God: from West to East and Back Again (Capítulo da obra A Questão de Deus na História da Filosofia, vol. 1, coord. M.L. Xavier, Lisboa, 2008) Scott Randall Paine University of Brasilia Introduction 1. 2. 3. 4. God in Aquinas: A What That is a Who a. A Detected Existence b. An Unplumbed Essence c. A Surprising, Personal Greeting The Hindu Brahman: a What and then a Who Buddhist shunyata: Atheism or just Negative Theology? The Chinese Tien: Who Lives in the Sky? Conclusion Introduction If we in the West could lift our minds above debates between theists and atheists, Jews and Muslims, Catholics and Protestants regarding the question of God’s existence, nature and ultimate ontological status—at least for a moment—and look for God in the religions of the East, we might make some discoveries that could help us understand our own queries in a larger context. The superficial impressions we gain are not much help in themselves at understanding the religions in question, but they are where we must begin. Hinduism may appear to the untutored Westerner to be but a pantheism gone to seed, Buddhism a godless program of psychological methods of concentration and the native traditions of the Far East to be but hospitable blends of Taoist, Confucionist and Buddhist views of a cosmos of surging powers, meridians of energy and crowds of nature divinities—but those impressions, as misleading and partial as they are, invite corrections which can make us think more realistically about even our own Western ideas regarding divinity. 1 I wish in this essay to begin with a few reflections on the Semitic notion of a personal God, which has developed and passed into our Western consciousness, and which is still today a subject of heated contention. I then propose to question the Hindu, Buddhist and home-grown Far Eastern traditions on this very matter, that is: Can we find any hints of the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, 1) in the Vedas and in the multiple Hindu traditions they nourish? And despite apparent disinterest in God, can we nonetheless find traces of him, however indirectly, 2) in the life and example of the Buddha and in the hundreds of millions of his followers today? And, finally, 3) in the great sky of China, peered into through a symbiosis of scriptures of the Taoist and Confucionist canons (to which the ferment of Buddhism is added) and the multifaceted wisdom about ourselves and the world they present us with, is there any plausible linkage with the Pure Act, the Self-Thinking Thought of Aristotle and Aquinas or with Him who speaks through the burning bush in Exodus? I offer these reflections only as exploratory ponderings, approximate suggestions inviting correction and complementation, results of my own years of study on matters of East-West understanding and of extensive travel in Asia and the Middle East. I intend them to be helpful and catalytic, rather than exhaustive or conclusive. Of this much I am sure: even a rudimentary understanding of how the East also, in certain ways, approaches the mystery of God can only help a Westerner understand his own approach in a more discerning way. But it will only be by fully appreciating the differences and the difficulties that we can espy whatever commonalities may be present. Indeed, even today’s atheists could stand to have a more adequate understanding of what they do not believe in. I am venturing in some ways unconscionable generalizations, as “the West” is hardly as monolithic in its views of God as I am outlining here, nor are the three great Oriental traditions I use as representatives of the East either so uniform in themselves or so inclusive of a number of significant minor traditions as to exhaust the non-Western approaches to divinity. Still, on the validity of a personalist, Semitically inspired view of God, supplemented by a Greek articulation of a supreme intelligence (especially in Aristotle), as predominant in the Occident—in both those who believe in him and those who don’t—and of a non-personalist understanding of ultimate reality (beyond personhood and attendant attributes) which holds sway, in different ways, in the Orient, 2 we can presume general consensus. My use of Thomas Aquinas as spokesman for the Western view is not meant to suggest that his metaphysics of the person is shared by all, but rather that his approach is profoundly typical of the West, and thus serves to highlight the contrasts I propose to discuss. I will not address here arguments for or against the existence of God, or even arguments against the arguments. That is to say, I am not concerned here with showing if and how the ontological argument, Aquinas’ five ways, or modern arguments based on a dynamism of the human spirit offer coherent grounds for bringing a mind to assent to God’s existence; or if and how appeals to the progressive conquests of science, manifest injustice and evil in human affairs or the misdeeds committed in the name of religion offer sufficient grounds to doubt his existence. Similarly, I will not speak about arguments directed at both these attempts and which insist that either to assert that God exists or to assert that he does not are equally vacuous uses of language, maintaining that neither theist nor atheist really knows what he is talking about. All this is of interest, but not to us here. I am instead addressing how God is viewed by those who do accept his reality, and even by most who do not, particularly in the West, and looking for analogues or contrasts in some traditional views of transcendence native to the East. 1. God in Aquinas: a What and then a Who a. A Detected Existence Thomas Aquinas makes a bold statement in his Disputed Questions on Power, one which modern atheists, and even more so agnostics, might do well to take note of. He is probably the most celebrated “God-talker” in the West, having generated hundreds of pages of scholastic reflection on theology, dipping both into natural experience and reason as well as faith in a supernatural disclosure as legitimate sources. But what he says, as he approaches the summit of theological discourse and tries to draw up a kind of conclusive lesson about our knowledge of God, may take the more ambitious of aspiring knowers of God by surprise: “This is the ultimate in human knowledge of God: that one knows that one does not know God.” 1 3 We must remind ourselves that Thomas had already assured us that it is quite possible to know that he is; our cognitive inadequacy shows up when we ponder who and what he is. This statement of Aquinas goes further than merely to highlight how so many of the divine attributes are negative (for instance, to say he is eternal is just to negate time of him; to say he’s infinite is to negate limit; to say he is simple is to negate composition). He is saying more than this, as we shall see in a moment. Nor are we relieved of the impact of his statement by limiting its pertinence to our philosophical knowledge, and not that obtained through divine revelation. It is precisely about God as known both through the meager but crucial deliverances of philosophy and the far more searching lights of divine revelation that Thomas advises us to take cognizance of our ignorance.2 We grow in knowledge and (consciousness of) ignorance of God pari passu. And even before we fully recover from this epistemological humiliation, we would do well to recall that even the created order of things, produced by this virtually unknowable God, does not readily deliver up its underlying blueprint to the human mind. “The essential principles of things are unknown to us.”3 The dark shadow of the divine mystery seems to cast a penumbra into what that very mystery created, and our mind finds itself wanting of light even when it comes to penetrating the intimate secrets of contingent creatures. Far from the impression of ambitious and exhaustive detail about God one might form from wielding the sheer bulk of the Summa Theologiae, its actual methodology is rather one of deliberate indirectness (the very criterium divisionis used by Thomas to divide the three parts: God known indirectly as principle—Part I; as end—Part II; and as means—Part III; but never as He is). Instead of taking us down discursive roads into the depths of the divine mysteries, Thomas—with almost Kantian application—cordons off one region of divinity after another, leaving us with multiple cognitions of what God is not, but precious little about what he is; and then when he crowns our docta ignorantia, it is with a crown of thorns, as he utters that final doxology cited above, which proclaims that our highest theological acquisition seems more an echo of Montaigne’s “que sais-je?” than a list of gnoseological conquests following a confident syllogistic ergo. However, there is one consolation, for this awareness of our ignorance regarding God is itself a positive acquisition: our highest knowledge of him is to know that we don’t know him. And that is truly to know something of utmost importance. 4 Thomas’ God, like Carlyle’s universe, is hardly but a “great unintelligible perhaps”. 4 True, our unaided intellect can blaze no easy rational trails into the divine essence, but there are a few viae, a few paths, by which reflective thought can follow certain cosmic traces of divine causality right up the chain of acts to an Existence. Not to an Essence, but to an Existence. But as mentioned, we shall not pronounce here upon the famous Five Ways in which God’s existence echoes into the mind according to Thomas’ celebrated analysis.5 Still, there is far more even to the much misunderstood first two ways than just imagining God at the end of miles upon miles of dominoes, giving the first kick. Facile dismissals of these arguments by those who have never made an effort to grasp what metaphysical resolutio meant to Thomas as a method of philosophical knowing, or how much natural philosophy and preparatory metaphysics is presupposed in their formulation, or how reduced and didactically simplified they appear in view of the manual for beginners they are written for, have been effectively countered elsewhere.6 It is of interest to us here that each of the viae leads us not to the God of the Bible (at least not in the self-revelatory mode he assumes there), but only to a label we give to something or someone we cannot see, but “what we understand to be, or call God” (…hoc omnes intelligent Deum ...quam omnes Deum nominant, …hoc dicimus Deum.7). We give this first mover, this first cause, this most necessary being, most perfect and intelligent entity a name8: God (theos, Deus, Gott, Dieu, Iddio, etc.), but though it is a name cast up in the face of a clearly ascertained Existence, the precise nature that is doing the existing remains heavily veiled. Now before I am cautioned that Thomas does indeed do more than just hold forth on what God is not, but also seconds the Aristotelian characterizations of God as Pure Act, Self-Thinking Thought, Unmoved Mover, and other so-called “pure perfections”, and indeed insists that the best positive philosophical title for God is Ipsum Esse Subsistens 9 (Subsistent Being Itself), we must take note of another matter that bears directly on knowing something essential about a perceived existence. b. An Unplumbed Essence 5 If astronomers knew about the existence of the recently demoted “planet” Pluto years before its discovery, due to the gravitational effects it manifested on other, already known celestial bodies, we can speak of having discovered the existence of something which was still, to a large degree, unknown in its essence. In a converse example, a zoologist can define the essence of a dinosaur with even genetically informed precision, all the while quite assured (and perhaps comforted) by the fact that they do not now exist. One day there may be a cure for arthritis or cancer, but if there is, it may well involve the concoction of a new chemical compound, the essence of which, once existent, is discovered to be effective. All of our queries about what was, what wasn’t, what is, what could be, what will be, what can never be, etc., dance around the varied tensions between essence and existence. Thomas’ metaphysical reflections come to a unique focus when he concludes that all created beings, even angels, are earmarked by a real distinction between these two principles.10 We cannot be completely in the dark about God, otherwise we would literally know nothing of what we were talking about. There are those attributes which God shares, analogically, with all his creatures, such as unity, goodness and truth, or with some of them, as intellectuality and indeed personhood (to which we will return); and then there are those which regard God’s relation to creation and which are, nonetheless, incommunicable to his creatures, such as omnipotence and omniscience. Precisely the unique relation between essence and existence in God, which is at once incommunicable to creatures (insofar as only God can be this way), but which is also the basis for his ability to communicate esse (the act of being) to creatures in creation, is, for Thomas—and this is the real message of the expression Ipsum Esse Subsistens— that in him, since there is no distinction at all between his essence and existence, his essence is to exist. He exists by nature. Whatever cogency adheres to so-called ontological arguments surely finds its power here, if not its final justification. We creatures are contingent (we can not be), but in order to be at all, even contingently, we must have some share in that great necessity of God’s being, and that we do by not being able not to be now [sic], once we are. The principle of non-contradiction is finally a statement of this very fact. Furthermore, creatures are, as creatures, because Some-thing(-one) is, as creator. I bring all this up because the whole question of ascertaining the existence of God, however 6 indirectly, involves by the very nature of the inseparability of divine essence and existence, something of his essence. He “who dwells in unapproachable light, whom no man has ever seen or can see” (1 Tim., 6,16), is still detectable as existing, and if existing is his nature, you cannot be entirely out of contact with that nature if you know it is “there”. “Subsistent Being Itself”—there are worlds of implications about our knowledge of God in that most compact and concise surrogate for a divine definition. Philosophical projects of pantheism, monism, panentheism, Berkeleyism, German Idealism, and, paradoxically, even atheism (a connection for which I politely beg leave to write a separate paper), draw whatever plausibility they have from the fact that God’s very be-ing has a mysterious mode of continuity/discontinuity with created be-ing. It is not the same, but neither is it entirely other. Depending on the philosophical temperament and personal background one brings to the question, the continuity might for some make the universe look divine, and then for others make the assertion of the existence of a non-cosmic reality seem unnecessary (God is really not outside of the cosmos anyway). Conversely, the discontinuity might make the universe look fragile and illusory, or make it seem to be but the outer dimension or projection of a transcendent being, which alone is. But as we cannot even ask if something exists without at least a minimally informative nominal definition, so when we say God exists we are already claiming to know something, however diminutive and approximate, about his essence. “For from the greatness and beauty of created things comes a corresponding perception of their Creator.” (Wisdom, 13, 811) That Old Testament confirmation of a “perceived” Existence, along with St. Paul’s, (“Ever since the creation of the world his invisible nature, namely his eternal power and deity, has been clearly perceived in the things that have been made.” Romans, 1,20), lend a Biblical voice to the common sense ascertainment we have all heard (and probably performed) as we look around at the big world and suspect there is something even “bigger” behind it. The philosopher may slightly shift the perspective and say that, however you divide it, analyze or extrapolate it, the universe simply does not explain itself. And yet it seems impregnated with meaning, and whenever the voice of the scientist tends to minimize this, the voice of the poets grows even louder. I suspect that it was much more poetic instinct than 7 philosophical analysis which led the Greco-Roman world to finally embrace the strange message that came out of Jerusalem. c. A Surprising, Personal Greeting A category central to the Abrahamitic, or Semitic, traditions is revelation, apocalypse. Although the idea is in the same family of notions as that of manifestation (a concept more germane to Neoplatonism and Eastern thought), there is a difference, and the difference is personal. We might say that the deities of the great mythological systems of the world (the Celtic, Nordic, Greco-Roman, Egyptian, Hindu, Mesoamerican, etc.) can be understood as manifestations of forces of nature, great values, perhaps even transcendent realities (spirits, angels, demons, etc.), but we do not find a prominent motive of their features and acts in a desire to reveal themselves to us and enter into communion with human beings. The traditions in Abraham’s lineage insist that God is intent on either communicating with us (Judaism and Islam) or even, in addition to this, on entering into communion with us (Christianity). A divine initiative purports to be at work which is more than just metaphysical—it claims to be free, thus personal and purposive. One of the closest approaches to this in the Hindu tradition is perhaps in the Bhagavad Gita, chapter 11, when Vishnu, through his avatar, Krishna, responds to Arjuna’s entreaty: “I desire to see Thy Ishvara-Form, O Supreme Purusha. If, O Lord, Thou thinkest me capable of seeing it, then, O Lord of Yogis, show me Thy immutable Self”.12 Though not without elements suggestive of the celestial visions of the Hebrew prophet Ezechiel, the Transfiguration of Jesus in the Gospel, or the apocalyptic Christ revealed to John at the beginning of the Book of Revelation, the subsequent showing forth of the cosmic Deva in the Gita is much more of a kaleidoscopic manifestation of how Brahman is in all, and all in Brahman, than a personal disclosure of an ultimate subjectivity inviting intimate communion. I highlight the difference not as between good and bad, or even necessarily good and better, but between one view of God and another. At the very least, we have apples and oranges here. In closing these loose reflections on Aquinas’ understanding of God, let us consider one more distinction likewise pregnant with implications. As the 8 essence/existence distinction is applied to God (in a way that is totally sui generis, since finally it proves to be an identity), its implications can be resolved within philosophy itself. Notwithstanding the resounding relevance of Ex. 3,14 where God self-identifies as He Who Is, the distinction is drawn out by Aquinas in predominantly metaphysical rather than Biblical or theological terms. The other distinction I refer to is perhaps not so partisan at first blush: that between nature and person. A small library has been written on how this distinction first arose, in all its significance, in the Trinitarian controversies of the early Christian church. The early Fathers attempted to explain the divinity attributed to the Father, the Son and the Spirit in Scripture in a way that preserves an inviolate monotheism, and to explain the dual nature—divine and human—evident in Christ’s quite singular person. Theological consensus is usually forthcoming on the unavailability of the Trinity and the Incarnation, as intrinsic mysteries, to natural reason, strain as it may. But the notions of nature and person themselves, as those of essence and existence, are philosophical; nowhere does the Bible define them, presuming we have philosophers for these labors. Once philosophy has delivered the notions of person and nature to the theologian, we witness the evolution of the most metaphysically charged discourse in all of theology: De Deo Trino (On the Triune God)13. We cannot here, of course, even begin to explore the rich conceptual outline Aquinas gives us of the variously contoured boundary-line between God as revealed and God as hidden, limned with notions such as divine processions, eternal generation, spiration, divine notions, and perhaps the intellectual jewel of the treatise: the idea of a divine Person as a subsistent relation. For the purposes of this essay, the only matter that needs to be underscored is that in our theological approach to God, understanding him to be personal is as high as it gets. There is no divine nature—even a hidden, super-transcendent, overarching one—which is not inalienably also and in a most intimate and absolute way personal. The suggestion that the personal dimension—whether on the ontological level of person as subject of being, or the psychological level of person as subject of acts of knowledge and will—is but an accommodation God makes when dealing with creatures is one utterly foreign to the Abrahamitic religions. Symbols and accommodations there are (God appearing in the thunder, or displaying human emotions in Scripture; or God depicted as a hand, or an old bearded man, or a dove, in art) but being personal is not 9 one of them. We haven’t the space here to address what Muslims and Jews may object to in the Christian idea of a Triune God, but let it be said that even the Christians understand their Trinity to be, paradoxically, an even higher form of affirming the oneness of God than just to say “one”. The Giver-Given-Gift, or Lover-Beloved-Love, or Knower-Known-Knowledge, or Generator-Generated-Generation are only so many ways to affirm that the one undivided essence is possessed threefold—in a triad that is not mathematical, but metaphysical—which shows forth Life, Word and Love of the One who says “I am He Who is”, and is all the more monotheistic “because” of it. It is the purpose of this essay to make a few enquiries as to how God is understood, typically, in the West and whether we can find him also in the East. Thus, the implications of introducing personhood into our talk about God have shown how our characteristic Occidental understanding of God as a “He” (I am prescinding here from the question of gender issues regarding God) is rooted in an understanding of revelation as a free, personal act on the part of God. How is Ultimate Reality presented to us east of the Middle East? 2. The Hindu Brahman: a What first, and then a Who As one travels through India, visiting one of the thousands of temples dedicated to Vishnu, Shiva or Shakti (Brahma, part of the trimurti triad with the first two, has only one well-known temple in Pushkar), spotting numerous statues of the elephant-god Ganesha and the monkey-god Hanuman, and hearing also habitual English-language references to “God” in the singular (without perceived contradiction), one might find it odd for anyone to claim that ultimate reality, for Hinduism, could be anything but personal. But not a few representatives of Indian philosophy, specifically of the more metaphysical Vedanta darshana (point of view, school)—and in that current of the school which follows the most influential of all Indian philosophers, Shankara (turn of 8th cent.)—would tell us that when you get down to absolute, unadulterated reality, divinity per se, all personality and all he-ness or she-ness must be stripped away as but lower-echelon accommodations to our limited minds and imaginations. Perhaps the most landmark text of this stripping away of everything that is not truly divine, truly absolute, we find in the Brhadaranyaka Upanishad, where a teacher 10 is questioned by his students about the nature of God, and the teacher begins to itemize the negations, “not this, not this” (in Sanskrit, neti neti). Certainly there are significant analogues to this in the Christian mystical tradition, notably in St. John of the Cross’ Ascent of Mount Carmel, where he ticks off the things we must leave in order to attain to God, apparently echoing the upanishadic mantra, but in Spanish: nada, nada, nada.14 But we would upset the Spanish mystic if we suggested that the Personhood of God also be checked off as a hindrance as we ascend the mount. Obviously one must be careful not to caricaturize a tradition not one’s own. If only lower, sentimentalized notions of personhood were to be eliminated, lower ideas of the ego as focus of attachment and pride, concordance could be reached between East and West. However, I suspect the matter is not so easily resolved. One of the most relevant precisions made in Vedantic doctrine is that which distinguishes two “sides” or dimensions in the Absolute, which is called Brahman (not to be confused with the particular deity Brahma above): there is Brahman saguna (the Absolute with attributes) and Brahman nirguna (the Absolute without attributes). Only the latter is, in the fullest sense, absolute. The former is invested with all the symbols, particular vestments, avataras (“descents” or popularly—though not entirely accurately—“incarnations”), mythologies, subordinate (and only partially true) teachings, colors, divisions, etc. which make the Absolute somehow accessible to lower sensibilities (such as ours). Interesting to us here is that one of these attributes is precisely personhood. All the Hindu divinities mentioned in the previous paragraph and with them all purportedly 30 million other gods and goddesses, are at best masks and manifestations of the one, non-personal and absolute Brahman nirguna. This Absolute is not a he, but a what—although we should perhaps qualify the last statement, inasmuch as the intelligent Vedantin will counter that the very distinction what/he does not apply either when referring to the nirguna Brahman, so that it would be truer to say that it is neither a he nor a what. This retreat, however, has no effect on the irreducible fact that one still cannot say of the Absolute that personhood is of its innermost, inalienable nature, and that fact alone leaves the Semitic traditions with one of two options. After all, they insist that it is the absolute and ultimate God who has revealed Himself to us and interacts with him on a personal basis that is not an accommodation but an innermost act of love. Although it would be unfair to attribute a high profile of 11 this distinction to all forms of Hinduism, past and present, it is prominent enough among Western exponents of the Vedanta to serve as a relevant issue of comparison. The first option left by this distinction to the Semitic view of things is that Yahweh of the Old Testament, Allah of the Koran, and the Triune God of the New Testament are just three more articulations of saguna Brahman, and that, therefore, they are as relative as Brahma, Shiva, Vishnu and Shakti, and must be abandoned if one is to turn to the divine essence in its highest, purest reality. Now one might suggest that just as the Vedantins, in the Indian tradition, penetrate through to the deity without attributes, likewise there are Cabbalists in Judaism, Sufis in Islam and Eckhartian mystics in Christianity who make similar distinctions. No doubt, but these latter movements are marginal in the respective traditions and even suspect, precisely in their attempts to reach something “deeper” than the very personal God who presents himself in the respective scriptures. The Vedanta, on the other hand, although variously interpreted (as in the readings of Ramanuja and Madhva, who diverge pointedly from that of Shankara), still presents its fundamentally Shankarian construal of the Vedic truth as the most accepted and influential metaphysical exposition of the sanatana dharma (the perennial teaching) of Hinduism, and the impersonal Absolute finally prevails. The other option would suggest that greater discernment is needed in differentiating between, on the one hand, accommodations in a necessary manifestation and, on the other, loving condescension in free acts of creation and salvation. It might be that the Vedantic analysis of the myriads of divinities as pedagogical vehicles of transmission of higher truth is accurate indeed regarding the role of Shiva and the avatars of Vishnu, for example. It could even be admitted that the roles played by angels and indeed prophets, in the Biblical tradition, is comparable to the role played by those pedagogical divinities. But it may be that the analysis does not apply to the God of the Bible, and for reasons that even Hindu teaching might suggest. If the Brahman nirguna is the Godhead without attributes, the Unknown God (one thinks of St. Paul’s remarks regarding the shrine to an unknown god in Athens, in Acts 17), one can read such absence of attributes as purporting something beyond all possible knowing in an absolute sense. And it is this reading which the Shankarian 12 Vedanta seems to embrace. But I suggest one could also read it as a higher species of hiddenness: the hiddenness which persons bear in their heart of hearts: things no one will ever know about them, unless they choose to reveal them. In other words, if the Godhead not only allowed personifications as mythological vehicles of its numerous aspects for purposes of accommodation and education, but were also in itself deeply personal (indeed, how could personifications be effective vehicles if there were no root of personhood in the Godhead whose aspects were thus vehicled?), then why would there not be an infinite dimension of intelligence and freedom within the innermost bosom of Brahman which also could reserve some knowledge of itself to itself only, unless it were one day to resolve, freely, to make it known. Such an unnecessary, but by no means impossible free “development” within Brahman nirguna is what, finally, the word revelation means in the Semitic tradition. It should not be overlooked, however, that in the Hindu tradition Brahman saguna, in its uppermost reaches, already points to the one God, as explicated in the strong Ishvara (personal god) tradition in India, one source of common references to God when English is spoken. This “Lord of the Universe” does come closest to a Western idea, as do others, such as Prajapati (lord of creatures), Bhagavan (exalted one), titles present in the Vedic scriptures. However, the accommodating nature of even such titles is brought home by the prevalent popular tradition of the Ishta-Deva (beloved, or chosen deity), that is, one of any of a number of gods chosen by a particular population or family as their personal or familial god. The plurality of possible Ishvaras seems to underscore that any and all of them are still but symbols thrown up in the face of the intrinsically impersonal. Two differences remain clear. One is that the God of the Bible is not easily assimilated to any of these singular Hindu deities. The unambiguously “jealous” characterization of the God of the patriarchs and prophets is not easy to match with the more “sociable” protagonists of the various epics and tales of the gods of India. A second difference is that all of these personalized properties must be dropped if one is to try and think of God in himself. But this personal quality is held on to tenaciously by the Semitic believer as the most inherent divine reality of all, to be purified of all created limitation and misunderstanding, to be sure, but personal nonetheless. 13 If it is at least possible for a Vedantin to accept that Brahman nirguna could surprise us all, and that such is the best way for an Indian to view the Semitic God of revelation, it could be that there would be no need for an irreconcilable opposition between Hinduism and Christianity in terms of their views of God. It could be that the latter’s claim is simply that the great and remote Absolute beyond the reach of symbols and forms was unknown and unknowable indeed, until in a certain corner of the earth He surprised us all and began to talk. 3. Buddhist shunyata: Atheism or just Negative Theology? Among those who know little of the vastness and multidimensionality of the Buddhist tradition, it is not uncommon to hear remarks to the effect that Buddhism is more of a philosophy than a religion, and that anyway, since religion usually has something to do with God, Buddhists don’t believe in one to begin with. It is thus sometimes called a form of atheism. As it is not our purpose here to explore, in detail, the many forms of Buddhism any more than of Hinduism, we shall focus upon this last suspicion, since it bears directly on how God figures, or not, in the perspective of wisdom inaugurated by Siddhartha Gautama so long ago. It is safe to say that in none of the principal branches of the Buddhist tradition (Theravada, and of the polymorph directions sired by the Mahayana: especially Pure Land, Zen and Vajrayana, or Tibetan), does the monotheistic notion of one God play an appreciable role. However, to say that this discovery justifies calling them atheists is problematic on at least three accounts: 1) atheism, like theism, is a Western term, the former deriving its sense entirely from a negation of the latter. This polemical context is not reproduced in India in the same way. Polemics there were, as Buddha denied the authority of the Vedas and the necessity of caste distinctions, but though these denials brought him in conflict with Hindu orthodoxy, he was not additionally alienated by a critique of God, or of any of the Hindu gods, for that matter. Only later would Buddhists (in first millennium A.D. India) quarrel with Hindu Ishvara representations. But for the Buddha himself, whether God or gods existed or not was of no concern to him. It was a non-issue, relevant only to the extent that practitioners of his dharma should be warned of the futility of such discussions. 2) Moreover, paradoxically, if you visit a broad 14 representative sampling of Buddhist temples from all the aforementioned currents (with few, though significant, exceptions), you will be struck by something which seems to give the lie to any allegation of atheism: an abundance of statues of quite obvious, and at times obtrusive, deities, gesticulating and sometimes glaring at devotees from their temple pedestals. Mahayana Buddhists, in particular, tend to outdo themselves in this, with the break-off tradition of Zen constituting a significant exception, but the other break-off tradition of Vajrayana being an over-the-top confirmation. There seems to be some need, and some justification, for such emphatic depiction of personal deities— hardly reconcilable with a programmatically atheist ambience. 3) On a more philosophical side of things (and whether or not Buddhism is only philosophical, it certainly is also philosophical), a distinction is to be made between alleging the matter of God’s existence to be irrelevant or unknowable, and declaring him not to exist at all. This last, for the Buddha, would be just as strident an offence as to affirm God’s reality. If one insists on using Western labels, the names ‘non-theist’ or even ‘agnostic’ might be more appropriate. We need not dwell here on the abundance of Mahayana divinities and the multiple buddhas and bodhisattvas who obtain quasi-divine status in the prayers of many Buddhists. There was a great deal of mutual influence in the centuries in which the Hindu bhakti traditions of Vaishnavism and Shaivism and the emerging Mahayana Buddhists cohabited in northern India (much of the first millennium AD), and certainly a great deal of this seeming re-hinduization of Buddhism (and, some Hindus would protest, buddhicization of Hinduism) can be attributed to this cross-pollination. At the very least, it exhibits the strong tendency of human religiosity to focus its devotion on the personal. The last-mentioned reservation, however, is even more pertinent when asking about Buddhism and the one God. To deny that God can be known, as we have seen, is hardly atheism. Neither is it atheism to deny that we can even know whether or not he exists. Such disclaimers merely situate us on one side of a famous philosophical debate. Although it is hard to generalize about such a diversely articulated tradition as the Buddhist—at least when one ventures beyond the Four Noble Truths—still, when we inquire about the nature of “ultimate reality” (about as close as a Buddhist can get to 15 inquiring about God), one notion has asserted itself as generally programmatic for Buddhist thought: shunyata (emptiness). If we made a small list of the notions which turn up inevitably in most any exposition of Buddhist doctrine, we can see the impact they would have on the idea of a subsistent, absolute Being: shunyata (emptiness), anatman (the non-existence of a self—any self-identical and abiding monad of existence), pratitya-samutpada (interdependent origination, the radical interdependence of all things and the absence of any fixed point of reference or causality), and, as the goal of all illumination, nirvana (literally, the “quenching”, or “despiration” of the flame of desire). Already in the Theravada Pali Canon we read: “The world is empty (sunya) of a Self and anything belonging to a Self.”15 The great Mahayana philosopher (arguably the most influential of all Buddhist thinkers), Nagarjuna (2nd/3rd centuries AD), made this notion, together with pratitya-samutpada, the cornerstone of the Buddhist view of reality. “Vanity of vanities, all is vanity” proclaims Solomon at the opening of the book of Ecclesiastes. The word vanity, of course, comes from the Latin for emptiness. St. Paul affirms that “the form [‘scheme’] of this world is passing away” (1 Cor. 7,31). For the Abrahamitic traditions, God is in a way the world is not, and the latter’s existence is necessarily transient, and in a very real sense “you can’t get there from here”—that is, you cannot think your way to God’s nature from created nature, but only to his existence (as shown above). A broad swath of Western thinking about God has fanned out, particularly in Eastern Orthodox theology, in what is known as apophaticism, or “negative theology”. We saw above how powerfully it makes itself felt even in the otherwise ostensibly “cataphatic” (affirmative) theology of Thomas Aquinas. A rereading of Clement of Alexandria, Ps.-Dionysius the Areopagite, Gregory of Nyssa, Gregory Palamas and a host of others in the theological and mystical traditions of Eastern Christendom might bring one to wonder if they are eastern in a more than geographical sense. Or is this to see things perhaps backwards? Could it not rather be that the existence of a strong apophatic tradition in Christianity, where belief in revelation and unquestionable personal theism is paramount, gives us pause before considering similarly negative approaches to the divine in Asia to be atheistic? Vladimir Lossky, the eminent Russian Orthodox 16 theologian of the 20th century, said of these Christian authors that they did not “ see, in apophaticism, revelation but the receptacle of revelation; they arrive at the personal presence of a hidden God. For them the negative way is not resolved in a void where subject and object will be reabsorbed; the human person is not dissolved but has access to a face to face encounter with God, a union without confusion according to grace.”16 In other words, the option should be left open that even Buddhist negativity regarding the question of God could be seen in terms more epistemological than ontological. Perhaps they stand rather with Kant in denying that we can know at all that most ultimate “thing in itself” that is God, and with Wittgenstein in bidding us be still about that regarding which we have nothing of pertinence to say. And perhaps they can at least see the coherence of the Abrahamitic assertion that one can only become cataphatic about God if you believe the he himself became so in revelation. 4. The Chinese Tien: Who Lives in the Sky? “Chinese philosophers, both ancient and modern, have been interested primarily in ethical, social, and political problems… Basic metaphysical problems, such as God, universals, space and time, matter and spirit, were either not discussed, except in Buddhism, or discussed only occasionally, and then always for the sake of ethics.” 17 In this way, the respected Chinese philosopher Wing-Tsit Chan highlights the relative absence of the “God problem” in Chinese thought. Native Chinese religion too holds no conspicuous monotheistic convictions. Some names used to refer to the sky itself as divine were Shangdi (Lord-on-high) and Tien (Heaven), but these never occupied positions either as central or as universal as God in the Semitic traditions. In the 17th century, Jesuit missionaries in China (most prominent among them, Matteo Ricci), impressed by the fund of wisdom inherent in the Far Eastern traditions (and perhaps intrigued by the Latin and Romance language conflation of the notions of ‘heaven’ and ‘sky’), petitioned Rome to allow the Catholic liturgy to acknowledge God also under such “celestial” titles, but to circumvent fellow-Christian suspicions of reducing God to an earlier Far Eastern deity, the Jesuits proposed the name Tienzhu (Lord of Heaven). This, along with planned integration of non-impetrative ancestor 17 veneration and special homage to Confucius, was hoped to become a means of allowing greater approximation between the Biblical message and the native legacy of the Chinese mind.18 All this was finally proscribed by Rome in the mid-18th century for reasons we cannot go into here. We shall never know what a different course modern Chinese history may have taken, had this and other suggestions of those missionaries been put into practice. The “rites controversy” around this matter surely made evident the difficulties inherent in any attempted approximation of Eastern divine beings, even those considered the highest among all, to an expressly revealed, personal God of Abrahamitic inspiration which excludes, as a matter of principle, any other beings except his own creatures. Despite the obvious suggestiveness of the thousands of religious statues in China, already mentioned, it is to the sky, the heavens, that the Chinese looks when considering ultimate reality, and in that sky it is the way, the Tao, which carries things on through time in a wonderful order that invites human emulation, as the masculine sky interacts with the feminine earth. The short but resounding text of the Tao-te Ching, attributed to Lao-tse, is perhaps the single most representative work that addresses the one Tao in a way that invites comparisons, or at least instructive contrasts, with the Semitic God. Although composed in apparent isolation from the Hindu and Buddhist traditions, we can hear both the “negative theology” reminiscent of the latter, A way that can be walked is not The Way A name that can be named is not The Name Tao is both Named and Nameless As Nameless, it is the origin of all things As Named, it is the mother of all things… and the triadic echos reminiscent of the former, Tao gives life to the one The one gives life to the two The two gives life to the three The three give life to ten thousand things19. Even a brief overview of the complex conjuncture of traditions which led the Chinese to call their country the “Land of the Three Teachings” (Taoism, Confucianism and Buddhism) is not possible in this essay. But in our attempt to identify the presence of some analogue to the Western God in the Far East, we may note that the Tao-te 18 Ching seems to identify the very Tao with Tien—that is to say, the Way of Things with the Sky, the Heavens. And this latter, as the missionaries intuited, might be assimilable not only to the residence of the Father “who is in heaven”, but in some measure to the Father himself. To give only one of many possible examples, we will close with a reference from the Taoist canon. In the Ling-pao Ching (Classic of the Sacred Jewel), which forms the doctrinal basis of one influential school of Taoism, the existence and supremacy of one god is declared. These scriptures (dated to the 3rd-5th centuries AD) are traditionally traced back in their ultimate origins to the beginning of time and to Yüan-shih t’ien-tsun (the Celestial Venerable of the Primordial Beginning). To him is attributed the creation of heaven and earth, the primordial revelation and a residence in the highest of the heavens, the “Heaven of Jade Purity”. Sometimes he is considered to be without beginning, the supreme being and even the principle of all being. 20 Maybe if the forward-looking projects of the early Jesuits had been put into practice, this “Land of the Three Teachings” may have added the Christian dimension as it did the Buddhist, and become a land of four teachings. If that were ever to happen, it would only be because out of the vast canopy of the Far Eastern sky which generates the great Way of things, one came to see a God who stepped forth from the vault of the heavens as if he had just unlocked the vault of a treasure, walking that Way indeed, but showing another way through it and beyond it. Conclusion The 21st century has opened, unexpectedly, with a flurry of debates about the existence or non-existence of God. Perhaps never before has the whole world been shaken quite so much by the idea of God—often enough, on the one hand by fundamentalist believers, on the other, by equally fundamentalist detractors. Even God’s strongest advocates in the West admit that, in the final analysis, the Deus absconditus continues to be mysterious even after revelation—perhaps even more so. Still, it is clear that not only confessional atheists are sadly uninformed about the true nature of the knowledge of God the Semitic traditions have claimed to possess, but even believers are more often 19 than not out of touch with the most astute teachings of their best theologians. If we make a brief and admittedly superficial visit to the Hindus, Buddhists and Far Easterners with whom we share the earth, we can hope at the very least to be reawakened to the deeper dimensions of our own Western tradition. In the prevalent Western view, out of the cloud of unknowing of Brahman nirguna, that which was most unknown and mysterious of all—a free, personal being— is believed to have made himself known. God is understood as Someone who stepped out of the darkness and introduced himself. Secondly, the inadequacy of human thought to truly conceive of ultimate reality, easily prey to prioritizing a negative theology, seeing the Absolute as empty of all permanence and true entity, gives way to a pleroma, full of significance, a God speaking a Word in place of an inarticulate void. God is encountered as Someone who talks to us. Finally, the sky above us—source of light, warmth, air and water (in short, source of life)—taken quite naturally by traditional Far Eastern instinct to be divine itself, is the place where God dwells (“Our Father, who art in heaven…”); even if the “up” suffered a demotion due to initial extrapolations of heliocentrism, later extensions of relativity have made the choice of a point of reference relative to begin with. So why not choose the framework of our common experience, as cultures everywhere have naturally done? Continue to fall down, without apologies to Copernicus; look up at the stars, and let the beauty and mystery of the sky remind you why it is also called the heavens. A Mystery Manifest, a Void Filled and a Sky Populated—it could be that the Westerner will travel back from his journey to the East only to rediscover the West. De Pot., q. 7, a. 5, ad 14m: “Hoc est ultimum cognitionis humanae de Deo; quod sciat se Deum nescire.” Contra Gentiles, I, c.5, n.3: “Est etiam necessarium huiusmodi veritatem ad credendum hominibus proponi ad Dei cognitionem veriorem habendam. Tunc enim solum Deum vere cognoscimus quando ipsum esse credimus supra omne id quod de Deo cogitari ab homine possibile est: eo quod naturalem hominis cognitionem divina substantia excedit, ut supra ostensum est. Per hoc ergo quod homini de Deo aliqua proponuntur quae rationem excedunt, firmatur in homine opinio quod Deus sit aliquid supra id quod cogitare potest.” 3 Com. In Aristotelem de Anima, I, 1, nr. 15. “Principia essentialia rerum sunt nobis ignota.” A penetrating commentary on this is to be found in Joseph Pieper’s The Silence of Saint Thomas, transl. J. Murray/D. O’Conner, Chicago: H. Regnery, 1957. 4 Thomas Carlyle, Past and Present, 1843. 5 Summa Theologiae, I, q. 2, a. 3, “An Deus sit”. 1 2 20 For example: Quinque sunt viae, Studi Tomistici 9, org. L. Elders, Cittá del Vaticano, 1980; “The Five Ways” in The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: from Finite Being to Uncreated Being, J.F. Whippel, Washington D.C.: CU Press, 2000, pp. 442-500. 7 Concluding phrases in the five ways, S.T. ib. 8 The etymology of ‘god’ is unclear, suggesting, as such unclarity often does, that the idea is so original and primordial that the word that expresses it is one of man’s first words—thus without derivation. Still, of possible candidates, the indoeuropean ghau- , which means ‘invoke’, is the strongest, and would also support our thesis that this was he who was named, called upon, addressed, but not necessarily known. 9 ST, I, q. 11c and passim. 10 “In solo Deo esse et essentia sunt idem realiter”, ST, I, q 2, a 1; q. 3 a.4, and passim. 11 I use the RSV translation of Bible texts. 12 Srimad Bhagavad-Gita, vv. 3-4, transl. By Swami Swarupananda, Kolkata, 2004. 13 For example, in Thomas’ most complete treatment: ST, I, qq. 27-43. 14 In any edition of the Ascent of Mount Carmelt , for example: Bk. 1, ch. 13 and Bk. 3, ch.1. 15 Samyutta-Nikaya, IV, 54, ed. L Feer, London, 1884-98. 16 Vladimir Lossky, Orthodox Theology: An Introduction, transl. I./I. Kesarcodi-Watson, Crestwood: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1989, p. 32. 17 Wing-Tsit Chan, “Syntheses in Chinese Metaphysics”, in The Chinese Mind, ed. Charles A. Moore, Honolulu: Univ. Press Hawaii, 1967, p. 132. 18 See D.E. Mungello, The Great Encounter of China and the West:1500-1800, Lanham, MD: Rowman/Littlefield, 2nd ed. 2005, pp. 81 f. 19 Tao Te Ching, transl. By Jonathan Star, New York: Penguin, 2001, verse 1, p. 14; verse 42, p. 55; we have followed Star’s preference for the transliteration of Tao with ‘t’. 20 See, for example, Stephen Bokenkamp: “Sources of the Ling-pao Scriptures” in Michel Strickmann, ed., Tantric and Taoist Studies in Honour of R.A. Stein, vol. 2: 434-486. Brussels: Institute Belge des Hautes Études Chinoises, 1983. 6 21