The Birth of Democracy There is so much to say about Socrates that might have made a full exploration of his teachings prohibitively long…before our digital age. But we live in magical times, and so we can get around the difficulty of linear expression that books have always present, because most stories go much deeper. And as Socrates is, by all accounts, the father of philosophy, I’d like to offer here as much as possible to help illuminate his purposes, his method of teaching, and how this process improves the mind, which is why it is still so important for anyone living in a democracy to understand. But in order to truly understand Socrates, it is essential to understand the social and political context into which he was born and in which he found himself challenged to do his part. As it turned out, his was a big part to play because with the birth of democracy came freedom of speech, and with this came the rise of much BS. To this point, before around 450 B.C.E., ones’ parents or ‘society’ had been the teachers of traditional wisdom and values (nomos), and the young learned, as they had in primal or folk cultures, as one generation passed the collected wisdom down to the next around the fire on a daily basis. But a revolution of sorts had occurred in Athenian education when, due in part to a multicultural infusion into Athens, nomos had come to appear merely relative, and so the old ways of teaching faced widespread skepticism. A class of professional teachers, called 'Sophists,' had grown out of this uncertainty, and their teachings were suspected by many (including Socrates, though for reasons other than most) to subvert the fabric of society. (Socrates worries, not because of the loss of tradition, per se (because injustice, for example, has a long tradition that ought to go out with the bathwater), but because the Sophists ways of teaching focused on rhetoric, which is a skill that is readily used to play on people's insecurities, fears, and emotions, making it a powerful tool of deceit and control. The Sophists, for their part, mix well with the oligarchs, the cities wealthy elite, who themselves cling heartily to nomos—if only because it preserves their privilege. It’s easy to overlook the power of empty rhetoric to persuade the demos (many) that untruth is true, and to underestimate the damage that was and is still done to truth and democracy by this popular means of deceit. But this is what the sophist teachers of Socrates’ day were so good at, that is, showing those who could afford large sums how to spin logic with emotion in such a way as to manipulate the opinions of the assembly and so win their cases in court. (In many respects, they were the early predecessors of today’s masters of advertising and public relations as we know them today.) It’s also important to remember that what was unique about democracy, and the real value of free speech, was precisely this jury system, in which one could make his case before large assemblies (which consisted of as much of the population as showed up on any given day), who then voted to decide the fate of defendants based on the perceived right or wrong of a particular case, just as they voted to elect officials to lead them based on the case they make for their suitability to lead. This system is what made democracy participatory, and this decision-making process was far superior to the notion of justice that had proceeded it, which too often resulted in unending blood feuds as powerful kings sought’ justice’ as an eye for an eye. You might remember from Homer’s Illiad that what the goddess Athena brought to the Greeks was the idea and process by which conflict might be resolved by way of impartial adjudicators, for when people put their heads together to make decisions, they are likely to come to better decisions than any given individual would, especially if that individual is acting only on self interest, and so unlikely to care for the common good. To this point, such decisions had been made by one or a few powerful and usually purely self-interested men (yes, men, for even in Athens, women were not considered citizens, though ‘free women’, that is, unmarried women, often had great influence as teachers, as we’ll see). But while the jury system was a vast improvement over the rule of sometimes tyrannical kings, it was nonetheless vulnerable to the power of empty rhetoric that played on the emotions of the assembly and persuaded them by way of fallacy and bad reasoning to act sometimes against their own better interests. So Sophists and tyrants worked well together to manipulate all manner of men to undertake all manner of unwise decisions and actions, based on what amounted to the power of BS. Then, as now, many elected officials got their power by means of such empty rhetoric that plays on the emotions of those who don’t know any better than to simply vote their gut feelings, which can be very easy to manipulate. So Socrates took it as his challenge to help educate the many to use their minds well enough so as not to be so easily manipulated by untruths of the few. This included all those who were unable to afford the Sophists high fees, so were largely defenseless against the wiles of twisted logic. One might hope this would still be the purpose of education in democracy today, but given that we don’t get an hour’s education in good reasoning skills, this is sadly not the case. All the more reason that we need what Socrates was trying to help us develop – for reason is an innate skill, but like any muscle, needs exercise to grow strong. Without skills in good reasoning, words can as easily lead to evil as to good. So it behooves us to understand the so-called Socratic method better than we do or have for almost 2500 years now, at least if we hope to save our democracy from the fate that befell the first democracy in Athena’s golden city. So let us begin with the parallel development of those Greeks who used their new found freedom of speech to search for truth, rather than to persuade with deceit. Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle are those we remember as the fathers of philosophy, but they themselves gave credit to many others for their wisdom, including women, slaves, foreigners, children, their ancestors, and the sages of the east, from whom they themselves learned. (*anchor this to eastern philosophy) It was, as we’ve said, the so-called golden age of Greece, at the very height of its glory -- a time when many still aspired to the highest of their potentials, and the ideal of talking things out reasonably was held dear by men and women of honor and justice. The dialogues they undertook during those days gave birth to our science, education, politics, economy, art, theatre, and medicine—many of which have gone awry in our time, making this is a tale well worth remembering. Indeed, there is arguably nothing we need more these days than the kind of moral pep talk for which Socrates was so well known. Still, for reasons that become apparent only in the telling, Socrates’ story is, arguably, the best kept secret of all time, told only, if at all these days, by those who have an interest in keeping it quiet. Why? Because Socrates would be the first to teach the young to question authority so to keep them honest, and sadly, even those who call themselves Socratic scholars do not wish to have their expertise questioned. Which helps explain why Socrates is, at once, the greatest and most misunderstood thinker the world has ever known, and why his qualifies as the greatest story never told. There are other reasons why a man could be remembered as ‘the father of western Philosophy,’ and yet remain cloaked in such mystery – like so much buried and reburied treasure? The answer is at least partly because most students make it all the way to college having learned nothing about philosophy, let alone Socrates (except perhaps what they learned from watching Bill and Ted’s Excellent Adventure – which leaves most of them wanting to call him So-crates.) Unfortunately, probably the deeper reason has to do with the intellectual demand of ancient literature, which was written for an under-stimulated audience -- something that those of us who grew up in an attention deficient age are clearly not. The consequent being that many settle for taking the word of their teachers about what Socrates and Plato had to say, insuring students only a surface understanding of what Socrates tried to teach. Indeed, Plato’s dialogues (which are one of only two surviving sources of the historical Socrates) are very possibly the most difficult works in the western tradition, in large part because Plato, like Socrates, deliberately does not say exactly what he is thinking. We might surmise this is because his outspoken mentor has recently been put to death for saying too much, but Plato insists that the reason goes much deeper than this, and it is one that primal peoples would understand better than we do today. In his Seventh Epistle, Plato explains that he has never put his deepest thought into words because written words cannot answer for themselves, and without the dialogic process that is necessary to dialectic understanding, they cannot take a reader all the way to deep understanding. As Zen scholar Alan Watts puts it, words are useful between people who already share an understanding of the experience, but words alone cannot teach one who does not, in a certain sense, already know. They are, again, like pointing tools, and just as a finger can point at the moon, it would be a great error to confuse the finger with the moon. Therefore, knowing the words is not the same as understanding the meaning of those words. So the consequent of saying too much straight out is that people who don’t truly understand will simply memorize the words, call them their own, and thus pretend to understanding they themselves don’t possess. Those who consider this to be the full extent of learning are likely to use such words to ends that are not good – as wolves might use sheep’s clothing. This is arguably the same reason that Aristotle’s ethics (these days called ‘virtue ethics’) would have us worry that ‘codes’ or ‘rules’ of ethics allow people to fake it, essentially, by simply going through the motions of being a good person…without ever having to think through to the point of understanding what the right thing to do actually is. Because rules and codes and principles are just general rules of thumb that need to be applied to particular circumstances, a truly virtuous person will be continuously and deliberately thinking through what the right thing to do is in any given circumstance. So these ancient writings, especially Plato’s, are deliberately difficult because a virtuous person does not want or need to be given direct answers, but rather to be provoked to think for themselves. For this reason, Plato’s dialogues do not give us direct answers, but rather challenge us to go through the process of reason that leads us to concluded for ourselves -- what do we think about the questions they are discussing and the myriad issues that arise in the process of searching for the truth together? Is it any wonder then, given the dearth of dialogue in our modern schools, that young people make it all the way to college learning virtually nothing about Socrates but what they could glean from Bill and Ted’s Excellent Adventure? Still, it’s become abundantly clear to me through so many hundreds of hours of teaching these remarkable dialogues that, once inspired by this ancient idealist to undertake these dialogues for themselves, young and old alike cannot help but take deliberate aim at our better selves an effect one cannot help but want to encourage on a much broader scale. So perhaps you can see why my coming to teach this material and my passion to offer a fresh appreciation of Socrates’ dialectic method grew out of a larger project to which I’ve been committed for almost two decades. It is, at heart, an adaptation of Plato’s Socratic dialogues to film. This is what moved me to spend my years in graduate school (Philosophy-Madison) completing a thorough exegesis of the works of Plato, as well all the relevant material from Aristotle, Xenophon, Thudycides, Plutarch, as well as many other ancient voices we have yet to truly hear. Only to discover in the process that it is as if Plato himself anticipated just such an integration - “as if all lines of discourse converge on a common center.” This subtle image presented on the first page of his Republic turns out to be the heart of his dialectic method. And the sheer beauty of the cumulative integration that emerged as these voices fell together compelled me to spend the next four years tuning these voices to our modern ear and finishing the extensive background research necessary to present this story accurately. For all that Plato did well, he did not give us the social and political context that gives this story its rich meaning, which accounts in large part for how his mentor could be so widely misunderstood, even (I was dismayed to discover) among Socratic scholars. So my goal has been to produce a faithful, albeit lean, adaptation of Plato’s Socratic Dialogues to screenplay format. I certainly don’t pretend to be able to improve upon Plato’s eloquent words, mind you, but only hope to inspire renewed interest in them, and perhaps encourage reevaluation of our traditional interpretations of this amazing story. Why film? Because, for all its limitations, film has the potential to uplift the human spirit in the time that it takes to sit through a single college power lecture. Teaching the works of Plato – who wrote for an under-stimulated audience – to 21st century Americans – who are anything but! – one cannot help but feel compelled to try to find a way to deliver the oft’ maligned teachings of this misunderstood thinker in such a way that Socrates might actually get a fair trial, once and for all. What’s more, it may be the best means by which the parallels between that so-called ‘golden age’ and our own can be dramatized (without being fictionalized or trivialized). Indeed, it may well be that film alone has what it takes to finally reach the diverse audience to whom Socrates actually spoke - which is to say, anyone who can suspend their disbelief in humanity for just a few short hours. So allow me to provide a relatively brief introduction to his story, which cannot, I think, be well understood apart from the lives of Pericles and those others who were principle in the Socratic dialogues, sometimes more by being the topic of discussion than participants. We come to know this notorious colonizer of dreams, as mentioned earlier, only from the Dialogues of Plato (32-34 of them, depending on how you count), as well as those of Xenophon (about 4 or 5). It is said that there were twenty some who wrote Socratic dialogues after his death, but these twp are the only dialogues that survive. If we were to read all the Socratic dialogues, we would meet him first as a young man, assisting his mother to midwife a birth, or perhaps visiting the Oracle of Delphi, or talking with the sophists who passed through Athens in their travels. But as most people initially read the dialogue called Plato’s Apology, we tend to meet Socrates first as a seventy-year-old father of toddlers, on trial for his life and presenting his own defense against charges of corrupting the youth of Athens by teaching them to question the gods of the state — charges brought against him by right-wing defenders of traditional piety (some of whom are Plato's closest relatives). Socrates begins his unapologetic defense by appeal to the jury - 'You be the judge,' he implores them. He's not much of a speaker, he says humbly, as he begins his astonishing oration, recounting the legendary mission that brought him to this destiny. He had been challenged to the life of inquiry, he explains, by the Sacred Oracle at Delphi who had declared him at a very young age to be the wisest man in Greece. In fact, Socrates of all people knew how truly little he actually knew—which is to say, how very much he had to learn. And so, in an attempt to find someone wiser than himself, he'd set out asking questions, especially of those who had cultivated a reputation for knowledge. Socrates never wrote a word himself nor took a single drachma for his trade, though he spent his entire life engaging the greatest minds of his day in a startlingly lucid discussion that encompasses the most profound questions humans in all times and places face. What is Justice? Wisdom? Courage? Temperance? Virtue? Happiness? Friendship? Love? By the seeds of such poignant questions, Socrates implanted himself in the hearts and memories of those who would follow him throughout his life – rulers and slaves, men and women, young and old, citizens and foreigners (a cast of characters so familiar that one can almost put contemporary names to them). Despite his quirky weirdness, and by way of his penetrating wit, Socrates proves to all who will listen that philosophy is indeed a power for the good. With his unwavering faith in human nature and his endearing way of treating everyone with equal respect, Socrates teaches good teaching, good politics, and even good medicine, by example— which is to say, by simple friendship. He shows by the way he lives that self-knowledge is self-mastery — and in mastering himself, he feels no need to master others. Through these conversations, we see how the light of reason sparked a fire in Plato and his friends that gave the age her golden glow. Encouraging the youth and the elders of his city alike to question what they casually assume and attend to the injustice they too comfortably ignore, Socrates reveals their conceits and deceits in a way that is most amusing to the listener, and yet likely to leave the most lasting best impression upon the person himself — a gentle method that was both humbling and empowering to the young men who grow up listening at his feet. Plato is one of those young men, and was, we learn at length, descended from great wealth and power. Indeed, he had been expected to take his place in the upper echelon of Athenian politics—before being challenged by a higher purpose by his esteemed friend and teacher, Socrates. We see through Plato’s dialogues that, even in keeping with his humble way of teaching, Socrates did not hesitate to humiliate arrogance where ever he found it. And he found it practically everywhere (as he, no doubt, would today). Enlightened by humility itself, Socrates endeavors to find the wise, but inadvertently discovers the ignorant—and in the process, comes to be thought of as a stinging gadfly to the lazy horse that is Athens. Yet he never fails to credit wisdom wherever he finds it—and the refreshing twist is that this unassuming old philosopher, turns out to be especially fond of citing Eastern visionaries, slaves, women and children—from whom he claims to have learned the most. Hardly the heartless intellectual he is so often misconstrued to be, Socrates examines himself for the sake of his listeners. He takes us by the conscience and compels us to look into our own eyes—to judge ourselves, rather than others—that we might see what is possible and take aim to actualize what is still and always our higher human potential. And what develops is truly a love story, in the very deepest sense of the word, for Socrates is committed to the good of each individual as an end in their own right, with the consequent that, by the end of the story, nearly everyone is, in a sense, ‘in love’ with Socrates—even, and perhaps most especially, those who author his death. We see through these talks the depth of Socrates' personal and untiring devotion to his many friends. Among them are Crito, his boyhood and lifelong companion; Phaedo, once prince of Ellis, made a slave to his Spartan captors, and ultimately freed by Pericles; Aspasia, mistress of the brothel and lifelong companion to Pericles, to whom Socrates introduced her. Socrates is also mentor to several of Plato's closest relatives, including his older brothers, Glaucon and Adeimantus, his cousin, Charmides, and his blood-thirsty oligarchic uncle, Critias. Pericles and Socrates had shared many teachers when they were young, including Aeschylus, Anaxagoras, and Damon - all of whom held both young men in high esteem. It was clear from the start that Pericles, son of Xanthippus, who had died in the battle of Marathon, had all the tools of greatness, and yet all he really seemed to want was to be an artist, a writer, an actor, and to produce plays that would retell history the way it actually happened - rather than as the oligarchs would have it be told. Pericles’ mother was Agariste, who had come from a fabled family. Her uncle was the so-called father of democracy, Cleisthenes, and Pericles understood the responsibility that came with this legacy. Socrates, for his part, was never sure what to make of the well-educated, ambitious and sweet voiced son of a military hero. Pericles was somewhat older than Socrates, and though he seldom engaged him in dialogue, he did seem to listen closely to Socrates’ discussions with others and even sometimes to hang on his every word. Neither was competitive, and yet both seemed challenged by the others’ intelligence. And they both shared the friendship of Xantippe, an artist and musician in her own right. She was the outspoken daughter of one of the wealthiest oligarchs in the city, and was respected by many of the young men for her candor and intelligence. As it turned out, however, the artistic life was not to be an option for either the daughter of an oligarch or the son of a war hero. Pericles, who had all the talents required of a statesman, found he had little choice but to go into politics when his city called him to lead. Following the dictum, ‘Of those to whom much is given, much is required,’ Pericles stepped up to the power he was born into. Whereas Socrates, the son of a stone mason, was much freer in this regard to follow the lead of his own inner voice and the calling of the sacred Oracle. Xantippe did not have the freedoms or choices of either Socrates or Pericles, and found herself—despite her friend’s best efforts—married off in an arrangement that suit her father’s business interests, as well as his interests in keeping her away from the young free thinkers whose company she so enjoyed. And yet all spent their days in the Agora whenever possible, talking and listening with anyone else who happened to be there. And together, their complimentarity brilliance had all of the city in awe, for each in their own right seemed capable of drawing out the brilliance in others. When Pericles and Socrates are both called out to battle, the city of Athens begins a swift decline in their absence. And upon their return, they find that the social and political conditions to which they have returned are overwhelming. The fifth century BC has seen a fervent return to democracy, at least in name, but society as a whole is in a period of transition, flux, and insecurity, and clings for safety to convention. There is considerable fear of intellectualism, and playwrights and orators play to this fear. And so, while Pericles answers the call of his own responsibilities, Socrates takes up the challenge of uplifting the democratic soul to its higher potentials. For the difference in good and bad men, he knew, is not whether they want what is good for them—for all do. It is rather how well they understand what that is. (*put Plato on soul?) Alcibiades, who became ward of Pericles when the boy’s father died in battle, did not understand this distinction, and became the lifelong worry of Socrates. Exalted by birth, elated by wealth, puffed up by his power, and spoiled by the people, Alcibiades suffered from his early miseducation, as well as his own inability to master his want of pleasure, especially of a sexual nature. He represented a great many Athenians, to whom the line between freedom and license was unclear. All, in their way, were worried about the bigger-than-life Alcibiades, who least of all deserved anyone’s love. But Socrates, above all, was uniquely committed to him. And though he was known for his intemperance, Alcibiades was nonetheless able to constrain his ignoble desires as long as he kept company with Socrates. However, a longing distance sets in between them when Alcibiades, still a boy, is seduced by the powerful democrat, Anytus, thereby alienating Socrates from his trust. And so we begin to understand why Socrates thereafter agonizes over the ubiquitous exploitation and corruption of the young. For the same oligarchs who are willing to pay the sophists large sums to be told what they want to hear, such as how to win favor in the law courts and generally keep their wealth by bending the public ear, are also those who use the same tricks in seducing the young. And the sophists who pander to the wealthy by teaching them to use words as weapons and tools of power, rather than as instruments of understanding, find the minds of the young most easy to play in this way. By subtly manipulating the appearance of what is real, true, good, and right, sophisticated rhetoricians are able to spin the minds of even careful listeners, and so the most trusting of young minds are particularly vulnerable to their wiles. So while these powers-that-be are able to stir up public insecurity, hate, and confusion by the mere suggestion of impropriety and scandal, they are also masters of the skill of making the truly scandalous seem perfectly acceptable, for they lived in an environment - not unlike our own - where empty rhetoric and ‘double-speak’ had become the order of the day. It is important to note that, while sexuality was treated by the Greeks as a marvelous fact of life and is a favorite topic of discussion among them, this had taken a tragic turn in Socrates day. For the sexual desires of the oligarchs too often became the very purpose of the ‘education’ they offered the young, who were seduced into this and other mutually exploitive attitudes. Because their own history was filled with stories of young men who fell in love with their somewhat older mentors, giving rise to same-sex relationships between honorable men (and women) who carried on life-long friendships with their partners, the Greeks were what we would call gay-friendly. But what was developing during the 5th century was a pattern of older, wealthy and powerful men seducing younger boys into sexual relationships that lacked the honor that ancient heroes had lived by. And while this was quickly becoming the norm, Socrates knew that these seemingly small missteps took on tragic dimensions in the character of the boys who were being used as means to the end of older men’s pleasure. So you will hear in Plato’s dialogues discussions in which Socrates and his friends assert the fine line between healthy and unhealthy relationships, that being the difference in caring for the beloved as an end in themselves, as opposed to caring for the beloved as a means to the lovers own pleasures. This is a distinction we would all do well to observe today, for what matters, they argue, is not the gender of who we love, but how well we truly love them. It is exploitive sexuality (whether homo- or hetero-) that is recognized to be immoral. Indeed, for all their talking about sexuality, the topic of ‘homosexuality’ (which might seem most controversial to some modern frames of reference) is never much of an issue for the Greeks – indeed, they do not even have a word to distinguish one from the other. And so it became clear that what was corroding values in Athens was the conceits and deceits of these wolves in sheep's clothing - the powerful few who lust after, prey upon, and corrupt the young of Athens with words, pleasure, power, and wealth, rather than treating them as true teachers ought. By their purposeful use of rhetoric, they were able to fan the flames of appetite and ambition in young minds, enraging their lusts, bigotry, and greed, catching them up in partisan bickering, all of which ensured that democracy would be poisoned from within. The only antidote to this, Socrates knew, was philosophy – that is, encouraging the better use of the mind in the young, so that they would be less vulnerable to the seductions of those who would exploit them. And this would require a better understanding of the proper function of words and the better use of reason. Receiving their education in this sophist sense, the young were being turned away from the good of the psyche altogether. As mentioned earlier, when the young are educated by way of words used in less than their true senses (e.g. love as desire, friendship as mere acquaintances, intelligence as merely smart, not wise), and when they learn to argue only to win, rather than to reach a better understanding, they become cynical about both ideas and people, what Socrates calls misology and misanthropy.1 Socrates cites those sophists who fight over ideas “like puppies fight over meat,” and in the process, turn young minds off to thinking altogether. Being miseducated about philosophy in this way “make them hate the whole business when they get older."2 In this way, empty rhetoric is unlikely to better anyone.3 He himself would have been turned off, Socrates says, if he had not had "so deep a passion" as to adhere him to philosophy all his life.4 It may seem a small difference, but as they say in the east, the flight of an arrow shows that what is far depends on what is near. Analogously, Socrates knew that children are sensitively dependent upon initial conditions, and the adults they grow into, will always bear the mark of their early miseducation and the effects of their teacher’s errors. Mistaking the physically beautiful for the truly beautiful, the material for the whole of reality, they are also likely to mistake the mere appearance of justice, knowledge, power, and wealth for the real thing. Errors in education about such fundamental matters, made early, can ultimately thwart human potential all together - not only in this life, Socrates feared, but in the next. (Plato, Pheado n.d.) (Plato’s Theaetetus168bc) 3 (Plato’s Theaetetus168bc) 4 (Plato’s Theaetetus169c) (Plato, Theaetetus n.d.) 1 2 When, some years later, Socrates saves Alcibiades' life in battle, the two rekindle their long silent friendship, but the damage is already done. For Socrates, this lifelong struggle to uplift Alcibiades to his better self - which no one else would even believe that he had - would end in deep disappointment, for the boy’s character had suffered apparently irredeemable damage by the selfish habits he had been taught at a very early age. And despite all Socrates’ efforts, and even Alcibiades’ deepest wish to please his friend, his habits were so strong that apparently nothing could be done to save his spoiled soul. And Pericles blames himself, though he could hardly have saved Alcibiades when he could not even save his own sons from the grip of the oligarchs, who had turned the spoiled boys against their father for no better reason than that he would not increase their allowance, which their oligarchic uncles had persuaded them he should. So Pericles turned his energies to the good of the rest of the population. Toward this end, Pericles developed a work program designed to bring the idle energy, skills, and imagination of the many unemployed together into great public construction projects - which would give rise to the great monuments for which Athens is remembered to this day. All of which irks the oligarchs for many reasons, of course, for besides diminishing the army of unemployed needed to do the work of providing for the leisured upper class, it brakes the illusion of their dependence that is needed for the oligoi to maintain control over the demos. Pericles had been pitted as a youth against Cimon, the son of his own father’s political enemies, who had gained popularity and political support by appearing to be the most generous of benefactors, surrounding himself with anyone whose service could be bought for land and privilege, just as the Spartans had come to control the Athenian nobles. To encourage the illusion that the oligarchs were needed to support the poor, Cimon occasionally opened his orchards and groves to the public, which made him appear to be a most generous and compassionate man. In fact, he was providing just enough to keep the Athenian people dependent, and therefore under his less-thantrustworthy control. Pericles’ work program, on the other hand, provided opportunities for the people to earn their own way by doing something they love, thereby freeing them from their dependence on the whimsical benevolence of the wealthy - and making their labor immortal in the process. No one would remember Sparta when both cities are gone, Pericles assured them, but thanks to these grand monuments, the whole world would remember Athens for all time. All the great monuments of ancient Greece, including the most awesome of all, the Parthenon, were completed within the reign of Pericles’ forty year administration. It was a feat of divine proportion, and the people of Athena’s city were lifted to their highest potentials by the inspiring grandeur of their creation. At the grand opening of the Parthenon in 436 BC, Athens could see visibly the zenith and unity of the life she had reached—her statesmanship, art, science, literature, philosophy, and morals—all woven into one many-colored fabric by the hands and imagination of her free and equal citizens. History credits Pericles with developing a unique and original vision of healthy democracy and the good citizen. It was a vision of a free people who could achieve their highest goals and capabilities as members of a free community, in which the people find and give their best work to their city, take turns governing and being governed, and make all the most important decisions in common.[Kagan, p.258] By contrast with the oligarchic and Spartan authoritarianism, the Periclean vision of democracy valued intelligence and talent, and was not embarrassed to reward both with public honor.[Kagan, p.258] Pericles understood that the only legitimate power is in education, and the only form of control that such a democracy needs is the kind that great intelligence wields.[Kagan, p.189] And whereas the tyrant, the Spartan, and the oligarch find their protection in suspicion and armed guards -- in a well-functioning democracy, it is the laws that guard the person of the citizen and the constitution of the state.[Aeschines, Against Timarchus 4-5][Kagan, p.270] Pericles controlled no army, not even a police force. He depended entirely on the continued and freely expressed support of the Athenian people. His only office was that of general, held for 30 years, even though subject to yearly elections, public inspection of his accounts, and constantly open to recall and public trial. Perhaps the most striking proof of Pericles' greatness lay in his ability to explain how the interests of the city and its citizens depended on each other for fulfillment.[Kagan, p.141] For "to win the necessary devotion, the city -- or rather its leaders, poets, and teachers – must show that its demands are compatible with the needs of the citizen, and even better, that the city is needed to achieve his own goals."[Kagan, p.141] Under his influence, Athenians embraced this democratic vision, and as a consequent, did not think of the customs and laws that govern them as a conspiracy by which the rich and propertied rule over the exploited masses.[Kagan, p.270] Instead -right or wrong -- they believe that respect for and obedience to the law are the fundamental safeguard of the weak and poor against the rich and powerful, and that popular government, which alone can ensure freedom, dignity, and self-respect to the ordinary man, depends on uncoerced adherence to the law.[Kagan, p.270] "We use the law for honoring the good and punishing the evil," Pericles said, “rather than as the tip of the whip.”[Lysias, Funeral Oration 17-19][Kagan, p.270] Democracy alone, he convinced them, respects the dignity and autonomy of every individual, and that its survival requires that each individual sees his own well-being as inextricably interconnected to that of the community as a whole.[Kagan, p.274] Faith in such an ideal is hard to muster in societies that have become cynical about politics thanks to unscrupulous leaders -- but Pericles was devoted to democracy from the start because he saw its capacity to bring out the greatness in each and every citizen – and uplifted his people's faith in this ideal.[Kagan, p.64] However, to succeed, democracy needs "leadership of a high order", "leaders with the talents to persuade their impatient citizens of a vision of the future, one that is powerful enough to sustain them through bad times as well as good, and compelling enough to inspire the sometimes difficult sacrifices that will be required of them in the growth of a just society.[Kagan, p.274] In light of all this, though Socrates never publically praised Pericles, it is worth wondering his conception of the ‘true king’ had Pericles in mind, for he clearly distinguish leaders who had the interest of the people from those wolves in sheep’s’ clothing who better characterize most politicians of his day. So while the oligarchs all attended the grand opening of the Parthenon, it made them furious to see Pericles policies succeed. Indeed, Pericles finds himself constantly at struggle with the conservative right wing, the oligoi (meaning 'the few'), both within his own government as well as with those who rule over Sparta - the other Greek superpower, which directly rivals Athens. The Spartans zealots (ephors) are especially threatened by this intelligent form of government called democracy, and appalled by the free speech that Pericles’ champions. Meanwhile, the Spartans have gotten into the habit of terrorizing the Athenian countryside, a technique designed to goad the Athenians into fighting - which is the one thing at which the Spartans excel. But Pericles recognizes the trap, for both cities are connected by an alliance of the rich and powerful who take their own side against the demos ('the many') of both cities alike, and want nothing more than to destroy democracy by any means possible. For democracy, more than any external enemy, threatens the privilege and property rights of the few – even those who are themselves the Athenian elite. While it helps keep order to call one’s city democratic, and to play along with elections and juries, to a point, it seems best of all, to the oligarchs, if a city can pass as democratic in name, without actually having to follow popular and participatory rule in practice. To his eternal regret, Pericles had stumbled into an oligarchic snare early in his young administration, having been persuaded (on the grounds it would prevent Athenian fathers from trading away their daughters to foreign merchants) to constrict the criteria for Greek citizenship strictly to those whose parents had both been Greek. Generosity would trickle down, he was assured by Cimon and Plato's uncle Critias, who was mainly interested in securing the public funds for 'the few' rather than 'the many'. A kinder and gentler attitude would grow among the people by way of his own generous treatment of the wealthy class, he was assured. In this, Pericles had helped set a trap into which he himself would one day step. For no sooner had Pericles passed the decree which constricted the line between citizen/voter and metic (in effect entrusting the good of the ever-growing many to the judgment of the ever decreasing few), when the oligarchs embarked upon myriad abuses of their growing power, making it possible for debt to be turned into slavery. By custom, wealthy Athenians had long bought and sold slaves from among those captured in war and offered this hard life as reprieve from a painful death. But this became the first instance in Athens’ already ancient history that Athenians were now free to buy and sell other Athenians. As political relations were severed, economic relations came to dominate, and before long, enslavement for debt became widespread and severe, until nearly one quarter of the Athenian population had been subsumed or sold off into slavery. For these and many other reasons, what would come to be called ‘Pericles’ law of Citizenship’ turned out to be a mistake that would haunt the otherwise popular leader throughout his forty-year administration. Most tragically, it would prevent him from marrying his life companion, Aspasia - his only true love - which would render his only truly worthy son illegitimate, and denying him citizenship in the process. So even before he is elected general, Pericles has already learned who not to trust. And though the Spartans, the oligarchs, and the most corruptible democrats never let up in their attempts to coerce him to serve their interests, Pericles keeps himself busy with the work of the people, engaging them in ongoing dialogue, espousing the cause of the poor wholeheartedly in public declarations, and excelling all speakers in this regard. So, unable to influence or bribe Pericles, the oligarchs pulled out all the stops to stir up the population in worry about the ‘tyranny’ of his administration. Pericles' preeminence as a speaker was made to seem suspect, as if strong leadership were incommensurate with democracy. In curious contradistinction to this, Pericles’ having his ear to the general will of the public was touted by his political enemies as evidence of his having no will of his own, and thus, no leadership capabilities. When their attempts to paint Pericles as a mere puppet of popularity prove ineffective, they attacked his work program as misuse of public funds, and while the people, for the most part, knew better, the oligarchs were nonetheless able to stir up suspicion among the allies of Athens that the money they'd contributed to their own defense was being used to glorify the city. While Pericles effectively reassured the allies that their money was indeed protecting them, he took drastic measures to show them that the monuments were indeed being built with the just spoils of a successful Athenian defense. He presented them with Pheidias, the chief architect of the Parthenon, and made display of his meticulous bookkeeping. Pheidias encouraged the assembly to weigh the gold of the statues, which had been designed so that they could. Twisting this evidence, the oligarchy undertook to rouse the people's jealousy, painting Pheidias as a pimp who brought Pericles lovers under the pretext of showing them the monuments. Next, Pericles is accused of sexual indiscretion of every kind, including an affair with his own sons’ wife. Though nothing could be further from the truth (his daughter-inlaw had come to him for council and out of trust, as women often did), the public was by this time thoroughly confused by the sheer number of accusations brought against their leader, unable to believe that at least some of them were not true. It was ironic indeed that the harder the oligarchs tried to prove Pericles rotten, the more they actually succeeded in proving his goodness. In a crowning blow, the oligarchs took up a more severe tactic. They begin arresting his friends, First among them is Pheidias, who had long been considered among the cities greatest jewels. The assembly indicts Pheidias for embezzlement, and removes him from the public eye to detention. Pericles, in his anger and frustration, takes his case directly to the people, offering to pay for the monuments out of his own pocket. In light of this noble gesture, the Athenian people are ashamed and begin to backpedal - so perhaps they don't mind paying for the monuments after all, they say. To counter this ambivalence of public opinion, the oligarchs start up a smear campaign against Pericles’ true love, the foreign born and politically astute Aspasia. And in a final blow, they succeed in so corrupting his older sons to the point that they actually publically deny him. Pericles is deeply anguished, and just when he is about to lose all faith, a worker is severely injured in a fall from one of the monuments, and as it turns out, no one but Pericles (who learns the cure from a goddess in a dream) is able to save him. And so the people's faith in their leader is temporarily restored - though not before Pheidias - Pericles’ friend and the greatest architect Athens had ever produced – is put to death in prison while the population is too distracted to notice. The oligarchs begin to encourage the Athenians to ask Pericles to sign an agreement that he would not make himself tyrant over them, Pericles loses his well known temperance. Righteously insulted, he tells his people that they will simply have to trust him and take it at his word that he would not abuse the power they have given him, or let him go. He didn’t want this job to begin with, he reminds them, and only took it because no one else stepped up to do it well. Partly out of regret, out of fear of losing him, and as a gesture of restitution for having taken the life of his friend, the assembly complies, and Pericles is restored to the pinnacle of power – albeit too briefly, for the fates would have other challenges in store for Athens. And it would have taken longer than his short life to undo the damage that had been done to the young democracy by the right wings efforts to turn the demos against the democracy itself, so ensure their government’s effort would fail. (*read about good leadership and why it’s so rare*) All this Athenian renown has worked up the insecurity of the Spartans, and there is a growing foreboding of war. The Spartan step up efforts to terrorize the Attic countryside, destroy Athenian crops and food storages, and threaten trade routes which are essential to Athenian survival, though a mere means to Athenian domination from the Spartans’ perspective. In what turns out to be a fateful move, Pericles also begins bringing those who live outside the walls of Athens back within the city for protection - unwittingly setting up conditions favorable to plague in the process. Pericles, who knows the choice is to protect those routes from the Spartan wolves or watch his city starve, also calls a council of all the cities of the Hellas. When the Megarians (once allies who had gone over to the Spartans) are reported to have killed the messenger who came to invite them to the council, Pericles puts out a decree of sanctions ordering economic embargo until arbitration brings them to peaceful terms. And when the oligarchies of both Megara and Sparta resist arbitration, Pericles refuses to rescind the decree, and tensions between the two cities explode. Though he too is furious, Pericles can barely restrain the hotheaded young Athenians from taking their revenge. He is famous for his ability to communicate a calming caution though, and he dissuades the angry troops from going prematurely into battle, saying -- "If you will not listen to me, you would do well to wait for that wisest of all counselors, Time." When many good citizens who would not wait end up dead, these words ring loud in the memory of the city, and bring Pericles great repute. Meanwhile, feeling war swooping down upon Athens and observing the growing signs of plague in the overcrowded city, Pericles consults the seer, Lampon, and the natural philosopher, Anaxagoras, on the wisdom of going to war - a war the sacred Oracle at Delphi had warned the Athenians would lose. The seer brings forth from Pericles country-home a one-horned goat, claiming this to be a sign that all the people of Greece would come together under one power. Whereupon Anaxagoras quickly beheads the goat and cuts open the head to show the natural cause to be that the brain of the animal had grown in an abnormal way. Pericles, properly appalled at the display, nonetheless duly considers the advice of both, and concludes just because there is a cause does not indicate that there is not also a meaning. And so with this he proceeds to prepare for war, which is beginning to appear inevitable. Soon thereafter, Anaxagoras is arrested. As the natural philosopher and teacher who was known to be responsible for Pericles' fearlessness in a time of widespread superstition, the oligarchs know Pericles would do almost anything to save him. Indeed, it takes the efforts of both Pericles and Socrates to even find him in exile, where he has been starved and is near death. Pericles blames himself, lamenting that ‘one who needs a lamp ought at least provide it with fuel.’ Before long, Pericles' sons come down with plague, his sister dies from it, as do some of his advisors, one by one. And as the oligarchs’ campaign to corrupt the voice of the people grows ever more effective, Aspasia herself is put on trial for impiety. In his sorrow and anger, Pericles takes on the assembly full force, where it is his tears that manage to free his lover and cherished advisor. And when the opportunity comes for him to revenge the myriad indignities that the Spartans had visited upon the Athenians, Pericles proves himself to be above it - for it was not a war between cities, after all, but a war of the rich and powerful few against the many poor to whom democracy would give voice and power. It may have been in their class interest that the oligarchs behaved, but they did not represent the whole class. Not all those who are rich are unjustly so! There are right ways to become and be wealthy too. And finally, his anger at the oligarchy for their role in deceiving and confusing the public—particularly his own sons—could be restrained no longer, which brings him at last to take up arms against the enemies of democracy. Thus, after thirty years of peace, the Athenians are flung into the Peloponnesian War - a campaign that would last twenty-seven years and would keep the city too preoccupied ever after to realize her full potentials again. And despite a lunar eclipse, which spooks his superstitious troops, Pericles is able to restore their confidence and move them to defend themselves, their city, and their rightful freedoms. And though Pericles himself is stricken with plague by now, he is said to have fought best of all. And at the funeral of his last 'legitimate' son, Pericles breaks down and cries for the loss of his city. The people of Athens, ashamed and filled with sympathy, are so moved that they vote to exempt his only truly worthy child, young Pericles, the son of his beloved Aspasia, from the law of citizenship that Pericles himself had decreed - thereby conferring upon Young Pericles his father's name and succession, and effectively forgiving the elder Pericles for his tragic humanness in the process. (read Funeral Oration*) Pericles, like all humans, could only do his best, which was, after all, never perfect. He made up for what he could not do by doing what he could. And to the best of his ability, Pericles kept an ideal of participatory democracy before the eyes of his people, knowing they could not hit a target they did not aim at! Pericles died soon thereafter, but not before all the great monuments had been completed in the course of his administration, all while the public treasury had steadily increased, and the people themselves had been fed and well kept. Though the plague had carried off a full quarter of her population, Athens herself has survived and ultimately prospered. And when it was discovered that in all his forty years at the pinnacle of power, Pericles had not increased his own estate by a single drachma, his true character came to light, and his loss was swiftly appreciated – for another like him was nowhere to be found. Athens had only wolves left to protect her, but who would protect her from the wolves? Pericles would be remembered as having achieved the balance of courage and temperance in his rule that Socrates so idealized – a goal that is seldom achieved in any human life, least of all one given to politics. But this success was not without cost to those he cared most about, including his sons and his ward, Alcibiades, whose proper rearing he was charged in hindsight with having neglected, as if anything more could have been done. This proved especially tragic considering that Alcibiades - despite Socrates best efforts - goes on to single-handedly become the ruin of Athens. After Pericles' death, the great general Nicias (Socrates' friend, student, and comrade in arms) was able to secure the peace for some time. Like Pericles, Nicias pledged to protect the city above all else, but his best efforts prove inadequate in the task, and his tenure as elder statesman proved ineffective. So when Alcibiades got the misguided notion into his head to invade Syracuse, the richest port in the sea, he is able to prey on the widespread discontent, using the power of the mob to put down his political rivals, including the well-respected Nicias. Nicias, who resisted Alcibiades ill-advised plan, was picked up bodily by the crowd on Alcibiades' urging, and set onto the boat that was to take him to his death. He was remembered by all who witnessed it to have wept like a sad child as the shores of his beloved Athens receded from his sight for the last time. When a messenger reported back to the Athenians that this once-great general, who had never lost a battle in his life and was well-loved by the people for it, had been taken prisoner and died in the custody of the Spartans, the story seemed so unbelievable that the messenger was stretched on the rack until word came that his story was actually true. At this, the mob was stupefied - for how could such a terrible end come to such a good man? And if this wasn’t bad enough, Socrates' dear friend and Plato's elder cousin, Charmides, is slain in the process as the so-called democracy expunges Athens of all her dissident voices. Plato himself is witness as Charmides is coerced by their own uncle Critias into the hopeless and ill-fated battle where he was certain to meet his death. (*read Socrates and Glaucon on how outward misfortunes do not measure a person’s happiness, for there is struggle in every life, and it is the ability to respond with strength and intelligence, or not, that makes good or harm come of it. Can Socrates show Nicias to have been happy in the truest sense of the word?*) Capable of such treachery as this, it is no surprise to anyone when Alcibiades was the first to come to mind when the sacred statues of Hermes were separated from their penises (though it may well have been Critias behind the plot). The assembly was quick to charge him with this most offensive impiety, and was about to arrest him, when Alcibiades fled to the enemy camp. Once there, Alcibiades took readily to Spartan ways, and quickly made friends with the king. It wasn’t long before he was giving away Athens’ war strategies, impregnating the king’s wife, and ultimately fleeing for his life to Persia, of all places, where he proceeded to trade both Athenian and Spartan military secrets for his protection. By this time, the so-called democracy, long since poisoned by the rhetoric of those who would profit by her demise, bears little resemblance to the real thing. Under the influence of Cleon, who corrupts the people's respect for the minority voice by breaking down the decorum of listening in assembly, public deliberation degenerates into partisan argument, and we see why democracy is vulnerable to manipulation and socalled ‘mob rule’ – which, ironically. Is a tactic used by the oligarchy to infiltrate and sabotage the demos with campaigns of misinformation…people using words they don’t understand (‘democracy’ and ‘republic’) to confuse others who don’t understand either. When the loudest and most solicitous voice can carry the day, participatory democracy is perverted into mere 'representative' - which it hardly ever is - and people then must face the problem of who to trust, having little choice but to believe the best liar. And what is left is democracy in name only. Indeed, it is just such a mob which, acting on Cleon's urging, rashly puts Young Pericles to death. And so we see what happens when reason fails and lies assert themselves as truth, for when honesty, selfknowledge, and dialogue - all essential to a healthy democracy - are lost, Athens quickly declines into a series of bloody massacres, including the brief 'Tyranny of the Thirty Oligarchs', in which Plato's uncle Critias is the prime and most bloodthirsty mover. And so, without a shepherd, the sheep come to be ruled by the wolves, and it is not long before all dissident voices come to be eaten alive. Socrates knew it was just a matter of time. Refusing to be made complicit in this or any tyranny, Socrates defies the wrath of the oligarchs by denying their order for him to assist in putting his friends to death. Critias cautions Socrates to desist from asking questions, or else—at which point Socrates seizes the opportunity to step it up, and inquires of Critias himself, ‘What is happiness made of, after all?’ and ‘What good is a tyrant, to himself, or to the state?’ This discussion (which comes down to us as ‘The Republic’ and other dialogues of the so-called middle period) spanned the reaches of human knowledge – in may ways, further advanced then than now. And in it, they sort what is from what could be, holding up the authoritarian pretext that passes for an ideal state to ask, ‘What is wrong with this picture?’ And in the process they discern the difference between the mere appearance of democracy and the real thing - a lesson we need desperately to remember! The Ancient Athenians learned the hard way that democracy, like everything else that is alive, is always changing - always either getting better or getting worse, either toward justice or away from it. As we have said, democracy is more than a form of government, it is a way of life based on the golden rule. If polity were understood better, we’d see that even in a system of representative democracy, we each and all have a part to play – especially when we do our part to teach the young well about how to participate at whatever level they work. This is why Socrates emphasizes doing one’s part, minding one’s business sounds, to us, to connote keeping out of politics, but understood properly, it’s more likely to represent seeing all our actions as political, that is, an exercise of power. This meant doing well in all that is a person’s proper sphere of response-ability. So a person was understood to have a moral obligation to do what they had the ability to do – not merely to appear good, but to actually be good. And that challenge is different for all – every hero’s journey is different. Yours is yours to make of what you will, recognizing that, being inextricably interconnected with others, those who fail to become hero let down more than themselves. So (whether you chose or merely would have chosen this life, it is everyone’s obligation to find the good that can be learned from all the challenges one faces on any given path. Learn from them, and pass them on. That’s what you are good for. :-) The critical variable, it turns out, is (as Aristotle later argues…read here*) is not how many rule, but how well -- which is to say, how justly. For democracy is as open to corruption as any other form of government, if it forgets to properly deliberate. For true ideals are easy to lose sight of, for what comes to light in our dialogue can disappear in our silence…especially when what is called ideal aims only at a low standard (such as they discuss in the form of the guardian state, that appears ideal, but doesn’t prevent injustice from arising: read here*). But ideals can be remembered with the help of an inspired voice – and Socrates is certainly this - the ultimate coach giving the supreme pep talk to the human race. Ultimately, it is the beautiful Alcibiades, who (much to the chagrin of his many other lovers) publicly proclaims his lifelong love for Socrates, and makes clear that it was indeed the power of love that the old philosopher was trying to teach, by doing what was good or the boy, not necessarily for himself. For ‘love is the only thing,’ Socrates ultimately concludes, ‘that I ever claim to know anything about.’ Being dedicated sincerely to Alcibiades true good, rather than to his own physical pleasures, Socrates was unlike Alcibiades’ other lovers in the temperance that he lived by. For having resisted Alcibiades' sexual advances all these many years (a fact the seductive Alcibiades could hardly believe possible) Socrates had proved himself capable of almost super-human inner strength. And with this Alcibiades ultimately proved himself both the greatest general and the worst turncoat the Athenians had ever known. Despite Socrates’ best efforts, Alcibiades turns out to have been a chameleon, after all. For though he managed to resist the worst elements of the democracy, he falls prey in the end to the seduction of the worst oligarchs, ultimately selling out the democracy and his own men for the sake of his own safe harbor. And in what might have been his final drunken stupor, Alcibiades confesses to his full host of sins, including trading military secrets with the enemy, and worse, selling out the democracy herself to the oligarchs in exchange for safe passage home. So we are not surprised at all when all - the Spartan King, the Persian satrap, the oligarchs and democrats alike - unleash their respective thugs to do away with Alcibiades. And his fiery death comes, as Socrates had foreseen, because the failure of his reason to master his appetites had ruined both him and his country. (*read Symposium here) And in his grief, Socrates is left wondering at the irony of it all - for saving Alcibiades' life had seemed like the right thing to do at the time… But since he had gone on to single-handedly ruin Athens and bring down her only hope for democracy, it was not at all clear in the end that it was for the good after all. Socrates did his best, but human power, like human knowledge, is limited…even doing one’s best can backfire. And so one’s best is never perfect. It is one’s best, all the same, and in doing it, one has done one’s part, even achieved excellence – a healthier ideal than perfection, after all. And with this, we return to the courtroom, where Socrates concludes his provocative defense. And among his closing arguments are his famous claims that “the unexamined life is not worth living,” and being afraid of death is just another way of pretending to know what we cannot possibly in this human life. For all we know, death might be the greatest good, for no harm can come to a good person! At least they won’t put you to death there for asking questions! If you will do justice by me, he entreats them, please make sure to behave toward my sons just as I have behaved toward yours. In the end, the corrupt democracy of Athens was—like our own—confused by the deceits, conceits, and violence of its age. And in 399 BC, the assembly voted to put Socrates to death for the crime of honoring the worthy by teaching the young to think for themselves. And the irony should not escape out notice that it was Anytus, youthful seducer and jealous lover of Alcibiades, who brought the charges against Socrates of ‘corrupting the youth of Athens’. For his part, Socrates only purpose was "to give the young a respite, lest they become disheartened by the cynicism of their age"—hope for which they have more need today than ever. Whether or not he succeeded remains to be seen, for as he made clear in his defense, and we’ve seen by how history has carried his example forward – you can more easily kill the dreamer than the dream. And so it was that, when the old philosopher was finally silenced by the so-called democracy for being a threat to the powers-that-be…all because he taught their sons, daughters, and importantly, their young lovers, to question their authority too intelligently (undoubtedly the same reason his voice is still obscured today), Plato dedicated his life to recalling Socrates’ voice for future generations to remember. Aware of the power of words for both good and evil, he resolved to take on the task of recalling for the future the astonishing events he has witnessed and the powerful lessons he had learned. Only time would tell if these mournful seeds would grow into something good, for while nothing dies that is remembered, nothing is remembered by those who die – and like many times throughout history, many have been put to death to encourage, and even compel, this deliberate forgetting, this active ignorance of truth, in favor of one version of it. Plato knew it is up to those who live on to carry the flame of truth forward. And so Plato, like Socrates, and Confucius, and so many others before him, took up his mission… After and during a long life of trying to promote Socrates philosopher king ideal (a mission that got him kidnapped and enslaved more than once, and is worthy of it’s own chapter, at least (*read here), Plato went on to found in the garden of Hacademus a school they would call his 'Academy', where Aristotle—arguably the most influential thinker of all time—would study for nearly twenty years (but that’s another story). It was at the Academy that Plato would undertake (against the will of his oligarchic family) what would become a lifelong mission of recalling the dialogues of Socrates for the world—which might actually be ready for them someday. One can only hope that day is soon. Because we are unlikely to get another chance! As we’ve seen, Plato himself shows up in these dialogues only once or twice, most pointedly when Socrates turns to him in court that fateful day and suggests that perhaps Plato would be the one who will remember all this for posterity. It would seem that, despite his caution about the danger of saying too much, Plato understood true power, the kind that would have us still learning from his writing all these many centuries later. And Plato was only one of many students who loved the quirky old Socrates and so grew up listening at his feet. Under the influence of his teaching, they would go on after his execution to change the world in a way no single generation ever had or perhaps would again. No less than twenty-nine of the young men of Athens undertook dialogues to commemorate Socrates voice after his death. Only Plato’s survive in their entirety, as far as we know. Xenophon too wrote memoirs that give us another eye on some of Plato’s account. Plato’s Academy would carry on continuously for nine full centuries, becoming the longest lasting educational establishment the world would ever know. But all along the sad and supreme irony remains that 'academics' so often become, like their ancient sophist counterparts, seduced by the political power of rhetoric as a tool of class interests, wealth, and privilege, rendering democracy virtually incapable of the intelligent deliberation that the ancients knew to be essential to justice. For all the effort that hard working teachers put in, it’s possible that we’ve all learned by a teaching model that has mislead our best intentions. For to deliberately teach what one generation of one culture has deemed appropriate for the next generation to learn opens the door to all kinds of inadvertent censorship, in that it assumes any generation knows best what truth is. The dialectic ideal of education would have us get out of the way of their discovery…let learning follow the lead of their questions. Education as the search for truth encourages other teaching qualities than follow the leader that tends to be our habit. Think for yourself, and let others help, is closer to the Socratic ideal of education as the mutual search for truth. And because of this, they knew, corrupt human nature is only a problem, unless and until we remember those Socratic potentials that human beings still and always have within – and how to teach them. For humans may forget, malign, and ignore it, but the good thing about the truth is that it stays true—and the challenge to humanity is to remember! And it remains true that anything that can be understood in one inspired moment lives on, and waits, to be recalled in yet another. Though Socrates' demise is held by generations since to have been the death of the Golden Age, it was also the birth of Western Culture—for whatever that's been or may yet be worth. Little did anyone realize then, except perhaps Socrates, that it would take 2000 years and the lucky ‘discovery’ of a ‘new world’ – not to mention rivers of blood - before the seeds of democracy would find fertile soil once again. But we are left wondering if we are indeed engaged in true democracy? Or have we misunderstood the ideal so much that we have missed the mark? What does this mean? It means – the ancients would teach us – that the ideal of democracy is actualized in how we live, how we talk to one another, now we contribute our work to the whole. And what we call the Socratic method, these days, was originally understood as a way of treating one another fairly, with due respect and good will. Sadly, thanks to the game of telephone that sometimes occurs in education, Socrates way of teaching is seldom remembered this way, but it can be shown that the Socratic method was both more, and in a sense less, than we have come to think of it. It is not merely a way of teaching, as we think of teaching, but a way of treating one another by way of the golden rule. It is the way of teaching that habituates sincere and thoughtful reasoning and encourages the democratic character by equal respect paid to others in our discussions with them and our actions that effect them. Understood in this healthy form, the Socratic method is simply the art of eye to eye dialogue, and done well, it has the power to heal human relationships. And we are, each and all, engaged in dialogic relationships, for we are more often than we realize both teachers and students. This ideal of dialectic education can be shown to be essential to healthy democracy, just as the history of the world’s first democracy can show democracy gone wrong. Perhaps you can tell by now why I say that the story of the decline of the world’s first democracy in Periclean Athens should ring hauntingly familiar to us. If not yet, you will as you become increasingly familiar with how our modern democracy has evolved, and how it too often dysfunctions today. And while this is exactly the reason we need this story told and retold, again and again, it is also the reason it’s unlikely to get its due in the American film industry (to which the concept of a ‘writing ethic’ is apparently completely foreign). So, while I continue to work on what has become a 1500 page manuscript (twenty-five hours of film, as screenplay formatting goes), after so many years of authenticating this story, I cannot possibly bring myself to simply ‘sell it’ and watch all my careful research and meticulous referencing go out the window for the sake of the bottom line. I owe it to Socrates not to let that happen. So I’ve resolved that, if I want to see this done well, I’m going to have to either produce it myself -- or find filmmakers whose hearts and motivations are beyond profit and politics. Wish me luck! Meanwhile, my research has become fodder for many other good things, such as this course, this book, and perhaps someday, a film about this, the life of Socrates, and the greatest story never told, that could still save our democracy, if we would only learn from it while there is time!