1NC 1NC “Resolved” before a colon reflects a legislative forum Army Officer School ‘04 (5-12, “# 12, Punctuation – The Colon and Semicolon”, http://usawocc.army.mil/IMI/wg12.htm) The colon introduces the following: a. A list, but only after "as follows," "the following," or a noun for which the list is an appositive: Each scout will carry the following: (colon) meals for three days, a survival knife, and his sleeping bag. The company had four new officers: (colon) Bill Smith, Frank Tucker, Peter Fillmore, and Oliver Lewis. b. A long quotation (one or more paragraphs): In The Killer Angels Michael Shaara wrote: (colon) You may find it a different story from the one you learned in school. There have been many versions of that battle [Gettysburg] and that war [the Civil War]. (The quote continues for two more paragraphs.) c. A formal quotation or question: The President declared: (colon) "The only thing we have to fear is fear itself." The question is: (colon) what can we do about it? d. A second independent clause which explains the first: Potter's motive is clear: (colon) he wants the assignment. e. After the introduction of a business letter: Dear Sirs: (colon) Dear Madam: (colon) f. The details following an announcement For sale: (colon) large lakeside cabin with dock g. A formal resolution, after the word "resolved:" Resolved: (colon) That this council petition the mayor. “The United States should” means the ballot is solely about a government policy Ericson ‘03 (Jon M., Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4) The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, each topic contains certain key elements, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. An agent doing the acting ---“The United States” in “The United States should adopt a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should—the first part of a verb phrase that urges action. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, should adopt here means to put a program or policy into action though governmental means. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose. Legalize means to make lawful by judicial or legislative sanction Business Dictionary No Date, "legalize", www.businessdictionary.com/definition/legalize.html legalize¶ Definition¶ To make enforceable, justifiable, or lawful by judicial or legislative sanction. It’s a voter for limits - they claim to win the debate for reasons other than the desirability of topical action. That undermines preparation and clash. Changing the question now leaves one side unprepared, resulting in shallow, uneducational debate. Requiring debate on a communal topic forces argument development and develops persuasive skills critical to any political outcome. Debate over a controversial point of action creates argumentative stasis—that’s key to avoid a devolution of debate into competing truth claims, which destroys the decision-making benefits of the activity Steinberg and Freeley ‘13 David Director of Debate at U Miami, Former President of CEDA, officer, American Forensic Association and National Communication Association. Lecturer in Communication studies and rhetoric. Advisor to Miami Urban Debate League, Masters in Communication, and Austin, JD, Suffolk University, attorney who focuses on criminal, personal injury and civil rights law, Argumentation and Debate Critical Thinking for Reasoned Decision Making, Thirteen Edition Debate is a means of settling differences, so there must be a controversy, a difference of opinion or a conflict of interest before there can be a debate. If everyone is in agreement on a feet or value or policy, there is no need or opportunity for debate; the matter can be settled by unanimous consent. Thus, for example, it would be pointless to attempt to debate "Resolved: That two plus two equals four,” because there is simply no controversy about this statement. Controversy is an essential prerequisite of debate. Where there is no clash of ideas, proposals, interests, or expressed positions of issues, there is no debate. Controversy invites decisive choice between competing positions. Debate cannot produce effective decisions without clear identification of a question or questions to be answered. For example, general argument may occur about the broad topic of illegal immigration. How many illegal immigrants live in the United States? What is the impact of illegal immigration and immigrants on our economy? What is their impact on our communities? Do they commit crimes? Do they take jobs from American workers? Do they pay taxes? Do they require social services? Is it a problem that some do not speak English? Is it the responsibility of employers to discourage illegal immigration by not hiring undocumented workers? Should they have the opportunity to gain citizenship? Does illegal immigration pose a security threat to our country? Do illegal immigrants do work that American workers are unwilling to do? Are their rights as workers and as human beings at risk due to their status? Are they abused by employers, law enforcement, housing, and businesses? How are their families impacted by their status? What is the moral and philosophical obligation of a nation state to maintain its borders? Should we build a wall on the Mexican border, establish a national identification card, or enforce existing laws against employers? Should we invite immigrants to become U.S. citizens? Surely you can think of many more concerns to be addressed by a conversation about the topic area of illegal immigration. Participation in this “debate” is likely to be emotional and intense. However, it is not likely to be productive or useful without focus on a particular question and identification of a line demarcating sides in the controversy. To be discussed and resolved effectively, controversies are best understood when seated clearly such that all parties to the debate share an understanding about the objective of the debate. This enables focus on substantive and objectively identifiable issues facilitating comparison of competing argumentation leading to effective decisions. Vague understanding results in unfocused deliberation and poor decisions, general feelings of tension without opportunity for resolution, frustration, and emotional distress, as evidenced by the failure of the U.S. Congress to make substantial progress on the immigration debate. Of course, arguments may be presented without disagreement. For example, claims are presented and supported within speeches, editorials, and advertisements even without opposing or refutational response. Argumentation occurs in a range of settings from informal to formal, and may not call upon an audience or judge to make a forced choice among competing claims. Informal discourse occurs as conversation or panel discussion without demanding a decision about a dichotomous or yes/no question. However, by definition, debate requires "reasoned judgment on a proposition. The proposition is a statement about which competing advocates will offer alternative (pro or con) argumentation calling upon their audience or adjudicator to decide. The proposition provides focus for the discourse and guides the decision process. Even when a decision will be made through a process of compromise, it is important to identify the beginning positions of competing advocates to begin negotiation and movement toward a center, or consensus position. It is frustrating and usually unproductive to attempt to make a decision when deciders are unclear as to what the decision is about. The proposition may be implicit in some applied debates (“Vote for me!”); however, when a vote or consequential decision is called for (as in the courtroom or in applied parliamentary debate) it is essential that the proposition be explicitly expressed (“the defendant is guilty!”). In academic debate, the proposition provides essential guidance for the preparation of the debaters prior to the debate, the case building and discourse presented during the debate, and the decision to be made by the debate judge after the debate. Someone disturbed by the problem of a growing underclass of poorly educated, socially disenfranchised youths might observe, “Public schools are doing a terrible job! They' are overcrowded, and many teachers are poorly qualified in their subject areas. Even the best teachers can do little more than struggle to maintain order in their classrooms." That same concerned citizen, facing a complex range of issues, might arrive at an unhelpful decision, such as "We ought to do something about this” or, worse, “It’s too complicated a problem to deal with." Groups of concerned citizens worried about the state of public education could join together to express their frustrations, anger, disillusionment, and emotions regarding the schools, but without a focus for their discussions, they could easily agree about the sorry state of education without finding points of clarity or potential solutions. A gripe session would follow. But if a precise question is posed—such as “What can be done to improve public education?”—then a more profitable area of discussion is opened up simply by placing a focus on the search for a concrete solution step. One or more judgments can be phrased in the form of debate propositions, motions for parliamentary debate, or bills for legislative assemblies, The statements "Resolved: That the federal government should implement a program of charter schools in at-risk communities” and “Resolved; That the state of Florida should adopt a school voucher program" more clearly identify specific ways of dealing with educational problems in a manageable form, suitable for debate. They provide specific policies to be investigated and aid discussants in identifying points of difference. This focus contributes to better and more informed decision making with the potential for better results. In academic debate, it provides better depth of argumentation and enhanced opportunity for reaping the educational benefits of participation. In the next section, we will consider the challenge of framing the proposition for debate, and its role in the debate. To have a productive debate, which facilitates effective decision making by directing and placing limits on the decision to be made, the basis for argument should be clearly defined. If we merely talk about a topic, such as ‘"homelessness,” or “abortion,” Or “crime,” or “global warming,” we are likely to have an interesting discussion but not to establish a profitable basis for argument. For example, the statement “Resolved: That the pen is mightier than the sword” is debatable, yet by itself fails to provide much basis for dear argumentation. If we take this statement to mean Iliad the written word is more effective than physical force for some purposes, we can identify a problem area: the comparative effectiveness of writing or physical force for a specific purpose, perhaps promoting positive social change. (Note that “loose” propositions, such as the example above, may be defined by their advocates in such a way as to facilitate a clear contrast of competing sides; through definitions and debate they “become” clearly understood statements even though they may not begin as such. There are formats for debate that often begin with this sort of proposition. However, in any debate, at some point, effective and meaningful discussion relies on identification of a clearly stated or understood proposition.) Back to the example of the written word versus physical force. Although we now have a general subject, we have not yet stated a problem. It is still too broad, too loosely worded to promote weII-organized argument. What sort of writing are we concerned with—poems, novels, government documents, website development, advertising, cyber-warfare, disinformation, or what? What does it mean to be “mightier" in this context? What kind of physical force is being compared—fists, dueling swords, bazookas, nuclear weapons, or what? A more specific question might be, “Would a mutual defense treaty or a visit by our fleet be more effective in assuring Laurania of our support in a certain crisis?” The basis for argument could be phrased in a debate proposition such as “Resolved: That the United States should enter into a mutual defense treaty with Laurania.” Negative advocates might oppose this proposition by arguing that fleet maneuvers would be a better solution. This is not to say that debates should completely avoid creative interpretation of the controversy by advocates, or that good debates cannot occur over competing interpretations of the controversy; in fact, these sorts of debates may be very engaging. The point is that debate is best facilitated by the guidance provided by focus on a particular point of difference, which will be outlined in the following discussion. Tailoring identity claims to common topics for deliberation is possible and desirable--the 1ac’s failure to affirm topical action impedes the debate---T is engagement, not exclusion Amanda Anderson 6, Andrew W. Mellon Professor of Humanities and English at Brown University, Spring 2006, “Reply to My Critic(s),” Criticism, Vol. 48, No. 2, p. 281-290 MY RECENT BOOK, The Way We Argue Now, has in a sense two theses. In the first place, the book makes the case for the importance of debate and argument to any vital democratic or pluralistic intellectual culture. This is in many ways an unexceptional position, but the premise of the book is that the claims of reasoned argument are often trumped, within the current intellectual terrain, by appeals to cultural identity and what I gather more broadly under the rubric of ethos, which includes cultural identity but also forms of ethical piety and charismatic authority. In promoting argument as a universal practice keyed to a human capacity for communicative reason, my book is a critique of relativism and identity politics, or the notion that forms of cultural authenticity or group identity have a certain unquestioned legitimacy, one that cannot or should not be subjected to the challenges of reason or principle, precisely because reason and what is often called "false universalism" are, according to this pattern of thinking, always involved in forms of exclusion, power, or domination. My book insists, by contrast, that argument is a form of respect, that the ideals of democracy, whether conceived from a nationalist or an internationalist perspective, rely fundamentally upon procedures of argumentation and debate in order to legitimate themselves and to keep their central institutions vital. And the idea that one should be protected from debate, that argument is somehow injurious to persons if it does not honor their desire to have their basic beliefs and claims and solidarities accepted without challenge, is strenuously opposed. As is the notion that any attempt to ask people to agree upon processes of reason-giving argument is somehow necessarily to impose a coercive norm, one that will disable the free expression and performance of identities, feelings, or solidarities. Disagreement is, by the terms of my book, a form of respect, not a form of disrespect. And by disagreement, I don't mean simply to say that we should expect disagreement rather than agreement, which is a frequently voiced-if misconceived-criticism of Habermas. Of course we should expect disagreement. My point is that we should focus on the moment of dissatisfaction in the face of disagreement-the internal dynamic in argument that imagines argument might be the beginning of a process of persuasion and exchange that could end in agreement (or partial agreement). For those who advocate reconciling ourselves to disagreements rather than arguing them out, by contrast, there is a complacent-and in some versions, even celebratory-attitude toward fixed disagreement. Refusing these options, I make the case for dissatisfied disagreement in the final chapter of the book and argue that people should be willing to justify their positions in dialogue with one another, especially if they hope to live together in a posttraditional pluralist society. One example of the trumping of argument by ethos is the form that was taken by the late stage of the Foucault/Habermas debate, where an appeal to ethos-specifically, an appeal to Foucault's style of ironic or negative critique, often seen as most in evidence in the interviews, where he would playfully refuse labels or evade direct answers-was used to exemplify an alternative to the forms of argument employed by Habermas and like-minded critics. (I should pause to say that I provide this example, and the framing summary of the book that surrounds it, not to take up airtime through expansive self-reference, but because neither of my respondents provided any contextualizing summary of the book's central arguments, though one certainly gets an incremental sense of the book's claims from Bruce Robbins. Because I don't assume that readers of this forum have necessarily read the book, and because I believe that it is the obligation of forum participants to provide sufficient context for their remarks, I will perform this task as economically as I can, with the recognition that it might have carried more weight if provided by a respondent rather than the author.) The Foucauldian countercritique importantly emphasizes a relation between style and position, but it obscures (1) the importance or value of the Habermasian critique and (2) the possibility that the other side of the debate might have its own ethos to advocate , one that has precisely to do with an ethos of argument, an ideal of reciprocal debate that involves taking distance on one's pre-given forms of identity or the norms of one's community, both so as to talk across differences and to articulate one's claims in relation to shared and even universal ideals. And this leads to the second thesis of the book, the insistence that an emphasis on ethos and character is interestingly present if not widely recognized in contemporary theory, and one of the ways its vitality and existential pertinence makes itself felt (even despite the occurrence of the kinds of unfair trumping moves I have mentioned). We often fail to notice this, because identity has so uniformly come to mean sociological, ascribed, or group identity-race, gender, class, nationality, ethnicity, sexuality, and so forth. Instances of the move toward character and ethos include the later Foucault (for whom ethos is a central concept), cosmopolitanism (whose aspiration it is to turn universalism into an ethos), and, more controversially, proceduralist ethics and politics (with its emphasis on sincerity and civility). Another version of this attentiveness to ethos and character appears in contemporary pragmatism, with its insistence on casualness of attitude, or insouciance in the face of contingency-recommendations that get elevated into full-fledged exemplary personae in Richard Rorty's notion of the "ironist" or Barbara Herrnstein Smiths portrait of the "postmodern skeptic." These examples-and the larger claim they support-are meant to defend theory as still living, despite the many reports of its demise, and in fact still interestingly and incessantly re-elaborating its relation to practice. This second aspect of the project is at once descriptive, motivated by the notion that characterology within theory is intrinsically interesting, and critical, in its attempt to identify how characterology can itself be used to cover or evade the claims of rational argument, as in appeals to charismatic authority or in what I identify as narrow personifications of theory (pragmatism, in its insistence on insouciance in the face of contingency, is a prime example of this second form). And as a complement to the critical agenda, there is a reconstructive agenda as well, an attempt to recuperate liberalism and proceduralism, in part by advocating the possibility, as I have suggested, of an ethos of argument. Robbins, in his extraordinarily rich and challenging response, zeroes in immediately on a crucial issue: who is to say exactly when argument is occurring or not, and what do we do when there is disagreement over the fundamentals (the primary one being over what counts as proper reasoning)? Interestingly, Robbins approaches this issue after first observing a certain tension in the book: on the one hand, The Way We Argue Now calls for dialogue, debate, argument; on the other, its project is "potentially something a bit stricter, or pushier: getting us all to agree on what should and should not count as true argument." What this point of entry into the larger issue reveals is a kind of blur that the book, I am now aware, invites. On the one hand, the book anatomizes academic debates, and in doing so is quite "debaterly" This can give the impression that what I mean by argument is a very specific form unique to disciplinary methodologies in higher education. But the book is not generally advocating a narrow practice of formal and philosophical argumentation in the culture at large, however much its author may relish adherence to the principle of non-contradiction in scholarly argument. I take pains to elaborate an ethos of argument that is linked to democratic debate and the forms of dissent that constitutional patriotism allows and even promotes. In this sense, while argument here is necessarily contextualized sociohistorically, the concept is not merely academic. It is a practice seen as integral to specific political forms and institutions in modern democracies, and to the more general activity of critique within modern societies-to the tradition of the public sphere, to speak in broad terms. Additionally, insofar as argument impels one to take distance on embedded customs, norms, and senses of given identity, it is a practice that at once acknowledges identity, the need to understand the perspectives of others, and the shared commitment to commonality and generality, to finding a way to live together under conditions of difference. More than this: the book also discusses at great length and from several different angles the issue that Robbins inexplicably claims I entirely ignore: the question of disagreement about what counts as argument. In the opening essay, "Debatable Performances," I fault the proponents of communicative ethics for not having a broader understanding of public expression, one that would include the disruptions of spectacle and performance. I return to and underscore this point in my final chapter, where I espouse a democratic politics that can embrace and accommodate a wide variety of expressions and modes. This is certainly a discussion of what counts as dialogue and hence argument in the broad sense in which I mean it, and in fact I fully acknowledge that taking distance from cultural norms and given identities can be advanced not only through critical reflection, but through ironic critique and defamiliarizing performance as well. But I do insist-and this is where I take a position on the fundamental disagreements that have arisen with respect to communicative ethics-that when they have an effect, these other dimensions of experience do not remain unreflective, and insofar as they do become reflective, they are contributing to the very form of reasoned analysis that their champions sometimes imagine they must refuse in order to liberate other modes of being (the affective, the narrative, the performative, the nonrational). If a narrative of human rights violation is persuasive in court, or in the broader cultural public sphere, it is because it draws attention to a violation of humanity that is condemned on principle; if a performance jolts people out of their normative understandings of sexuality and gender, it prompts forms of understanding that can be affirmed and communicated and also can be used to justify political positions and legislative agendas . Ethics in an absurd world demands that we enter into mutual discussion of the consequences of institutionalized values and accept that we may be wrong through constructive argument on fair terms – this commitment to democratic dialogue, embodied in debate over specific policy proposals and the consideration of their results rather than clashing ideologies, is all that can save us from authoritarianism, nihilism, and extinction David Spritzen 1988 – Prof philosophy @ U Long Island; Camus: A Critical Introduction; note – we reject the use of gendered language in this evidence; p 266-267 If there is an absolute for Camus, it is an absolute of evidence grounded in human possibilities. It is an absolute given; its significance remains hypothetical and nonexclusive with respect to others, but it defines the range of our commitment. If experience is to prove fruitful, thought must be relativized and corrigible. “Persuasion demands leisure,” observes Camus, “and friendship a structure that will never be completed.” (R, 247). We are recalled once again to the definition of dialogue: an open inquiry among persons. The persons are the basic unit; the inquiry seeks to achieve and to maintain guidelines for interaction; while the openness refers to the recognition and acceptance of the permanent possibility of novelty entering into human experience. The political problem therefore becomes that of seeking to institutionalize, first, the method of inquiry; and second, its always provisional and pragmatically considered results. The freedom, dignity, and growth of the person, and the collectivity are the reference points and limits of action. To pose the problems outside these limits is to remove the discussion from the ethical dimension. The institutionalization of the method of dialogue just referred to is what Camus means by democracy. He has written: “Justice implies rights. Rights imply the liberty to defend them. In order to act, man has to speak. We know what we are defending…I am speaking for a society which does not impose silence.” (A/I, 229) Such an act requires a commitment to values that transcend the purely political. The commitment to democracy is at bottom just such a politically transcending commitment to the human community. “The democrat, after all, is the one who admits that the adversary may be right, who permits him to express himself, and who agrees to reflect upon his arguments.” (A/I, 125) What is fundamental is not any specific political society or set of laws by which it may be given constitutional embodiment. These structures are no more fundamental than the concepts we use to regulate our lives. The actual basis of such arrangements is to be found in the experience of community, which is essentially the experience of unity – that is, the felt communality of actions grounded in common practices and common perceptions of meaning. Where we have the core notion of community: shared meaningful activity through time. Its method of communication through reciprocal approximation and mutual development of meanings in response to novel experiences is what is meant by dialogue. “We must be fought today is fear and silence, and with them, the separation of minds and souls which accompanies them. What must be defended is dialogue and universal communication among men. Servitude, injustices, lies are the curses (les fléaux) which break this communication and prevent dialogue. (A/I, 177) Speaking of the principles revealed by revolt, which provide the basis for dialogue, Camus sums up much of the thesis in these words: “Nothing justifies the assertion that these principles have existed eternally; it is of no use to declare that they will one day exist. But they do exist, in the very period in which we exist. With us, and throughout history, they deny servitude, falsehood, and terror.” There is, in fact, nothing in common between a master and a slave; it is impossible to communicate with a person who has been reduced to servitude. Instead of the implicit and untrammeled dialogue through which we come to recognize our similarity and consecrate our destiny, servitude gives sway to the most terrible of silences. If injustice is bad for the rebel, it is not because it contradicts an eternal idea of justice, but because it perpetuates the silent hostility that separates the oppressor from the oppressed. It kills the small part of existence that can be realized on this earth through the mutual understanding of men…the mutual understanding and communication discovered by rebellion can survive only in free exchange of conversation. Every ambiguity, every misunderstanding, leads to death; clear language and simple words are the only salvation from this death. The climax of every tragedy lies in the deafness of its heroes. Plato is right and not Moses and Nietzsche. Dialogue on the level of mankind is less costly than the gospel preached by totalitarian regimes in the form of a monologue dictated from the top of a lonely mountain. On the stage as in reality, the monologue precedes death. (R, 283-4). Dialogue grounded in truth and integrity is all that can protect us from the despair of nihilism in a world that offers no meaning beyond what we can conjointly construct. “We have a right to think,” Camus wrote a year or two before he died, “that truth with a capital letter is relative. But facts are facts. And whoever says that the sky is blue when it is grey is prostituting words and preparing the way for tyranny. This is not so much an implied theory of knowledge as a statement of the moral role of intelligence. The question of Truth becomes derivative; the importance of truths for experience, fundamental. Intelligence must bear witness to the facts of existence. It must disintoxicate politics, as an essential condition for maintaining dialogue. 1NC The 1AC theorizes Ferguson protests incorrectly – their politics of surrender mystifies agency – a proper historical account would avoid the white liberal sympathy of the ballot – this makes the case contradictory when it would be strong without the gesture when physical guns are not being pointed Dora Apel 2014 Wayne State University Art History Professor Theory & Event > Volume 17, Issue 3 Supplement, 2014 “Hands Up, Don’t Shoot”: If the shooting of Michael Brown is considered by many to be justified, and protest, no matter how supplicating, is regarded as infuriating and intolerable, then we must see such cop killings of unarmed black men as a form of modern legalized lynching. At the height of private and spectacle lynchings from the 1890s to the 1930s, if black people were not sufficiently deferential and submissive, then they were considered “uppity,” which could be grounds for lethal action. Not much has changed in decades since then for cops and racist whites. A Huffington Post/YouGov poll finds that 76 percent of black respondents say the shooting is part of a broader pattern in the way police treat black men, nearly double the number of whites who agree (40 percent).2 Similarly, a Pew Research Center poll finds that 80 percent of blacks favor the statement that Brown’s shooting “raises important issues about race that need to be discussed” while only 18 percent of whites favor this statement over another that says “the issue of race is getting more attention than it deserves.”3 While the performance of non-resistance expressed by the “hands up, don’t shoot” gesture of defenseless surrender is meant to advance black interests by exposing the violation of basic civil rights and due process, it also is meant to pressure and shame the racist establishment into effective reform . But for the racists in charge, the cops are just “doing their job” when they humiliate, brutalize, and kill black people on the street. The cops have always been the front-line defenders of a racist capitalist system that is built on the repression of poor, black, Latino and working people in the service of a tiny wealthy elite, the ones to whom the cops are accountable. As if demonstrating their power to kill with impunity, despite this recent round of protests, two days later in Los Angeles cops killed Ezell Ford, another unarmed black man; eight days later and less than four miles away from where Brown was killed, police in St. Louis shot to death Kajieme Powell, an agitated black man on the street holding a knife. The submissive hands up gesture of black protesters facing a militarized police force is meant to appeal to liberal sympathies by showing that they are “respectful” and law-abiding, suggesting the opposite of “uppity.” Yet the deference of the act has the paradoxical effect of reinforcing white stereotypes about black people. As Martin Berger demonstrates in his revisionist study of iconic civil rights photos, Seeing through Race, white-run newspapers selected civil rights photos showing black passivity in the face of police violence while blackrun newspapers selected photos that showed both protesters and police as active agents. Berger suggests that images of blacks offering no resistance to police violence were selected by white editors because it was easier to gain white liberal sympathy by visually defining racism as excessive acts of brutality, from which moderate and liberal whites could distance themselves, while at the same time their racial anxiety could be quelled by the picturing of black non-resistance, which meant that whites were still in charge.4 Black editors, on the other hand, often preferred to show black agency . Similar juxtapositions are established by the visual record of Ferguson. The hyper-militarized police deploy tanks and automatic assault rifles, flash bombs, tear gas and rubber bullets, weapons that recall the water cannons and dogs of the civil rights era. Both then and now, photos of the militarized police facing black protesters who are non-resistant perform reassuring symbolic work that manages white anxieties about race. Whites are still in control and racism is understood as brutal acts of violence , not as part of the insidious indignities and brutalization of everyday life. Picturing blacks as non-threatening and nonresistant effectively places them in a role of limited power; it does not fundamentally threaten white racial power. As Berger observes of civil rights photos, “The photographs presented story lines that allowed magnanimous and sympathetic whites to imagine themselves bestowing rights on blacks, given that the dignified and suffering blacks of the photographic record appeared in no position to take anything from white America.”5 Whether progressive or reactionary, whites, not blacks , are constructed as the agents of change while normalizing black passivity and even subtly promoting ongoing black humiliation. It must be understood that equating racism only with acts of police brutality obscures the values of whiteness that are foundational to the racial hierarchy and that repress black agency.6 Demonstrating their control of the black body even after death, the police left Michael Brown’s body in the street for more than four hours, lying face down with blood streaming from his head in broad daylight in the summer sun. Although officers quickly secured the area with yellow tape, they stood at a distance while horrified neighbors called news stations, shielded their children and took shaky cellphone videos that have found their way into the national media. Although Brown’s body was covered after a brief period with a sheet by a passing paramedic, his feet were left exposed and his blood was visible. More cops were called to the scene as the tension levels mounted among shocked residents. The Ferguson police defended the long delay by asserting that “the time that elapsed in getting detectives to the scene was not out of the ordinary, and that conditions made it unusually difficult to do all that they needed.”7 The former New York City chief medical examiner, Dr. Michael M. Baden, who was hired by the Brown family’s lawyers to do an autopsy, observed that there was “no forensic reason” for leaving the body in view for so long.8 At best, allowing Brown’s body to remain in public view in the presence of distressed family members suggests gross incompetence and insensitivity. At worst, it continues the legacy of American lynching in which white supremacists left murdered black bodies exposed as warnings to members of the black community to “stay in their place.” Images of nonresistant protesters are not the only photos available, however. Another iconic image taken in Ferguson is that of a young black man wearing an American flag t-shirt and hurling a tear-gas canister back at the police with one hand while casually holding a bag of potato chips in the other (Figure 3). This is an act of self-defense against the perpetrators of violence. For blacks, confronting the police and throwing back a tear gas canister that had been flung at them became a badge of honor.9 For racist whites who are predisposed to see images of blacks as active agents in their own defense as a form of “violence,” such an image may validate what they believe about the proper hierarchy of racial power. The real fear of seeing blacks as more than passive and non-resistant, that is, as active agents in defense of their rights, is the specter it raises of more organized social and political struggle , in concert with allied whites, against the racist capitalist system of injustice that allows the criminalization of blackness and the wanton killing of black people. The police have become so militarized in great part as a response to the threat of social struggle. Militarygrade hardware found its way into the hands of local police forces around the country long before the attacks of 9/11. In 1990, the National Defense Authorization Act empowered the Pentagon to transfer to federal and state agencies Department of Defense equipment “suitable for use by such agencies in counter-drug activities.”10 Thus the “war on drugs,” which targeted black men disproportionately, greatly furthered the militarization of the police and stockpiling of hardware that we see in towns and cities such as Ferguson today. SWAT teams, in which helmeted and masked police enter homes with guns drawn, knocking down the door with a battering ram and rushing inside, were originally formed to deal with “civil unrest” as well as life-threatening situations. Today they are routinely deployed to serve drug-related warrants in private homes.11 As economic inequality continues to grow exponentially, the state invests in ever more security , surveillance and weaponry. Far more money is spent on policing and government efforts to counteract protest movements than on rebuilding our declining cities by creating jobs, renewing infrastructure, providing adequate housing, city services, or access to health care and education. While it is more difficult to photograph the complex social dynamics of poverty and economic decline in hundreds of cities across the nation and the criminalization of black people, another Ferguson image alludes to the larger racial dynamic in America. A young black protester holds a sign written on cardboard that says, “My blackness is not a weapon” (https://twitter.com/erikasway/status/502289519178444800). This assertion recognizes that in a country where racial equality has yet to be achieved, blackness itself is regarded as a threat, especially if you are young and male. As conservative pundit Ben Stein openly said of Michael Brown on Newsmax, “He wasn't unarmed. He was armed with his incredibly strong, scary self.”12 Blackness itself evokes white racial anxiety and the need to contain and control that anxiety through racist repression. Such repression can only be countered by organized social struggle with clear emancipatory goals . Moral appeals through passive non-resistance, or other symbolic gestures, while courageous and useful in raising the visibility of injustice, will not be enough . Musical identity politics reinforce exclusion by fetishizing cultural objects as a mode of resistance- this occludes critical analysis of materiality John Hutnyk 2000 “Critique of Exotica: Music, Politics and the Culture Industry” pg. 132-134 Hutnyk is Senior Lecturer in Anthropology at Goldsmiths College, London. He is the author of The Rumour of Calcutta: Tourism, Charity and the Poverty of Representations (1996) and co-editor of Dis-Orienting Rhythms (1996). Exclusive identity affiliation and separatism poses an obstacle for alliance and solidarity, but it is possible to imagine affiliations across identifications (see Sharma and Housee 1999). In an interview With Lowe, Angela Davis offered the formula of 'basing identity on politics rather than the politics on identity' (Davis 1997). Since groupings like Asian, South Asian, and even Indian or Pakistani, as well as British Asian, Asian-American, etc., Can only be usefully thought Of as socially constructed entities and never in the natural or static ways that are deployed by racists, nationalists and dullards, any strategic deployment Of these terms in a 'positive essentialism' should maintain a watch over the ways terms may be reified and become counter-productive even within the politics for which they are deployed. The 'scrupulously visible political interest' proposed by Spivak ( 1987 : 205) must do serious duty in the context of alliance formation with other groups in colour, class, sexuality and gender-based struggles. Lowe cites Fanon's recognition that any movement to dismantle colonialism faces the challenge Of providing a 'new order' that does not reproduce 'the social structure Of the Old system' nor any assimilation to the 'dominant culture's roles and positions by the emergent group, which would merely caricature the old colonialism' (Lowe 1996: 72). Fanon's text about anti-colonial nationalism proves instructive in the context Of the so-called postcolonial, as elite and comprador classes seem to have failed exactly this challenge, and have done so, it would seem, by way Of abandoning the Leninist project which required Of revolutionaries that they first Of all smash the State apparatus. Schools, communications media, the legal system, etc., work to assimilate diverse differences in a melting pot public domain" which operates a rhetoric of equality or rights but consistently forgets and occludes the material inequalities that persist — for clear historical and political reasons — within that domain.ls This is yet again the same trick Which suggests that the sale Of labour power by the worker to the capitalist is a fair and free exchange. In the culture industry's fascination with curry and cornershop, hip-hop and dreadlocks, and so on, it is possible to witness the cultural operation of this rhetoric of equality which appreciates difference on the basis Of an oblique blindness to inequality and material opportunity. The recognition of this contradiction, in which fetishised and celebrated 'objects' of culture come to do duty for obscured social relations between really existing people, is a first, but insufficient, step towards a cultural politics. While it is certainly necessary to take part in the fight against the ways inequalities are Obscured by pluralist multiculturalism and its restricted notions of identity, we also need to take up a more militant and Organised project which goes beyond this first Step Of learning to 'think through the ways in which culture may be rearticulated as a site for alternative histories and memories that provide the grounds to imagine subject, community, and practice in new ways' (Lowe 1996:96). It is also possible that the isolated announcement that culturalism enacts an exclusion of material reality is itself in danger of reinforcing that very exclusion, especially where the prescribed action is also culturalist, however strategic. What is missing here is how a culturalist politics cannot just recognise real material issues but must actually attempt to do something about them. In groups together 'testimony, personal narrative, oral history, literature, film, visual arts, and other cultural forms as sites through which subject, community, and struggle are stratified and mediated' as 'oppositional narratives'. These 'are crucial to the imagination and rearticulation Of new forms Of political subjectivity, collectivity, and practice' (Inwe 1996: 158). Very good. But this 'alternative politicization', on its own, is in danger Of operating only an administrative change at the helm of the institutions of cultural management (dusky brethren curating the new museums, a few postcolonial superstars on the conference circuit, feted rap and sports personalities, but between these examples and the material reality of cultural operation exists the same difference between the service personnel Of a five Star hotel and the international jet-setting guests). Lowe's occasional references to the formation of a 'new' workforce 'within the global reorganization of capitalism' Which is 'linked to an emergent political formation, organizing across race, class, and national boundaries' are offered in programmatic terms only at the end of the book and not in detail. The call remains for 'alternative forms of cultural practice that integrate yet move beyond those of cultural nationalism' (Lowe 1996: 1 71); for 'oppositional and contestatory' immigrant cultures, provoking contradictions which may be 'critically politicized in cultural forms and so as to be 'utilized in the formation Of alternative social practices'; as part of a 'process based on strategic alliances between different sectors, not on their abstract identity' (Lowe 1996: 172); and to 'propose, enact, and embody subjects and practices not contained by the narrative Of American citizenship' (Lowe 1996: 176). While the 'explicit dimension' of 'Rap's cultural politics lie in its lyrical expression', Tricia Rose reminds us that alongside this, there are other important factors. It is the struggle over public space, meanings and interpretations that is critical in 'contemporary cultural politics' (Rose 1994: 124). It is crucial to add that the struggle of black Americans to claim public Space is not one — however large a percentage Of the Billboard top 40 chart may be claimed by Def Jam, and however much rap provides the soundtrack for urban lives — that is easily won. The key problem here, as in — to use Rose's own formulation — the case With cultural production in general, is that there is more than one context, more than one public, more than one interpretation and more than one struggle, many reactions, many things to say. This is the contradictory nature Of the cultural industry — at the very same time as a struggle for meaning and space opens possibilities Of articulation that were previously closed, the extension of 'saying' into public space in a larger context can risk closing off other possibilities, or engaging a ventriloquy which speaks on behalf Of Others. That Apache Indian becomes the sole representative Of bhangra is a case in point: bhangra, South Asian musics, even Apache himself, are much too complex to be glossed in this, albeit understandable in the context, fashion. The contradiction which is to be kept in mind is that progressive sounds in one space may become the agents Of imperialism (and sales projections for Nike) in another. The nature of commodity fetishism and the ever multiplying fragmentation of 'culture' and social relations into a million products in the market is what requires critical analysis. Difference is selling well on the display tables of tourism, technology, television and tele-marketing. Difference is in style. Yet if we recall the ways these commodities (souvenirs, identities, band Width, melody — anything that can in the culture-vulture tradehouse hall) are, as Marx explained, congealed social relations between people in, however refracted, communication with each other, we can begin to reconsider difference as something to be reclaimed, not as identity-product, but as a grounding for solidarity and unity and a possible way beyond the culture industry. Cap’s the root cause of racial oppression and makes extinction inevitable Peter Mclaren 4, Education and Urban Schooling Division prof, UCLA—and Valerie ScatamburloD'Annibale; University of Windsor, Educational Philosophy and Theory, Vol. 36, No. 2, 2004, www.freireproject.org/articles/node%2065/RCGS/class_dismissed-val-peter.10.pdf For example, E. San Juan (2003) argues that race relations and race conflict are necessarily structured by the larger totality of the political economy of a given society, as well as by modifications in the structure of the world economy. He further notes that the capitalist mode of production has articulated ‘race’ with class in a peculiar way. He too is worth a substantial quotation:¶ While the stagnation of rural life imposed a racial or castelike rigidity to the peasantry, the rapid accumulation of wealth through the ever more intensifying exploitation of labor by capital could not so easily ‘racialize’ the wage-workers of a particular nation, given the alienability of labor power—unless certain physical or cultural characteristics can be utilized to divide the workers or render one group an outcast or pariah removed from the domain of ‘free labor.’ In the capitalist development of U.S. society, African, Mexican, and Asian bodies—more precisely, their labor power and its reproductive efficacy—were colonized and racialized; hence the idea of ‘internal colonialism’ retains explanatory validity. ‘Race’ is thus constructed out of raw materials furnished by class relations, the history of class conflicts, and the vicissitudes of colonial/capitalist expansion and the building of imperial hegemony. It is dialecticallyaccented and operationalized not just to differentiate the price of wagelabor within and outside the territory of the metropolitan power, but alsoto reproduce relations of domination–subordination invested with an auraof naturality and fatality. The refunctioning of physical or cultural traits as ideological and political signifiers of class identity reifies social relations. Such ‘racial’ markers enter the field of the alienated laborprocess, concealing the artificial nature of meanings and norms, and essentializing or naturalizing historical traditions and values which are contingent on mutable circumstances. ¶ For San Juan, racism and nationalism are modalities in which class struggles articulate themselves at strategic points in history. He argues thatracism arose with thecreation and expansion of the capitalist world economy. He maintains, rightly in our view, that racial or ethnic group solidarity is given ‘meaning and value in terms of theirplace within the social organization ofproduction and reproduction of the ideological-political order; ideologies of racism as collective social evaluation of solidarities arise to reinforce structural constraints which preserve the exploited and oppressed position of these “racial” solidarities’.¶ It is remarkable, in our opinion, that so much of contemporary social theory has largely abandoned the problems of labor, capitalist exploitation, and class analysis at a time when capitalism is becoming more universal, more ruthless and more deadly. The metaphor of a contemporary ‘tower of Babel’ seems appropriate here—academics striking radical poses in the seminar rooms while remaining oblivious to the possibility that their seemingly radical discursive maneuvers do nothing to further the struggles ‘against oppression and exploitation which continue to be real, material, and not merely “discursive” problems of the contemporary world’ (Dirlik, 1997, p. 176). Harvey (1998, pp. 29–31) indicts the new academic entrepreneurs, the ‘masters of theory-in-and-for-itself’ whose ‘discourse radicalism’ has deftly side-stepped ‘the enduring conundrums of class struggle’ and who have, against a ‘sobering background of cheapened discourse and opportunistic politics,’ been ‘stripped of their self-advertised radicalism.’ For years, they ‘contested socialism,’ ridiculed Marxists, and promoted ‘their own alternative theories of liberatory politics’ but now they have largely been ‘reduced to the role of supplicants in the most degraded form of pluralist politics imaginable.’ As they pursue the politics of difference, the ‘class war rages unabated’ and they seem ‘either unwilling or unable to focus on the unprecedented economic carnage occurring around the globe.’¶ Harvey’s searing criticism suggests that post-Marxists have been busy fiddling while Rome burns and his comments echo those made by Marx (1978, p. 149) in his critique of the Young Hegelians who were, ‘in spite of their allegedly “worldshattering” statements, the staunchest conservatives.’ Marx lamented that the Young Hegelians were simply fighting ‘phrases’ and that they failed to acknowledge that in offering only counter-phrases, they were in no way ‘combating the real existing world’ but merely combating the phrases of the world. Taking a cue from Marx and substituting ‘phrases’ with ‘discourses’ or ‘resignifications’ we would contend that the practitioners of difference politics who operate within exaggerated culturalist frameworks that privilege the realm of representation as the primary arena of political struggle question some discourses of power while legitimating others. Moreover, because they lack a class perspective, their gestures of radicalism are belied by their own class positions.10 As Ahmad (1997a, p. 104) notes:¶ One may speak of any number of disorientations and even oppressions, but one cultivates all kinds of politeness and indirection about the structure of capitalist class relations in which those oppressions are embedded. To speak of any of that directly and simply is to be ‘vulgar.’ In this climate of Aesopian languages it is absolutely essential to reiterate that most things are a matter of class. That kind of statement is … surprising only in a culture like that of the North American university … But it is precisely in that kind of culture that people need to hear such obvious truths. ¶ Ahmad’s provocative observations imply that substantive analyses of the carnage wrought by ‘globalized’ class exploitation have, for the most part, been marginalized by the kind of radicalism that has been instituted among the academic Left in North America. He further suggests that while various post-Marxists have invited us to join their euphoric celebrations honoring the decentering of capitalism, the abandonment of class politics, and the decline of metanarratives (particularly those of Marxism and socialism), they have failed to see that the most ‘meta of all metanarratives of the past three centuries, the creeping annexation of the globe for the dominance of capital over laboring humanity has met, during those same decades, with stunning success’ (Ahmad, 1997b, p. 364). As such, Ahmad invites us to ask anew, the proverbial question: What, then, must be done? To this question we offer no simple theoretical, pedagogical or political prescriptions. Yet we would argue that if social change is the aim, progressive educators and theorists must cease displacing class analysis with the politics of difference. ¶ Conclusion … we will take our stand against the evils [of capitalism, imperialism, and racism] with a solidarity derived from a proletarian internationalism born of socialist idealism. —National Office of the Black Panther Party, February 1970¶ For well over two decades we have witnessed the jubilant liberal and conservative pronouncements of the demise of socialism. Concomitantly, history’s presumed failure to defang existing capitalist relations has been read by many self-identified ‘radicals’ as an advertisement for capitalism’s inevitability. As a result, the chorus refrain ‘There Is No Alternative’, sung by liberals and conservatives, has been buttressed by the symphony of post-Marxist voices recommending that we give socialism a decent burial and move on. Within this context, to speak of the promise of Marx and socialism may appear anachronistic, even naïve, especially since the post-al intellectual vanguard has presumably demonstrated the folly of doing so. Yet we stubbornly believe that the chants of T.I.N.A. must be combated for they offer as a fait accompli, something which progressive Leftists should refuse to accept—namely the triumph of capitalism and its political bedfellow neo-liberalism, which have worked together to naturalize suffering, undermine collective struggle, and obliterate hope. We concur with Amin (1998), who claims that such chants must be defied and revealed as absurd and criminal, and who puts the challenge we face in no uncertain terms: humanity may let itself be led by capitalism’s logic to a fate of collective suicide or it may pave the way for an alternative humanist project of global socialism.¶ The grosteque conditions that inspired Marx to pen his original critique of capitalism are present and flourishing. The inequalities of wealth and the gross imbalances of power that exist today are leading to abuses that exceed those encountered in Marx’s day (Greider, 1998, p. 39). Global capitalism has paved the way for the obscene concentration of wealth in fewer and fewer hands and created a world increasingly divided between those who enjoy opulent affluence and those who languish in dehumanizing conditions and economic misery. In every corner of the globe, we are witnessing social disintegration as revealed by a rise in abject poverty and inequality. At the current historical juncture, the combined assets of the 225 richest people is roughly equal to the annual income of the poorest 47 percent of the world’s population, while the combined assets of the three richest people exceed the combined GDP of the 48 poorest nations (CCPA, 2002, p. 3). Approximately 2.8 billion people—almost half of the world’s population—struggle in desperation to live on less than two dollars a day (McQuaig, 2001, p. 27). As many as 250 million children are wage slaves and there are over a billion workers who are either un- or under-employed. These are the concrete realities of our time—realities that require a vigorous class analysis, an unrelenting critique of capitalism and an oppositional politics capable of confronting what Ahmad (1998, p. 2) refers to as ‘capitalist universality.’ They are realities that require something more than that which is offered by the prophets of ‘difference’ and post-Marxists who would have us relegate socialism to the scrapheap of history and mummify Marxism along with Lenin’s corpse. Never before has a Marxian analysis of capitalism and class rule been so desperately needed. That is not to say that everything Marx said or anticipated has come true, for that is clearly not the case. Many critiques of Marx focus on his strategy for moving toward socialism, and with ample justification; nonetheless Marx did provide us with fundamental insights into class society that have held true to this day. Marx’s enduring relevance lies in his indictment of capitalism which continues to wreak havoc in the lives of most. While capitalism’s cheerleaders have attempted to hide its sordid underbelly, Marx’s description of capitalism as the sorcerer’s dark power is even more apt in light of contemporary historical and economic conditions. Rather than jettisoning Marx, decentering the role of capitalism, and discrediting class analysis, radical educators must continue to engage Marx’s oeuvre and extrapolate from it that which is useful pedagogically, theoretically, and, most importantly, politically in light of the challenges that confront us. The alternative is to reconceptualize democracy as a starting point for unique forms of civic engagement - rejecting the aff's consumptive scholarship is a pre-requisite to fostering radical imagination in public spheres Henry Giroux January 13, 2014"Reclaiming the Radical Imagination: Challenging Casino Capitalism's Punishing Factories "http://www.truth-out.org/opinion/item/21113-disimagination-machines-andpunishing-factories-in-the-age-of-casino-capitalism Henry A. Giroux currently holds the Global TV Network Chair Professorship at McMaster University in the English and Cultural Studies Department and a Distinguished Visiting Professorship at Ryerson University. In my view, the American public is no longer offered the guidance, opportunities and modes of civic education that cultivate their capacity for critical thinking and engaged citizenship. As public values are written out of the vocabulary circulating within important pedagogical spheres such as public and higher education, for example, a mode of civic illiteracy and moral irresponsibility emerges in which it becomes difficult for young people and the broader American public to translate private troubles into public concerns. When civic literacy declines and the attacks on civic values intensify, the commanding institutions of society are divorced from matters of ethics, social responsibility and civic engagement. One consequence is the emergence of a kind of anti-politics in which the discourses of privatization, possessive individualism and crass materialism inundate every aspect of social life, making it easy for people to lose their faith in the critical function of civic education and the culture of an open and substantive democracy. The very essence of politics has been emptied of any substantive meaning and is now largely employed as a form of anti-politics legitimating a range of anti-democratic policies and practices ranging from attacks on women’s reproduction rights and the voting rights act to a war on unions, public servants, public school teachers, young people immigrants and poor minorities. As public spaces are transformed into spaces of consumption, the formative cultures that provide the preconditions for critical thought and agency crucial to any viable notion of democracy are eviscerated. The conditions for encouraging the radical imagination has been transformed into the spectacle of illiteracy, repression, state violence, massive surveillance, the end of privacy, and the ruthless consolidation of power by the ultrarich and powerful financial interest. The imagination is under intense assault and increasingly is relegated to the dead zone of casino capitalism, where social and civil death has become the norm. Under such circumstances, civil society along with critical thought cannot be sustained and become short-lived, fickle and ephemeral. At the same time, it becomes more difficult for individuals to comprehend what they have in common with others and what it means to be held together by shared responsibilities rather than shared fears and competitive struggles. As the dominant culture is emptied out of any substantive meaning and filled with the spectacles of the entertainment industry, the banality of celebrity culture, and a winner-take-all consumer mentality, the American people lose both the languages and the public spheres in which they can actually "think" politics; can, in Tony Judt’s words, "respond energetically or imaginatively to new challenges"; and can collectively organize to influence the commanding ideologies, social practices, and institutions that bear down daily on their lives.[19] Numbed into a moral and political stupor, large segments of the American public and media have not only renounced the political obligation to question authority but also the moral obligation to care for the fate and well-being of others. In a market-driven system in which economic and political decisions are removed from social costs, the flight from responsibility and critical thought is further accentuated by a toxic fog that resembles a moral coma. In such instances, as Wendy Brown has noted, depoliticization works its way through the social order, removing social relations from the configurations of power that shape them and substituting "emotional and personal vocabularies for political ones in formulating solutions to political problems." [20] As private interests trump the public good, public spaces are corroded, and short-term personal advantage replaces any larger notion of civic engagement and social responsibility. Missing from the neoliberal market society are those public spheres - from public and higher education to the mainstream media and digital screen culture - where people can develop what might be called the civic imagination. In my judgment, for-profit spheres are increasingly replacing the spaces in which the civic and radical imagination enables individuals to understand and hold accountable the larger historical, social, political and economic forces that bear down on their lives. The rules of commerce now dictate the meaning of what it means to be educated. Yet, spaces that promote a radical imaginary are crucial in a democracy because they are foundational for developing those formative cultures necessary for young and old alike to develop the knowledge, skills and values central to democratic forms of education, engagement, and agency. What is particularly troubling in American society is the growing absence of a formative culture necessary to construct questioning agents who are capable of dissent and collective action in an imperiled democracy. Matters of justice, equality, and political participation are foundational to any functioning democracy, but it is important to recognize that they have to be rooted in a vibrant formative culture in which democracy is understood not just as a political and economic structure but also as a civic force enabling justice, equality and freedom to flourish. Case Trends lines and historical anecdotes disprove the pessimistic thesis of the 1AC- the myopia of Hands-Up-Don’t-Shoot abandons progressive strategies of truth and hope that are key to solve their impacts Larry Elder January 2, 2015 “Hands Up, Don't Shoot' Activists -- and Historical Ignorance”http://www.realclearpolitics.com/articles/2015/01/02/hands_up_dont_shoot_activists_-_and_historical_ignorance_125117.html Elder earned his B.A.. in political science in 1974 from Brown University. He then earned his J.D. from University of Michigan Law School in 1977.[5] After graduation, he worked with a law firm in Cleveland, Ohio, where he practiced litigation. What to say about "activists" pushing the "Hands Up, Don't Shoot" "movement," even as police shootings of blacks are actually down 75 percent over the last 45 years? Some protestors, many old enough to know better, say ridiculous things about race relations, like "things have gone backward." Time for perspective. Booker T. Washington was born a slave. In his autobiography, "Up From Slavery," written in 1901 -- just a mere 36 years after the Civil War -- Washington wrote: "As a rule, not only did the members of my race entertain no feelings of bitterness against the whites before and during the war, but there are many instances of Negroes tenderly caring for their former masters and mistresses who for some reason have become poor and dependent since the war. I know of instances where the former masters of slaves have for years been supplied with money by their former slaves to keep them from suffering. ... One sends him a little coffee or sugar, another a little meat, and so on. Nothing that the coloured people possess is too good for the son of 'old Mars' Tom,' who will perhaps never be permitted to suffer while any remain on the place who knew directly or indirectly of 'old Mars' Tom.'... "From some things that I have said one may get the idea that some of the slaves did not want freedom. This is not true. I have never seen one who did not want to be free, or one who would return to slavery. "I pity from the bottom of my heart any nation or body of people that is so unfortunate as to get entangled in the net of slavery. I have long since ceased to cherish any spirit of bitterness against the Southern white people on account of the enslavement of my race. No one section of our country was wholly responsible for its introduction, and, besides, it was recognized and protected for years by the General Government. Having once got its tentacles fastened on to the economic and social life of the Republic, it was no easy matter for the country to relieve itself of the institution. Then, when we rid ourselves of prejudice, or racial feeling, and look facts in the face, we must acknowledge that, notwithstanding the cruelty and moral wrong of slavery, the ten million Negroes inhabiting this country, who themselves or whose ancestors went through the school of American slavery, are in a stronger and more hopeful condition, materially, intellectually, morally, and religiously, than is true of an equal number of black people in any other portion of the globe. ... "This I say, not to justify slavery -on the other hand, I condemn it as an institution, as we all know that in America it was established for selfish and financial reasons, and not from a missionary motive -- but to call attention to a fact, and to show how Providence so often uses men and institutions to accomplish a purpose." As for the future, Washington said: "When a Negro girl learns to cook, to wash dishes, to sew, to write a book, or a Negro boy learns to groom horses, or to grow sweet potatoes, or to produce butter, or to build a house, or to be able to practice medicine, as well or better than some one else, they will be rewarded regardless of race or colour. In the long run, the world is going to have the best, and any difference in race, religion, or previous history will not long keep the world from what it wants." Nelson Mandela was beaten and imprisoned for almost three decades. When released at last, some supporters criticized him for showing too much grace and forgiveness toward his enemies. But Mandela's attitude toward forgiveness set the tone for the nation. After his death, a South African wrote: "History now shows (Mandela) did lead South Africa back from the abyss. But he did more, and it was this that sealed his reputation forever. He showed the world and his countrymen -- black, white, rich, poor -- that revenge is not the answer to years of injustice (emphasis added). Who among us, in coming out of prison after 27 years, would have had the generosity to turn away from settling scores? Who among us would have refused to avenge ourselves on those who had treated us with such cruelty? "But he did. Nelson Mandela sat down with his enemies and forgave them and moved on. And in doing so, he rescued his country, and he rescued each one of us, and gave us hope that there could be a future for our beautiful, fractured land. And for the greater earth that we all share." Washington, born a slave, and Mandela, held captive for nearly 28 years, demonstrate the power of forgiveness -- and of looking ahead. And these men forgave their actual oppressors. My mother, born in the Jim Crow South, used to say, "The truth will not set you free -- if delivered without hope." The "Hands Up, Don't Shoot" "movement" is neither truthful nor hopeful. Suicide ethics are counterproductive to rehabilitation. Positive self-love is mutually exclusive with death, and a most coherent and productive response to the illness of the status quo. Sullivan 2012 (Shannon Sullivan, Professor of Philosophy, Women's Studies, and African American Studies, Philosophy Department Head at Penn State University, “On the Need for a New Ethos of White Antiracism,” PhiloSOPHIA, Vol 2, Issue 1, Muse) This is not something that most “good” white people want to hear. Wise recounts a story that underscores this point, as well as confirms Marcano’s insight into the lack of trust across race lines. When giving a presentation on whiteness to a predominantly white college audience, a young white woman asked Wise how his work was received by black people and admitted that she didn’t think she could do the same sort of work because black people wouldn’t trust her. Wise replied that while there occasionally was some mistrust, he never felt hated or resented once black people had seen him work and “walk the walk,” not just “talk the talk.” At that point, an extremely agitated black woman raised her hand and responded, “Make NO mistake . . . we do hate you and we don’t trust you, not for one minute!” (Wise 2005, 97). The young white woman was so distressed that she nearly fell apart. The black woman’s response apparently confirmed all her worst fears as a “good” white person. Wise, however, calmly replied to the black woman that he was sorry to hear this, but it was okay since he ultimately wasn’t fighting racism for the sake of nonwhite people. Upon hearing this, the entire audience snapped to attention as if a bomb had been dropped in the room, and even the agitated black woman looked puzzled. So Wise (2005, 98) continued, “I mean no disrespect by saying that. . . . It’s just that I don’t view it as my job to fight racism so as to save you from it. That would be paternalistic. . . . I fight [racism] because it’s a sickness in my community, and I’m trying to save myself from it.”¶ On a dominant understanding of morality, Wise’s reply appears to selfishly care for himself and his racial group more than he cares about the black woman and other black people. This is why his audience was shocked by his reply to the black woman’s mistrust. In addition to being uncaring and selfish, Wise doesn’t prioritize the establishment of close, trusting relationships between himself and other people of color as a goal, or even a means of his activist work. On a conventional understanding of how white antiracism should operate, the distance Wise allows between himself and people of color makes his activism ineffective at best, and scandalous at worst. But we can view Wise’s reply and his activist work through the lens of a different ethos, one that encourages white people’s “selfish” attention to their own race and understands the importance [End Page 34] of white self-love to their work for racial justice. Wise is fighting for white people’s racial health, rather than their racial goodness, and he sees that their improved health will make them better able to join with communities of color in a relationship of genuine respect, rather than paternalistic domination.¶ “Selfishly” cleaning up their own house is one of the best ways that white people today can contribute to racial justice and transform the meaning and effects of whiteness. In Lucius Outlaw’s (2004) terms, it is the way that whiteness can be “rehabilitated,” or returned to a condition of good health . I’m not sure that whiteness has ever been very healthy, as I think Outlaw would agree, so the return here is very much in question. But the sickness and need for better health are not. White people have been ill from white domination for centuries. If they are to recover, they need answers to the question of what a healthier whiteness might be, answers, in Outlaw’s (2004, 161) words, “that must be taken up and lived by folks who identify as ‘white.’” This is not work white people can ask or demand that people of color do for them, which is not to say that white people don’t have a great deal to learn about themselves from nonwhite people.14 While they cannot do it in a white solipsistic vacuum, white people need to develop a new ethos for their white identities. No one else can live their whiteness for them. So what will they—we, I—do with it? I think the best answers to this question will be ones that emerge apart from the dominance of white guilt and shame. By developing a bestowing self-love that helps transform whiteness , white people can make positive and ongoing contributions to struggles for racial justice.15 Artifacts designed to convey a the depth structural racism render an illusion of particularity that essentializes resistance strategies- crowds out all other forms of engagement Ben Pitcher 2014 “Consuming Race” pg. 144-6 Pitcher is a Senior Lecturer in Sociology at the University of Westminster, London This book has explored some of the ways in which we are all of us involved in the production and reproduction of racial meanings in acts of everyday consumption. It has suggested that race is very much a part of the ordinary business of being a human being in the contemporary world. An engagement with race on the terms set out in this book undermines racial essentialisms, working against investments in race as the property of particular groups and individuals. As I have shown, racial meanings can — as everybody already knows - be divisive and destructive by elaborating harmful distinctions between groups and individuals: racial meanings can produce raeisms, practices of discrimination and inequality. Yet as I have also shown, the meanings of race exceed racism. As a mechanism of desire, understanding, exploration and transformation, race is also a creative resource that we use to navigate our way through our contemporary cultures. To engage with race does not make you a racist, any more than engaging with gender makes you a sexist. The analogy with gender is a useful one, and not only because, like race, it has historically tended to be indexed to and guaranteed by ideas about biological essence. Certainly, we can (and should) use gender to talk about inequality, but we also can (and should) use gender to talk in broader terms about the production of human differences, differences that it makes absolutely no sense to think about in terms of ‘right’ or ‘wrong’ or ‘good’ or ‘bad’. As poststructuralist feminist theory so adeptly shows, we can (and should) also use gender to talk about challenging, redefining and reworking those differences, in the name of freer, fairer, alternative or more interesting futures. The ‘end’ of gender is hypothetically possible, but we only get there by ‘doing’ gender in gendered cultures, not through fantasy mechanisms of transcendence and overcoming. I would make precisely the same points about race: we can (and should) talk about race in critical, descriptive and transformative terms; there is no reason why we should confine ourselves only to the first of these, because in fact these terms are all implicated in and require one another. One way that it might be useful to think about this is in relation to what is often conceived of in discussions of racism as the determining force of racial histories. Because of the resilient way in which race continues to be a part of our cultures, it is common to think about race in terms of a kind of stubborn ‘weight’ of history. Histories of race can be afforded a real force and agency that is used to explain race’s persistence in the con- temporary world. In such analyses, it is as if racial histories quantify race, turning it into a heavy object inexorably bearing down upon and patterning human culture. Race as a determining force is often present, too, in the language of ‘structure’ and ‘institutions’ that anti-racists often deploy to describe race’s apparent ‘depth’ of cultural embeddedness, the way in which racist cultures cannot simply be changed like an individual might change their mind. These metaphors of weight and structural depth can all provide some useful ways of thinking about the cultural politics of race, but it is nevertheless important that we hold on to the fact that they are metaphors, and be careful that they do encourage us to think about race as an entity or phenomenon beyond human intervention. Whether intentionally or otherwise, there is often a curious tendency to evasion in antiracist pronouncements that, intent on stressing the seriousness and profundity of race, seem to close the subject off to thinking in any detail about how it actually gets made and remade (how, in other words, that historical weight and depth is manifested). We get a portentous sense of the importance of race, but not much of a grasp of how and why it has this status, potentially leaving us with the feeling that we probably can’t do very much about it. This book has tried to make an argument that helps to fill in some of those conceptual gaps, and refuse the fatalism that can accompany such a strong sense of racial determination. I have tried in this book’s examples to show some of the ways iI1 which we are all enmeshed and invested in the production of racial meanings. Race is implicated in multiple aspects of our social and cultural lives. The metaphor of ‘depth’ might be better conceived as ‘breadth’, for as I have been arguing, race is not a ‘narrow’ thing (to do with just racism), but is dispersed right across the realm of human experience. The advantage of this recognition — which is an acknowledgement that we are necessarily involved in race, but that this does not necessarily make us racists — is that it gives us an idea of how we might productively engage with the subject. From this perspective, race is no longer an inaccessible and unfathomable thing, reaching up from the depths of history to be treated with a fearful reverence. Race is something that touches and entangles us all. The cultural politics of race become an active and ongoing question of and for the present, of living relationships not dead relationships. This does not mean we can vanish racism in a utopian gesture of wishing it away, but it does mean we can examine in a more clear-sighted way the terrain of racial practice.” This terrain, as I have been arguing, is a complex and complicated one. It does not have the false clarity derived from counterposing racism and anti-racism as a description of race. Every single cultural reference and preference — from a choice of clothing to a taste in literature to a taste in men to the act of typing a Search term into a web browser — is potentially an act of consuming race, and can be scrutinized as such. Every single cultural move potentially positions us within and contributes to the activity of racial formation. To see what race is, and what it does, we need to open our eyes to it and start looking everywhere about us, the space of our desire and pleasure as well as our responsibility. We may have arrived, at the end of this book, with a renewed orientation towards the injustices and inequalities of race, but this has only been made possible by what I would suggest is a necessary detour through a series of themes in which injustice and inequality are not necessarily the first, most obvious, or indeed most significant elements. It is a detour that helps us to understand that anti-racism is not only to do with taking a stance on some setpiece act of racism (important as this may be), but a complicated process that we all of us live through, day by day, as we go about the practice of being human beings. At a historical moment when anti-racist hegemony prompts for many the suggestion that we might have got ‘beyond’ race, it is useful to be reminded how racial meanings are, in truth, absolutely everywhere we look. 2NC 2NC OV Their arg that their personal experience determines the validity of their argument is solipsism—it stifles dialogue and is reductionist David Bridges, Centre for Applied Research in Education, University of East Anglia, 2001, The Ethics of Outsider Research, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Vol. 35, No. 3 First, it is argued that only those who have shared in, and have been part of, a particular experience can understand or can properly understand (and perhaps `properly' is particularly heavily loaded here) what it is like. You need to be a woman to understand what it is like to live as a woman; to be disabled to understand what it is like to live as a disabled person etc. Thus Charlton writes of `the innate inability of able-bodied people, regardless of fancy credentials and awards, to understand the disability experience' (Charlton, 1998, p. 128).¶ Charlton's choice of language here is indicative of the rhetorical character which these arguments tend to assume. This arises perhaps from the strength of feeling from which they issue, but it warns of a need for caution in their treatment and acceptance. Even if able-bodied people have this `inability' it is difficult to see in what sense it is `innate'. Are all credentials `fancy' or might some (e.g. those reflecting a sustained, humble and patient attempt to grapple with the issues) be pertinent to that ability? And does Charlton really wish to maintain that there is a single experience which is the experience of disability, whatever solidarity disabled people might feel for each other?¶ The understanding that any of us have of our own conditions or experience is unique and special, though recent work on personal narratives also shows that it is itself multi-layered and inconstant, i.e. that we have and can provide many different understandings even of our own lives (see, for example, Tierney, 1993). Nevertheless, our own understanding has a special status: it provides among other things a data source for others' interpretations of our actions; it stands in a unique relationship to our own experiencing; and no one else can have quite the same understanding. It is also plausible that people who share certain kinds of experience in common stand in a special position in terms of understanding those shared aspects of experience. However, once this argument is applied to such broad categories as `women' or `blacks', it has to deal with some very heterogeneous groups; the different social, personal and situational characteristics that constitute their individuality may well outweigh the shared characteristics; and there may indeed be greater barriers to mutual understanding than there are gateways.¶ These arguments, however, all risk a descent into solipsism: if our individual understanding is so particular, how can we have communication with or any understanding of anyone else? But, granted Wittgenstein's persuasive argument against a private language (Wittgenstein, 1963, perhaps more straightforwardly presented in Rhees, 1970), we cannot in these circumstances even describe or have any real understanding of our own condition in such an isolated world. Rather it is in talking to each other, in participating in a shared language, that we construct the conceptual apparatus that allows us to understand our own situation in relation to others, and this is a construction which involves under- standing differences as well as similarities.¶ Besides, we have good reason to treat with some scepticism accounts provided by individuals of their own experience and by extension accounts provided by members of a particular category or community of people. We know that such accounts can be riddled with special pleading, selective memory, careless error, self-centredness, myopia, prejudice and a good deal more. A lesbian scholar illustrates some of the pressures that can bear, for example, on an insider researcher in her own community:¶ As an insider, the lesbian has an important sensitivity to offer, yet she is also more vulnerable than the non-lesbian researcher, both to the pressure from the heterosexual world--that her studies conform to previous works and describe lesbian reality in terms of its relationship with the outside-- and to pressure from the inside, from within the lesbian community itself--that her studies mirror not the reality of that community but its self-protective ideology. (Kreiger, 1982, p. 108)¶ In other words, while individuals from within a community have access to a particular kind of understanding of their experience, this does not automatically attach special authority (though it might attach special interest) to their own representations of that experience. Moreover, while we might acknowledge the limitations of the understanding which someone from outside a community (or someone other than the individual who is the focus of the research) can develop, this does not entail that they cannot develop and present an understanding or that such understanding is worthless. Individuals can indeed find benefit in the understandings that others offer of their experience in, for example, a counselling relationship, or when a researcher adopts a supportive role with teachers engaged in reflection on or research into their own practice. Many have echoed the plea of the Scottish poet, Robert Burns (in `To a louse'):¶ O wad some Pow'r the giftie gie us To see oursels as others see us!3¶ --even if they might have been horrified with what such power revealed to them. Russell argued that it was the function of philosophy (and why not research too?) `to suggest many possibilities which enlarge our thoughts and free them from the tyranny of custom . . .It keeps alive our sense of wonder by showing familiar things in an unfamiliar aspect' (Russell, 1912, p. 91). `Making the familiar strange', as Stenhouse called it, often requires the assistance of someone unfamiliar with our own world who can look at our taken-for-granted experience through, precisely, the eye of a stranger. Sparkes (1994) writes very much in these terms in describing his own research, as a white, heterosexual middle- aged male, into the life history of a lesbian PE teacher. He describes his own struggle with the question `is it possible for heterosexual people to undertake research into homosexual populations?' but he concludes that being a `phenomenological stranger' who asks `dumb questions' may be a useful and illuminating experience for the research subject in that they may have to return to first principles in reviewing their story. This could, of course be an elaborate piece of self-justification, but it is interesting that someone like Max Biddulph, who writes from a gay/bisexual stand- point, can quote this conclusion with apparent approval (Biddulph, 1996).¶ People from outside a community clearly can have an understanding of the experience of those who are inside that community. It is almost certainly a different understanding from that of the insiders. Whether it is of any value will depend among other things on the extent to which they have immersed themselves in the world of the other and portrayed it in its richness and complexity; on the empathy and imagination that they have brought to their enquiry and writing; on whether their stories are honest, responsible and critical (Barone, 1992). Nevertheless, this value will also depend on qualities derived from the researchers' exter- nality: their capacity to relate one set of experiences to others (perhaps from their own community); their outsider perspective on the structures which surround and help to define the experience of the community; on the reactions and responses to that community of individuals and groups external to it.4¶ Finally, it must surely follow that if we hold that a researcher, who (to take the favourable case) seeks honestly, sensitively and with humility to understand and to represent the experience of a community to which he or she does not belong, is incapable of such understanding and representation, then how can he or she understand either that same experience as mediated through the research of someone from that community? The argument which excludes the outsider from under- standing a community through the effort of their own research, a fortiori excludes the outsider from that understanding through the secondary source in the form of the effort of an insider researcher or indeed any other means. Again, the point can only be maintained by insisting that a particular (and itself ill-defined) understanding is the only kind of understanding which is worth having.¶ The epistemological argument (that outsiders cannot understand the experience of a community to which they do not belong) becomes an ethical argument when this is taken to entail the further proposition that they ought not therefore attempt to research that community. I hope to have shown that this argument is based on a false premise. Even if the premise were sound, however, it would not necessarily follow that researchers should be prevented or excluded from attempting to under- stand this experience, unless it could be shown that in so doing they would cause some harm. This is indeed part of the argument emerging from disempowered communities and it is to this that I shall now turn. No reason ballot key – neg on presumption A Reasonability Makes judge intervention inevitable – either you defend a policy action or you don’t – allowing leeway makes predictable ground of what is topical impossible. Clear definition of terms is key Resnick, assistant professor of political science – Yeshiva University, ‘1 (Evan, “Defining Engagement,” Journal of International Affairs, Vol. 54, Iss. 2) In matters of national security, establishing a clear definition of terms is a precondition for effective policymaking. Decisionmakers who invoke critical terms in an erratic, ad hoc fashion risk alienating their constituencies. They also risk exacerbating misperceptions and hostility among those the policies target. Scholars who commit the same error undercut their ability to conduct valuable empirical research. Hence, if scholars and policymakers fail rigorously to define "engagement," they undermine the ability to build an effective foreign policy. PIC Vote negative to endorse the suicide of whiteness without the involvement of physicians The creation of more medicalized control cause mass violence – short-circuits the entire case Enoch 4 (Simon Enoch, Ryerson university. 2004, http://www.foucault-studies.com/no1/enoch.pdf, 7/10/09) We do not endorse Holocaust Trivialization Finally, what is perhaps the most disconcerting and destabilizing aspect of Foucault’s conception of thanato-politics is his insistence that this murderous potential always remains latent within the management and regulation of life processes that constitute modern biopolitics. Thus, to dismiss the actions of Nazi doctors as an “aberration” or as a “lethal outbreak of anachronistic barbarism,” is to view these events as a singular anomaly in the otherwise progressive trajectory of modernity, rather than a potential inherent within modernity itself.80 However, Foucault’s analysis cautions against such an interpretation. The surfacing of a thanato-politics from a regime of bio-politics should not be construed as uniquely peculiar to Nazism, rather it should be viewed as a potential latent in any bio-political regime, regardless of its outward political appearance.81 Thanato-politics is the counterpart “of a power that exerts a positive influence on life, that endeavors to administer, optimize, and multiply it, subjecting it to precise controls and comprehensive regulations.”82 While Nazism perhaps represents the most grotesque manifestation of the thanato-politics latent within the regulatory and disciplinary techniques of modern biopower, Foucault reminds us that; They used and extended mechanisms already present in most other societies. More than that: in spite of their own internal madness, they used to a largeextent the ideas and devices of our political rationality.83 Similarly, Nazi medicine should not be viewed as a perversion of mainstream scientific canons, but as extending the underlying rationality of modern science itself. As Mario Biagioli observes, much of the scholarship on Nazi medicine tends to present Nazi scientific practices as a major anomaly in the history of science or as a deviation from proper medical practice.84 However, Biagioli argues that such a view constitutes a “dangerous naivety” that prevents us from viewing “normal” medical science as implicated in the Final Solution.85 Indeed, as Lerner has shown, The biologizing of prejudice, discrimination, and ultimately the call for genocide was invented and promoted by “normal scientists,” and indeed by leaders within their professions. Not only can these scientists, in hindsight, be regarded as among the top professionals in their fields at the time of their work: they also saw themselves with some justification as having the same status as such people as Pasteur, Koch, and Lister.86 Similarly, Lifton’s interviews with the assistants of Dr. Josef Mengele illustrates the degree to which practices that we now consider irrational were once regarded as scientifically legitimate. As Lifton explains, Mengele’s assistant considered the scientific method employed at the camps, [M]ore or less standard for the time, the norm for anthropological work. She recognized it as the same approach she had been trained in at her Polish university under a distinguished anthropologist with German, pre-Nazi academic connections.87 Furthermore, as Milchman and Rosenberg demonstrate, the “myth of modern medicine” with its utopian designs towards the engineering of the healthy society through the eradication of disease and death pervades the Nazi bio- medical vision.88 Rather than constituting a radical break with the modern tenets of medical science, Nazi medicine extended the same methods and rationality of mainstream medicine, albeit to a terrifying degree. To label such practices as “bad science,” fraudulent, or methodologically incompetent in hindsight is to disregard Foucault’s emphasis on the historically contingent nature of all forms of knowledge, medical science included. Indeed, that such practices were viewed as rational and legitimate at the time, employed by eminent scientific professionals, calls into question the very legitimacy and rationality of scientific practices conducted in our own present. Thus, Foucault exposes what Milchman and Rosenberg deem “the dark side of modernity,” revealing the potential for genocidal practices not as a result of deviations from the values of reason and rationality that constitute modernity, but inherent within modernity itself. Foucault thereby alerts us to the dangers within the purported rational and progressive practices and techniques that characterize modernity.89 While the surfacing of this murderous potential ensconced within modernity is neither inevitable or inescapable, Foucault’s insistence that we recognize and interrogate this potential forces us to realize that “modernity is not a one-way trip to freedom,” and that we must maintain a vigilant pessimism in regards to the truth claims of modernity in order to forestall potential future holocausts. A2 Accessibility The law is produced and maintained by the production of cultural narratives and assumptions---engagement with legal structures is vital to alter those cultural norms--this turns their offense because it’s directly in the interests of the powerful for law to be seen as narrow and exclusionary---the more activists refuse to engage with the legal system, the more the powerful consolidate their control. This proves there’s a topical version of the aff, and only that version solves their offense. Linda H. Edwards 13, the E.L. Cord Foundation Professor of Law, William S. Boyd School of Law, University of Nevada Las Vegas, Fall/Winter 2013, “Where Do the Prophets Stand? Hamdi, Myth, and the Master's Tools,” Connecticut Public Interest Law Journal, 13 Conn. Pub. Int. L.J. 43, p. lexis I. Introduction Imagine an ancient walled city. Inside the walls, the city's inhabitants busily go about their work. They have routines. They have a common language. They do not always agree with each other, but they meet in common places and use accepted methods and procedures to decide the city's issues. Outside the wall stands a small group of prophets . The prophets have messages for the city's people, and they are trying to be heard over the city's walls. Occasionally a few city dwellers become aware that someone is shouting from outside the walls, but the words fall strangely on city dwellers' ears . The distant voices, barely audible, are lost among the background sounds of ongoing city life. Occasionally, a city leader looks over the walls, notices the prophets, and lobs a verbal assault in their direction, but city life is unaffected. Year after year, the prophets speak, and year after year, the city ignores them.¶ Does this image of the ancient walled city and the prophets excluded from it describe the relationship of oppositionists with law? Have people like Patricia Williams, Robin West, Kimberle Crenshaw, Richard Delgado, Mari Matsuda, and the late Derrick Bell been standing outside the gates for over thirty years, critiquing the city of law and the work of its inhabitants? Many traditionalist n1 leaders seem to think so. Inside the city, they have been going about their work unaffected, n2 using the same language and methods they learned from their mentors. Occasionally a traditionalist defender reacts to the prophets, usually with name-calling derision. Consider this from Richard Posner:¶ [*44] ¶ What is most arresting about critical race theory is that . . . it turns its back on the Western tradition of rational inquiry, forswearing analysis for narrative. Rather than marshal logical arguments and empirical data, critical race theorists tell stories - fictional, science-fictional, autobiographical, anecdotal - designed to expose the pervasive and debilitating racism of America today. By repudiating reasoned argumentation, the storytellers reinforce stereotypes about the intellectual capacities of nonwhites. n3¶ Posner goes on, using terms like "lunatic core," "postmodernist virus," "loony Afrocentrism," and "goofy ideas and irresponsible dicta." n4 He calls critical race theorists "whiners and wolf-criers," coming across as "labile and intellectually limited." n5 He says, "Their grasp of social reality is weak; their diagnoses are inaccurate; their suggested cures . . . are tried and true failures. Their lodgment in the law schools is a disgrace to legal education, which lacks the moral courage and the intellectual self-confidence to pronounce a minority movement's scholarship bunk." n6 Having hurled his attack over the city walls, he goes back to his own work, unaffected by oppositionist critique.¶ Posner and other traditionalists thus maintain that oppositionists stand outside the gates of law . If they are on law faculties, they should not be. n7 Whether this view is accurate depends, in large part, on what we mean by law. Some of history's best scholars and judges have been tramping around in that field for a long time, so one might wonder how much ground remains untrod. Still, we need to find some new territory, because we are far from a satisfactory answer. What's worse is that we do not seem able to have a productive conversation, as Posner demonstrates. The loudest traditionalist voices ridicule both critical theory's narrative methods , n8 and critical theorists themselves . n9 To the traditionalist eye, critical theorists repudiate traditional legal discourse as nothing more than domination and power politics. n10 It is as if the two camps are speaking [*45] different languages. In fact, in some important ways, they are.¶ The twenty-fifth anniversary of the publication of Peter Goodrich's Legal Discourse: Studies in Linguistics, Rhetoric and Legal Analysis n11 offers an appropriate opportunity to revisit this topic. This article's modest goal is to suggest that narrative theory and cognitive science n12 can help traditionalists better understand the language of critical theory n13 - specifically, why critical theory insists on telling stories and why those narrative critiques are legitimately a part of law. n14 Since the article's primary goal is to speak to traditionalists , it begins by using what Posner wants-logical argument-to "reason" its way to the conclusion that critical theory critiques law from the inside. A key part of that deductive argument is the premise that cultural myths and other master stories operate at a largely hidden and unconscious level beneath the language of traditional law talk. To explain and demonstrate that premise, the article offers a short course in myth and then looks at the role of one myth-the myth of redemptive violence-in legal decision-making. The article explains the myth and how it is pervasively reinforced through movies, video games, and other media and then shows how it affected the deliberations in Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, the saga of an American citizen imprisoned without due process by his own government. n15¶ Deductive argument cannot be the end of the matter, however, because naive reliance on "reason" is actually the antithesis of this article's primary point and certainly inconsistent with critical theory itself. What we mean by "law" is not a matter of some seemingly preordained logical structure- [*46] this one or any other. Rather, it is a matter of human choice, and as with all matters of human choice, it is driven by contested values, frames, power, and politics . This article, therefore, offers some nondeductive reasons for choosing to define "law" broadly enough to include critical theory's critiques. First, though, a deductive argument:¶ II. Defining "Law" Deductively: A Four-step Dance¶ A. Step One: Law includes legal outcomes and the articulated reasons for those outcomes.¶ To start simply, law includes constitutions, statutes, regulations, and judicial decisions. Traditional law talk interprets and applies these texts using a cadre of traditional methods: semantic interpretation of authoritative text; reliance on canons of statutory construction; the use of careful or creative analogies; and the support of relevant social policy, economic theory, or moral principle. n16 These methods have long been treated as legitimately part of "law" because they claim to account for legal results, shaping how the law is applied and how it may change. When lawyers and judges use these methods, no one would dispute that they are using the methods of the law. When Richard Posner finishes his tirade against critical race theory and returns to his normal daily work, these are his tools. n17¶ B. Step Two: These tools are the stated reasons for legal decisions, but they do not fully or fundamentally account for legal outcomes.¶ As both oppositionists and rhetoricians have pointed out, legal results are not simply the result of adherence to authority or policy. n18 Rather, they are the product of underlying values and assumptions about human nature [*47] and the world, what Peter Goodrich calls "preconstructions, preferred meanings, rhetorical and ideological dimensions." n19 Among these preconstructions are the cultural myths, n20 metaphors, and meta-narratives that frame the way those in power see the world. Far more effectively than authorities or policies, these implicit but largely unrecognized n21 frames (values, assumptions, social and political structures) account for where we are and how we got here. n22 Thus, myths and other frames operate silently but powerfully beneath traditional law talk about objective reasons.¶ C. Step Three: If cultural myths and other preconstructions guide and constrain legal decisions (step two), then surely these preconstructions are also part of law .¶ It would be a curious position to say that law includes the reasons that claim- perhaps inaccurately-to account for legal results but not the actual, though unstated, reasons for those same legal results. n23 Powerful forces cultivate these preconstructions and are simultaneously captured by them, as will be discussed below. Their problematic operation is or should be a target of oppositionist critique of law . n24 Dominant myths and other such frames have been instrumental in building and maintaining the master's house and are among the master's most important tools. n25 Therefore, logically, they are part of "law," just as the unseen foundation is part of a house.¶ D. Step Four: If myths and other stories are part of law when used implicitly by the masters in making law (step three), they are surely part of law when used explicitly by those who critique law .¶ Quite rightly, early oppositional critique used those same tools-especially stories-to challenge the way the world looks to those inhabiting the halls of power. n26 The turn to narrative was part of the early brilliance of critical theory, made at a time when few others had realized the significance of narrative in law. Are these myths, metaphors, and outsider stories part of law? If narrative is part of law when it is used by the dominant group to justify particular legal results (step three), it is surely also part of law when used by critical theory to critique those same results. It would seem, then, that Goodrich is right. n27 Oppositional critique is within law, not external to it.¶ The key difference between traditional law-talk and oppositionist critique is that those controlling myths, metaphors, and meta-narratives are kept implicit in traditional law-talk. We don't speak of those things. We confine the discourse to rationalist, scientific, putatively objective language. As oppositionists and rhetoricians have pointed out, it is in the interests of those in power to limit law to this "self-protective" view. But to oppositionists and at least some rhetoricians, such traditional law talk is [*49] only an attempt to justify a result chosen for other and often unstated reasons. n28 In a way comparable to a psychoanalyst looking for what lies beneath an explicit behavior, oppositionists try to look deeper to ask what is really going on. Is that permissible in the discourse community? Can such things be said inside the wall? Law is clearly, even in the most traditionalist view, the product of argument . I will contend here that justificatory argument in rationalist objectivist language is half of an argument with oppositionist critique constituting the other half. For law to progress, for it to live in dynamic tension, we need both sides of the argument inside the wall . The rationalists are free to deny and refute oppositionist critique, but not to silence or exile it.¶ Like any deductive argument, this little four-step dance is subject to challenge at several key points. It might be vulnerable in step two, for instance, in the face of skepticism about admitting a legal role for the myths and other frames that support the power of the dominant group. It is certainly vulnerable in step three, for one could fairly say that once we include in "law" the largely unconscious cultural frames that operate within us, then law includes everything and the question loses its meaning. Perhaps these more foundational but unconscious myths and other frames are not part of law because their effects are ubiquitous, defining, and constraining our views of the world in every part of life. One might argue, then, that oppositionist critique both originates from outside law and critiques something other than law. n29 With these two legitimate challenges on the table, it is fair to require me to say more about the legal role of myths and other frames and about what is at stake when we choose a definition for law. 1NR Alt Now The alternative is to reconceptualize democracy as a starting point for unique forms of civic engagement- developing a new political language that posits democracy as an axiom for collective resistance solves- that’s Giroux 14- student intellectuals are key to displace the consumptive nature of pedagogical spaces like debate which is conceded warrant/link Here more evidence on that Nixon ‘11 (Rob, Rachel Carson Professor of English, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Slow Violence and the Environmentalism of the Poor, pgs. 14-16) How do we bring home-and bring emotionally to life-threats that take time to wreak their havoc, threats that never materialize in one spectacular, explosive, cinematic scene? Apprehension is a critical word here, a crossover term that draws together the domains of perception, emotion, and action. To engage slow violence is to confront layered predicaments of apprehension: to apprehend-to arrest, or at least mitigate-often imperceptible threats requires rendering them apprehensible to the senses through the work of scientific and imaginative testimony. An influential lineage of environmental thought gives primacy to immediate sensory apprehension, to sight above all, as foundational for any environmental ethics of place. George Perkins Marsh, the mid-nineteenth-century environmental pioneer, argued in Man and Nature that "the power most important to cultivate and at the same time, hardest to acquire, is that of seeing what is before him." Aldo Leopold similarly insisted that "we can be ethical only toward what we can see.'?' But what happens when we are unsighted, when what extends before us-in the space and time that we most deeply inhabit-remains invisible? How, indeed, are we to act ethically toward human and biotic communities that lie beyond our sensory ken? What then, in the fullest sense of the phrase, is the place of seeing in the world that we now inhabit? What, moreover, is the place of the other senses? How do we both make slow violence visible yet also challenge the privileging of the visible? Such questions have profound consequences for the apprehension of slow violence, whether on a cellular or a transnational scale. Planetary consciousness (a notion that has undergone a host of theoretical formulations) becomes pertinent here, perhaps most usefully in the sense in which Mary Louise Pratt elaborates it, linking questions of power and perspective, keeping front and center the often latent, often invisible violence in the view. Who gets to see, and from where? When and how does such empowered seeing become normative? And what perspectives-not least those of the poor or women or the colonized-do hegemonic sight conventions of visuality obscure? Pratt's formulation of planetary consciousness remains invaluable because it allows us to connect forms of apprehension to forms of imperial violence." Against this backdrop, 1want to introduce the third central concern of this book. Alongside slow violence and the environmentalism of the poor, the chapters that follow are critically concerned with the political, imaginative, and strategic role of environmental writer-activists. Writer-activists can help us apprehend threats imaginatively that remain imperceptible to the senses, either because they are geographically remote, too vast or too minute in scale, or are played out across a time span that exceeds the instance of observation or even the physiological life of the human observer. In a world permeated by insidious, yet unseen or imperceptible violence, imaginative writing can help make the unapparent appear, making it accessible and tangible by humanizing drawn-out threats inaccessible to the immediate senses. Writing can challenge perceptual habits that downplay the damage slow violence inflicts and bring into imaginative focus apprehensions that elude sensory corroboration. The narrative imaginings of writer-activists may thus offer us a different kind of witnessing: of sights unseen. To allay states of apprehension-trepidations, forebodings, shadows cast by the invisible-entails facing the challenge, at once imaginative and scientific, of giving the unapparent a materiality upon which we can act. Yet poor communities, often disproportionately exposed to the force fields of slow violence-be they military residues or imported e-waste or the rising tides of climate change-are the communities least likely to attract sustained scientific inquiry into causes, effects, and potential redress. Such poor communities are abandoned to sporadic science at best and usually no science at all; they are also disproportionately subjected to involuntary pharmaceutical experiments. Indeed, when such communities raise concerns, they often become targets of well-funded antiscience by forces that have a legal or commercial interest in manufacturing and disseminating doubt." Such embattled communities, beset by officially unacknowledged hazards, must find ways to broadcast their inhabited fears, their lived sense of a corroded environment, within the broader global struggles over apprehension. It is here that writers, filmmakers, and digital activists may play a mediating role in helping counter the layered invisibility that results from insidious threats, from temporal protractedness, and from the fact that the afflicted are people whose quality of life-and often whose very existence-is of indifferent interest to the corporate media. Using the events in Ferguson a dialogical starting point for radical democratic vision solves 100% of the case Henry A. Giroux August 18, 2014 "The Militarization of Racism and Neoliberal Violence" http://www.truth-out.org/opinion/item/25660-the-militarization-of-racism-and-neoliberal-violence Henry A. Giroux currently holds the Global TV Network Chair Professorship at McMaster University in the English and Cultural Studies Department and a Distinguished Visiting Professorship at Ryerson University. The recent killing of an unarmed 18-year-old African-American, Michael Brown, in Ferguson, Missouri, by a white police officer has made visible how a kind of racist, military metaphysics now dominates American life. His subsequent demonization by the media only confirms its entrance into the public consciousness as a form of vicious entertainment. The police have been turned into soldiers who view the neighborhoods in which they operate as war zones. Outfitted with full riot gear, submachine guns, armored vehicles, and other lethal weapons imported from the battlefields of Iraq and Afghanistan, their mission is to assume battle-ready behavior. Is it any wonder that violence rather than painstaking, neighborhood police work and community outreach and engagement becomes the norm for dealing with alleged "criminals," especially at a time when more and more behaviors are being criminalized? But I want to introduce a caveat. I think it is a mistake to simply focus on the militarization of the police and their racist actions in addressing the killing of Michael Brown. What we are witnessing in this brutal killing and mobilization of state violence is symptomatic of the neoliberal, racist, punishing state emerging all over the world, with its encroaching machinery of social death. The neoliberal killing machine is on the march globally. The spectacle of neoliberal misery is too great to deny any more and the only mode of control left by corporate-controlled societies is violence, but a violence that is waged against the most disposable such as immigrant children, protesting youth, the unemployed, the new precariat and black youth. Neoliberal states can no longer justify and legitimate their exercise of ruthless power and its effects under casino capitalism. Given the fact that corporate power now floats above and beyond national boundaries, the financial elite can dispense with political concessions in order to pursue their toxic agendas. Moreover, as Slavoj Žižek argues "worldwide capitalism can no longer sustain or tolerate . . . global equality. It is just too much." (1) Moreover, in the face of massive inequality, increasing poverty, the rise of the punishing state, and the attack on all public spheres, neoliberalism can no longer pass itself off as synonymous with democracy. The capitalist elite, whether they are hedge fund managers, the new billionaires from Silicon Valley, or the heads of banks and corporations, is no longer interested in ideology as their chief mode of legitimation. Force is now the arbiter of their power and ability to maintain control over the commanding institutions of American society. Finally, I think it is fair to say that they are too arrogant and indifferent to how the public feels.¶ Neoliberal capitalism has nothing to do with democracy and this has become more and more evident among people, especially youth all over the globe. As Žižek has observed, "the link between democracy and capitalism has been broken." (2) The important question of justice has been subordinated to the violence of unreason, to a market logic that divorces itself from social costs, and a ruling elite that has an allegiance to nothing but profit and will do anything to protect their interests. This is why I think it is dreadfully wrong to just talk about the militarization of local police forces without recognizing that the metaphor of "war zone" is apt for a global politics in which the social state and public spheres have been replaced by the machinery of finance, the militarization of entire societies not just the police, and the widespread use of punishment that extends from the prison to the schools to the streets. Some have rightly argued that these tactics have been going on in the black community for a long time and are not new. Police violence certainly has been going on for some time, but what is new is that the intensity of violence and the level of military-style machinery of death being employed is much more sophisticated and deadly. For instance, as Kevin Zeese and Margaret Flowers point out, the militarization of the police in the United States is a recent phenomenon that dates back to 1971. They write:¶ The militarization of police is a more recent phenomenon [and marks] the rapid rise of Police Paramilitary Units (PPUs, informally SWAT teams) which are modeled after special operations teams in the military. PPUs did not exist anywhere until 1971when Los Angeles under the leadership of the infamous police chief Daryl Gates, formed the first one and used it for demolishing homes with tanks equipped with battering rams. By 2000, there were 30,000 police SWAT teams [and] by the late 1990s, 89% of police departments in cities of over 50,000 had PPUs, almost double the mid-80s figure; and in smaller towns of between 25,000 and 50,000 by 2007, 80% had a PPU quadrupling from 20% in the mid-80s. [Moreover,] SWAT teams were active with 45,000 deployments in 2007 compared to 3,000 in the early 80s. The most common use . . . was for serving drug search warrants where they were used 80% of the time, but they were also increasingly used for patrolling neighborhoods. (3)¶ At the same time, the impact of the rapid militarization of local police forces on poor black communities is nothing short of terrifying and symptomatic of the violence that takes place in advanced genocidal states. For instance, according to a recent report entitled "Operation Ghetto Storm," produced by the Malcolm X Grassroots Movement, "police officers, security guards, or self-appointed vigilantes extra judicially killed at least 313 African-Americans in 2012. . . . This means a black person was killed by a security officer every 28 hours. The report suggests that "the real number could be much higher." (4)¶ The emergence of the warrior cop and the surveillance state go hand in hand and are indicative not only of state sanctioned racism but also of the rise of an authoritarian society and the dismantling of civil liberties. Brutality mixed with attacks on freedom dissent, and peaceful protest harbors memories of past brutal regimes such as the dictatorships in Latin America in the 1970s and 1980s. The events in Ferguson speak to a history of representation in both the United States and abroad that Americans have chosen to forget at their own risk. In spite of his generally right-wing political views, Rand Paul got it right in arguing that "When you couple this militarization of law enforcement with an erosion of civil liberties and due process that allows the police to become judge and jury - national security letters, no-knock searches, broad general warrants, pre-conviction forfeiture - we begin to have a very serious problem on our hands." What he does not name is the problem, as Danielle LaSusa has observed, which is a society that is not simply on the precipice of authoritarianism, but has fallen over the edge. Truly, as Hannah Arendt pointed out, we live in "dark times." Under the regime of neoliberalism, the circle of those considered disposable and subject to state violence is now expanding. The heavy hand of the state is not only racist; it is also part of an authoritarian mode of governance willing to do violence to anyone who threatens neoliberal capitalism, white Christian fundamentalism, and the power of the military-industrial-academicsurveillance state. The United States' embrace of murderous weapons to be used on enemies abroad has taken a new turn and now will be used on those considered disposable at home. As the police become more militarized, the weapons of death become more sophisticated and the legacy of killing civilians becomes both an element of domestic as well as foreign policy. Amid the growing intensity of state terrorism, violence becomes the DNA of a society that refuses to deal with larger structural issues such as massive inequality in wealth and power, a government that now unapologetically serves the rich and powerful corporate interests, and makes violence the organizing principle of governance. (5)¶ The worldwide response to what is happening in Ferguson sheds a light on the racist and militarized nature of American society so as to make its claim to democracy seem both hypocritical and politically insipid. At the same time, such protests make visible what the artist Francisco Goya called the sleep of reason, a lapse in witnessing, attentiveness, and the failure of conscience, which lie at the heart of neoliberal's ongoing attempt to depoliticize the American public. Political life has come alive once again in the United States, moving away from its withdrawal into consumer fantasies and privatized obsessions. The time has come to recognize that Ferguson is not only about the violence and consolidation of white power and racism in one town; it is also symptomatic of white power and the deep-seated legacy of racism in the country as a whole, which goes along with what the United States has become under the intensifying politics of market fundamentalism, militarism and disposability.¶ Ferguson prompts us to rethink the meaning of politics and to begin to think not about reform but a major restructuring of our values, institutions and notions of what a real democracy might look like. We need to live in a country in which we are alarmed rather than entertained by violence. It is time for the American people to unite around our shared fate as stakeholders in a radical democracy, rather than being united around our shared fears and the toxic glue of state terrorism and everyday violence. Ferguson points to some nefarious truths about our past and present. But the public response points in another more hopeful direction. What Ferguson has told us is that the political and moral imagination is still alive, thirsting for justice, and unwilling to let the dark clouds of authoritarianism put the lights out for good. But for that to happen we must move from moral outrage to collective struggles as part of a wider effort to dismantle the mass incarceration society, the surveillance state and the military-industrial-academic complex. How many more children, black youth, immigrants and others have to die before the struggle deepens? A2 Permutation Reformism DA—even if they destabilize race—cap ensures a constant reshuffling of artificial divisions—perm is deck chairs Dave Hill, teaches at Middlesex University and is Visiting Professor of Critical Education Policy and Equality Studies at the University of Limerick, Ireland. Culturalist and Materialist Explanations of Class and "Race", Cultural Logic 2009 http://clogic.eserver.org/2009/Hill.pdf In contrast to both Critical Race Theorists and revisionist socialists/left liberals/equivalence theorists, and those who see caste as the primary form of oppression, Marxists would agree that objectivelywhatever our “race” or gender or sexuality or current level of academic attainment or religious identity, whatever the individual and group history and fear of oppression and attack- the fundamental objective and material form of oppression in capitalism is class oppression. Black and Women capitalists, or Jewish and Arab capitalists, or Dalit capitalists in India, exploit the labour power of their multi-ethnic men and women workers, essentially (in terms of the exploitation of labour power and the appropriation of surplus value) in just the same way as do white male capitalists, or uppercaste capitalists. But the subjective consciousness of identity, this subjective affirmation of one particular identity, while seared into the souls of its victims, should not mask the objective nature of contemporary oppression under capitalism – class oppression that, of course, hits some “raced” and gendered and caste and occupational sections of the working class harder than others. Martha Gimenez (2001:24) succinctly explains that “class is not simply another ideology legitimating oppression.” Rather, class denotes “exploitative relations between people mediated by their relations to the means of production.” Apple’s “parallellist,” or equivalence model of exploitation (equivalence of exploitation based on “race,” class and gender, his “tryptarchic” model of inequality) produces valuable data and insights into aspects of and the extent and manifestations of gender oppression and “race” oppression in capitalist USA. However, such analyses serve to occlude the class-capital relation, the class struggle, to obscure an essential and defining nature of capitalism, class conflict. Objectively, whatever our “race” or gender or caste or sexual orientation or scholastic attainment, whatever the individual and group history and fear of oppression and attack, the fundamental form of oppression in capitalism is class oppression. While the capitalist class is predominantly white and male, capital in theory and in practice can be blind to colour and gender and caste – even if that does not happen very often. African Marxist-Leninists such as Ngugi wa Thiong’o (e.g., Ngugi wa Thiong’o and Ngugi wa Mirii, 1985) know very well that when the white colonialist oppressors were ejected from direct rule over African states in the 1950s and 60s, the white bourgeoisie in some African states such as Kenya was replaced by a black bourgeoisie, acting in concert with transnational capital and/or capital(ists) of the former colonial power. Similarly in India, capitalism is no longer exclusively white. It is Indian, not white British alone. As Bellamy observes, the diminution of class analysis “denies immanent critique of any critical bite,” effectively disarming a meaningful opposition to the capitalist thesis (Bellamy, 1997:25). And as Harvey notes, neoliberal rhetoric, with its foundational emphasis upon individual freedoms, has the power to split off libertarianism, identity politics, multiculturalism, and eventually narcissistic consumerism from the social forces ranged in pursuit of justice through the conquest of state power. (Harvey, 2005:41) To return to the broader relationship between “race,” gender, and social class, and to turn to the USA, are there many who would deny that Condoleeza Rice and Colin Powell have more in common with the Bushes and the rest of the Unites States capitalist class, be it white, black or Latina/o, than they do with the workers whose individual ownership of wealth and power is an infinetismal fraction of those individual members of the ruling and capitalist class? The various oppressions, of caste, gender, “race,” religion, for example, are functional in dividing the working class and securing the reproduction of capital; constructing social conflict between men and women, or black and white, or different castes, or tribes, or religious groups, or skilled and unskilled, thereby tending to dissolve the conflict between capital and labor, thus occluding the class-capital relation, the class struggle, and to obscure the essential and defining nature of capitalism, the labor-capital relation and its attendant class conflict. Footnoting DA ---locating class alongside identity strips class of its concrete, socioeconomic nature McLaren, Distinguished Fellow – Critical Studies @ Chapman U and UCLA urban schooling prof, and Scatamburlo-D’Annibale, associate professor of Communication – U Windsor, ‘4 (Peter and Valerie, “Class Dismissed? Historical materialism and the politics of ‘difference’,” Educational Philosophy and Theory Vol. 36, Issue 2, p. 183-199) In stating this, we need to include an important caveat that differentiates our approach from those invoking the well-worn race/class/gender triplet which can sound, to the uninitiated, both radical and vaguely Marxian. It is not. Race, class and gender, while they invariably intersect and interact, are not co-primary. This ‘triplet’ approximates what the ‘philosophers might call a category mistake.’ On the surface the triplet may be convincing—some people are oppressed because of their race, others as a result of their gender, yet others because of their class—but this ‘is grossly misleading’ for it is not that ‘some individuals manifest certain characteristics known as “class” which then results in their oppression; on the contrary, to be a member of a social class just is to be oppressed’ and in this regard class is ‘a wholly social category’ (Eagleton, 1998, p. 289). Furthermore, even though ‘class’ is usually invoked as part of the aforementioned and much vaunted triptych, it is usually gutted of its practical, social dimension or treated solely as a cultural phenomenon—as just another form of ‘difference.’ In these instances, class is transformed from an economic and, indeed, social category to an exclusively cultural or discursive one or one in which class merely signifies a ‘subject position.’ Class is therefore cut off from the political economy of capitalism and class power severed from exploitation and a power structure ‘in which those who control collectively produced resources only do so because of the value generated by those who do not’ (Hennessy & Ingraham, 1997, p. 2). Such theorizing has had the effect of replacing an historical materialist class analysis with a cultural analysis of class. As a result, many post-Marxists have also stripped the idea of class of precisely that element which, for Marx, made it radical—namely its status as a universal form of exploitation whose abolition required (and was also central to) the abolition of all manifestations of oppression (Marx, 1978, p. 60). With regard to this issue, Kovel (2002) is particularly insightful, for he explicitly addresses an issue which continues to vex the Left—namely the priority given to different categories of what he calls ‘dominative splitting’—those categories of ‘gender, class, race, ethnic and national exclusion,’ etc. Kovel argues that we need to ask the question of priority with respect to what? He notes that if we mean priority with respect to time, then the category of gender would have priority since there are traces of gender oppression in all other forms of oppression. If we were to prioritize in terms of existential significance, Kovel suggests that we would have to depend upon the immediate historical forces that bear down on distinct groups of people—he offers examples of Jews in 1930s Germany who suffered from brutal forms of anti-Semitism and Palestinians today who experience anti-Arab racism under Israeli domination. The question of what has political priority, however, would depend upon which transformation of relations of oppression are practically more urgent and, while this would certainly depend upon the preceding categories, it would also depend upon the fashion in which all the forces acting in a , the priority would have to be given to class since class relations entail the state as an instrument of enforcement and control, and it is the state that shapes and organizes the splits that appear in human ecosystems. Thus class is both logically and historically distinct from other forms of exclusion (hence we should not talk of ‘classism’ to go along with ‘sexism’ and ‘racism,’ and ‘species-ism’). This is, first of all, because class is an essentially man-made category, without root in even a mystified biology. We cannot imagine a human world without gender concrete situation are deployed. As to the question of which split sets into motion all of the others distinctions—although we can imagine a world without domination by gender. But a world without class is eminently imaginable—indeed, such was the human world for the great majority of our species’ time on earth, during all of which considerable fuss was made over gender. Historically, the difference arises because ‘class’ signifies one side of a larger figure that includes a state apparatus whose conquests and regulations create races and shape gender relations. Thus there will be no true resolution of racism so long as class society stands, inasmuch as a racially oppressed society implies the activities of a classdefending state. Nor can gender inequality be enacted away so long as class society, with its state, demands the super-exploitation of women's labor. (Kovel, 2002, pp. 123–124) Contrary to what many have claimed, Marxist theory does not relegate categories of ‘difference’ to the conceptual mausoleum; rather, it has sought to reanimate these categories by interrogating how they are refracted through material relations of power and privilege and linked to relations of production. Moreover, it has emphasized and insisted that the wider political and economic system in which they are embedded needs to be thoroughly understood in all its complexity. Indeed, Marx made clear how constructions of race and ethnicity ‘are implicated in the circulation process of variable capital.’ To the extent that ‘gender, race, and ethnicity are all understood as social constructions rather than as essentialist categories’ the effect of exploring their insertion into the ‘circulation of variable capital (including positioning within the internal heterogeneity of collective labor and hence, within the division of labor and the class system)’ must be interpreted as a ‘powerful force reconstructing them in distinctly capitalist ways’ (Harvey, 2000, p. 106). Unlike contemporary narratives which tend to focus on one or another form of oppression, the irrefragable power of historical materialism resides in its ability to reveal (1) how forms of oppression based on categories of difference do not possess relative autonomy from class relations but rather constitute the ways in which oppression is lived/experienced within a class-based system; and (2) how all forms of social oppression function within an overarching capitalist system. This framework must be further distinguished from those that invoke the terms ‘classism’ and/or ‘class elitism’ to (ostensibly) foreground the idea that ‘class matters’ (cf. hooks, 2000) since we agree with Gimenez (2001, p. 24) that ‘class is not simply another ideology legitimating oppression.’ Rather, class denotes ‘exploitative relations between people mediated by their relations to the means of production.’ To marginalize such a conceptualization of class is to conflate an individual's objective location in the intersection of structures of inequality with people's subjective understandings of who they really are based on their ‘experiences.’ All links are DA’s to the perm H-U-D-S Link Hands-Up-Don’t-Shoot directly trades off with class solidarity- historical analysis proves we control the root cause debate Luciana Bohne 12-3-2014 “Race”: a Political Weapon, Counter Punch, http://www.counterpunch.org/2014/12/03/race-a-political-weapon/ Co-founder of Film Criticism, a journal of cinema studies, and teaches at Edinboro University in Pennsylvania. According to a widely circulated statistic, the police kill a young black man every twenty-eight hours in America. Without doubt, the police have a problem with race. Moreover, the justice system appears to have a problem, too, as proven by the Grand Jury’s failed indictment of Darren Wilson in the killing this summer of young Michael Brown in Ferguson, Missouri. The failed indictment does not mean that Wilson is innocent; only that he will not be brought to trial. This is a terrible perversion of the path to justice. It suggests deliberate prevention of trial on the nearly 100% certainty that Wilson would be found guilty if tried. I am disturbed, however, by the well-intentioned flagellants among the white, nonracist community virtually calling for “America’s” white male blood, metaphorically speaking. I am disturbed because this is the wrong response to the judicial outrage in Ferguson. We should be calling for ruling-class blood, not dividing ourselves into blacks and whites. Isn’t this division a benefit that our divide-and-rule oppressors hardly deserve? Let us not play with the cards in their deck. To begin with, is “America” racist? Real, existing Americans voted for a black candidate for president, one, moreover, who ticked off only the “African American” category on race in the US Census of 2010. In choosing the less privileged racial group than white, Obama adhered to the principle of “hypo descent,” which the US has traditionally used to determine the race of a child born of a mixed-race union. We have a black political class in the Congress; a black Supreme Court justice; two blacks have been secretary of state (one a woman). We have not one institution in which blacks don’t figure more or less prominently. Mixed marriages have been legal since 1967. In 2008, about 14% of all first marriages were mixed race; 9% of whites, 16% of blacks, 26% of Hispanics, and 31% of Asians were interracially married. Nonetheless, racism persists in the black communities, mainly among the poor. We know that black Americans suffer oppression and injustice at a rate far greater than that of any other group. According to the 2010 US Census, 38.2% of black children lived in poverty, the highest rate of any group. According to the Institute of Medicine in 2002, more than 4 million black Americans died prematurely between 1940 and 1999 because of health-care disparity and, at least in part, physicians’ prejudice. 26% of 34 million black Americans live below the poverty line. There seems to be something definitely racist about American institutions. Let us not even mention the appalling incarceration rates of black men. Thus, pointing to the white man in the street or in your bed as the culprit is a little myopic. Does he run the police, the courts, and the Pentagon? Racism is not an individual psychosis, specific to generic “white man.” Racism is the weapon of the powerful. They invented “race.” The psychotic history of that invention is inextricably tied to that of capitalism and imperialism. The age of capital gave us “scientific racism.” This pseudo-science twins American racism to its European original. One of our founding fathers, Thomas Jefferson, a naturalist, proposed, based on “observation,” that blacks slept more because their minds were empty. Indeed, the 18th century into which the US was born developed the discourse of race, mainly as a justification for colonial imperialism. Francois Bernier, French physician to Moghul Emperor Shah Jahan, is considered the first thinker since classical Greece to have classified people by race. Aristotle, of course, classified as “barbarians” those races, which lived outside the polis—the Greek city-state, organized around written laws. In 1684, Bernier published Nouvelle division de la terre par les différentes espèces ou races qui l’habitent (“New Division of the Earth according to Different Species or Races which Inhabit it”). The 18th century continued the discourse of “race,” as a scientific category. Botanist Carl Linnaeus color-coded people by races—red (H. sapiens americanus) , white (H. sapiens Europeans) , yellow (H. sapiens asiaticus), and black (H. Sapiens afer). According to Linnaeus, the European breed was the superior of the four. The science expanded to become the propaganda for European and American imperialism. The alleged superiority of the European and the Euro-American was the result of no neutral science. As European imperialism took off in the 18th century and Euro-Americans “pacified” the native nations, science came up with all sorts of studies to prove that the looters of the world were on a “civilizing mission” to lift up the inferior races of the world from their obscurantist primitivism. Resistance was met with genocide in the Americas. Samuel J. Morton (1799-1851), American and Scottish educated physician and natural scientist, may well be the father of “scientific racism.” He founded the discipline of ethnography and advanced the theory of phrenology. According to Morton, size of brain mattered, whites possessing the largest cranium; blacks the smallest (or vice-versa if evidence contested). The abuses of the pseudo-science of “craniometry” was historically researched by paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould in The Mismeasure of Man, just as the theory resurfaced in The Bell Curve, a racist apology for the Reagan administration’s attacks on the welfare state by blaming black poverty on poverty of black intellect. In keeping with the politicized science of the day, the first American census (1790) categorized people by race, but the categories have changed twenty-four times since then. Today, the US Census defines race as a social construct and provides a dazzling array of choices and permutations, making the category practically null. You can be an African American of European descent with a Hawaian component and a Native American culture. Scientifically, of course race does not exist. Genes cannot identify race. The human Genome Project has proven that biologically we are a single human race (“species” would be more accurate). Go tell it on the mountain because pernicious elements in American society continue to use race as though there is more than one. The truth is that racism is a powerful tool of social control and an arm of US expansionist propaganda. Racism is political. Superficially reforming existing institutions cannot eradicate it. It must be made clear who the promoters of racism are and for what purpose they promote it. Racism is the legacy of colonialism and slavery, but this does not explain why it persists so fundamentally in American institutions today. Unless one is prepared to call the US imperialist. Imperialism impoverishes people abroad by stealing their resources, under developing their industries, destroying their labor unions, their laws for environmental protection, and flooding their markets with goods they once made themselves. It impoverishes people at home. The wars for expansion cost, and the people pay. Look at the US: has it not been third- worldized? Is it not, therefore, likely that at a certain point the people will rise up, go on strike, boycott, sabotage, interfere with profits? Very likely. But not if they are racially divided and racially afraid. Enter racism—the imperialist’s trump card. Let’s have two, three Fergusons. Let white racists hit and run. Let non-racists beat their breasts. Let the police put on a horror show. Let black separatism rise; they can be picked off like the Black Panthers were. Let’s have separatism by all means: white non-racists fighting racism on white turf; blacks on black turf. Separate but equal, ha-ha. Let there be race war so the class war can go on. But we have an alternative: class solidarity in resistance.