AN INTRODUCTION TO CONTRACTS: THE LAW OF TRANSACTIONS PREVIEW OF THE SECOND SEMESTER We begin the second half of the course by looking at various ways in which the bargaining process might go wrong because of misbehavior by the parties or because of serious disparities in bargaining power. Law will withhold enforcement of contracts that are not fair and voluntary transactions between competent parties because they do not reliably produce the “win-win” exchanges that are valued by the basic theory of contract. Contracts that fail this test may be “voidable” because of infancy, mental incapacity, fraud, duress, bad faith, undue influence, and unconscionability. We will then look more closely at the process of forming a Paradigm 2 contract through negotiation, drafting, and signing an agreement. This will involve the role of the parol evidence rule in securing the finality and reliability of the written agreements that emerge from this process. Along the way we will repeatedly encounter the problems of contract interpretation and construction that we have already met in the law of offer and acceptance. Another recurring theme this semester will be the ways in which the law of contracts deals with the problems of risk and uncertainty. Most of the problems that contract parties encounter arise from their imperfect knowledge of the world, as it is and as it becomes. The prospect of an ugly surprise is always lurking. It is part of the role of contract agreements to allocate this risk between the parties. For example, at the outset one or both parties may be laboring under a mistake about the subject matter of the contract. They may allocate this risk by using the law of conditions and warranty. If they fail to do so, the law must sometimes allocate the risk by the law of mistake. The primary way in which contract promisors deal with the risk of an unknown is to protect themselves by using express conditions. Conditions relieve a promisor from the duty of performance if certain events occur after the contract is made. An example is the force majeure clause, which excuses non-performance in the event of a disaster. The semester will end with an introduction to judicial remedies for breach of contract. The principles that govern the award of money damages are not unique to contract law, but will also apply in tort and property law. One of the lessons of these materials is that a legal dispute is never fully resolved by a finding of liability: determining the appropriate remedy is critical to a just outcome. While the first semester focused on litigation issues, you will increasingly be asked to take the view of a transaction lawyer in the second semester. Rules of contract law such as those relating to parol evidence and express conditions enable attorneys to plan and design the legal structures that house their clients’ transactions, but they also present pitfalls that skillful attorneys must avoid. Unit 29: Capacity to Contract: Rules and Standards Read: Halbman v Lemke and Ortelere v Teachers Retirement Board in the SUPPLEMENT RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS §§ 12, 14, and 15. Key Concepts: Legal Capacity; Infancy; Rules and Standards. The course began last semester by positing an idealized model of a contractual exchange, exemplified by the Beer and Broccoli Deal. Legal enforcement of promises was justified as a way of facilitating such exchanges on the assumption that they benefit both parties. However, the assumption of mutual benefit requires that both parties are able to protect their own interests and that they have roughly equal bargaining power. In order to maximize their mutual benefits according to their own best judgment, such parties should have complete freedom of contract to design their transaction and the court should give legal effect to the deal they make. The next few units examine the scope of freedom of contract when the assumption of rationality and bargaining equality fails. An enforceable contract is a privately-made law that binds the parties. Public laws that are created by legislatures are subject to the constraints of the political process and the constitutional limits enforced by the judiciary. Those structural elements provide some limits on the degree of oppression and unfairness of public law. Private contract parties are not constrained by constitutional or political limits, however, and any limitation of their exercise of power over each other through the device of contract must come from the courts or the legislatures in the form of the rules and principles we are about to review. You may think of these rules as limitations on private advantage-taking through the use of contracts and as corrections to a regime of untrammeled freedom of contract. These rules and principles rest on inherently value-laden ideas, with the values more obvious than those that are implicit in the rules of contract that we have been studying. The source of these values is harder to describe than the economic or utilitarian justifications of law and economics reasoning. Indeed, some law and economics scholars and judges reject traditionally-conceived values, such as good faith, justice, and fairness, which have furnished the historical underpinning of these doctrines. Lawyers who appear before such judges must be “bilingual,” able to speak the language of tradition and of law and economics as the occasion may call for. Rules and Standards This Unit also introduces an important jurisprudential concept with a wide application. The difference between rules and standards is a distinction that you will encounter throughout your legal career. To illustrate it, consider the difference between these two traffic regulations: (1) "All motor vehicles traveling on a class two highway must not exceed 50 miles per hour." (2) "All motor vehicles traveling on a class two highway must travel at a reasonable rate of speed in light of road conditions." Each of these is a common form of enforceable legal rule. They differ in the degree of specificity with which they describe the prohibited conduct. The first refers to a definite, measurable quantity, while the second uses a general, purposeful description. It has become common to refer to the sort of regulation exemplified in (1) as a "rule" [or "bright-line rule" or "per se" rule] and to the sort of regulation exemplified in (2) as a "standard." So the word "rule", somewhat confusingly, can refer either to any sort of regulation or law or to a law framed in specific, quantifiable terms. Here is an example of each kind of regulation from the UCC statute of frauds, § 2-201 (2): Between merchants if within a reasonable time a writing in confirmation of the contract and sufficient against the sender is received and the party receiving it has reason to know its contents, it satisfies the requirements of subsection (1) against such party unless written notice of objection to its contents is given within ten days after it is received. The first emphasized phrase is a standard, the second is a rule. In tort law, you will encounter numerous examples of rules and standards. "Negligence" is sometimes defined as conduct that is “unreasonably dangerous,” which is a standard. But violation of some safety regulations is "Negligence per se", which is a rule. Property law too has its rules (e.g. the statutory period of time an adverse possessor must satisfy to acquire title) and its standards (a residential landlord must provide "habitable" premises.) You will find numerous rules in Constitutional law (e.g. a candidate for president must be 35 years old) but even more standards (no one may be deprived of life, liberty, or property without "due process of law"; persons are to be secure in their persons, houses, papers and effects against "unreasonable" searches and seizures.) Although the "rules" of civil procedure contain mostly "rule" rules (e.g. 20 days to answer a complaint) even here one can find lurking a few "standard" rules (e.g. Rule 11's requirement that a pleader's certification be formed after an inquiry "reasonable under the circumstances.") Rules and standards each have advantages and disadvantages. In light of their purposes, rules can be under-inclusive over-inclusive: they can miss some of their intended targets and hit some unintended targets. This problem results because rules often must use something as an objective test that does not perfectly correlate with their intended purpose. For example, speed limits are aimed at unsafe driving, but miles-perhour is an imperfect measure of unsafe driving. Some people might be able to drive safely at over-the-limit speeds and some drivers are unsafe even within the speed limit. For another example, some employees can work effectively well beyond the age of 65, while others should retire at 50. Because rules operate arbitrarily, they tend to beget exceptions that are expressed as standards. Thus, we temper the contract infancy rule described in Halbman with an exception for "necessaries," which is a flexible, context-specific term that a court can use to achieve justice in cases in which operation of the rule might seem arbitrary. Other examples are the exceptions to bright-line rules where "justice" requires. An example appears the damages rule of RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 351 (3). In a similar way, standards tend to beget bright-line rules that increase their predictability and decrease the cost of litigation. Rule-like offspring of standards include "safe harbors" and per se rules. For example, negligence is a standard turning on the reasonableness of the defendant's conduct, but if the defendant violates a certain type of statute she is negligent per se. This is a bright line drawn within a vague category. Contract law offers another example: a contract offer lapses after a "reasonable time" (a standard) but automatically upon the death of the offeror (a bright-line rule). Today’s cases involve both a classic rule (Halbman) and a classic standard (Ortolere) in the context of contractual incapacity. Capacity refers to the legal ability to bind oneself to a contract. Here is what the Restatement of Contracts says about the capacity to enter legally binding contracts: SEC. 12: Capacity to Contract. (1) No one can be bound by contract who has not legal capacity to incur at least voidable contractual duties. Capacity to contract may be partial and its existence in respect of a particular transaction may depend upon the nature of the transaction or upon other circumstances. (2) A natural person who manifests assent to a contract has full legal capacity to incur contractual duties thereby unless he is (a) under guardianship, or (b) an infant, or (c) mentally ill or defective, or (d) intoxicated. The first thing to notice about the list in subsection (2) is that it is limited: there is, for example, no exception for persons who are naive, overly-trusting, unfamiliar with the dominant culture or language, impoverished, buzzed-but-not-drunk, desperate, uneducated, unintelligent, or who have very poor judgment. Second, this list purports to be exhaustive. Unlike the standard of good faith, which is an excluder term that is never comprehensively defined, capacity is deemed to exist unless one of four enumerated circumstances exists. This suggests that the concept may be underinclusive because it will not reach some circumstances that would justify avoidability. Third, this list is historically contingent: at certain times and in some jurisdictions, it has included members of certain racial and national groups, married women, and others who now have the full capacity to contract. Finally, the list is dichotomous, not a continuum: a person is either competent or incompetent. If you are only somewhat subnormal in intelligence or judgment, you are "fair game." Advantage-taking through contracting is officially approved unless a rather dramatic invalidating cause can be found. Nevertheless, despite the rule-like nature of these categories, some of them lend themselves to "standard-like" definitions, e.g. "intoxicated." Is it an advantage or a disadvantage to be included in this list? (Trick question: the answer is “yes.”) THE JURISPRUDENCE OF RULES: INFANCY Halbman v. Lemke 298 N.W.2d 562 (Wisc. 1980). Callow, J. On this review we must decide whether a minor who disaffirms a contract for the purchase of a vehicle which is not a necessity must make restitution to the vendor for damage sustained by the vehicle prior to the time the contract was disaffirmed. The court of appeals affirmed the judgment in part, reversed in part, and remanded the cause to the [trial] court . . . On or about July 13, 1973, James Halbman, Jr. (Halbman), a minor, entered into an agreement with Michael Lemke (Lemke) whereby Lemke agreed to sell Halbman a 1968 Oldsmobile for the sum of $1,250. Lemke was the manager of L & M Standard Station in Greenfield, Wisconsin, and Halbman was an employee at L & M. At the time the agreement was made Halbman paid Lemke $1,000 cash and took possession of the car. Arrangements were made for Halbman to pay $25 per week until the balance was paid, at which time title would be transferred. About five weeks after the purchase agreement, and after Halbman had paid a total of $1,100 of the purchase price, a connecting rod on the vehicle's engine broke. Lemke, while denying any obligation, offered to assist Halbman in installing a used engine in the vehicle if Halbman, at his expense, could secure one. Halbman declined the offer and in September took the vehicle to a garage where it was repaired at a cost of $637.40. Halbman did not pay the repair bill. In October of 1973, Lemke endorsed the vehicle's title over to Halbman, although the full purchase price had not been paid by Halbman, in an effort to avoid any liability for the operation, maintenance, or use of the vehicle. On October 15, 1973, Halbman returned the title to Lemke by letter which disaffirmed the purchase contract and demanded the return of all money theretofore paid by Halbman. Lemke did not return the money paid by Halbman. The repair bill remained unpaid, and the vehicle remained in the garage where the repairs had been made. In the spring of 1974, in satisfaction of a garageman's lien for the outstanding amount, the garage elected to remove the vehicle's engine and transmission and then towed the vehicle to the residence of James Halbman, Sr., the father of the plaintiff minor. Lemke was asked several times to remove the vehicle from the senior Halbman's home, but he declined to do so, claiming he was under no legal obligation to remove it. During the period when the vehicle was at the garage and then subsequently at the home of the plaintiff's father, it was subjected to vandalism, making it unsalvageable. Halbman initiated this action seeking the return of the $1,100 he had paid toward the purchase of the vehicle, and Lemke counterclaimed for $150, the amount still owing on the contract. Based upon the uncontroverted facts, the trial court granted judgment in favor of Halbman, concluding that when a minor disaffirms a contract for the purchase of an item, he need only offer to return the property remaining in his hands without making restitution for any use or depreciation. In the order granting judgment, the trial court also allowed interest to the plaintiff dating from the disaffirmance of the contract. On post-judgment motions, the court amended its order for judgment to allow interest to the plaintiff from the date of the original order for judgment, July 26, 1978. Lemke appealed to the court of appeals, and Halbman cross-appealed from the disallowance of prejudgment interest. The appellate court affirmed the trial court with respect to the question of restitution for depreciation, but reversed on the question of prejudgment interest, remanding the cause for re-imposition of interest dating from the date of disaffirmance. The question of prejudgment interest is not before us on this review. The sole issue before us is whether a minor, having disaffirmed a contract for the purchase of an item which is not a necessity and having tendered the property back to the vendor, must make restitution to the vendor for damage to the property prior to the disaffirmance. Lemke argues that he should be entitled to recover for the damage to the vehicle up to the time of disaffirmance, which he claims equals the amount of the repair bill. Neither party challenges the absolute right of a minor to disaffirm a contract for the purchase of items which are not necessities. That right, variously known as the doctrine of incapacity or the "infancy doctrine," is one of the oldest and most venerable of our common law traditions. c\o Although the origins of the doctrine are somewhat obscure, it is generally recognized that its purpose is the protection of minors from foolishly squandering their wealth through improvident contracts with crafty adults who would take advantage of them in the marketplace. Thus it is settled law in this state that a contract of a minor for items which are not necessities is void or voidable at the minor's option. c/o Once there has been a disaffirmance, however, as in this case between a minor vendee and an adult vendor, unresolved problems arise regarding the rights and responsibilities of the parties relative to the disposition of the consideration exchanged on the contract. As a general rule a minor who disaffirms a contract is entitled to recover all consideration he has conferred incident to the transaction. In return the minor is expected to restore as much of the consideration as, at the time of disaffirmance, remains in the minor's possession. c\o The minor's right to disaffirm is not contingent upon the return of the property, however, as disaffirmance is permitted even where such return cannot be made. c\o The return of property remaining in the hands of the minor is not the issue presented here. In this case we have a situation where the property cannot be returned to the vendor in its entirety because it has been damaged and therefore diminished in value, and the vendor seeks to recover the depreciation. Although this court has been cognizant of this issue on previous occasions, we have not heretofore resolved it. c\o The law regarding the rights and responsibilities of the parties relative to the consideration exchanged on a disaffirmed contract is characterized by confusion, inconsistency, and a general lack of uniformity as jurisdictions attempt to reach a fair application of the infancy doctrine in today's marketplace. c\o That both parties rely on this court's decision in Olson v. Veum, supra, is symptomatic of the problem. In Olson a minor, with his brother, an adult, purchased farm implements and materials, paying by signing notes payable at a future date. Prior to the maturity of the first note, the brothers ceased their joint farming business, and the minor abandoned his interest in the material purchased by leaving it with his brother. The vendor initiated an action against the minor to recover on the note, and the minor (who had by then reached majority) disaffirmed. The trial court ordered judgment for the plaintiff on the note, finding there had been insufficient disaffirmance to sustain the plea of infancy. This court reversed, holding that the contract of a minor for the purchase of items which are not necessities may be disaffirmed even when the minor cannot make restitution. Lemke calls our attention to the following language in that decision: To sustain the judgment below is to overlook the substantial distinction between a mere denial by an infant of contract liability where the other party is seeking to enforce it and those cases where he who was the minor not only disaffirms such contract but seeks the aid of the court to restore to him that with which he has parted at the making of the contract. In the one case he is using his infancy merely as a shield, in the other also as a sword. From this Lemke infers that when a minor, as a plaintiff, seeks to disaffirm a contract and recover his consideration, different rules should apply than if the minor is defending against an action on the contract by the other party. This theory is not without some support among scholars. c\o Additionally, Lemke advances the thesis in the dissenting opinion by court of appeals Judge Cannon, arguing that a disaffirming minor's obligation to make restitution turns upon his ability to do so. For this proposition, the following language in Olson is cited: The authorities are clear that when it is shown, as it is here, that the infant cannot make restitution, then his absolute right to disaffirm is not to be questioned. In this case Lemke argues that the Olson language excuses the minor only when restitution is not possible. Here Lemke holds Halbman's $1,100, and accordingly there is no question as to Halbman's ability to make restitution. Halbman argues in response that, while the "sword-shield" dichotomy may apply where the minor has misrepresented his age to induce the contract, that did not occur here and he may avoid the contract without making restitution notwithstanding his ability to do so. The principal problem is the use of the word "restitution" in Olson. A minor, as we have stated, is under an enforceable duty to return to the vendor, upon disaffirmance, as much of the consideration as remains in his possession. When the contract is disaffirmed, title to that part of the purchased property which is retained by the minor revests in the vendor; it no longer belongs to the minor. The rationale for the rule is plain: a minor who disaffirms a purchase and recovers his purchase price should not also be permitted to profit by retaining the property purchased. The infancy doctrine is designed to protect the minor, sometimes at the expense of an innocent vendor, but it is not to be used to bilk merchants out of property as well as proceeds of the sale. Consequently, it is clear that, when the minor no longer possesses the property which was the subject matter of the contract, the rule requiring the return of property does not apply.1 The minor will not be required to give up what he does not have. We conclude that Olson does no more than set forth the foregoing rationale and that the word "restitution" as it is used in that opinion is limited to the return of the property to the vendor. We do not agree with Lemke and the court of appeals dissent that Olson requires a minor to make restitution for loss or damage to the property if he is capable of doing so. . Although we are not presented with the question here, we recognize there is 1 considerable disagreement among the authorities on whether a minor who disposes of the property should be made to restore the vendor with something in its stead. The general rule appears to limit the minor's responsibility for restoration to specie only. c/o But see: Boyce v. Doyle, adopting a "status quo" theory which requires the minor to restore the precontract status quo, even if it means returning proceeds or other value; Fisher v. Taylor Motor Co., requiring the minor to restore only the property remaining in the hands of the minor, "'or account for so much of its value as may have been invested in other property which he has in hand or owns and controls.'" Finally, some attention is given to the "New Hampshire Rule" or benefits theory which requires the disaffirming minor to pay for the contract to the extent he benefited from it.c/o Here Lemke seeks restitution of the value of the depreciation by virtue of the damage to the vehicle prior to disaffirmance. Such a recovery would require Halbman to return more than that remaining in his possession. It seeks compensatory value for that which he cannot return. Where there is misrepresentation by a minor or willful destruction of property, the vendor may be able to recover damages in tort. c/o But absent these factors, as in the present case, we believe that to require a disaffirming minor to make restitution for diminished value is, in effect, to bind the minor to a part of the obligation which by law he is privileged to avoid. The cases upon which the petitioner relies for the proposition that a disaffirming minor must make restitution for loss and depreciation serve to illustrate some of the ways other jurisdictions have approached this problem of balancing the needs of minors against the rights of innocent merchants. In Barber v. Gross, the South Dakota Supreme Court held that a minor could disaffirm a contract as a defense to an action by the merchant to enforce the contract but that the minor was obligated by a South Dakota statute, upon sufficient proof of loss by the plaintiff, to make restitution for depreciation. Cain v. Coleman, involved a minor seeking to disaffirm a contract for the purchase of a used car where the dealer claimed the minor had misrepresented his age. In reversing summary judgment granted in favor of the minor, the court recognized the minor's obligation to make restitution for the depreciation of the vehicle. In a case where there was no issue of misrepresentation, the Texas court has also ruled that upon disaffirmance and tender by a minor the vendor is obligated to take the property "as is." Scalone v. Talley Motors and Rose v. Sheehan Buick represent the proposition that a disaffirming minor must do equity in the form of restitution for loss or depreciation of the property returned. Because these cases would at some point force the minor to bear the cost of the very improvidence from which the infancy doctrine is supposed to protect him, we cannot follow them. As we noted in Kiefer, modifications of the rules governing the capacity of infants to contract are best left to the legislature. Until such changes are forthcoming, however, we hold that, absent misrepresentation or tortious damage to the property, a minor who disaffirms a contract for the purchase of an item which is not a necessity may recover his purchase price without liability for use, depreciation, damage, or other diminution in value. . . . QUESTIONS The rule that a minor may avoid any contract entered before the age of majority is a classic example of a "bright line" legal rule. We know exactly to what cases it applies and exactly how it applies in such cases. One minute before one's eighteenth birthday, one can enter only voidable obligations; one minute afterward, one's contracts are fully enforceable. The contracts are either completely voidable (regardless of their fairness) or they are completely enforceable. The infancy rule exhibits all the typical strengths and weaknesses of a bright line rule. What are they? Could you recast the infancy rule into a standard? If so, how? Could you recast the remedy into a standard? If so, how? Which would be better, the rule we have or the standard you have devised? Would Halbman be liable to Lemke, either in tort or contract, if he had, as a minor,: (1) borrowed Lemke's car and destroyed it while driving negligently? (2) intentionally misrepresented his age to Lemke at the time of the contract? (3) made a promise that forseeably induced Lemke's reliance? (4) having purchased the car from Lemke, he had sold it to a third party for $1100? If he disaffirms, must he turn over the money? What if he spent the money before disaffirming? (5) had received an insurance payment for the vandalism? (6) intentionally destroyed the car before disaffirming? What if he only negligently destroyed it? Does making Halbman liable for negligent harm "in effect, . . bind the minor to a part of the obligation which by law he is privileged to avoid"? Would it "at some point force the minor to bear the cost of the very improvidence from which the infancy doctrine is supposed to protect him"? Under the infancy rule, a minor who enters a contract with an adult may disaffirm or avoid the contract unless he ratifies it after gaining majority. Even if the contract has been fully performed on both sides, as e.g. when goods have been delivered and accepted and the price has been paid, the minor may rescind the transaction. The adult's promise is, however, enforceable if the minor chooses not to disaffirm. DISCUSSION PROBLEM: After graduating from SU law school and passing the bar you are approached by the parents of a student at SAS, the high school a few blocks north of here on 12th. They want to file a class action on behalf of the graduating seniors at SAS against Starbucks, seeking return of all the money the students have spent at Starbucks during their years at SAS. Can the students disaffirm and avoid their purchase contracts as the minor did in Halbman? (If this suit is successful, their next target will be Nordstrom’s.) Is it time to change the minority rule by lowering the age at which people can make binding contracts? Prepare a brief argument to the Washington Legislature on the point. You may imagine that the committee you are addressing is considering legislation lowering the age from 18, but has no specific legislation pending. In many states, by statute the contracts of certain minors are enforceable against them: emancipated or married minors, sports or entertainment performers, etc. The Juvenile Justice Standards recommended by the Criminal Justice Section of the American Bar Association contain the following: MINORS' CONTRACTS. The validity of contracts of minors [defined as persons below the age of 18], . . . should be governed by the following principles: A. The contract of a minor who is at least twelve years of age should be valid and enforceable by and against the minor, as long as such a contract of an adult would be valid and enforceable, if: 1. the minor's parent or duly constituted guardian consented in writing to the contract; or 2. the minor represented to the other party that he or she was at least eighteen years of age and a reasonable person under the circumstances would have believed the representation; or 3. the minor was a purchaser and is unable to return the goods to the seller in substantially the condition they were in when purchased because the minor lost or caused them to be damaged, the minor consumed them, or the minor gave them away. B. The contract of a minor who has not reached the age of twelve should be void. C. Release of a tort claim by a minor should be valid, if an adult's release would be valid under the same circumstances: 1. if the minor is at least twelve years of age, if the release is approved by the minor, the minor's parent, and, if suit is pending, by the court; or 2. if the minor has not reached the age of twelve, if the release is approved by the minor's parent, and, if suit is pending, by the court. In tort law children as young as six years old are liable for their intentional and negligent torts. You should also be aware that an infant charged with a crime is competent to waive constitutional rights, such as the right to counsel or the right to remain silent, and to plead guilty to crimes, including capital crimes. Are these rules consistent with the infancy rule in contract law? THE JURISPRUDENCE OF STANDARDS: MENTAL INCAPACITY Ortelere v. Teachers' Retirement Board 250 N.E.2d 460; (NY.Ct. App. 1969) Breitel, J. This appeal involves the revocability of an election of benefits under a public employees' retirement system and suggests the need for a renewed examination of the kinds of mental incompetency which may render voidable the exercise of contractual rights. The particular issue arises on the evidently unwise and foolhardy selection of benefits by a 60-year-old teacher, on leave for mental illness and suffering from cerebral arteriosclerosis, after service as a public schoolteacher and participation in a public retirement system for over 40 years. The teacher died a little less than two months after making her election of maximum benefits, payable to her during her life, thus causing the entire reserve to fall in. She left surviving her husband of 38 years of marriage and two grown children. There is no doubt that any retirement system depends for its soundness on an actuarial experience based on the purely prospective selections of benefits and mortality rates among the covered group, and that retrospective or adverse selection after the fact would be destructive of a sound system. It is also true that members of retirement systems are free to make choices which to others may seem unwise or foolhardy. The issue here is narrower than any suggested by these basic principles. It is whether an otherwise irrevocable election may be avoided for incapacity because of known mental illness which resulted in the election when, except in the barest actuarial sense, the system would sustain no unfavorable consequences. The husband and executor of Grace W. Ortelere, the deceased New York City schoolteacher, sues to set aside her application for retirement without option, in the event of her death. It is alleged that Mrs. Ortelere, on February 11, 1965, two months before her death from natural causes, was not mentally competent to execute a retirement application. By this application, effective the next day, she elected the maximum retirement allowance She thus revoked her earlier election of benefits under which she named her husband a beneficiary of the unexhausted reserve upon her death. Selection of the maximum allowance extinguished all interests upon her death. Following a nonjury trial in Supreme Court, it was held that Grace Ortelere had been mentally incompetent at the time of her February 11 application, thus rendering it "null and void and of no legal effect". The Appellate Division, by a divided court, reversed the judgment of the Supreme Court and held that, as a matter of law, there was insufficient proof of mental incompetency as to this transaction. Mrs. Ortelere's mental illness, indeed, psychosis, is undisputed. It is not seriously disputable, however, that she had complete cognitive judgment or awareness when she made her selection. A modern understanding of mental illness, however, suggests that incapacity to contract or exercise contractual rights may exist, because of volitional and affective impediments or disruptions in the personality, despite the intellectual or cognitive ability to understand. It will be recognized as the civil law parallel to the question of criminal responsibility which has been the recent concern of so many and has resulted in statutory and decisional changes in the criminal law. Mrs. Ortelere, an elementary schoolteacher since 1924, suffered a "nervous breakdown" in March, 1964 and went on a leave of absence expiring February 5, 1965. She was then 60 years old and had been happily married for 38 years. On July 1, 1964 she came under the care of Dr. D'Angelo, a psychiatrist, who diagnosed her breakdown as involutional psychosis, melancholia type. Dr. D'Angelo prescribed, and for about six weeks decedent underwent, tranquilizer and shock therapy. Although moderately successful, the therapy was not continued since it was suspected that she also suffered from cerebral arteriosclerosis, an ailment later confirmed. However, the psychiatrist continued to see her at monthly intervals until March, 1965. On March 28, 1965 she was hospitalized after collapsing at home from an aneurysm. She died 10 days later; the cause of death was "Cerebral thrombosis due to [Hypertensive] [Heart] [Disease]." As a teacher she had been a member of the Teachers' Retirement System of the City of New York (Administrative Code, § B20-30). This entitled her to certain annuity and pension rights, preretirement death benefits, and empowered her to exercise various options concerning the payment of her retirement allowance. Some years before, on June 28, 1958, she had executed a "Selection of Benefits under Option One" naming her husband as beneficiary of the unexhausted reserve. Under this option upon retirement her allowance would be less by way of periodic retirement allowances, but if she died before receipt of her full reserve the balance of the reserve would be payable to her husband. On June 16, 1960, two years later, she had designated her husband as beneficiary of her service death benefits in the event of her death prior to retirement. Then on February 11, 1965, when her leave of absence had just expired and she was still under treatment, she executed a retirement application, the one here involved, selecting the maximum retirement allowance payable during her lifetime with nothing payable on or after death. She also, at this time, borrowed from the system the maximum cash withdrawal permitted, namely, $8,760. Three days earlier she had written the board, stating that she intended to retire on February 12 or 15 or as soon as she received "the information I need in order to decide whether to take an option or maximum allowance." She then listed eight specific questions, reflecting great understanding of the retirement system, concerning the various alternatives available. An extremely detailed reply was sent, by letter of February 15, 1965, although by that date it was technically impossible for her to change her selection. However, the board's chief clerk, before whom Mrs. Ortelere executed the application, testified that the questions were "answered verbally by me on February 11th." Her retirement reserve totalled $62,165 (after deducting the $8,760 withdrawal), and the difference between electing the maximum retirement allowance (no option) and the allowance under "option one" was $901 per year or $75 per month. That is, had the teacher selected "option one" she would have received an annual allowance of $4,494 or $375 per month, while if no option had been selected she would have received an annual allowance of $5,395 or $450 per month. Had she not withdrawn the cash the annual figures would be $5,247 and $6,148 respectively. Following her taking a leave of absence for her condition, Mrs. Ortelere had become very depressed and was unable to care for herself. As a result, her husband gave up his electrician's job, in which he earned $222 per week, to stay home and take care of her on a full-time basis. She left their home only when he accompanied her. Although he took her to the Retirement Board on February 11, 1965, he did not know why she went, and did not question her for fear "she'd start crying hysterically that I was scolding her. That's the way she was. And I wouldn't upset her." The Orteleres were in quite modest circumstances. They owned their own home, valued at $20,000, and had $8,000 in a savings account. They also owned some farm land worth about $5,000. Under these circumstances, as revealed in this record, retirement for both of the Orteleres or the survivor of them had to be provided, as a practical matter, largely out of Mrs. Ortelere's retirement benefits. According to Dr. D'Angelo, the psychiatrist who treated her, Mrs. Ortelere never improved enough to "warrant my sending her back [to teaching]." A physician for the Board of Education examined her on February 2, 1965 to determine her fitness to return to teaching. Although not a psychiatrist but rather a specialist in internal medicine, this physician "judged that she had apparently recovered from the depression" and that she appeared rational. However, before allowing her to return to teaching, a report was requested from Dr. D'Angelo concerning her condition. It is notable that the Medical Division of the Board of Education on February 24, 1965 requested that Mrs. Ortelere report to the board's "panel psychiatrist" on March 11, 1965. Dr. D'Angelo stated "[at] no time since she was under my care was she ever mentally competent"; that "[mentally] she couldn't make a decision of any kind, actually, of any kind, small or large." He also described how involutional melancholia affects the judgment process: "They can't think rationally, no matter what the situation is. They will even tell you, 'I used to be able to think of anything and make any decision. Now,' they say, 'even getting up, I don't know whether I should get up or whether I should stay in bed.' Or, 'I don't even know how to make a slice of toast any more.' Everything is impossible to decide, and everything is too great an effort to even think of doing. They just don't have the effort, actually, because their nervous breakdown drains them of all their physical energies." While the psychiatrist used terms referring to "rationality", it is quite evident that Mrs. Ortelere's psychopathology did not lend itself to a classification under the legal test of irrationality. It is undoubtedly, for this reason, that the Appellate Division was unable to accept his testimony and the trial court's finding of irrationality in the light of the prevailing rules as they have been formulated. The well-established rule is that contracts of a mentally incompetent person who has not been adjudicated insane are voidable. Even where the contract has been partly or fully performed it will still be avoided upon restoration of the status quo. Traditionally, in this State and elsewhere, contractual mental capacity has been measured by what is largely a cognitive standard. Under this standard the "inquiry" is whether the mind was "so affected as to render him wholly and absolutely incompetent to comprehend and understand the nature of the transaction" A requirement that the party also be able to make a rational judgment concerning the particular transaction qualified the cognitive test. Conversely, it is also well recognized that contractual ability would be affected by insane delusions intimately related to the particular transaction These traditional standards governing competency to contract were formulated when psychiatric knowledge was quite primitive. They fail to account for one who by reason of mental illness is unable to control his conduct even though his cognitive ability seems unimpaired. When these standards were evolving it was thought that all the mental faculties were simultaneously affected by mental illness. This is no longer the prevailing view. Of course, the greatest movement in revamping legal notions of mental responsibility has occurred in the criminal law. The nineteenth century cognitive test embraced in the M'Naghten rules has long been criticized and changed by statute and decision in many jurisdictions. While the policy considerations for the criminal law and the civil law are different, both share in common the premise that policy considerations must be based on a sound understanding of the human mind and, therefore, its illnesses. Hence, because the cognitive rules are, for the most part, too restrictive and rest on a false factual basis they must be re-examined. Once it is understood that, accepting plaintiff's proof, Mrs. Ortelere was psychotic and because of that psychosis could have been incapable of making a voluntary selection of her retirement system benefits, there is an issue that a modern jurisprudence should not exclude, merely because her mind could pass a "cognition" test based on nineteenth century psychology. There has also been some movement on the civil law side to achieve a modern posture. For the most part, the movement has been glacial and has been disguised under traditional formulations. Various devices have been used to avoid unacceptable results under the old rules by finding unfairness or overreaching in order to avoid transactions. In this State there has been at least one candid approach. In Faber v. Sweet Style Mfg. Co., Justice Meyer wrote: "[incompetence] to contract also exists when a contract is entered into under the compulsion of a mental disease or disorder but for which the contract would not have been made". This is the first known time a court has recognized that the traditional standards of incompetency for contractual capacity are inadequate in light of contemporary psychiatric learning and applied modern standards. Prior to this, courts applied the cognitive standard giving great weight to objective evidence of rationality. It is quite significant that Restatement, 2d, Contracts, states the modern rule on competency to contract. This is in evident recognition, and the Reporter's Notes support this inference, that, regardless of how the cases formulated their reasoning, the old cognitive test no longer explains the results. Thus, the new Restatement section reads: "(1) A person incurs only voidable contractual duties by entering into a transaction if by reason of mental illness or defect (b) he is unable to act in a reasonable manner in relation to the transaction and the other party has reason to know of his condition." (RESTATEMENT, 2D, CONTRACTS § 18C.) (C/o “a complete test for contractual incapacity should provide protection to those persons whose contracts are merely uncontrolled reactions to their mental illness, as well as for those who could not understand the nature and consequences of their actions".) The avoidance of duties under an agreement entered into by those who have done so by reason of mental illness, but who have understanding, depends on balancing competing policy considerations. There must be stability in contractual relations and protection of the expectations of parties who bargain in good faith. On the other hand, it is also desirable to protect persons who may understand the nature of the transaction but who, due to mental illness, cannot control their conduct. Hence, there should be relief only if the other party knew or was put on notice as to the contractor's mental illness. Thus, the Restatement provision for avoidance contemplates that "the other party has reason to know" of the mental illness. When, however, the other party is without knowledge of the contractor's mental illness and the agreement is made on fair terms, the proposed Restatement rule is: "The power of avoidance under subsection (1) terminates to the extent that the contract has been so performed in whole or in part or the circumstances have so changed that avoidance would be inequitable. In such a case a court may grant relief on such equitable terms as the situation requires." The system was, or should have been, fully aware of Mrs. Ortelere's condition. They, or the Board of Education, knew of her leave of absence for medical reasons and the resort to staff psychiatrists by the Board of Education. Hence, the other of the conditions for avoidance is satisfied. Lastly, there are no significant changes of position by the system other than those that flow from the barest actuarial consequences of benefit selection. Nor should one ignore that in the relationship between retirement system and member, and especially in a public system, there is not involved a commercial, let alone an ordinary commercial, transaction. Instead the nature of the system and its announced goal is the protection of its members and those in whom its members have an interest. It is not a sound scheme which would permit 40 years of contribution and participation in the system to be nullified by a one-instant act committed by one known to be mentally ill. This is especially true if there would be no substantial harm to the system if the act were avoided. On the record none may gainsay that her selection of a "no option" retirement while under psychiatric care, ill with cerebral arteriosclerosis, aged 60, and with a family in which she had always manifested concern, was so unwise and foolhardy that a factfinder might conclude that it was explainable only as a product of psychosis. On this analysis it is not difficult to see that plaintiff's evidence was sufficient to sustain a finding that, when she acted as she did on February 11, 1965, she did so solely as a result of serious mental illness, namely, psychosis. Of course, nothing less serious than medically classified psychosis should suffice or else few contracts would be invulnerable to some kind of psychological attack. Mrs. Ortelere's psychiatrist testified quite flatly that as an involutional melancholiac in depression she was incapable of making a voluntary "rational" decision. Of course, as noted earlier, the trial court's finding and perhaps some of the testimony attempted to fit into the rubrics of the traditional rules. For that reason rather than reinstatement of the judgment at Trial Term there should be a new trial under the proper standards frankly considered and applied. Accordingly, the order of the Appellate Division should be reversed, without costs, and the action remanded to Trial Term for a new trial. Jasen, J. (dissenting). Where there has been no previous adjudication of incompetency, the burden of proving mental incompetence is upon the party alleging it. I agree with the majority at the Appellate Division that the plaintiff, the husband of the decedent, failed to sustain the burden incumbent upon him of proving deceased's incompetence. The evidence conclusively establishes that the decedent, at the time she made her application to retire, understood not only that she was retiring, but also that she had selected the maximum payment during her lifetime. Indeed, the letter written by the deceased to the Teachers' Retirement System prior to her retirement demonstrates her full mental capacity to understand and to decide whether to take an option or the maximum allowance. The full text of the letter reads as follows: February 8, 1965. Gentlemen: I would like to retire on Feb. 12 or Feb. 15. In other words, just as soon as possible after I receive the information I need in order to decide whether to take an option or maximum allowance. Following are the questions I would like to have answered: 1. What is my 'average' five-year salary? 2. What is my maximum allowance? 3. I am 60 years old. If I select option four-a with a beneficiary (female) 27 years younger, what is my allowance? 4. If I select four-a on the pension part only, and take the maximum annuity, what is my allowance? 5. If I take a loan of 89% of my year's salary before retirement, what would my maixmum allowance be? 6. If I take a loan of $5,000 before retiring, and select option four-a on both the pension and annuity, what would my allowance be? 7. What is my total service credit? I have been on a leave without pay since Oct. 26, 1964. 8. What is the 'factor' used for calculating option four-a with the above beneficiary? Thank you for your promptness in making the necessary calculations. I will come to your office on Thursday afternoon of this week. It seems clear that this detailed, explicit and extremely pertinent list of queries reveals a mind fully in command of the salient features of the Teachers' Retirement System. Certainly, it cannot be said that the decedent could possess sufficient capacity to compose a letter indicating such a comprehensive understanding of the retirement system, and yet lack the capacity to understand the answers. As I read the record, the evidence establishes that the decedent's election to receive maximum payments was predicated on the need for a higher income to support two retired persons -- her husband and herself. Since the only source of income available to decedent and her husband was decedent's retirement pay, the additional payment of $75 per month which she would receive by electing the maximal payment was a necessity. Indeed, the additional payments represented an increase of 20% over the benefits payable under option 1. Under these circumstances, an election of maximal income during decedent's lifetime was not only a rational, but a necessary decision. Further indication of decedent's knowledge of the financial needs of her family is evidenced by the fact that she took a loan for the maximum amount ($8,760) permitted by the retirement system, at the time she made application for retirement. Moreover, there is nothing in the record to indicate that the decedent had any warning, premonition, knowledge or indication at the time of retirement that her life expectancy was, in any way, reduced by her condition. Decedent's election of the maximum retirement benefits, therefore, was not so contrary to her best interests so as to create an inference of her mental incompetence. Indeed, concerning election of options under a retirement system, it has been held: "Even where no previous election has been made, the court must make the election for an incompetent which would be in accordance with what would have been his manifest and reasonable choice if he were sane, and, in the absence of convincing evidence that the incompetent would have made a different selection, it is presumed that he would have chosen the option yielding the largest returns in his lifetime." Nor can I agree with the majority's view that the traditional rules governing competency to contract "are, for the most part, too restrictive and rest on a false factual basis". The issue confronting the courts concerning mental capacity to contract is under what circumstances and conditions should a party be relieved of contractual obligations freely entered. This is peculiarly a legal decision, although, of course, available medical knowledge forms a datum which influences the legal choice. It is common knowledge that the present state of psychiatric knowledge is inadequate to provide a fixed rule for each and every type of mental disorder. Thus, the generally accepted rules which have evolved to determine mental responsibility are general enough in application to encompass all types of mental disorders, and phrased in a manner which can be understood and practically applied by juries composed of laymen. The generally accepted test of mental competency to contract which has thus evolved is whether the party attempting to avoid the contract was capable of understanding and appreciating the nature and consequences of the particular act or transaction which he challenges. This rule represents a balance struck between policies to protect the security of transactions between individuals and freedom of contract on the one hand, and protection of those mentally handicapped on the other hand. In my opinion, this rule has proven workable in practice and fair in result. A broad range of evidence including psychiatric testimony is admissible under the existing rules to establish a party's mental condition. In the final analysis, the lay jury will infer the state of the party's mind from his observed behavior as indicated by the evidence presented at trial. Each juror instinctively judges what is normal and what is abnormal conduct from his own experience, and the generally accepted test harmonizes the competing policy considerations with human experience to achieve the fairest result in the greatest number of cases. As in every situation where the law must draw a line between liability and nonliability, between responsibility and nonresponsibility, there will be borderline cases, and injustices may occur by deciding erroneously that an individual belongs on one side of the line or the other. To minimize the chances of such injustices occurring, the line should be drawn as clearly as possible. The Appellate Division correctly found that the deceased was capable of understanding the nature and effect of her retirement benefits, and exercised rational judgment in electing to receive the maximum allowance during her lifetime. I fear that the majority's refinement of the generally accepted rules will prove unworkable in practice, and make many contracts vulnerable to psychological attack. Any benefit to those who understand what they are doing, but are unable to exercise self-discipline, will be outweighed by frivolous claims which will burden our courts and undermine the security of contracts. The reasonable expectations of those who innocently deal with persons who appear rational and who understand what they are doing should be protected. Accordingly, I would affirm the order appealed from. QUESTIONS 1. Judge Brietel condemns as “unwise and foolhardy” Ortelere’s election to receive greater pension benefits during her lifetime in lieu of her spouse’s entitlement to receive post-death benefits under the plan. Was it? 2. In what way was the traditional test of mental capacity based on “nineteenth century psychology”? 3. Is Judge Brietel applying “twentieth century psychology”? 4. What policy arguments does the dissent make concerning the appropriate test to be applied? 5. Is Ortelere governed by a rule or a standard? In either case, state it as simply as you can. 6. What would the Restatement outcome have been if the Retirement Board had not known of Ortolere’s condition? 7. Was the Retirement Board at fault, according to the majority? Suppose they had consulted you after receiving a letter from another retired teacher similar to the one written by Mrs. Ortelere? Would you advise them to require her to prove that she was mentally competent before they implemented her decision? 8. Does the majority articulate a rule/standard that ordinary people can implement in their business transactions? 9. Summarize the argument of the dissent. Which argument is more compelling? Clearly, the choice between rules and standards has many policy implications. As practicing lawyers, you should become skilled at making arguments both (1) for and (2) against both (3) rules and (4) standards. Lawyers often are engaged in the drafting of legislation; administrative regulation; public and private codes of conduct; organizational policies; and contracts. You will often have to choose the optimum regulatory term, whether rule or standard. You should be able to advise your clients about the costs and benefits of each kind of term. Your knowledge about the differences between rules and standards will grow with your experience.