Citizens with practical wisdom and citizens following what the wise rulers say (an inquiry on Nichomachean Ethics VI, 12-13)1 I Can citizens be called “virtuous” solely on the grounds of being obedient to the Law and/or of abiding to what sage rulers say? Is φρόνησις a quality that an individual might obtain by its mere acting in a φρόνιμον way, without being –at the same time– φρόνιμος? Is there a distinction between citizens that are φρόνιμοι and citizens that are not but act according to what φρόνησις dictates? Or, to put it otherwise, can one distinguish between the citizen that disposes practical wisdom and the one who does not, albeit it acts according to what practical wisdom dictates? Addressing these questions may utterly come down to addressing the fundamental question of whether an agent that has the quality F can be distinguished from one that has it not but acts as if it had it. It might be argued that the very question is meaningless and that there is no such distinction whatsoever. More precisely, it might be argued that the distinction is meaningless on the basis of there being no empirical grounds upon which the question might be decided – i.e. of there being no testing procedure by which one can discern the citizen who has the quality F and the one who acts as if it had it. Ludwig Wittgenstein’s late philosophy might be called for supporting the answer that the very distinction collapses under this lack of any empirical way to distinguish between the two.2 Karl Popper’s criterion of falsifability might be called for the same reason.3 Suppose there being a person claiming that another person who acts in each and every occasion in a φρόνιμον way is not in itself φρόνιμος but acts as if it were. Is there any empirical way to falsify that statement? Theoretically there is none! For in an action –on the occasion this person’s action– there is no empirical way to decide whether the person acts in that way because it has the property F, or because it just happens –by pure coincidence– to act according to what possessing F would have dictated. The thought experiment is here supposed to assume the presence of a φρόνιμον behavior to everything the subject does. There is nothing contradictory in such an assumption and, therefore, it is logically possible that such a person exists. So, how one is supposed to distinguish this person from the “essentially φρόνιμος”? If this is impossible, the distinction –it might be argued– collapses. 1 A substantial part of this paper was presented at a conference of the European Society for Ancient Philosophy (Athens, 27-29 Mars 2008) on Nicomachean Ethics VI, 13. I am much indebted to all the participants and especially to Michail Peramatzis with whom we worked together for the above mentioned presentation. This paper would not even have being possible, without his co-operation. However we disagree as for the κατά-μετά hierarchy (cf. parts III and IV). As for that matter, I am the sole responsible for the view put forward in the present paper. 2 See L. WITTGENSTEIN, Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, Oxford, 1953 (2nd part), and Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Vols. 1 and 2, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright, Oxford, 1980. 3 See for example K. POPPER, Conjectures and Refutations, London, 1963, pp. 33-39. 1 These kind of problems bare similarities and can in fact be reduced to the general problem of distinguishing between rational creatures and automata. The problem being here the lack of any criterion for distinguishing between a rational animal –say a human being– and an automaton (robot, zombie etc) that acts as if it had rationality. If such a criterion is lacking, the very notion of “having rationality” or indeed “having soul/mind” is put into trial, according to some thinkers among which Wittgenstein, Popper or even Gilbert Ryle.4 Aristotle is not to be counted among these thinkers. Although some passages of De anima suggest that “having soul” is equivalent with being a specific tool and functioning well,5 there is no much doubt that Aristotle’s essentialism commits him to distinguishing between “having the quality F” (“being F”) and “having all the characteristics that the quality F implies”. The former implies the latter, while the latter does not. In other words, there is, for Aristotle, a distinction between being essentially something and the bundle of properties that this “something” implies. The essence of a thing is not (identical to) this bundle of properties.6 Consequently, there has to be a distinction between having the property/quality of being φρόνιμος and the bundle of behavioristic features that being φρόνιμος presupposes. The following conclusion is straightforward: granted that there is a distinction between being essentially F and having the bundle of properties that F implies, there has to be a distinction between being essentially φρόνιμος (counting φρόνησις among one’s essential characteristic) and behaving according to what this essential characteristic dictates. Now, as we have already said, De anima III represents a kind exegetical “minority report” to the, otherwise widely attested, Aristotle’s essentialism. But, even there, the anti-essentialist part of the doctrine is confined to the realm of psyche. This part of the doctrine seems to suggest that there can be no distinction between a human being that possess a mind and the statement that this human being performs the function(s) essential to this possession. (If it doesn’t, it is a human being by homonymia, or “it has no mind”).7 Antiessentialism in Aristotle never leaves the above specific ground of critique for a more general one. It never leaves the specific characteristic of “having a mind” for the more general “having (the property) F” and, consequently, “having φρόνησις”/“being φρόνιμος”. The (essentially) φρόνιμος is to be distinguished from the citizen who acts according to what practical wisdom dictates but does not posses it. On the occasion from the person who abides to the Law and to what the sage rulers propose, but has no practical wisdom of its own. II Granted that Aristotle is expected to distinguish between “having φρóνησις” and “acting according to what φρόνησις dictates”, let us see whether this is confirmed by the corpus. 4 Cf. G. RYLE, The Concept of the Mind, Oxford, 1949. See esp. De Anima, 431b29 – 432a3, 412a19-22, 412b10-22, 408a25-31, 408b13-15. 6 See esp. Metaphysics Ζ. 7 Cf. De Anima, 412b10-22. 5 2 In Nicomachean Ethics VI, 12, we encounter a passage suggesting that it makes no difference for the city, whether the citizen acts in a φρόνιμον way because it is φρόνιμος, or because he does what the φρόνιμοι require him to do. εἰ δὲ μὴ τούτων χάριν φρόνιμον ῥητέον ἀλλὰ τοῦ γίνεσθαι, τοῖς οὖσι σπουδαίοις οὐθὲν ἂν εἴη χρήσιμος· ἔτι δ' οὐδὲ τοῖς μὴ ἔχουσιν· οὐδὲν γὰρ διοίσει αὐτοὺς ἔχειν ἢ ἄλλοις ἔχουσι πείθεσθαι, ἱκανῶς τ' ἔχοι ἂν ἡμῖν ὥσπερ καὶ περὶ τὴν ὑγίειαν· βουλόμενοι γὰρ ὑγιαίνειν ὅμως οὐ μανθάνομεν ἰατρικήν. 8 But in the subsequent final chapter of the Nicomachean Ethics VI this schema will be reversed (refuted) and the citizen will be required not only to act according to a φρόνιμον way, but also to possess φρόνησις. For example in 1144b30-33, we read: δῆλον οὖν ἐκ τῶν εἰρημένων ὅτι οὐχ οἷόν τε ἀγαθὸν εἶναι κυρίως ἄνευ φρονήσεως, οὐδὲ φρόνιμον ἄνευ τῆς ἠθικῆς ἀρετῆς. and some lines bellow (1145a2-5): δῆλον δέ, κἂν εἰ μὴ πρακτικὴ ἦν, ὅτι ἔδει ἂν αὐτῆς διὰ τὸ τοῦ μορίου ἀρετὴν εἶναι, καὶ ὅτι οὐκ ἔσται ἡ προαίρεσις ὀρθὴ ἄνευ φρονήσεως οὐδ' ἄνευ ἀρετῆς· Mere obedience to the Laws and to the sage rulers suffices no more. The citizen, in order to be virtuous κυρίως, has to have φρόνησις. In order to deliberate correctly, he needs to have φρόνησις. However there is an exegetical problem within this same chapter. In lines 1144b26ff Aristotle distinguishes between “being according to φρόνησις” (κατά την φρόνησιν) and “being accompanied by (co-operating with) φρόνησις” (μετά φρονήσεως). Prima facie he seems to suggest that the latter implies the former but not vice versa. Some scholars9 have found problems in this understanding of the text. The problem they think they have found is the following. Acting according to (κατά) φρόνησις does not exclude following what φρόνησις dictates without, at the same time, being φρόνιμος – cf. the case of the ignorant citizen following the sage ruler. Moreover, according to the prima facie interpretation mentioned above being according to (κατά) implies either (i) 8 Nicomachean Ethics VI, 12, 1143b28-33. See esp. J. A. SMITH, “Aristotelica”, Classical Quarterly, 14, 1920, pp. 16-22, and W. F. R. HARDIE, Aristotle’s Ethical Theory, Oxford, 1968. 9 3 following some external rule10 or (ii) following some rule unconsciously.11 On the other hand, Aristotle unambiguously suggests in the same passage that the human being, when virtuous, should be μετά φρονήσεως; this necessitates that its soul disposes φρόνησις. If so κατά should not be implied by μετά, for, if it did it, would have implied exactly the opposite of what is required: i.e. it would imply that it does not dispose φρόνησις but that it follows it either as an external rule, or unconsciously. In order to remedy this contradiction of the prima facie reading, Smith and Hardie put forward some other interpretation. We are not going to present it here. We are, instead, going to argue that the problem these authors find in the prima facie reading emanates from the misleading assumption that κατά means here following some external rule or following some rule unconsciously. In the rest of this article we will argue that the weaker/trivial interpretation of κατά as according to presents no difficulty for the prima facie interpretation and therefore presents no problem for the thesis that μετά is here stronger than κατά. We will proceed as follows. First we will present the crucial passage with a translation together with a central exegetical point about μετά not being synonymous with ουκ ανευ in that passage. Second, we will present a Commentary on that passage, and finally we will draw some conclusions. The paper closes with an Appendix having some illuminating passages. ΙII Nicomachean Ethics VI, 13, 1144b17-30: διόπερ τινές φασι πάσας τὰς ἀρετὰς φρονήσεις εἶναι, καὶ Σωκράτης τῇ μὲν ὀρθῶς ἐζήτει τῇ δ' ἡμάρτανεν· ὅτι μὲν γὰρ φρονήσεις ᾤετο εἶναι πάσας τὰς ἀρετάς, ἡμάρτανεν, ὅτι δ' οὐκ ἄνευ φρονήσεως, καλῶς ἔλεγεν. σημεῖον δέ· καὶ γὰρ νῦν πάντες, ὅταν ὁρίζωνται τὴν ἀρετήν, προστιθέασι, τὴν ἕξιν εἰπόντες καὶ πρὸς ἅ ἐστι, τὴν κατὰ τὸν ὀρθὸν λόγον· ὀρθὸς δ' ὁ κατὰ τὴν φρόνησιν. ἐοίκασι δὴ μαντεύεσθαί πως ἅπαντες ὅτι ἡ τοιαύτη ἕξις ἀρετή ἐστιν, ἡ κατὰ τὴν φρόνησιν. δεῖ δὲ μικρὸν μεταβῆναι. ἔστι γὰρ οὐ μόνον ἡ κατὰ τὸν ὀρθὸν λόγον, ἀλλ' ἡ μετὰ τοῦ ὀρθοῦ λόγου ἕξις ἀρετή ἐστιν· ὀρθὸς δὲ λόγος περὶ τῶν τοιούτων ἡ φρόνησίς ἐστιν. Σωκράτης μὲν οὖν λόγους τὰς ἀρετὰς ᾤετο εἶναι (ἐπιστήμας γὰρ εἶναι πάσας), ἡμεῖς δὲ μετὰ λόγου. “For this reason, precisely, some say that all virtues are types of practical wisdom, and Socrates in one way was in the correct path of inquiry but in another was off the track; for insofar as he thought that all virtues are types of practical wisdom he was mistaken, while insofar as he held that they are not without practical wisdom Cf. J. A. SMITH, “Aristotelica”, op. cit. (The view is reported by Smith; it is not his own. For Smith’s own view see infra.) 11 J. A. STEWART, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, 2 vols., Oxford, 1892. 10 4 he was speaking correctly. And an indication of this is the following: everybody nowadays, when defining virtue, adds, over and above specifying the state and what it is related to, that it [the state] is the one in accordance with the correct reason; and correct [reason] is the one in accordance with practical wisdom. All these theorists, then, look like they somehow divine the claim that virtue is this sort of state, the one in accordance with practical wisdom. We must, however, slightly modify this. For it is not the state only in accordance with correct reason but [also] the one together with correct reason that is virtue; and the correct reason about such things is what practical wisdom is. Socrates, then, thought that virtues are types of reason (for [he thought that] they are all types of knowledge), while we hold that they are together with reason”.12 I will argue here that the κατά thesis in the above passage is weaker than the μετά thesis; that although μετά implies κατά, κατά does not imply μετά. As it will become obvious in part IV, my reconstruction depends upon a central terminological assumption: that ουκ ανευ as it stands in lines b21-22 is not equivalent/synonymous with μετά in lines b28ff. This interpretation depends on the above assumption, and if the assumption is false, my interpretation falls with it. On the other hand, the thesis that κατά is stronger than μετά gets a great amount of help, if ουκ ανευ in lines 21-22 is synonymous with μετά. (Smith for example, who argues for the priority of κατά over μετά, takes ουκ άνευ to mean the same with μετά). For my part, I want to suggest that although the meaning of μετά as it appears after line 27 is the strong/functional “in co-operation with”/“with the help of”, the sense of ουκ ανευ is weaker and perhaps formal/definitional. It just means: in the definition of virtue “φρόνησις” needs to occur, φρόνησις makes essential part of κυρία virtue, as specified in line b17. Let me mention three reasons why one should not take ουκ άνευ φρονήσεως meaning the same as μετά φρονήσεως, and should take μετά as weaker than κατά. The first is form the corpus. In the first passage of the Appendix one can find strong if not irrefutable evidence that Aristotle formally distinguishes between μετά and ουκ άνευ. The passage is about the characteristics one has to look for in happiness. What can be unambiguously deduced from the passage is that these characteristics are either accompanied by (μετά) or not without (ουκ άνευ) pleasure. Ergo there are things that are not without pleasure, but they are not accompanied by pleasure. So, on the basis of (i) having strong evidence that Aristotle does not in general use μετά and ουκ άνευ without discrimination, (ii) the fact that this distinction as it appears in the passage seems to be technical and standardized – I focus your attention on the fact that Aristotle makes no explanatory comment after the passage, as he usually does when he introduces ad hoc non standard terminological distinctions– (iii) the fact that the repeated alternative occurrences of ουκ άνευ and μετά in our passage of Nicomachean Ethics VI are within 10 lines or so and (iv) Aristotle’s characteristic sensitivity and carefulness about the use of terms, I find it most improbable, if not impossible, that Aristotle has here decided to 12 The translation is by Michail Peramatzis. 5 switch from what looks like a self-evident distinction both to himself and to his intended readers in book I to an indiscernible use in book VI. My second point. Let us grand for argument’s sake that ουκ άνευ and μετά are used indiscernibly in Nicomachean Ethics VI, 13. The interpretation identifying these two expressions does not solely rest upon the claim that they have the same meaning. It also specifies the meaning of μετά as the strong/functional “in co-operation with”/“with the help of”. Let us then also agree that μετά is not the plain “with”, but the stronger “in co-operation with”/“by the help of”. These assumptions imply that the part of the Socratic viewpoint that Aristotle approves of (i.e. the ουκ άνευ thesis of b20-21) means also “in co-operation with”. However, this same part of Socrates’ viewpoint needs to be deducible from, or at least needs to be compatible with, the rest of the Socratic thesis (i.e. that all virtues are φρονήσεις). Now, it seems to me that it is neither compatible with it, nor a fortiori deducible from it. If something is identical with something, it doesn’t co-operate with that thing, nor does it get any help from it; it is that thing. The plain “not without” or the technical “it appears within the definition of” are to be preferred. Thirdly (this is in substance the same as the previous point), by imposing a strong sense upon ουκ άνευ in lines 20-21 (i.e. making it synonymous with μετά), I can see no way one can make it deducible from κατά. For the σημείον of lines 21ff seems to be evidence of how correct Socrates was in believing (saying) that no virtue is άνευ φρονήσεως. If the ουκ άνευ φρονήσεως of lines b20-21 means μετά φρονήσεως, how else could the κατά την φρόνησιν of line b24 imply the correctness of Socrates’ thesis that all virtues are ουκ άνευ φρονήσεως=μετά φρονήσεως, unless μετά is stronger than κατά? But being in accordance with something does not necessarily mean co-operating with that same thing, as in fact it doesn’t when the two “things” are one and the same (the Socratic viewpoint). Summing up. Everybody nowadays (b21) claims that all virtues are κατά την φρόνησιν. This can be seen as partly Socratic: some of the thinkers claiming such a thing do so because of the thesis that all virtues are φρονήσεις; the Socratic thesis. If they are φρονήσεις, they can only be in accordance with what they are, i.e. be κατά την φρόνησιν. This is satisfactory in a sense, because indeed it happens to be so: all virtues are κατά την φρόνησιν. However, it is not entirely satisfactory, because they are such not on the basis of their being φρονήσεις, but on the basis of their essentially co-operating with φρόνησις. They are, therefore, κατά την φρόνησιν, without being φρονήσεις. Moreover, being κατά την φρόνησιν, on the basis of being φρονήσεις, does not imply co-operating with φρόνησις, for in such case the virtue is φρόνησις, it does co-operate with it. According to the above understanding, the μετά thesis is stronger than the κατά thesis, since it implies but it is not implied by it, and it is also closer to the Socratic thesis, according to which all virtues are φρονήσεις. It can be seen as compatible with the Socratic thesis that all virtues are φρονήσεις, while the μετά thesis cannot. In the following part, I will present this exegetical schema in more detail. 6 IV Commentary – Paraphrasis Nicomachean Ethics VI, 13, 1144b16-30 [b16-21] Among the two kinds of virtue, the natural and the κύρια, the latter does not occur without φρόνησις. And it is for exactly that reason that some –among which Socrates himself– were saying that all virtues are φρονήσεις. Aristotle says this, because if a virtue is φρόνησις, then it cannot be without φρόνησις, meaning here that “virtue” makes part of its essence. This is correct, for if something is identical to something, then it cannot be without the thing it is identical with. But it so happens that on the one hand Socrates was right, while on the other mislead. He was right in believing that no virtue occurs without φρόνησις. He was wrong as for the reason he thought that this is so, or (which is the same) as for the principle upon which he based the fact that no virtue occurs without φρόνησις. For he thought that this is so because virtues are (identical to) φρονήσεις. [b21-25] Further support to the claim that no virtue occurs without φρόνησις is that even nowadays all, when defining virtue, and after having introduced the εξις and the things it refers to (πρός α), they add <the one –i.e. έξις+the thing it refers to> “in accordance with ορθός λόγος”. Now, in accordance with ορθός λόγος is in accordance with φρόνησις. All seem to conjecture that this particular kind of εξις which is virtue is the one in accordance with φρόνησις. That this is evidence of the correctness of the claim that no virtue occurs without φρόνησις comes as follows. There is universal consensus upon all virtues being essentially in accordance with φρόνησις. And if something is essentially in accordance with something, then it cannot occur without the thing it is in accordance with. [b25-28] This again is exact, but, again, the correct conclusion is (correctly) drawn from the wrong premise. For although (i) all virtues are in accordance with φρόνησις and (ii) no virtue occurs without φρόνησις, that (iii) they are (identical to) φρονήσεις is not the correct explanation of the phenomenon. Yes, the latter claim implies the former two, which are both exact. But they are not so on that basis. This is why Aristotle has said that these people (b24) “are guessing” (μαντεύεσθαι) as for that matter. They arrive at a true conclusion, but since their argument is not sound, it is rather a happy coincidence (a lucky guess) that leads them to it.13 Therefore, we need for our part to ameliorate a little bit the whole argument/thesis, and supply the correct explanation of why all virtues are in accordance with φρόνησις and do not occur without it. They are not only in accordance with ορθός λόγος, they are also co-operating with (together with)14 ορθός λόγος, and ορθός λόγος on these matters –i.e. on each and every among the προς α– is φρόνησις. Aristotle says this, because he apparently believes that if something essentially cooperates with something else, then it can never operate without the thing it essentially cooperates with, and he also believes that it will always need to operate in accordance with that same thing; that it has been tuned (as for some parameters at least), in accordance with that thing, and that it cannot operate (as for the same parameters), in discord with it. The fact that it co-operates with it provides one with the correct reason why it cannot occur without it and why it operates in accordance with it. So, both the thesis that all 13 14 I owe this point to Miira Tuominen. Cf. passage no 2 of the Appendix. 7 virtues are φρονήσεις and the thesis that all virtues co-operate with φρόνησις imply the required facts, but only the latter is true. [b28-30] Socrates held the former for he held that virtues are λόγοι; he took virtues to be επιστήμαι, and λόγοι are the intentional objects of επιστήμαι; an επιστήμη is an επιστήμη of some λόγος. (“Επιστήμη” is systematically ambiguous: it can either mean the knowledge of a certain thing, or the thing known in itself –here the λόγος– qua known.)15 Aristotle, however, holds that virtues essentially co-operate with λογοι, not that they are λόγοι. Here Aristotle says λόγοι instead the ορθός λόγος, because by referring to επιστήμη he narrows the domain of λόγοι down to the domain of ορθοί λόγοι. No one can know a λόγος that is not ορθός. *** Some further comments on the terms and the implications κατά: in accordance with.16 …ουκ άνευ---: not without, essentially bound to; as for definitions: the term on the right (…) has to appear in the definition of the item denoted by the term on the left (---). μετά: in co-operation with.17 ουκ άνευ and κατά weaker than μετά. being φρόνησις (Socrates’ view) being μετά φρονήσεως (Aristotle’s view) being κατά την φρόνησιν (universal consensus) being ουκ άνευ φρονήσεως (Implications are from top down. Side by side items are mutually exclusive) A being (identical to) B implies: (i) A being κατά B, (ii) A being ουκ άνευ B, but not (iii) A being μετά B. A in this last case in not co-operating with B it is B. A being μετά B implies (i) A being κατά B and (ii) A being ουκ άνευ B, but not (iii) A being (identical to) B. Summing up: “virtue is φρόνησις” (i.e. the Socratic view), implies being in accordance with φρόνησις (being κατά την φρόνησιν), for nothing can be in discord with what it is identical to. Therefore, “being κατά την φρόνησιν” allows “being φρόνησις”. On the other hand, “co-operating with φρόνησις” (Aristotle’s view) also implies being in accordance with φρόνησις, for nothing can be in discord with what it is essentially cooperating with. Finally, they both imply being ουκ άνευ φρονήσεως, since being κατά την φρόνησιν implies being ουκ άνευ φρονήσεως, and being κατά την φρόνησιν is implied by them both. So, and as for our general question about κατά/μετά: μετά is, in this context, stronger than κατά. A virtue μετά φρονήσεως has to be κατά την φρόνησιν. However, a 15 Cf. passage no 3 of the Appendix. Cf. LSJ, sense B.IV. 17 Cf. LSJ, sense A.II. 16 8 virtue κατά την φρόνησιν need not being μετά φρονήσεως, for if the virtue is φρόνησις, φρόνησις is not co-operating with it, it literally is that virtue. Nota Bene: By this interpretation μετά becomes stronger than κατά, but it is not necessary to assume that, when Aristotle attacks the Socratic viewpoint, he attacks a thesis that makes φρόνησις external to the individual, or that he attacks a thesis according to which the individual is not fully conscious of the φρόνησις it has. If the individual is virtuous, and virtue is φρόνησις, then the individual does have the ορθός λογος/φρόνησις. It is internal to the individual and the individual is conscious of it too (cf. επιστήμη in context). All this is trivially compatible with the κατά thesis: the virtue is in accordance with itself. On the other hand, the μετά thesis is also compatible with φρόνησις being internal to the individual and so with the κατά thesis; the stake is not on the external/internal or conscious/unconscious distinction. More precisely, my argument is that since taking κατά to be weaker than μετά does not necessarily imply the previous two conclusions the grounds upon which κατά has to be taken as stronger than μετά are considerably weakened. So, although this interpretation of κατά/μετά makes μετά stronger than κατά, one needs not conclude that Aristotle –in so far as he attacks the Socratic viewpoint and endorses the μετά thesis– attacks what he is supposed to adopt and praises what he is supposed to criticize. Doukas KAPANTAÏS (Athens) APPENDIX 1) Nicomachean Ethics I, 8, 1098b22-25 Φαίνεται δὲ καὶ τὰ ἐπιζητούμενα τὰ περὶ τὴν εὐδαιμονίαν ἅπανθ' ὑπάρχειν τῷ λεχθέντι. τοῖς μὲν γὰρ ἀρετὴ τοῖς δὲ φρόνησις ἄλλοις δὲ σοφία τις εἶναι δοκεῖ, τοῖς δὲ ταῦτα ἢ τούτων τι μεθ' ἡδονῆς ἢ οὐκ ἄνευ ἡδονῆς· ἕτεροι δὲ καὶ τὴν ἐκτὸς εὐετηρίαν συμπαραλαμβάνουσιν. 2) Aspasii in Eth. Nicom. (22, 17-22) τοῖς δὲ ταῦτα, τουτέστι πάσας τὰς ἀρετὰς ἢ τούτων τινά, φiλoσοφίαν ἢ φρόνησιν, εἶναι τὴν εὐδαιμονίαν μεθ' ἡδονῆς ἢ οὐκ ἄνευ ἡδονῆς συναρμόζει τὴν ἑαυτοῦ δόξαν διὰ τῶν ἑξῆς. τὸ δὲ μεθ' ἡδονῆς ἢ οὐκ ἄνευ ἡδονῆς διαφέρει τι. μεθ' ἡδονῆς μὲν οἱ λέγοντες μέρος τῆς εὐδαιμονίας ποιοῦσι τὴν ἡδονήν, οἱ δὲ οὐκ ἄνευ ἡδονῆς, οὐ μέρος ἀλλ' ὧν οὐκ ἄνευ ἡ εὐδαιμονία λέγουσι τὴν ἡδονήν. 3) Eustratii in Eth. Nicom. (402, 36 – 403, 7) 9 Τὴν διαφορὰν τίθησιν ἣν ἔχουσί πως αὐτὸς καὶ Σωκράτης περὶ ἀρετῆς λέγοντες, ἵνα μή τις φαίη περιττὸν εἶναι αὐτόν, ἐπεὶ τοῦ Σωκράτους καθάπτεται ὥς τι παρ' αὐτὸν ἄλλο λέγοντος, ἐπεὶ κἀκεῖνος καὶ οὗτος λόγον παραλαμβάνουσιν ἐν τῷ λέγειν περὶ ἀρετῆς, καί φησιν ἐκεῖνον μὲν αὐτὸ τοῦτο λόγους λέγειν τὰς ἀρετάς, ἐπεὶ ἐπιστήμας αὐτὰς ὑπελάμβανεν (αἱ γὰρ ἐπιστῆμαι λόγοι γνωστικοὶ τῶν ἐπιστητῶν), οὗτος δ' οὐ λόγους ἀλλὰ μετὰ λόγου ταύτας εἶναι ἡμῖν παραδέδωκεν. ἕτερον δέ ἐστι τὸ εἶναί τι τόδε τι καὶ μετὰ τοῦδέ τινος εἶναι. 10