Announcements • Clarifying Universal Grammar vs Internalized Grammatical Rules – UG = a theory that all languages rely on a set of highly abstract, unconscious rules—innate knowledge of the general form that language can take (Nature) – IGR = learning through experience the specific grammatical rules of a particular language but learning the overall “rules” rather than word by word (Nurture) • Fast-mapping (the word need not be contrasted with anything, it is quick word to world mapping/pairing through brief exposure or incidental learning rather than direct teaching) Mental State Reasoning: ‘Theory of Mind’ Today’s Plan: • Last of Video on Non-human ‘language’ and symbol use • A little Trivia Exercise • Research on mental state reasoning or ‘Theory of Mind’ • How one’s ‘theory of mind’ can help learn language Theory of mind is the ability to reason about psychological/mental states in one’s self or in someone else. (e.g. “mind”-reading, not ESP) How do infants, children, adults, non-human animals (?), understand or reason about the mind e.g. Emotions, Desires, Intentions, Knowledge,Thoughts/Beliefs, etc. It is one thing to HAVE emotions, thoughts, etc.—it is quite another to be able to THINK about them! Why do we need a theory of mind? Reason 1: Understanding what a person is thinking, feeling, believes etc helps us predict how they will act and/or interpret their behavior For example: • Sarah’s dog is missing. • Sarah hears a scratching noise in the shed. • She goes to the shed and opens the door and finds a squirrel. • She begins to cry. How do we make sense of behavior? (e.g. triangles moving clip, Stewardess in the aisle that bumps herself on the forehead) Why do we need a theory of mind? Reason 2: Successful communication with another person requires appreciating what the other person knows, doesn’t know, and how knowledge can be acquired. e.g. teaching Reason 3: Learning through social transmission (knowing who knows more, who to learn from) e.g. deciding who or when to learn from someone Others reasons: e.g. deception, surprises, tricks, jokes, etc. How to test for a ‘Theory of Mind’? • Historical Background: Research began in 1970s with chimps—do they reason about the beliefs of other chimps? – Where will Chimp A think Chimp B will look? Location A or Location B (where the food is) – Chimp A expected Chimp B to look in Location B – Interpretation: Chimp A thinks Chimp B believes the food is in Location B – Criticism: Could succeed without any understanding of the mind of the other, to show theory of mind they must reason about a false belief (counter to reality) • The birth of the classic test: False Belief tasks as a litmus test of a theory of mind 1. Displacement Tasks (aka Sally-Ann or Maxi Tasks) 2. The Unexpected Contents Task (aka the “Smarties” task) 3. Appearance-Reality Tasks Video Segment: A Change of Mind False Belief Results • Results from the classic false belief tasks: –4 year olds succeed at the task, 3 year olds fail!! • What do the results mean? –Children younger than four do not understand that people can hold beliefs that are false? • Or is there an alternative explanation? Two Broad Theories 1) Radical Shift Theory—Conceptual Change View – children prior to the age of four are unable to attribute belief states to themselves and others. – lack concept of false beliefs—kids have a ‘copy-theory’ of the world (the mind = reality) 2) Processing Demands Theory – More continuous view of development – young children fail these tasks because they lack the attentional, mneumonic, linguistic, or processing resources, rather than the ability to attribute false beliefs. An example of a Processing Demands View A ‘Curse of Knowledge’ Account Definition: A difficulty appreciating a more naïve perspective as the result of being biased by one’s own knowledge. Examples Car salesmen Anagram Study ‘Sarcastic’ passages study Parallels Between Adults’ and Children’s Knowledge Reasoning Predicting What Others will Think • Subjects read descriptions of events that could have various outcomes. In one condition, subjects were told the outcome, in another condition they were not. • They were asked to judge what others who did not know the outcome would predict. • Subjects who knew the outcome thought others would be much more likely to predict that outcome. . Fischhoff (1975) Like the children who claimed Sally would know that her chocolate had been moved, adults claimed that others would share their outcome knowledge. Parallels Between Adults’ and Children’s Knowledge Reasoning Recalling Your Own Earlier Thoughts • Subjects were asked prior to Nixon’s trip to China and the USSR to estimate the probability of the various outcomes. • 2 weeks - 6 months later they were asked to recall their predictions • Subjects remembered giving much higher probabilities than they actually had to the outcomes that took place. Fischhoff & Beyth (1975) Like children who claimed they knew all along that there were pencils in the box, adults showed a more subtle effect by giving biased recollections of what they had previously predicted. Questions of Interest • Do young children find it easier to assess what someone else will know when they are not “cursed” with knowledge? • Are younger children more susceptible to the curse of knowledge than older children? • Is this why young children do poorly on false belief tasks? Method Familiar Unfamiliar “Percy’s played with all of these toys before! He brought all of these from home.” “Percy’s never ever seen these toys before! These are brand new.” No Curse (Ignorant) Cursed (Knowledgeable) Children were told there was a special little thing in each one. Children were shown what was inside each one before it was closed again. Experimenter: “Does Percy know what’s inside this one?” Predictions Children would judge that Percy knows what is inside the toys he is familiar with, and will not know what is inside the toys he is unfamiliar with. But, the curse of knowledge would work against this appreciation, leading children to overestimate Percy’s knowledge when they knew what was inside. The magnitude of the curse of knowledge would decline with age. "Yes" Responses Yes Responses to “Does Percy Know What is Inside?” 6 Familiar 5 Unfamiliar 4 3 2 1 0 Age 3 Age 4 Age 5 Significant main effect of familiarity Significant effect of familiarity at each age “Does Percy know what is inside?” (for Unfamiliar toys) Child Knowledgeable 6 Child Ignorant "Yes" Responses 5 4 p < .05 p < .05 3 2 1 0 3 4 5 Age in Years • 3- and 4-year-olds, but not 5-year-olds, overestimated Percy’s knowledge when they were knowledgeable. • The magnitude of the curse significantly decreased from age 3 to age 5. Birch & Bloom (2003) Psychological Science “Does Percy know what is inside?” (for Familiar toys) Child Knowledgeable Child Ignorant 6 "Yes" Responses 5 4 3 2 1 0 3 4 5 Age in Years • an asymmetry in perspective-taking--No ‘curse of ignorance’ • when taking another point of view—it is harder to put aside one’s knowledge than one’s ignorance. •You get the same asymmetry pattern with adult’s reaction times and trivia judgments Percy’s Knowledge Study: Conclusions • Children are sensitive to the knowledge states of others, but the curse of knowledge can work against this sensitivity • The magnitude of the curse of knowledge decreases significantly from age 3 to age 5 • Children’s knowledge assessments are biased asymmetrically and cannot be reduced to ‘egocentrism’. – They are biased by their knowledge when assessing what someone else knows, but are not biased by their ignorance (see Birch & Bloom, 2003, Psychological Science) False Belief Experiment Would adults experience difficulty attributing false beliefs if they were knowledgeable of the outcome, compared to adults who did not know the outcome? False Belief Experiment Participants • 210 Introductory Psychology Students Design • ‘Sally-Ann’ Questionnaire using 4 locations instead 2. • Probability judgments were measured instead of where will she look False Belief Attribution • Vicki places her violin in the blue box and goes outside. False Belief Attribution • While Vicki is outside, her sister, Denise, comes in and rearranges all the boxes. False Belief Attribution ? a ? ? Cursed (standard) Condition = object is moved to “the red” container (the participant knows where it is) No Curse Condition = object is moved to “another” container (the participant does not know where it is) When Vicki comes back she wants to find her violin, what’s the probability she will first look in each of the containers? Red Green Purple Blue No Curse 23% 3% 2% 71% Curse 34% 4% 6% 59% Birch & Bloom (under review), Cognition; see also Birch & Bloom (2004) Trends in Cognitive Science Mechanisms and Implications Mechanisms (Why the decrease with age?) • Increasing inhibitory control? • Increasing source memory? Implications • Decreased empathy? Increased guilt, shame? • Indirect effects (social judgments)? • Education, Law, Business, Politics, all interpersonal communication This is Linda. This is Jeff. Artwork by Susan Chen Jeff pulls Linda’s hair. How mean is Jeff? Keep in mind… •There is more to passing the false belief task than theory of mind. •There is more to theory of mind than passing the false belief task So how do they do it? Solving the Reference Problem • • • • • Whole Object Bias Taxonomic Bias Basic-level Bias Shape Bias Linguistic Context (grammatical form of the word) • Syntactic Bootstrapping (grammatical structure of sentence) • Mutual Exclusivity Bias • Theory of Mind and Pragmatics Theory of Mind and Word Learning • Pragmatic explanation of Lexical Contrast • Joint attention and Inferred Intent? • Sensitivity to when a goal is satisfied (Bucket Study) • Deciding Who is More Knowledgeable. Who do I want to learn from? (e.g. Tracking knowledge over time) • Body language, gestures, and paralinguistic info indicative of knowledge/confidence Mutual Exclusivity (revisited) Where is the blicket? Theory of Mind and Word Learning “Look at this one. It’s a jop! See, it’s a jop. This is a jop”. “Look at this one. It’s nice. This one is cool. It’s neat.” “Can you give me the bem?” Pragmatic (Theory of Mind) account of Lexical Contrast “Can you give me the bem?” The speaker wants one of those two objects. If she wanted me to give her the one she called jop she would have done so in some way I would understand (e.g. She knows I know what a jop is). But instead she used a different word--She must intend to refer to something different. “Look at this one. My uncle gave me this one. My uncle gave this to me. This is the one my uncle gave to me.” “Look at this one. It’s nice. This one is cool. It’s neat.” “Can you give me the one I keep in the kitchen?” Same Speaker Results: The other one--not the one my uncle gave me Different Speaker Results: 50/50 Not specific constraint to word learning, but specific to the mind of the other person. Theory of Mind and Word Learning • Pragmatic explanation of Lexical Contrast • Joint attention and Inferred Intent? • Sensitivity to when a goal is satisfied (Bucket Study) • Deciding Who is More Knowledgeable. Who do I want to learn from? • Body language, gestures, and paralinguistic info indicative of knowledge/confidence Joint Attention & Inferred intent/desire Eyes as a Window to the Mind What the eyes can say Keeping Track of Previously Knowledgeable Speakers History Phase “I think that’s a spoon. Yeah, that’s a spoon. I think that’s a comb. Yeah, that’s a comb.” etc. History Phase “I think that’s a fork. Yeah, that’s a fork. I think that’s a shoe. Yeah, that’s a shoe.” etc. Naming Phase Ben: “I think that’s a ferber. Yeah, That’s a ferber. Do you see the ferber?” Jenny: “I think that’s a ferber. Yeah, That’s a ferber. Do you see the ferber?” Testing Phase “Can you give me the ferber? Where’s the ferber?” Testing Phase ? Different Word Test Condition: “Can you give me the koba? Where’s the koba?” Word Learning: Paralinguistic and Nonverbal Cues Imitation: Nonverbal Cues Putting Cues together Example: Learning a Proper Name “There’s Jessie!” Cues to a Proper Name’s Referent • Syntax, Linguistic Context (Katz, Baker, & Macnamara, 1974) • Range of reference (Hall, 1996; Hall & Belanger, in press) • Eye-Gaze, joint attention (Baldwin, 1991) • Mutual Exclusivity (Clark, 1993; Hall & Graham, 1999; see also Diesendruck & Markson, 2001) • Animacy (Gelman & Taylor, 1984; Hall, 1994; Katz et. al., 1974) –Ownership/hierarchy of importance? (Hall) • Knowing about knowledge, Familiarity, Theory of Mind (e.g. Birch & Bloom, 2002) Question of Interest • Do children understand the relationship between knowledge and familiarity? That one needs familiarity or experience with someone to know about unobservable properties (e.g. siblings, proper names) • Are they sensitive to the speaker’s knowledge state, and can they use this to help them learn the referent of a new word? That is, if a speaker uses a proper name such as “Jessie”, do they know it is more likely to apply to an individual with whom she is familiar? Method Familiar “I brought these from home. I’ve played with all of these animals before.” Unfamiliar This bag of animals is ‘discovered’. “Wow! I’ve never seen that dog before.” Proper Name Condition: “Where’s Jessie? Can you find Jessie?” Common Noun Condition: “Where’s the dog? Can you find the dog?” Results Proper Name Condition Common Noun Condition 100% 100% 80% 80% 60% 60% 40% 40% 20% 20% 0% 0% Adult s Age 4 Age 3 Age 2 Adult s Age 4 Age 3 Age 2 Proper Name Study: Summary Children as young as two are sensitive to the speaker’s knowledge state when learning new words. –They appreciate that the speaker must be familiar with an individual in order to know its proper name. –They appreciate that familiarity with a specific individual is not necessary to know a common noun. Book Recommendations ‘The Language Instinct’ by Steven Pinker ‘How Children Learning the Meanings of Words’ by Paul Bloom