Risk, Reasonableness, and Rationality Robin Gregory Decision Research, University of Victoria and UBC Office address: Galiano Island, B.C. Canada Tel: 250-539-5701 E-mail: rgregory@interchange.ubc.ca Presentation to Risk & Rationality Conference Queen’s College, Cambridge March 29-31, 2007 Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 1 Risk, Reasonableness, and Rationality Introduction: Rationality vs. reasonableness Public engagement : Structured decision making Example 1: Treating interface fires Example 2: Facing taboo trade-offs Example 3: Recognizing invisible values Discussion: What should be done? Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 2 Risk, Reasonableness, and Rationality: Introduction Management of risks is a central concern of society Highly skilled people – risk managers, scientists, elected officials – view their job as helping citizens to make / support more rational choices across competing riskreduction & mitigation possibilities. In 1970’s, work of Paul Slovic, Sarah Lichtenstein, & Baruch Fishchhoff – my Decision Research colleagues -instrumental in initiating a dialogue about the standard of rationality that guides people’s perceptions of risk. Expanded set of factors considered as contributors to risk: voluntariness of exposure, familiarity, dread. Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 3 Risk, Reasonableness, and Rationality: Introduction How might rational risk choices be defined? Ignoring philosophical debates, I suggest three criteria: Concern for risk management is higher among those experiencing adverse consequences People think carefully about consequential risk topics and seek out information to become better informed The factual base for estimating risk impacts is repeatable and reflects observations based in “good science” In my experience, these minimum criteria are repeatedly violated. What does this mean? Friday, March 30, 2007 People are irrational - no There are other standards besides rationality - yes Risk managers and policies need to reflect more than just rational / cognitive responses to risk - yes UK Cambridge presentation 4 Risk and rationality: Introduction In this talk, I will focus on public engagement as input to risk managers and decision makers Context: Risk problems involving multiple dimensions: economic, social, environmental, cultural, health & safety Participants: Diverse stakeholders (public, government, industry, academics, interest groups, indigenous populations) Management dilemma: Increases on one dimension (protection of biodiversity, fewer illnesses ) mean decreases on another (fewer jobs, higher costs) Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 5 Risk and rationality: Introduction to Structured Decision Making One useful approach for public engagement in risk management: Structured decision making Based in insights from decision analysis and behavioral decision theory Widely used in stakeholder deliberations when problems are complex and involve tough choices across multiple dimensions of value Goal is insight for decision makers: show pros and cons of risk management alternatives Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 6 Steps in a structured decision making approach Define Problem 1 2 Define Issues, Objectives & Measures 3 Develop Alternatives 4 Estimate Consequences 5 Make Trade-Offs and Select 6 Implement and Monitor Iterate as required Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 7 Terminology Objectives The things that matter in the decision Performance Measures (or attributes) The specific information used to report the consequences of the alternatives on the objectives Alternatives (or options) The means of achieving the objectives Trade-offs (or balancing across objectives) Differences in performance among objectives; the key to understanding tough choices that decision makers have to make Constructed preferences The recognition that for many policy options, we don’t really know what the components are or how we feel. So we construct our situation-dependent preferences in relation to cues. Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 8 Example: Use of SDM to help address management of Cultus Lake sockeye (with G. Long, Compass Resource Mgt) Worked with multi-stakeholder committee (approx. 20 people) over 1 month period (April, 2006) – but issues contentious for over a decade! Key risk tradeoff: Environmental protection (of endangered stocks) vs. Economic (commercial fishing revenues) Multiple interests: High visibility species, High importance to Conservation (COSEWIC listed) Commercial fishers, and First Nations Data quality variable (and controversial) Multiple management options (exploitation rate, captive breeding, predator removal) but uncertainty about consequences of actions Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 9 SDM Cultus Sub-committee Objectives & Performance Measures Sockeye conservation Probability of meeting Recovery Plan objectives 1 and 2 Returns in years 2010 and average of 2016-19 Probability of extirpation by 2036 % Enhanced in 2010 and average of 2016-19 Costs Total costs over 12 years, levelized No cost allocation attempted Catch Traditional commercial catch Commercial TAC available upstream of Vedder Total First Nations FSC Jobs Employment opportunities directly related to enhancement and freshwater projects Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 10 SDM Cultus Sub-committee Alternatives Alternatives created by assembling ‘blocks’ of options: Cultus Exploitation Rate % Lates (Upstream) Exploitation Rate % Enhancement options Freshwater projects options (Note: these included those factors considered to be most important; fine tuning to occur at a later time) Make use of strategy tables to encourage creative thinking. Two examples: Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 11 Building Alternatives – A Strategy Table Alternative 1: “Status Quo 2005” Cultus Exp Rate Lates Harvest Differential Location Enhancement FW Projects 5 0, As Cultus SQ – Downstream Only None None 10-12 (2005) 10 Mixed Current: Captive Brood Current Milfoil 20 20 UpRiver (Vedder) Current Ongoing Moderate Milfoil 30 30 Double Current Smolt Full Milfoil 40 Unconstrained Max Enhancement Current Pikeminnow (<5%) Ongoing dbl current cap Moderate Pikeminnow (520%) Full Pikeminnow (+20%) Hire Stewardship Coordinator Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 12 Building Alternatives – A Strategy Table Alternative 6: “Spread the Pain 2” Cultus Exp Rate Lates Harvest Differential Location Enhancement FW Projects 5 0, As Cultus SQ – Downstream Only None None 10-12 (2005) 10 Mixed Current: Captive Brood Current Milfoil 20 20 UpRiver (Vedder) Current Ongoing Moderate Milfoil 30 30 Double Current Smolt Full Milfoil 40 Unconstrained Max Enhancement Current Pikeminnow (<5%) Ongoing dbl current cap Moderate Pikeminnow (520%) Full Pikeminnow (+20%) Hire Stewardship Coordinator Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 13 SDM Cultus Sub-committee Alternatives Exploration of alternatives through iterative SDM process: creation, analysis, elimination Step 1 created 6 alternatives Step 2 Reviewed these 6 and created 3 more Step 3 reviewed all 9, eliminated 6 because they were dominated (others the same or better on objs) agreed on several key components for all altsf Focused on one, favoured alternative and created 6 new simpler variations Use of VISTA (G. Long): Displays objectives & alternatives in consequence matrices, highlighting tradeoffs (pros and cons) Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 14 SDM Cultus Sub-committee Trade-Off Analysis Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 15 Cultus Lake: SDM trade-off analysis Participants examined how well different alternatives “satisfied” the objectives Recognition that some objectives are easily & cheaply met – common sense to retain these “low-hanging fruit” in all alternatives Recognition of need to simplify the decision problem through elimination of relevant objectives and alternatives. Do this via exploration of Friday, March 30, 2007 Redundancy: where performance measures do not vary across alternatives Dominance: where one alternative is better than or equal to all (or, by collective agreement, nearly all) aspects of another UK Cambridge presentation 16 SDM Cultus Sub-committee Trade-Off Analysis Three alternatives remained at the end of this process: Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 17 Establish/communicate areas of agreement and disagreement One alternative favoured by group (8) Agreement on common features: Full predator-removal program Full habitat-improvement program Employ habitat stewardship coordinator Bound & deliberate on remaining issues: Degree of enhancement (100-150k) Exploitation rate (20% - 40%) Provide information on areas of agreement and disagreement to decision makers, also provide process recommendations Current status: discussions continuing !!! Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 18 Risk and rationality: SDM and insights SDM / risk engagement assumes there is a problem to be addressed, that it can be characterized in terms of values and measurable attributes, and that people’s preferences for management options will reflect their values. New research in behavioral decision making suggests otherwise: Friday, March 30, 2007 The role of emotions (pre-cognitive) (Damasio & Loewenstein & Hsee) The importance of affect (judgements of good and bad) (Slovic & Peters) The role of judgemental heuristics (Kahenman & Tversky, Thaler & Knetsch) UK Cambridge presentation 19 Risk v. reasonableness: Role of affect Four roles of affect (Peters, 2006) As Information: feelings act as information to guide the judgment or decision process As a spotlight: focusing us on different information (e.g., numerical cues) As motivator: we can take action or devote more attention to aspects of tasks As common currency: facilitates the comparison of unlike options Affect is thus an active component in the construction of preferences: Friday, March 30, 2007 conditions more delayed cognitive responses works in parallel with cognition UK Cambridge presentation 20 Rationality v. reasonableness: Examples This tension between affect and cognition is a challenge for decision aiding approaches that seek to assist in the development of risk policies through public engagement (prescriptive) Three examples: Friday, March 30, 2007 Interface fires (public engagement) - Canada Facing taboo choices (experimental) – US Recognizing invisible values (NSF, science and local / aboriginal knowledge) – Canada, US, Thailand, New Zealand UK Cambridge presentation 21 Example 1: Interface forest fires -- the role of emotions (with Joe Arvai) Context: public groups and surveys in aftermath of severe forest fires in western Canada Goal: aid risk managers in making fire management decisions (fuels, “speed bumps,” evacuation plans, replanting, harvest timing, equipment) Analysis: Friday, March 30, 2007 starting point was structured dialogue with stakeholders, asking: What do you think are key sources of risk? What might be done to reduce risks? UK Cambridge presentation 22 Risk and rationality: Interface fires Factual result: Most high risk areas remain so, even after burning. In some cases, risks increase. Expected finding: Wake-up call people in high-risk fire areas, having already experienced losses, will seek added protection & risk reduction (e.g., US after 9/11) Actual result: Letdown people in high-risk areas feel safer – the low-probability event already has happened, and “lightning doesn’t strike twice in the same place.” Source: Arvai, Gregory et al. 2006. Letdowns, wake-up calls, and constructed preferences: People’s responses to wildfire risks. Journal of Forestry 104: 173-181. Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 23 Risk and rationality: Interface fires Post exposure wake-up call vs. post-exposure letdown Kelowna SURVEY ITEM Vernon P X SE X SE 1. Calm vs. Upset (1=very upset, 7=very calm) 2.80 0.16 2.62 0.26 ns 2. Safe vs. At Risk (1=very much at risk, 7=very safe) 3.58 0.25 2.62 0.30 0.05 3. Confident vs., Unconfident (1=not at all confident, 7=very confident) 3.51 0.22 2.86 0.27 0.05 4. Optimistic vs. Pessimistic (1=very pessimistic, 7=very optimistic) 5.67 0.21 4.08 0.32 <0.0001 5. At Ease vs. Worried (1=very worried, 7=very at ease) 3.80 0.24 2.68 0.22 0.001 6. Level of Concern about Future Fires (1=low, 7=extreme) 5.51 0.19 6.16 0.19 0.05 7. Level of Motivation (1=low, 7=high) 4.89 0.21 6.11 0.20 <0.0001 Homeowners’ self-ratings of affect (items 1-5; midpoint = “neutral” in all cases), and levels of concern and motivation in an exposed (Kelowna) and unexposed community (Vernon). Responses were provided on seven-point Likert scales. Comparisons between the two samples were made using a 2-sample t-test. Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 24 Risk and Rationality: Interface Fires Practical implications of affective response Little demand for risk mitigation in many high-risk communities – people feel more safe than they really are Homeowners in high-risk areas not willing to undertake risk mitigation – not at threshold of risk identification High level of trust (unfounded) in protection efforts Emphasis on context & history-specific construction of preferences for management actions: what? and who? Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 25 Example 2: Facing taboo choices (with J. Irwin and S. Lichtenstein) Context: some decision situations are so difficult or repugnant that people dislike or refuse to make a choice. Literature refers to these as “taboo” choices (Tetlock), “protected values” (Baron), or “protest votes”’ (CVM) From standpoint of SDM / DA, it’s important to distinguish choices that are difficult or confusing – provide help? -- from those that truly are taboo – respect (and leave alone?). Source: S. Lichtenstein, R. Gregory, J. Irwin. What’s Bad is Easy: Taboo Values, Affect, and Cognition. Ms. under editorial review. Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 26 Risk and rationality: facing taboo choices as part of public engagement Examples: Do not eat foods containing modified genes Do not make choices that will increase risks to one’s own children Do not jail citizens on basis of DNA profiling Characteristics of such values: Friday, March 30, 2007 Quantity insensitivity: 10 deaths = 20 Agent relativity: it matters who makes the TO Moral obligation: a social, as well as personal, reference (effects beyond the individual) UK Cambridge presentation 27 Risk and rationality: Taboo choices Study goals: distinguish mere disapproval from protest and from taboo values understand reasons for disapproval develop rules for public engagement: when to probe or educate vs. when to leave alone Study design: 22 brief scenarios, covering range of issues. Ex: Cut old-growth trees to assist in development of new drugs Transplant organs from patients in deep coma to help otherwise terminal patients. 16 reasons, both affective (this plan disgusts me) and cognitive (this plan is complex) Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 28 Risk and rationality: Taboo choices Note U-shape of figure: scenarios judged most difficult to think about are intermediate in affect, whereas scenarios judged lowest and highest in affect are judged easy to think about. Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 29 Risk and rationality: Taboo choices The worst and the best scenarios are the easiest to think about. Thus it may be difficult to get people to accept assistance in thinking through tough decisions: What’s bad is easy! Leads to polarization as part of engagement. Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 30 Example 3: Recognizing invisible values (with L. Failing, M. Harstone, N Turner, T. Satterfield) Risk management choices should reflect the “best available knowledge” – few would disagree But in the context of public deliberations about risks, What does this mean? Typically, three sources of knowledge: Science (technical) Community (local) Aboriginal (indigenous – First Nations / First Peoples) Source: L. Failing, R. Gregory, M. Harstone. Integrating Science and Local Knowledge in Environmental Risk Management: A DecisionFocused Approach. Ecological Economics. (In press) Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 31 Recognizing invisible values – the limitations of science Typical link is from knowledge to facts: a “rational” approach to identifying risk consequences leads to the examination of factual evidence. But this assumption may be too limiting: Friday, March 30, 2007 Knowledge of local communities includes concerns such as pride, integrity, lifestyle Knowledge of Aboriginal communities includes spiritual and ceremonial concerns, also impacts on ancestors Access to knowledge and values remains closed until basic level of trust is established UK Cambridge presentation 32 Recognizing invisible values-- the limitations of science Effective risk management thus must also look to values as a source of knowledge. In some cases, key impacts may be unobservable by “neutral” participants. Examples: In Alaska: impacts of oil/gas exploration on visible walrus populations vs. “Great” walrus In British Columbia, impacts of development on grizzly bear populations vs. “Spirit” bears In New Zealand, impacts of GMO foods on Maori culture (T. Satterfield) In Thailand, impacts of development on “spirits” of forest and on “ghosts” of historical inhabitants Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 33 Invisible values: the limitations of science Practical implications for risk engagement Requires expansion of measures of value in assessing risks. Food contamination (GMOs) – health impacts, also spiritual, ceremonial, social relations impacts Brings focus to affective and emotional considerations: worry, shame, fear, reverence Brings focus to constructed preferences / TOs Leads to questions about tradeoffs: cultural survival, transmission of knowledge across generations Leads to questions about elicitation: how to conduct “public” engagement with Elders Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 34 Rationality v. Reasonableness in Risk Management: What should be done? Issues of fact are typically resolvable: new studies, more deliberation, better models Issues of value are usually not resolvable: no reason to expect that values will align Usual tools – rational, decompositional, analytical – may not work well in contexts where emotions and culture underlie risk exposure and risk management choices This leaves those of us working on public engagement in risk management with several (wonderful & perplexing) challenges Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 35 Challenge 1: Developing useful performance measures / attributes Best measures of risk are natural, easily understood: e.g. lives, dollars, kilometers. But often need to use casespecific “constructed” measures: ecological health Inter-generational knowledge transmission degree of cultural or lifestyle change worry or shame or fear How can different measures best be used to capture dimensions of value without overstepping limitations of analysis (compartmentalization)? What are criteria for distinguishing successful from inappropriate measures / attributes? Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 36 Challenge 2: Public engagement in highly affective situations “Rational” risk management may make sense to experts but not to stakeholders: don’t want too little risk reduction: initiatives overturned by post-exposure letdown don’t want too much risk reduction: initiatives inflated by affective worry or fear Reasonable suggestions: Friday, March 30, 2007 Employ affect in risk communication (markers) Use non-traditional measures of risk Use risk language of local participants Address affective issues as prelude to risk reduction Recognize influence of affect on other judgements (e.g., assessment of probabilities & consequences) UK Cambridge presentation 37 Challenge 3: Applying RA or SDM techniques in other cultures Engagement need to reflect culturally “reasonable” tools of analysis – stories, qualitative analyses, narrative Engagement needs to be flexible Friday, March 30, 2007 Where cultural worldviews are more holistic Where spiritual values are more important Where trust in “outside” experts is missing Where key tradeoffs include invisible beings Where stakeholder expression of values is unusual (taboo to speak to outsiders) Where key populations are marginalized or unapproachable (thus speaking out is unsafe) UK Cambridge presentation 38 Risk, Rationality and Reasonableness: Conclusions Reasonable risk tradeoffs are informed by both rationality and emotion / affect Preferences for risk management options will be informed by culture and values as well as by factual knowledge – science plus community/local knowledge Structured engagement methods need to work with expanded set of concerns and make use of constructed attributes / measures to incorporate diverse values Successful public engagement needs to recognize constructed nature of preferences Successful facilitators need to adapt tools (probability assessments with Elders?) and learn new ways to probe or question (stories? narrative? walks?) Establishment of trust may be precursor to actions Friday, March 30, 2007 UK Cambridge presentation 39