself within these controlling structures, toying with the language of rights and deploying alternative definitions deeply influenced by Derridean understandings of the ‘slippage’ and ‘seepage’ inherent in language. Cornell’s ‘right’ to ‘freedom’ is dependent upon a legal system that recognises the absolute agency and legal personhood of the individual, irrespective of their gender or sexuality. I argue that recognition of a specifically Cornellian version of legal personhood leads to an inviolable responsibility on the part of the UK asylum court. Social and state behaviours that preclude, discriminate against, or persecute non-normative intimate relationships/family forms, directly counter the ethos of the imaginary domain and would therefore establish eligibility for refugee status. Additionally, the imaginary domain I claim, troubles the Refugee Convention’s understanding of identity as fixed. The ‘imaginary domain’ would allow for a more open conceptualisation of the grounds of the Convention, providing an understanding of identity that does not function on the basis of immutability or the compartmentalization of identity traits, but on the indivisibility of gender, race, religion, class and how these facets are informed by context, by politics and by self-conceptualisation. By giving individuals freedom to explore their own being, the imaginary domain also provides a mechanism to engage in the law while trying to deconstruct the language at its core. Johnson 11 Lecturer in Law, University of Leicester, UK (Toni A.M., “Beyond Accommodation: The legacy of feminist critique and the search for justice”, Vol 1, No 1 (2011), http://journals.kent.ac.uk/index.php/feministsatlaw/article/view/17/61) Cornell’s legal reformist project of the imaginary domain, which has at its heart a desire to give individuals the freedom to ‘create ourselves as sexed beings, as feeling and reasoning persons’, provides a useful tool to both engage with law whilst at the same time trying to deconstruct the language that gives law its power.15 The imaginary domain gives individuals the space to conceptualise their optimum vision of private life and legally protects the practice of living out that life. Cornell’s feminism aligned with deconstruction’s breadth of openness to the Other, to language, and the ethical, underpins Cornell’s analysis and ensures that her work still sits at the cutting edge of a radical social transformatory philosophy. Cornell’s analysis refrains from any definitive conceptualisations or limitations placed on identity, with such impositions and assumptions viewed as a violent assertion. These tropes inform Beyond Accommodation, The Imaginary Domain and At the Heart of Freedom and underpin Cornell’s conception of law, which is informed by a feminist, ethical, postmodern analysis. AFF ANSWERS: A2: Courts bad for topic areas Federal judges are challenging executive authority on target killings Shane, July 13 reporter, New York Times (Scott , July 20, 2013 “Judge Challenges White House Claims on Authority in Drone Killings.” http://www.nytimes.com/2013/07/20/us/politics/judge-challenges-white-house-claims-on-authority-indrone-killings.html?_r=0) WASHINGTON — A federal judge on Friday sharply and repeatedly challenged the Obama administration’s claim that courts have no power over targeted drone killings of American citizens overseas. Judge Rosemary M. Collyer of the United States District Court here was hearing the government’s request to dismiss a lawsuit filed by relatives of three Americans killed in two drone strikes in Yemen in 2011: Anwar al-Awlaki, the radical cleric who had joined Al Qaeda in the Arabian Peninsula; Mr. Awlaki’s 16-year-old son, Abdulrahman, who had no involvement in terrorism; and Samir Khan, a 30-year-old North Carolina man who had become a propagandist for the same Qaeda branch. Judge Collyer said she was “troubled” by the government’s assertion that it could kill American citizens it designated as dangerous, with no role for courts to review the decision. “Are you saying that a U.S. citizen targeted by the United States in a foreign country has no constitutional rights?” she asked Brian Hauck, a deputy assistant attorney general. “How broadly are you asserting the right of the United States to target an American citizen? Where is the limit to this?” She provided her own answer: “The limit is the courthouse door.” Courts show no signs of leaving detention policy to executive discretion Dehn 11 Assistant Professor, Department of Law, United States Military Academy; J.S.D. Candidate, Columbia University Law School. (John C, Spring, 2011, Temple Law Review, 83 Temp. L. Rev. 599, 35085 words, "THE COMMANDER-IN-CHIEF AND THE NECESSITIES OF WAR: A CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK.") Whatever the precise limits , there is no indication that the Court would leave everything to complete executive discretion or allow Congress to arbitrarily sanction extreme measures, such as torture or inhuman treatment. n377 It would seem that governmental necessity and judicial strict scrutiny are related in this context. All permit the derogation of rights only so far as justified by a clear, identifiable, and compelling public interest. n378 Then again, as Koh’s observations suggest, without a viable legal or political forum to vindicate those rights, their existence or preservation may depend entirely upon executive self-restraint. n379 Ironically, this condition was precisely what the Colonists sought to remedy by declaring independence, and what the Framers sought to avoid by separating national powers over war and the military. Ultimately, arguments relying on political question doctrine or Court deference should not be used to eliminate the Court as a plausible and desirable agent of action. Fisher 05 senior specialist in separation of powers with the Congressional Research Service, the Library of Congress (Louis, “Judicial Review of the War Power” Presidential Studies Quarterly 35.3, September 2005) A close examination of judicial rulings over the last two centuries reveals that the automatic association of war power with the political question category is a misconception. Not only did courts decide war power issues, they sometimes spoke against the authority of the president to venture in warmaking activities against the express will or the silence of Congress. The fact that some of the earliest of these decisions were written by justices who had been members of the Constitutional Convention or participated in state ratifying conventions lends additional weight to the importance of these early interpretations. Brecher supports court action for cyberattacks. Despite Brecher’s argument advocating an Executive Order for a covert framework, he still admits that judicial review matters and that the Constitutional issues deserve consideration. He might even favor the Court in an instance where “fiat” or hypothetical adoption is available. Brecher 12 (JD candidate, University of Michigan Law School (AaronP., 111 Mich. L. Rev. 423 “Cyberattacks and the Covert Action Statute: Toward a Domestic Legal Framework for Offensive Cyberoperations”) Though separation of powers analysis is normally applied as a tool for judicial scrutiny, whether a major cyberattack can be said to have been conducted with the blessing of both Congress and the president is of serious constitutional import. The fact that activities may not be subject to judicial review n143 makes it even more important that the two other major constitutional actors in the American system conduct themselves with their constitutional obligations in mind. Also, a careful understanding of how the separation of powers applies to a novel means of statecraft and warfare can contribute to the public understanding of the national constitutional ethos. n144 A cyberattack’s massive potential for unintended consequences demands a cautious constitutional approach to the conduct. The covert action statute serves this function by enabling the president to act with congressional approval. Courts has the ability to update the WPR to reach a resolution that maintains constitutional provisions Patera 12 First Lieutenant at United States Air Force and Judicial Law Clerk to the Honorable M. Jacqueline Regis at State of Minnesota (John, 33 Hamline J. Pub. L. & Pol'y 387, Spring 2012, “War Powers Resolution in the Age of Drone Warfare: How Drone Technology has Dramatically Reduced the Resolution's Effectiveness as a Curb on Executive Power”) The Resolution came into being during a time when there was strong popular support for curtailing unilateral action by the Executive Branch. There are, however, two factors that have dampened its effectiveness. First, scholars and jurists have argued that the Resolution is an unconstitutional exercise of legislative power. Second, commentators have questioned its effectiveness because it has yet to be judicially enforced. If the intent of the War Powers Resolution—“to ensure that Congress has a mechanism to ensure its concurrent participation in the decision to involve the Nation in armed conflict”—is enforced, than drone strikes would be included in the definition of action requiring consultation. yes, this is something Congress could very easily do (and Patera advocates legislation to update the WPR), but the Court could also accomplish the same goals in a number of different way, even pursuing angles outside the WPR and rooted more directly in the Constitution or previous precedent. The Supreme Court is the key war powers arbiter. The importance of the Youngstown decision, in particular Justice Jackson’s concurring opinion in the case, proves it. Dehn 11 Assistant Professor, Department of Law, United States Military Academy; J.S.D. Candidate, Columbia University Law School. (John C, Spring, 2011, Temple Law Review, 83 Temp. L. Rev. 599, 35085 words, "THE COMMANDER-IN-CHIEF AND THE NECESSITIES OF WAR: A CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK.") In spite of its status as only an element of a concurring opinion, Justice Jackson’s three-tiered analytical framework continues to dominate scholarship over the relative powers of Congress and the Executive in matters of war and foreign affairs. See Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 610-11 (1952) (exploring the limits of executive power under the Constitution, stating that it “is an inadmissibly narrow conception of American constitutional law to confine it to the words of the Constitution and to disregard the gloss which life has written upon them.”). The President possesses constitutional powers as the Commander in Chief. The Court determines whether particular actions taken by the President are within those constitutional powers. Justice Black, 1952 in Youngstown (Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 641 (1952) (Jackson, J., concurring) (commenting on the commander-in-chief power). BLACK, J., Opinion of the Court MR. JUSTICE BLACK delivered the opinion of the Court. We are asked to decide whether the President was acting within his constitutional power when he issued an order directing the Secretary of Commerce to take possession of and operate most of the Nation’s steel mills. The mill owners argue that the President’s order amounts to lawmaking, a legislative function which the Constitution has expressly confided to the Congress, and not to the President. The Government’s position is that the order was made on findings of the President that his action was necessary to avert a national catastrophe which would inevitably result from a stoppage of steel production, and that, in meeting this grave emergency, the President was acting within the aggregate of his constitutional powers as the Nation’s Chief Executive and the Commander in Chief of the Armed Forces of the United States. Court balancing is the most useful way to frame the question of war powers Barron & Lederman 08 Professor of Law at Harvard Law School & Associate Professor of Law at the Georgetown University Law Center (David J. and Martin S. "The Commander in Chief at the Lowest Ebb – Framing the Problem, Doctrine, and Original Understanding," 121 Harv. L. Rev. 689 (2008) Barron & Lederman I, supra note 15, at 726-31) The most useful way to frame the question is to draw important distinctions among the authorities that the Commander in Chief Clause conveys to the President – to identify the preclusive core, if any, of the President’s war powers and to distinguish it from the remaining, more “peripheral” Commander in Chief powers that are subject to statutory and treaty-based regulation. Courts produce social change through the symbolic impact on public opinion Tucker 95 Professor of Political Science at the University of Melbourne, D.F.B., The Rehnquist Court and Civil Rights, p35-36) One important issue is whether Rosenberg’s (and Dahl’s) ‘constrained court’ view overlooks the indirect impact that landmark decisions may have. What I have in mind is whether courts can act as some sort of catalyst to facilitate the mobilization of political forces for change. Perhaps they can influence outcomes by shaping the political agenda so that issues that would otherwise escape attention are brought into public focus. Perhaps important cases serve as symbols so that the members of social movements are prevented from despair and even inspired to increase their efforts to work for change. In a review of Rosenberg’s The Hollow Hope Malcolm Feeley suggests that judicial decisions do produce indirect effects of this kind.27 He wonders whether Rosenberg has overlooked the various and subtle ways that courts can raise expectations and, by offering a hope of victory motivate reformers. Certainly the cases that Rosenberg focuses on in his study (Brown v. Board of Education, Roe v. Wade, Mapp v. Ohio, Miranda v. Arizona and Baker v. Carr) do serve as important symbols in United States cultural life. A2: CRT takes out case solvency Pushing back against racism through action will succeed. Linking together the kinds of state-sponsored racism in World War II internment to the blatant Islamophobia we are witnessing today is one mechanism of pushing back. Ali 12, J.D., University of California, Berkeley (Yaser, August, 2012 “Shariah and Citizenship - How Islamophobia Is Creating a Second-Class Citizenry in America,” 100 Calif. L. Rev. 1027) At this crucial stage, where Islamophobia continues to strip away the citizenship of American Muslims, Justice Stone's powerful statement regarding the treatment of Japanese Americans in World War II serves as an important reminder: "Distinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry are by their very nature odious to a free people whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality." n254 While there is a concerted and institutionalized attempt to perpetuate those distinctions towards the Muslim community, there are also increasing opportunities and platforms to push back against this discrimination, just as past groups were able to do. Through such efforts, American Muslims will be able to regain equal citizenship and exercise, alongside their fellow citizens, "the rights of Americans as Americans." n255 Turn: CRT compounds conflation between Arabs and Muslims. CRT can be useful, but not for Arab Americans or Muslim Americans. Our advocacy is necessary for the application. Saloom 05, Attorney, Atlanta, GA, J.D. graduate, University of Georgia School of Law; M.A., Middle Eastern Studies, University of Chicago (Rachel “I Know You Are, But What Am I? Arab-American Experiences Through the Critical Race Theory Lens." Hamline Journal of Public Law & Policy, 27 Hamline J. Pub. L. & Pol'y 55) CRT contends that racism is "like a cancer that permeates the body ... despite a massive blitzkrieg, racism may persevere, spread, and even appear to be in remission for awhile, only to reappear in a more virulent form." n4 The term CRT encompasses a wide variety of scholarship and thought. Most CRT scholars, however, agree that race plays a role in the way the legal system operates. More broadly CRT views racism as "endemic to American life." n5 CRT theorists argue that racism is a "normal" part of American life and is entrenched in society. n6 Another tenet of CRT is that "race is not biologically determined." n7 Therefore, recognizing that race is socially constructed is very important to CRT scholars. This social construction of race is particularly vital to understanding the plight of Arab-Americans. Unfortunately, CRT scholarship has often overlooked Arab-Americans as a category of analysis. There may be many reasons for this, including how Arab-Americans are defined. There is much confusion surrounding the examination of race and Arab-Americans. This confusion is only compounded by the conflation of the terms Arab and Muslim. There is a popular misconception that all Arabs are Muslim and vice versa, but this is not true. In fact, only 12% of Muslims are Arabs, while 90% of [*58] Arabs are Muslims worldwide. n8 In the United States, however, a Zogby survey showed that only 23% of Arab-Americans were Muslim. n9 Their link is off, and their alternative is too generic. Yes, race plays a huge role in the treatment of Arab Americans, but it’s a particular form of whiteness that must evaluate specific context and history. Saloom 05, Attorney, Atlanta, GA, J.D. graduate, University of Georgia School of Law; M.A., Middle Eastern Studies, University of Chicago (Rachel “I Know You Are, But What Am I? Arab-American Experiences Through the Critical Race Theory Lens." Hamline Journal of Public Law & Policy, 27 Hamline J. Pub. L. & Pol'y 55) Arab American discrimination occurs long before 9/11 Under a CRT analysis, the examination of racism and stereotyping is paramount. Racism against Arab-Americans has a long history. Arab immigrants that were called Syrian were often discriminated against in a variety of ways. Janice Terry, professor of Middle Eastern history, in her study of Arab stereotyping defines stereotype as "a "mental package' in which a collection of traits or characteristics are combined to delineate or identify a group or a member of that group without reference to particular individual differences or complexities ... these "identifying characteristics' are half-truths which distort or obfuscate the full reality." n24In Birmingham, Alabama in the 1920s, a candidate for coroner handed out flyers that said, "They have disqualified the negro, an American citizen, from voting in the white primary. The Greek and Syrian should also be disqualified. Arab-Americans were also targets of the Ku Klux Klan because they were often identified as "colored." n26 Arab-Americans faced problems in the voting rights arena and were often disenfranchised in the South. n27 In cities where the Ku Klux Klan had power, these early Syrian immigrants were [*62] discriminated against because they were "colored, Catholic, and foreign." n28 I DON'T WANT THEIR VOTE. If I can't be elected by white men, I don't want the office." n25 Moreover, Our historical approach solves their race arguments and impacts. Because terrorist profiling of Arab Americans occurred long before 9/11—something we emphasize in our 1AC—our history can address their impacts. Saloom 05, Attorney, Atlanta, GA, J.D. graduate, University of Georgia School of Law; M.A., Middle Eastern Studies, University of Chicago (Rachel “I Know You Are, But What Am I? Arab-American Experiences Through the Critical Race Theory Lens." Hamline Journal of Public Law & Policy, 27 Hamline J. Pub. L. & Pol'y 55) A popular misconception is that the stereotyping of Arab-Americans is a post 9/11 phenomenon. The stereotyping of Arabs and Arab-Americans as terrorists, among other stereotypes, however, has occurred for years. One of the most important works that discusses Arab stereotyping is Edward Said's Orientalism, first published in 1978. Said's book demonstrates that post 9/11 stereotyping and racism is not a new phenomenon. Said argues that the Orient is viewed as the "other" as compared to the West. The Western attitude toward Arabs is imbued with stereotypical tendencies. Said states that "the web of racism, cultural stereotypes, political imperialism, dehumanizing ideology holding in the Arab or the Muslim is very strong indeed." n29 In the South in the 1950s, many Arabs were often subjected to racism and were not allowed into the facilities that were exclusively white. n30 Racism against Arab-Americans continued to be a problem in the United States. Terms such as "camel jockey" and "sand nigger" were used to describe Arab-Americans. n31 Arab-Americans are often viewed as being racially distinct and different from dominant white culture. n32 The Merriam-Webster Thesaurus in 1978 defined synonyms of Arab as "vagabond," "peddler," "bum," derelict," and "tramp." n33 Jack Shaheen, an expert on the media and the Middle [*63] East, has described stereotypes of Arabs as "billionaires, bombers, or belly dancers--villains of choice." n34Another popular theme is that Arabs as a group become even more racialized during crisis. Joanna Kadi eloquently recounts this phenomenon: As Arabs, like other people of color in this racist society, our race is simultaneously emphasized and ignored. For long periods of time no one can remember that Arabs even exist ... Of course, this forgetfulness changes once there is another "crisis' in the Middle East... During crises, Arabs can be reassured we exist as a distinct racial group. We will remember it, in the dark of night and the light of day. We will feel the effects of the social construction of "the Arabs' that has cast us as enemy, other, fanatical terrorist, crazy Muslim. n35 Court action against racism that targets Muslims can solve. Applying anti-discrimination laws to racism experienced by Muslims could be a huge step forward in terms of color consciousness and the larger struggle against racism. Ibrahim 09 civil rights attorney with the lawfirm of Hadsell Stormer Keeny Richardson & Renick. She is also an alumna of the UCLA School of Law Critical Race Studies Program (Nagwa, The Origins of Muslim Racialization in U.S. Law, 7 UCLA J. ISLAMIC & NEAR E.L. 121, 121 (2008/09) First, the Court recognizes that race is not fixed but ever changing and as such Jews, while now considered white, were at a particular moment in history not white and therefore a racial "other." Second the Court, for the purposes of anti-discrimination law, is implicitly expanding the notion of immutability as it relates to race through recognition of Jews, a religious group, as being once a racial "other." This precedent can be used to argue that the Court, while recognizing that race is not fixed, has expanded the definition of racial discrimination, to include discrimination based in part on religious differences. This expanded definition of race that includes religious differences should equally be applied to Muslims and Muslim-looking peoples employing antidiscrimination laws including the Equal Protection Clause to fight against profiling by the government and private perpetrators. This is especially true because, as illustrated, Muslims have experienced a history of societal discrimination, a history of political powerlessness, status as a discrete and insular minority, and characteristics of immutability based on religious differences from the dominant Christian majority. n108 Achieving this step of expanding the definition of race to include characteristics beyond just phenotype by having the courts recognize Muslims' and Muslim-looking peoples' claim of racial discrimination on the basis of religious or perceived religious differences would have a huge impact, not just in protecting the rights of Muslims, but also in helping establish more expansive, inclusive, race-conscious remedies for other groups of color. Equal protection can be broadened to help protect Muslims against racist actions by the government Ibrahim 09 civil rights attorney with the lawfirm of Hadsell Stormer Keeny Richardson & Renick. She is also an alumna of the UCLA School of Law Critical Race Studies Program (Nagwa, The Origins of Muslim Racialization in U.S. Law, 7 UCLA J. ISLAMIC & NEAR E.L. 121, 121 (2008/09) However, in this Section, to illustrate this point, I will focus exclusively on U.S. antidiscrimination laws. The exercise of religious freedom, under the Free Exercise Clause, is so fundamental a right that government attempts to deny that right are subjected to the highest form of scrutiny by the courts. n97 However, the Free Exercise Clause, while important, does not address the full scope of what is happening toMuslims and Muslim-looking peoples for it only protects against the denial of a religious group's right to practice. Moreover, religious minorities, such as Muslims, are much less successful in winning Free Exercise claims in court. n98 The Equal Protection Clause, as opposed to the Free Exercise Clause, more adequately addresses the injustice occurring against Muslims and Muslim-looking peoples, who are being discriminated against on the basis of religious or perceived religious identity. However, while one can bring a claim under the Equal Protection Clause for discrimination based on religious group identity, such claims are scarce and have been largely unsuccessful. n99 Moreover, the profiling of Muslims is occurring on the basis of religious conduct and the Equal Protection Doctrine does not easily support this type of religious discrimination claim, even if the conduct defines or is thought to define group identity. n100 However, expanding the Equal Protection Clause to protect Muslims and Muslimlooking peoples against racial discrimination on the basis of religious differences might more readily subject government profiling of Muslims and Muslim-looking peoples to greater skepticism by the judiciary. Furthermore this expanded definition of racial discrimination would more accurately address the type of racial subordination occurring today. The Equal Protection Clause prohibits the state from discriminating based on race, national origin, alienage, or religious affiliation because these are suspect classifications (i.e., laws that categorize on the basis of one of these protected categories are deserving of the greatest judicial scrutiny.) n101 What makes a classification suspect is contingent upon a group's history of being subjected to societal discrimination, its history of political powerlessness, the extent to which it is a discreet and insular minority, and the immutability of the characteristic being classified. n102 The categories, which satisfy the immutability criteria, are race and national origin. As such, race is still largely defined by phenotype despite the fact that the construction of racial identities involves attaching social meaning to physical as well as linguistic, religious and cultural differences. n103Therefore, in order to more fully address issues of race, the immutability criteria should be interpreted to include the historical and social processes that attach immutability to attributes, whether or not such attributes are in fact immutable. For example, skin color is an immutable characteristic whereas one's religious affiliations are perceived, although not always, as a choice. However, as demonstrated with Muslims in the U.S. both historically and currently, social meanings of inferiority can be attached to both skin color and religious identity, which then translates into legal initiatives that deny civil and human rights to those who possess or are perceived to possess "innate, inferior attributes."n104 This interpretation of immutability to include religious differences that are treated as innate inferior attributes more accurately reflects the complexities of race, racial formation and racial discrimination in the United States today. For example, as explained by Margaret Chon and Donna E. Arzt in Walking While Muslim, "when religion is factored into 'race,' it is easier to see that the profile of Muslims and Muslim-looking peoples expands far beyond the young Middle-Eastern looking male." n105 This expanded definition of race to include various intersections such as phenotype and religious identity is necessary to establish anti-discrimination laws that are more relevant and effective. Legal precedent supports—broadening Equal Protection can solve Ibrahim 09 civil rights attorney with the lawfirm of Hadsell Stormer Keeny Richardson & Renick. She is also an alumna of the UCLA School of Law Critical Race Studies Program (Nagwa, The Origins of Muslim Racialization in U.S. Law, 7 UCLA J. ISLAMIC & NEAR E.L. 121, 121 (2008/09) Additionally there is legal precedent that supports a more broadened interpretation of race and anti-discrimination law. In the 1987 Supreme Court case, Shaare Tefila Congregation v. Cobb, a synagogue was painted with anti-Semitic slogans, phrases, and symbols. Petitioners brought suit in federal district court, alleging that the desecration by respondents amounted to racial discrimination in violation of 42 U.S.C § 1982. The district court dismissed petitioners's claim, and the court of appeals affirmed, arguing that [*154] Jews cannot make a racial discrimination claim under § 1982. However, the Supreme Court reversed the decision, holding that Jews can state a § 1982 claim of racial discrimination since they "were among the peoples considered to be distinct races and hence within the protection of the statute at the time it was passed."n106 Justice White, delivering the opinion of the Court, states: We agree with petitioners, however, that the Court of Appeals erred in holding that Jews cannot state a § 1982 claim against other white defendants. That view rested on the notion that because Jews today are not thought to be members of a separate race, they cannot make out a claim of racial discrimination within the meaning of § 1982. That construction of the section we have today rejected in Saint Francis College v. Al-Khazraji. Our opinion in that case observed that definitions of race when § 1982 was passed were not the same as they are today and concluded that the section was "intended to protect from discrimination identifiable classes of persons who are subjected to intentional discrimination solely because of their ancestry or ethnic characteristics." As Saint Francis makes clear, the question before us is not whether Jews are considered to be a separate race by today's standards, but whether, at the time § 1982 was adopted, Jews constituted a group of people that Congress intended to protect. It is evident from the legislative history of the section reviewed in Saint Francis College, a review that we need not repeat here, that Jews and Arabs were among the peoples then considered to be distinct races, and hence within the protection of the statute. Jews are not foreclosed from stating a cause of action against other members of what today is considered to be a part of the Caucasian race. n107 AT: CRT framework good Advocating CRT theory rather than plan action guarantees academic failure Ladson-Billings 99 Professor of Education at the University of Wisconsin-Madison (Gloria, Race is…Race isn’t, Pg. 26-27) It is the pattern in educational research for a new idea or innovation to take hold and proliferate. Sometimes an idea takes a while to take root, but once it does, most likely its creators lose control of the idea. Consider what happened with the notion of cooperative learning. When Cohen and Roper (1972) proposed cooperative classroom structures to equalize the status of White and African American students, their work held great promise for helping teachers to develop curricular and instructional strategies for improving the academic performance of all children in desegregated classrooms. However, somehow their findings got distilled into day-long workshops and five-step lesson plans. School systems throughout the United States were adopting cooperative learning without any thought to improving the performance of children of color. A similar transmutation of theory is occurring in the area of multicultural education. Although scholars such as James Banks, Carl Grant, and Geneva Gay7 began on a scholarly path designed to change schools as institutions so that students might be prepared to reconstruct the society, in its current practice iteration, multicultural education is but a shadow of its conceptual self. Rather than engage students in provocative thinking about the contradictions of U.s. ideals and lived realities, teachers often find themselves encouraging students to sing "ethnic" songs, eat ethnic foods, and do ethnic dances. Consistently, manifestations of multicultural education in the classroom are superficial and trivial "celebrations of diversity." What, then, might happen to CRT in the hands of educational researchers and school personnel? Well, to be honest, like Lani Guinier, I doubt if it will go very far into the mainstream. Rather, CRT in education is likely to become the "darling" of the radical left, continue to generate scholarly papers and debate, and never penetrate the classrooms and daily experiences of students of color. But, students of color, their families, and their communities cannot afford the luxury of CRT scholars' ruminations any more than they could afford those of critical and postmodern theorists, where the ideas are laudable but the practice leaves much to be desired. Critical race theory in critical legal studies abuses the identity of marginalized groups. It is a form of tokenism, in order to gain status in the academia which feeds the elitism Goodrich 93 professor of law at the University of London Peter, University of London Professor of Law, “Sleeping with the Enemy”, New York Law Journal ,May, http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/nylr68&div=23&g_sent=1&collection=journals In an empirical sense, CLS has nothing to do with legal education, with the teaching practice of legal scholars, and it has only the most marginal of relations to the academic discipline of law, if that discipline is defined in doctrinal or pedagogic terms. Instead, it obeys a mediological law: "For the media, the objective world-the thing there is something to speak of-is what the other media are saying. Be it hell or heaven, from now on we are going to have to live in this haunted hall where mirrors 3 1 reflect mirrors and shadows chase shadows." The radicalism of American CLS does not appear to extend to the lives of its practitioners. It does not threaten the institutional safety, tenured security, economic comfort, or frequently elite status of the critics. Were its product not so frequently intellectually tawdry, it would be tempting to regard the movement as a form of designer chic within the legal academy, an imported fashion, the latest in prepackaging "from the shelf to it can simply and cynically be argued that legal academics in America long ago were bought out by the size of their professional salaries, that they suffer "an enlightened false consciousness," a you" without need for alteration. At one level, thoroughgoing cynicism or modem form of "unhappy consciousness." '32 Such unhappy consciousness is a species of pseudo-critique in which critical stances are subordinated to professional roles, the immediate politics of the institution to totalizing theories of the particular, and conflicts of value in the workplace to the exigencies of privatized therapies which attempt to order happiness, goodrelations with colleagues, or at least a realistic deference to the mecha- nisms of institutional advancement. Let us be more specific as to the features of the counter-revolution. The American law professor is too well paid to be politically committed, too status conscious to be intellectually engaged, and too insular-too bound to the parochial and monolingual culture of the law review-to be scholarly. This state of affairs is the legacy of mass legal culture, of the stupefaction which passes for legal education and at best produces a blend of intellectual naivety and doomed political enthusiasm. Its history appears from the outside to have been one of therapeutic self-confir- mation hiding behind a legitimizing romanticism critique is in pragmatic terms no more and no less than the essentially liberal yet nonetheless imperialistic desire to embrace and to include any stranger, any other, any nomad, any political infant, or any woman who can plausibly represent an outside within the academy . These, however, are the tokens of radical- ism, the coinage of hubris, whereby an inauthentic and uneasy bureaucratic elite salvages its which views political radicalism as a species of patronage: conscience by buying in representatives of re- pressed, marginalized, or disadvantaged groups. More than that, however, the American translation of European so- cial theory-of the "new philosophies" and the "new politics"-seems predicated upon the belief that by supporting the marginal, the foreign, the peripheral, or the outsider, the intellectual within the institution be- comes, presumably by projection, marginal or foreign-and so ipso facto politically radical himself. It is as if the greatest injustice known to the world were the indignity of being fired from Yale, refused tenure at Harvard, or barred from promotion at Stanford or Pennsylvania. Critical race theory in critical legal studies perpetuates the problems Goodrich 93 professor of law at the University of London Peter, University of London Professor of Law, “Sleeping with the Enemy”, New York Law Journal ,May, http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/nylr68&div=23&g_sent=1&collection=journals Whatever the self-perception of CLS in America, whether marginal or central to the academy, its most striking attribute from a sociological perspective is its media status and international profile. In superficially descriptive terms, CLS has had all the glamour of schism within the Vat- ican, dissent amongst the synod, or Sister Teresa amongst the Spanish nuns. It also has had the high visibility of foreign fashion, of being the importer of European trends, new vocabularies, and a commitment to political culture which for once aspires to extend beyond the cloisters of the legal academy. To the extent that the movement represents an intel- lectual departure from the earlier theory of Legal Realism, it does so not least by virtue of its neoscholasticism, its return to the philosophical tradition, and its importation of European social theory. 16 While copious reference to the translated works of continental philosophy are no guarantee of any substantial theoretical genealogy,1 7 they do have the elite function of identifying a community and of legitimating an esoteric marginality in relation to traditional doctrinal scholarship. In terms of the sociology of intellectuals, however, there is an undoubted irony in the opposition between the critics' claim to an outsider status, to a leftist marginality, and the elite hubris or kudos of the repeated invocation of continental theory. CLS as an imported phenomenon, as a politics of intellectual credentials, also finds itself bound to the patronage of the Ivy League law schools and the media d6cor that those schools attract. The defining criterion of high intellectual culture in mediatic terms is simply the "ability to gain access to the means of mass communication," ' 8 and that ability, more than anything else, defines the power of the elite institutions. One interpretation of this phenomenon is that the postmodern path to intellectual success, star status, and political preferment no longer lies exclusively in the traditional route through the academic institution. CLS may represent the first moment of an intellectual "mediology" within the legal academy. 19 It would be in one sense a method of bypassing the established institutional route to preferment, while in a more substantial sense it would reflect the changed political and technical context of intellectual work. Empirical studies of European intellectual cul- ture indicate that the social space of intellectual success and of international recognition does not stem from institutional academic conformity but rather from marginal disciplines and from the polemical work of the institutional outsider-the researcher or writer who defines her social identity in terms of writing rather than in terms of academic commitment or institutional service. 2 0 While the American media may still reserve the full focus of publicity for intellectuals associated with the highest status schools, the role and transhumant career of the media intellectual is an established fact of an electronic culture of "paratexts," 21 graphic simulations, and liquid crystal transmission. The media intellectual is frequently presented as a figure of in- authenticity, one who is by nature immoral. The move from text to paratext, from the linearity of script to the nodal constellation of video text, is viewed ethically as a move from a world of reference to a world of simulation, from substance to fantasy, from signs that signal something to signs that signal nothing beyond themselves: "a degree xerox of cul- ture." '22 The irony to be observed in the career patterns or trajectories confirm the mediological proposition that there is a massive overproduction of texts and, in more technological contexts, of signs. While this irony has been pointed out in criticisms of the self-referential present context not that of the isessentially puritanical or properly Protestant rejection of images and of the intellectual imaginary, but rather that culture of the contemporary university and the academicization or cooptation of the Left, it has been encountered also in criticisms of the style and jargon of CLS. The new legal intellectuals, it is argued, write for themselves in an esoteric and exclusionary rhetoric which circulates internally within the academy and signifies nothing much more than the fact of having been published. Such publication confers a certain symbolic credit within the institution, but it has no wider significance beyond creating a class of nouveau riche intellectuals whose publications represent a constant aspiration toward upward mobility. There is a further significance to the critical aspirations of the more visible or prominent of the movement 23 scholars, those patrons, merchants, and middlemen of the new legal art. Without entering the debate on the politics of rhetoric or the institutional consequences of the reproductive function of scholarship, its institution of an order of succession, is predicated upon production. In mediological terms, the positivity of CLS must be viewed in terms of its literary product, in terms of its material output and the institutional consequences of its graphematic substance, its writing. Here the politics of CLS becomes more opaque. The claim to being "a political location," "subversive," "oppositional," or simply leftist does not necessarily carry to the alternately febrile and flippant products of its harbingers. Aside from an early and now dated Marxist sociology of law which has been largely legal academic style, it is still appropriate to point out that abandoned and which itself was imported, the defining feature of the critics arguably has been a naive and somewhat bowdlerized translation of continental social the literature has only a limited audience which is in the legal academy itself. Its success was its failure, its external visibility was its strongest form of internal secession, and its text was its context. More theory into an American legal idiom. 2 6 One consequence has been that interestingly and ironically, however, a literature bent upon importation and translation across languages, continents, and jurisdictions has only an indirect relation to the immediate politics of the institution or practice of law. Such may yet, however, be 2 7the critics' greatest strength: not only does the repressed return, but those that are either literally or figuratively expelled can use the rupture of institutional place as the most striking of emblems of injustice and as the strongest of ethical grounds for the call to change. Although this opportunity is certainly one aspect of the critical movement's biography, it is not yet a defining feature of its politics. In a bureaucratic age, the scholar is by profession a teacher. What is striking about the literature of critique is its almost complete absence of relation to teaching practice and to the immediate politics of the institution which it otherwise supports and publicizes. CLS could be termed "critique without copula" in that offers an order of succession of academics, a transmission of a self-referential and exclusory form of symbolic capital, which refers by way of only the most distant signals to the lifeworld of the legal pedagogue. If CLS purportedly offers a local poli- tics, it it is not at all clear what or where that locale is; if it offers a "relational politics," it is equally hard to discern to what or with whom that relationship is intended. 29 The field would seem to be divided at best between heterotopias of literature and difference on the one hand, and the moralism of the outsider seeking domicile on the other. While both projects may well have an ethical value, such value or ethics is not yet connected to the life or practice of the academic institution. The most striking facet of American CLS is its failure to penetrate, subvert, or de- viate from the established norms of legal educational practice. With only occasional exceptions 30 -and even these exceptions have not called for substantial changes in the syllabus or the classificatory grid of educational practice-the casebook and the Socratic method reign supreme.