Persons and Psychological Frameworks: A Critique of Tye “As one [split-brain] patient remarked immediately after seeing herself make a left-hand response of this kind, ‘Now I know it wasn’t me did that!’” (Sperry, 1968: 733) 1. Introduction This paper concerns the relationships between persons, brains, behavior, and psychological explanation. Tye defines a “psychological framework” (PF) as a set of token beliefs, desires, intentions, memories, streams of consciousness, higher-order mental states, etc., that “form a coherent whole” and against which a creature’s “behavior can be explained” (141).1 A person is the subject of such a psychological framework. Each person has one PF, and with each new PF there is a new person. Meanwhile materialism tells us, according to Tye, that brains are the bearers of mental states. In other words, “each person is a brain” (142)—or rather a “global physical state of the brain,” since Tye believes that a single brain might realize multiple PFs and thus constitute multiple persons. Tye draws a very strong evidential link between being a single person and acting in an integrated fashion. He therefore tries to show that split-brain subjects2, whose day-to-day behavior is integrated, are single persons. I argue that although split-brain subjects do behave in what Tye calls a “unified” fashion, they do so despite lacking the minimal kind of psychological coherence that Tye makes necessary to being a single person. But it is on independent grounds concerning the causal structure of psychological frameworks that I then argue that split-brain subjects have two such frameworks. Tye must therefore decide between identifying split-brain 1 All references to Tye, 2003. 2 I use the term split-brain subjects to refer to humans who have undergone callosotomy. The term “subjects” is meant to be neutral with respect to any claims about personal identity; it is not to be taken as synonymous with “subjects of experience,” for example. (I use this term instead of “patients” because many split-brain subjects are not patients; they are simply voluntary participants in split-brain experiments.) 1 subjects with multiple persons—thereby losing the connection between acting in a unified fashion and being a single person—or dropping the connection between being a single person and having a single PF. Either way, the psychological frameworks that Tye makes the backbone of psychological explanation must be individuated partly architecturally, and not just on the basis of superficial behavioral properties. Most of this paper simply assumes Tye’s account of personal identity, in order to expose certain contradictions within what Tye says about personhood in split-brain subjects. Towards the end of the paper, however, I turn to alternative accounts of persons. While a method of individuating persons grounded in scientific psychology would identify persons with psychological frameworks, as Tye does, perhaps an account of personhood grounded either in a non-psychological science, or in non-scientific psychology, would better fit the interests we have in personal identity. 2. “Split” brains and streams of consciousness “Split-brain” subjects are humans who have had their corpora callosa partially or wholly severed, and whose cerebral hemispheres therefore function, to a significant degree, independently of each other. They are famous for the unusual behavioral dissociations they exhibit under carefully controlled experimental situations. A blindfolded split-brain subject, S, holding a pipe in his left hand, can’t tell you what he’s holding. When you take the pipe from him and ask him what he was holding a moment ago, he says he doesn’t know. Yet when you instruct him to reach, with that same left hand, into a box of objects and to select the object he was holding a minute ago, he easily does so (under control of his right hemisphere), all the while complaining (via his left hemisphere) that the task is unfair, since as he has already told you he doesn’t know what he was holding. Many philosophers and psychologists have concluded from experiments like these that a split-brain subject’s two hemispheres are associated with distinct experiences, beliefs, memories, and so forth. Split-brain subjects are also famous, however, for not obviously evidencing any cognitive dissociation in their daily behavior (at least not frequently). Once the blindfold is removed, S tells you he is holding a pipe, and laughs, “I guess it was a pipe I was holding when 2 you asked before. Why didn’t I get that?” You cannot (reliably) obtain any very clear evidence of dissociation in split-brain subjects unless you go to some lengths to do so, lateralizing perceptual information to one hemisphere or the other while scrupulously preventing the subject from engaging in any cross-cuing behaviors. In daily life, that is, split-brain subjects give little evidence of having two streams of consciousness, though in fact many who have studied the split-brain phenomena have insisted that the two streams are nonetheless always there. Tye’s own position on the question of how many streams of consciousness split-brain subjects have is that for some moments during split-brain experiments, a subject like S has two such streams, one associated with each hemisphere.3 Tye maintains, however, that a split-brain subject has one PF and is therefore one person. In this paper I merely assume that Tye is correct in claiming that the disconnected right hemisphere sustains conscious phenomena and that splitbrain subjects have two streams of consciousness for at least some moments during split-brain experiments. Both these claims are in fact controversial, but I set them to one side here in order to focus on Tye’s account of persons and PFs in particular. 3. Psychological coherence and unified behavior Tye’s account of personhood, according to which a person is a subject of a PF, relies on the assumption that a single person has “a set of propositional attitudes with an internal coherence” (114), though it should be stressed at the outset that he does not require perfect coherence of a single PF, as we shall see. Tye also relies heavily on unified behavior as evidence of a single PF; the fact that split-brain subjects generally behave in a unified or integrated fashion becomes, in Tye’s hands, the major positive argument in favor of their being single persons. But in what sense is their behavior unified? In the sense, Tye says, that the subjects: walk, run, swim, play the piano, and engage in any number of everyday activities in the normal way. Moreover, they do not report any breakdown or division in 3 Elsewhere in Consciousness and Persons Tye argues that outside of experimental situations split-brain subjects will enjoy a unified consciousness. This unified consciousness is admittedly generated by two functionally independent patterns of neural activity, but these patterns are redundant in terms of their phenomenal properties, and 3 the visual field. How could this be, if split-brains are really two different persons? Split-brain patients typically act as if they are single persons with a unified conception of the world and what is going on around them. Those who know split-brain patients cannot help but think of them and relate to them as single subjects. (115, emphasis in the original) This is not much in the way of a definition, however, so I propose that we say that behavior that isn’t unified is of the type that two or more people might engage in when they are in some degree of conflict with each other, and that behavior which isn’t like this is unified.4 Thus split-brain subjects normally exhibit unified behavior insofar as they do not usually slap one hand with the other, or slap their own faces to force themselves to get up after over-sleeping, or violently shake and come to the aid of a loved one simultaneously, or button their shirt with one hand while unbuttoning with the other, or struggle to pull their pants up and down at the same time. Note that I said “usually”: these are in fact all things that split-brain subjects have been observed to do outside of experimental situations.5 As fascinating as these behaviors are (partly because they are presumably entirely absent in “normals” i.e. non-split-brain subjects), they are admittedly rare even in the split-brain population. I will therefore accept that split-brain subjects therefore are associated with one and the same stream of consciousness. I reject this claim elsewhere (Schechter, forthcoming), but do not treat this issue here, choosing to focus on Tye’s account of personal identity instead. 4 The account of “unified behavior” I offer here still doesn’t allow us to uncontroversially identify unified or disunified behavior independent of any beliefs about the behavior’s mental causes, of course. For note that we won’t even identify two people as being in conflict with each other in the relevant sense unless we perceive their intentions to be in conflict with each other. (If we see two people who are slammed into each other by a third party or a strong wind, we won’t see these people as “in conflict with each other” in the relevant, i.e. psychological, sense.) Thus even on this definition, we won’t perceive a single person as behaving in a disunified fashion unless that person is behaving in a way we think two people would behave if they were in some kind of psychological conflict with each other. There is, in general, a bi-directional relationship between individuating behaviors and locating their psychological causes, which makes it impossible to identify “unified behavior” or “disunified behavior” in an entirely non-(psychological)-theory-laden way. I don’t pretend then to have offered a definition of “disunified behavior” that can be used in an entirely uncontroversial way; at this point I am just trying to describe the type of behavior Tye seems to have in mind when he calls behavior unified or disunified. 5 Bogen, 1987; Dimond, 1980; Gazzaniga, 1970; Bogen, 1987; LeDoux 2002. 4 behave in a unified fashion in their daily lives. Ultimately, what Tye means when he uses split-brains subjects’ unified behavior as evidence for their being single persons, is that their daily behavior seems no less the behavior of a single person than does the behavior of a non-split-brain subject, and that their daily behavior gives us no reason to think that they have more PFs than do “normals.” Let us grant that this is the case, and even accept that the unified behavior of split-brain subjects outside of experimental situations provides powerful evidence that they have single PFs. Is there any other evidence to the contrary which might outweigh this conclusion? There is such evidence: evidence showing that, underlying her or his behavior, a splitbrain subject’s cognitive architecture is fundamentally divided. Why, then, is Tye led to the contrary conclusion? For he does allow that PFs are composed of mental tokens, and acknowledges at one point that he and his duplicate on twin earth, to whom he is “causally unconnected”, have different PFs and are therefore different persons, even though both are subject to all the same types of mental states. Since both sets of tokens are type-identical (and since Tye allows that a single human being can be associated with multiple persons), these frameworks are plausibly individuated by reference to the different cognitive or perhaps neural architectures in which they are located. Here Tye acknowledges a connection between the psychological frameworks used to explain human behavior, and the causal structure of those frameworks; he also implicitly accepts a connection between who you are and the causal forces responsible for your mental life. Throughout most of his discussion, however, these insights are neglected, and Tye chooses instead to focus only on superficial properties of persons and of psychological frameworks. It is because of this shallow focus that he misses (or misinterprets) very compelling evidence that split-brain subjects have multiple PFs. He is therefore led to offer an unconvincing account of split-brain subjects’ cognition and behavior during experimental situations, one that misses the important causal differences between the cognition of split-brain and non-split-brain subjects. 4. Persons and subjects of belief 5 The two most obvious positions to take on personal identity in split-brain subjects are that each such subject is associated with one person, or that each such subject is associated with two persons. Before I discuss these positions, we should note that there is a third possibility, which is that split-brain subjects are normally associated with single persons, but are associated with two persons for at least some moments during split-brain experiments. This third option is regarded by most philosophers as something of a last choice, however, since it is unclear how sealing a subject’s nostril or removing her blindfold could call a second person into existence or destroy her, respectively. There is, furthermore, a fourth possible position on personhood in the splitbrain subject, which is that a split-brain subject is associated with an indeterminate number of persons (Nagel, 1971). (See also Parfit (1984, 1995), who argues that in any reductionist account of personal identity, cases of indeterminate identity will be possible.) This paper focuses on the two main options: that a split-brain subject is associated with one person, and that she is associated with two persons. I am still at this point assuming Tye’s account of persons, according to which a person is the subject of single, coherent PF. (Alternative accounts of persons will be considered in Section 8.) The split-brain experiments seem to provide good evidence that each split-brain subject is associated with two persons. When S correctly selects the pipe he was just holding (under the control of his right hemisphere), while protesting (via his left hemisphere) that he doesn’t know what he was holding, he appears simultaneously to (consciously) believe that he was just holding a pipe and to not (consciously) believe that he was just holding a pipe. If Tye is correct that persons are the proper subjects of belief, and that S is (associated with) only a single person, however, then S cannot both believe and not believe that he was just holding a pipe. For this is a logical contradiction. In the following sections I shall examine Tye’s attempts to avoid this contradiction while maintaining his commitments on persons and PFs. I shall argue that these attempts fail. 5. Not believing versus believing not Tye offers two alternative explanations of S’s behavior during the split-brain experiment, neither of which involves logical contradiction. I reject the first alternative in this section and turn to the 6 second alternative in the next. The first alternative explanation of S’s behavior is that S doesn’t both believe and not believe that he just felt a pipe; rather, S believes both that he did and that he did not feel a pipe. And this, Tye says, is normal; “There are many such examples in everyday life”: Consider. . . . Samantha’s saying sincerely that people, whatever their skin color, should be treated alike, while always choosing to sit next to white people on the bus she takes to work. Or take my believing that sunny weather is wonderful, as I sit relaxing by the pool, and my also believing at that time that sunny weather is not so terrific (given its effects on the skin, etc.). (116) When faced with what might appear to be a case of S both believing and not believing that P, Tye says that it is really just a case of S simultaneously believing P and believing not-P. To do this, he relies on an analogy to normal cases of “contradictory” beliefs, as when I believe that ice cream is both good (tastes yummy!) and bad (too fattening!). It is plain that this move cannot work. To start with, every example of holding contradictory beliefs that Tye offers involves ambivalence. And ambivalence (certainly in these examples) seems to arise only with respect to an object as a whole (or at least to a plurality of its features), and not with respect to any individual feature. I am not ambivalent about how ice cream tastes, nor am I ambivalent about weight gain. Samantha is not ambivalent about how other white people ought to treat black people. But ice cream and race relations have several elements, and several effects, and we might feel differently about each of these elements and effects. I love the taste but not the caloric content of ice cream; I want to eat it but I don’t want to store it as fat cells. . . . My ambivalence about ice cream may indeed sometimes lead me to engage in “disunified” or “contradictory” behavior with regard to it, firmly stating my intention not to eat any and then eating quite a lot. (Note that this sort of weak-willed behavior arguably does meet the operational definition of “disunified behavior” I offered earlier: you might yell, “No no, I don’t want any ice cream!” while I forced it upon you. It is, of course, also depressingly 7 common.) But this is still not like the split-brain subject who was spied trying to pull his pants up with one hand and down with another simultaneously. When S selects the correct object, while incorrectly insisting that he can’t, this is not due to ambivalence: it isn’t because he has mixed feelings about pipes, or likes demonstrating his good cognitive-neurological functioning but dislikes any compliance with authority. Second of all—and here the causal difference between S and myself comes into sharp relief—the term “mixed feelings” makes sense when applied to me, and not when applied to S. My belief that ice cream is good-because-it’s-yummy and my belief that it’s bad-because-it’sfattening can interact, resulting in my never eating as much ice cream as I say I want and always eating more than I say I will. When interaction between conflicting mental states is possible, ambivalence frequently manifests itself behaviorally partly in the form of hesitancy or reluctance. Contrast this again with S’s behavior when he is blindfolded and asked what he was just holding in his left hand. He doesn’t say, “Well, I guess it might’ve been a pipe, but I’m really not sure.” He says, “I don’t know.” If he reaches into the box of objects using his right hand (directed by his left hemisphere), he doesn’t linger over the pipe (see Sperry, 1968): he rejects it.6 If he reaches into the box of objects using his left hand (controlled by his right hemisphere), he similarly displays no hesitancy or reluctance: he selects the pipe. Most importantly, when S is asked at t1 what he was holding at t0 and says he does not know, surely we don’t want to say that S, or his left hemisphere, believes that he did not feel a pipe, as opposed to saying that S, or his left hemisphere, does not believe that he felt one. In the former case we posit possession of an occurrent mental state to explain S’s verbal behavior: the belief that he absolutely did not feel a pipe. In the latter case we explain S’s behavior by talking about an occurrent mental state that S lacks: the belief that he felt a pipe. These two ways of explaining S’s behavior are not explanatorily equivalent, and the second explanation is more accurate. Granted, Tye may be right—see page 116—that once you ask S, at t2, “Were you holding 6 It may be that once he feels the pipe with his right hand (using his left hemisphere), S, in rejecting it, has formed the left hemisphere belief, “I wasn’t holding a pipe.” But even if he forms this belief that not-P at that moment, this does not show that he had this belief prior to feeling the pipe. I return to this point in a moment. 8 a pipe?”, he will acquire an occurrent left hemisphere belief that he was not holding a pipe at t0.7 But this still would not show that S had this belief prior to being asked. At t1, prior to being asked about a pipe, specifically, how would S (or S’s left hemisphere) have formed the occurrent belief that S wasn’t holding a pipe, specifically? The only possibility I can see isn’t a serious one: S (or S’s left hemisphere) performed some sort of inference from a belief with the content, “I don’t know what I was holding” to a belief with the content, “I wasn’t holding a pipe.” But unless an inference to a belief with this particular content happens through sheer magic, S (or S’s left hemisphere) must have made a similar inference to a seemingly endless number of other beliefs about what S wasn’t holding: “I wasn’t holding a donut,” “I wasn’t holding a wide-tooth comb,” etc. An inference (or a series of inferences) of this magnitude will of course not be computationally tractable. Prior to being asked about a pipe, specifically, S or S’s left hemisphere may of course have the dispositional belief that he wasn’t holding a pipe, as well as the dispositional belief that he wasn’t holding a donut, or a wide-tooth comb, etc. But this dispositional belief is not one to which we can refer in order to realistically explain S’s verbal denial at t1 that he knows what he was holding. If our mind/brain sciences ever get to a point where we can actually locate beliefs or belief-instantiating entities in the brain, and you start looking for the realizers of these two beliefs in a split-brain subject like S—the belief that he felt a pipe and the belief that he didn’t—you wouldn’t find either in his left hemisphere at t1.8 7 This is not necessarily the case, however: it is possible that once you ask S whether he was holding a pipe, specifically, he will say yes, using his left hemisphere, even though, prior to being asked, his left hemisphere did not know that it was a pipe he’d been holding. It is hypothesized that “binary” information can be transferred between the hemispheres in some instances, and certainly affective states seem to carry over. Thus, when S is asked, “What were you holding?”, his right hemisphere knows the answer but cannot communicate to his left hemisphere the correct object, among all the objects in the world; but when S is asked, “Could it have been a pipe?”, his right hemisphere may be capable of transferring to the left an affirmative answer—either directly or in effect (e.g. by generating a positive affective state which the left hemisphere then feels and interprets as signifying an affirmative response). See for example Sperry, Zaidel, and Zaidel, 1979, for examples of the use of affective information to answer yes/no questions; see Corballis 1995 generally for a review of some of the relevant literature on interhemispheric interaction in split-brain patients. 8 It might be argued that at the very moment when his behavior is disunified, S does not both believe and not believe that he was holding a pipe just earlier. At t0, S palpates a pipe in his left hand. At t1, when asked what he was holding a moment ago, S says he does not know. At t2, when asked whether he was holding a pipe, S says “No.” At t3, when asked to use his left hand to select from a box of objects the object he was holding a moment ago, S selects the pipe. 9 Though Samantha’s behavior towards black people and S’s behavior during the splitbrain experiment may both be “disunified” in some sense, the causal stories explaining those behaviors are without question very different, and Tye is wrong to conflate them. We explain Samantha’s behavior by referring to the types of mental states she possesses and to the contents of those states. Why does Samantha extol equal treatment yet treat the races unequally? Because of her unconscious negative attitudes towards black people, her conscious belief that discriminatory behavior towards black people is bad, and her powerful desire to believe that she is a good person. But to explain S’s behavior, we need to refer to something more: we still need to refer to the types of token mental states S has, and to the contents of those states, but we also need to refer to the different hemispheres or to the different psychological frameworks in which those mental tokens are located. Insofar as S can be characterized as holding “contradictory beliefs” about whether he just felt a pipe, this is best explained by the fact that S has two computationally isolated belief-generating systems in which these “contradictory beliefs” are located. Why does S select the pipe but say he wasn’t holding anything? Because his mental architecture is fundamentally different from Samantha’s: his beliefs and experiences just can’t interact in the way hers can. S selects the correct object while saying he can’t because the largest fiber tract in his brain was surgically severed, resulting in his left and right hemisphere mental states being unable to interact with each other in the way that they once could, and meanwhile his right hemisphere has a kind of felt access to his left hand that his left hemisphere lacks. 6. Psychological vs. Neural Explanation Perhaps S’s behavior is only disunified between t2 and t3. (Indeed, the experiment could potentially be set up such that S was both verbally denying having felt a pipe, specifically, and manually selecting the pipe at the very same moment: t2 = t3, in other words.) Now, the best explanation for S’s selecting the pipe at t 3 is that S believes he was holding a pipe at t0, a belief he has held continuously since that time; the best explanation for S’s behavior at t 2 is (I will assume here) that he believes he was not holding a pipe. At t2, therefore, S both believes he was holding a pipe and believes that he wasn’t—but this involves no logical contradiction, Tye notes. My argument, though, is that an essential part of the explanation for why S comes to believe at t2 that he was not holding a pipe at t0 is that at t1, S did not believe that he was holding a pipe. At t1, in other words, S both believed and did not believe he’d held a pipe—which of course is a logical contradiction. And to deny the need to acknowledge this, on the grounds that there is not yet any disunified behavior at t1 and no longer any logical contradiction at t3, is blatant behaviorism. 10 A natural objection at this point would be that the preceding line of argument is premised upon an uncharitable interpretation of Tye’s proposed explanation for S’s behavior during the splitbrain experiment. It might be said, and Tye may simply mean, that in order to explain why S says he doesn’t know what he was holding even while correctly selecting the pipe, we need only refer to S’s neural architecture, and that doing so obviates the need to refer to multiple persons or psychological frameworks. It might be said, that is, that we need not say either that S believes he was not holding a pipe, or that S does not believe he was holding a pipe. There is a third possibility: we say that S does believe he was holding a pipe, but that, due to his commissurotomy, S is incapable either of accessing this belief or of verbally expressing it. This provides a coherent way of explaining the degree of behavioral disunity S exhibits under experimental conditions, one that avoids the mistake of analogizing S’s disunified behavior to straightforward cases of ambivalence, while also avoiding the prima facie extravagance of identifying S with multiple persons or PFs (an identification made to look especially extravagant in light of S’s normally unified behavior). It is of course true as a general rule that apparently inconsistent attributions of mental properties may be easily reconciled when we learn more about the neural architecture underlying them. For example, we can say that a stroke victim with visual agnosia consciously sees a fork, knows what a fork is, and yet cannot verbally identify it as a fork. We can say all this about the stroke victim knowing that the stroke has compromised some high-level visual areas of her brain, depriving her, perhaps, of the visual template for “fork,” and therefore making her incapable of seeing a fork as a fork, though she can verbally identify a fork by touch. Note, however, that we can say all this about the stroke victim not just because she has an “unusual” neural architecture, but because of what we know about that architecture. Thus in the case of a stroke victim who can verbally identify a fork as a fork after touching it, but not after looking at it, there is of course no need to postulate multiple subjects of experience, a feeling subject who knows what a fork is and a seeing one who doesn’t. Tye sees the split-brain case analogously. Of a case in which the word “pen” has been projected to only the left visual field/right hemisphere of a split-brain subject, he writes: “The fact that the split-brain patient doesn’t say ‘pen’, when asked what he saw, doesn’t show that he 11 doesn’t believe that he saw ‘pen’. He does believe that. It’s just [that], given the commissurotomy, he can’t verbally express that belief” (116). Tye is of course correct that in general, considerations of neural architecture may obviate any need to postulate multiple subjects of belief, and other prima facie mental extravagances. But commissurotomy is a particular, not a general, case, with at least one strikingly different feature from (most) other unusual neural architectures. While many cases of unusual neural architecture may involve some compromised access between mental systems, and while the split-brain case does of course involve this, in the split-brain case each of the mental systems in question—that associated with the left hemisphere and that associated with the right—is capable of supporting a mind “comfortably characterizable as human” (Marks 1981: 47, fn. 18). Both hemispheres can sustain (I am assuming along with Tye) conscious experiences—experiences to which the other hemisphere is not subject. Either hemisphere can guide intelligent behavior, apparently without the help (indeed, sometimes despite the hindrance) of the other. There is even evidence that, in split-brain subjects, the hemispheres separately sustain autobiographical memories and different emotional responses to these memories (Schiffer et al., 1998). Evidence not only from split-brain studies but from those rare cases of left or right hemispherectomy following (basically) normal development lends further support to the conclusion that each hemisphere is at least a candidate for being the subject of a unique PF (as Tye himself acknowledges in a slightly different context; see p. 150).9 In the split-brain case, in other words, the very neural architecture, reference to which might be claimed to make unnecessary the positing of multiple persons or PFs, is in fact one of the strongest pieces of evidence in favor of there being multiple persons or PFs to begin with. The fact that there are two potential persons in the split-brain case gives the claim that S believes he was holding a pipe, but can’t access this belief, two different interpretations, while the claim that the stroke patient sees a fork and knows what a fork is, but can’t verbally identify it as such, only has one. In the latter case we readily interpret the claim as stating that the stroke patient is one and only one person, who sees a fork but does not recognize it as a fork, even though she knows what forks are. In the former case, however, we are faced with two competing interpretations of the claim. On the one hand Tye might mean that the whole split-brain subject 9 See Boatman et al., 1999; Burklund and Smith, 1977; Gott, 1973; Smith, 1966, 1969. 12 (the organism) has the belief that he was just holding a pipe, but that this belief can’t be accessed in all the same ways that, say, my belief that I just saw a bird can be accessed. This is clearly correct, but not relevant given Tye’s account of personal identity, which is couched in psychological, not in organismic, terms. (Recall that in Tye’s account it is a global physical state of the brain, rather than a whole organism, that is the bearer of beliefs and so forth.) The claim might alternatively be interpreted as saying that there is a single person associated with the splitbrain subject S, and that this person believes he felt a pipe but just can’t access this belief. This claim is clearly relevant but not clearly correct, since, again, what makes the split-brain case so different from the stroke case is that in S’s case there are two neural architectures we could identify with persons. The question is whether we should do so. Before I return, in the last section of this paper, to that question in particular, I will briefly explain why, contra Tye, and regardless of which account of personal identity we adopt, we must at least attribute to each of S’s hemispheres a unique psychological framework. 7. Individuating psychological frameworks If we looked only at the types (and contents) of mental states born by each of S’s hemispheres, we might conclude that these hemispheres are associated with one and the same psychological framework. While the degree to which the hemispheres will bear the same types of mental states has probably been exaggerated in some of the commissurotomy literature, given that the hemispheres don’t just have different perceptual access to the world but are also functionally non-identical in their cognitive and perceptual processing, still, there will of course be a large degree of overlap in the types (and contents) of mental states they bear at any one time. Furthermore, even those states and contents which differ between the hemispheres may not be incoherent.10 10 I say this because not all differences in, say, the contents of experience, amount to incoherence or inconsistency. Experiences that differ between the hemispheres may simply be of different parts of the world (and the body), or of different aspects of the same part of the world. It is largely in the context of personal identity concerns that mere differences of this sort begin to look like inconsistencies, roughly I think because we equate a person with a subject of experience, and believe that such a subject’s experiences are all phenomenally unified (or co-conscious) with each other. The hemispheres of a “normal” subject, then, may also contain different experiences; but we believe that in the 13 But psychological frameworks are not ultimately about type identity or coherent contents. Of course a psychological framework must include a variety of types of mental state; no set of informational states, alone, absent motivational states, could explain a creature’s behavior, for instance. But PFs are composed of mental tokens: particular neural events, individuated by their functional and intentional properties, and by the particular causal relationships they bear to other neural events. Mental tokens compose a framework by bearing certain causal relations to each other; a thought can belong to a framework even if its content is semantically unrelated to or even inconsistent with the other contents born by that framework, so long as that thought bears appropriate causal relationships to (some) other states within the framework. Since causal interaction between mental states occurs both within and between persons, minds, and bodies, let us distinguish two kinds of causal interactions that can occur between mental events: direct and indirect interactions. I propose to define “direct” interaction negatively, in terms of “indirect” interaction. Indirect interactions are interactions between mental events that supervene on events that no mental state supervenes on, such as behavioral and environmental events. And direct interactions are interactions between mental events that are not indirect. Note that while my mental states and my sister’s mental states may interact richly with each other, they will do so only indirectly. My mental states may also bear many indirect relationships to each other; there will, nonetheless, be a rich web of direct interactions between my mental states as well. This distinction between direct and indirect causal relationships allows a way of delineating psychological frameworks as causal centers of thought and experience. When we attend to the causal interactions that occur within and between the two hemispheres of a splitbrain subject, we observe many direct intra-hemispheric causal relationships and few direct inter-hemispheric causal relationships. In particular, there are few direct inter-hemispheric relationships at the level of conscious thought and experience.11 The brain of a split-brain subject “normal” subject there is a single subject of experience for whom these right and left hemisphere experiences are all co-conscious with each other. 11 Though there are many unresolved complexities and uncertainties regarding the nature of inter-hemispheric emotional interaction, particularly regarding the individuation of token emotions, I would be happy to concede, at least for the sake of argument, that conscious emotion may constitute an exception to this general finding. Beneath 14 appears to have two causal centers of cognition and perception, especially conscious cognition and perception, that interact with each other primarily via behavioral and environmental (and other non-mental) events. It is in this sense that it is said that S’s two hemispheres each sustain a cognitive system meeting the criteria for a psychological framework largely independently of the other—i.e. absent much direct causal interaction. Note that while the criterion for individuating PFs proposed here does not appeal to psychological coherence, some limited appeal to coherence could be worked into it; but causal structure and not coherence remains at its heart. Due to the fact that the “disconnected” hemispheres of a split-brain subject actually remain connected via subcortical structures, however, their causal independence is not absolute. I admit, that is, the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject may fall somewhere between the two hemispheres of a “normal” subject and two hemispheres located in two different human beings, e.g. myself and my sister, in terms of their capacity for direct interaction. Indeed some (notably Lockwood, 1989) have constructed models of a split-brain subject’s consciousness according to which it is neither dual (divided) nor wholly unified but rather partially unified. Someone who accepted such a model might argue, against both Tye and myself, that there is no precise number of psychological frameworks that a split-brain subject has. While I have doubts about the ultimate plausibility of the partial unity model of consciousness, and believe that the degree to which subcortical structures sustain direct interaction between the two (cortically) “disconnected” hemispheres is still open to question, I also believe that split-brain subjects have two PFs in any event. The mental states of various types that compose a PF must be capable of direct interaction with each other in all the ways tokens of those types characteristically interact (whatever ways those are). Thus within at least a human’s psychological framework, it isn’t just emotional or affective states, or primitive perceptual states, etc., that can interact directly; within a human’s psychological framework some the level of conscious experience, meanwhile, there may be further direct relationships between the two “disconnected” hemispheres of a split-brain subject—relationships sustained by (intact) sub-cortical structures. These structures may sustain apparent unity of the ambient visual field as proposed by Trevarthen and Sperry (1973), and may permit the transfer of binary information about stimuli, as suggested earlier—and the transfer of response information (as opposed to stimulus information), which may play a role in guiding unified behavioral responses (see Corballis and Forster, 2003). For a general review of inter-hemispheric integration in the visual realm (via the “second visual system”), see Corballis 1995. 15 fairly rich degree of direct interaction between mental states of various types is possible. I can agree to assume, then, that the hemispheres of a split-brain subject do interact, directly, at the level of affect, and at the level of some “implicit” mental processes. Cognition at these levels will still just provide a kind of scaffolding upon which each hemisphere separately builds a further, unique, rich cognitive structure. We can therefore still locate two psychological frameworks in the split-brain subject, albeit frameworks whose foundations are not entirely distinct. Finally, even if this is wrong, and even if split-brain subjects do possess an indeterminate number of psychological frameworks, my most fundamental objection against Tye still stands: when he turns to split-brain subjects, he errs in individuating their psychological frameworks entirely in terms of shallow intentional, rather than functional/causal, properties. The approach to individuating psychological frameworks that I’ve advocated makes clear why it is so unappealing to attribute to S one PF most of the time and two PFs during the splitbrain experiment. For while the split-brain experimental paradigm imposes behavioral and environmental constraints not present outside the laboratory, thus limiting the degree of indirect causal interaction that can take place between S’s two hemispheres, the one thing it does not change is the underlying neural architecture responsible for affording direct causal interactions between mental states. As Rey once said about split-brain subjects: [their] hemispheres. . . . constitute a significant part of their [personal] embodiment, and. . . if they are detached from one another, seem to be each sufficiently complex and sufficiently autonomous to be regarded as separate persons. At least they seem so for the duration of the experiments. But these experiments in no way disturb the underlying structures: they simply lay them bare. (Rey 1975: 7; emphasis added) The major objection to attributing to S two psychological frameworks remains that S’s behavior is generally so unified outside of experimental situations. In fact, as Nagel (1971) once noted, and as Tye also indicates, it is fairly unified even within experimental situations. But S’s two frameworks may be highly similar, and having a single psychological framework is, I 16 believe, not the most important unifier of behavior. While behavioral unity no doubt has many sources, I suspect that it largely emerges out of mental, sensory, and motor processes that need not involve direct interaction between frameworks or hemispheres (e.g. increasing left hemisphere dominance, cross-cueing, the strengthening of ipsilateral motor and sensory circuits) and out of internal, causal forces that exist below the level of cognition and experience (e.g., postural reflexes, pattern generators in the spinal cord), and out of constraints posed by embodiment (e.g., the impossibility of being in two places at one time), and out of regularities in the environment (e.g., the world is largely the same on both sides of the vertical meridian— chimeras are rare), including social environment (e.g., one encounters largely the same people from day to day). And as Gazzaniga (1985) has emphasized, certain general features of human psychology—such as the desire to see one’s behavior as coherent and rational and voluntarily generated—must also play a role in unifying behavior. These features of human psychology, however, also don’t require direct interaction between the two mental systems or hemispheres. If psychological frameworks are composed of mental tokens, as Tye believes, then a splitbrain subject such as S has two psychological frameworks. This is not simply because S’s hemispheres are associated with distinct mental tokens, something that may be true of any subject’s two hemispheres. It is certainly not simply because S lacks a corpus callosum. Conclusions about psychological frameworks in split-brain subjects would say little, for example, about psychological frameworks in acallosal subjects (subjects born without corpora callosa), since the corpus callosum is individuated anatomically, not functionally, and other anatomical structures in other brains may serve a functional role identical to that played by the corpus callosum in a “normal” brain (and to that not played by any neural structure in the callosotomized brain). Because psychological frameworks are composed of token mental states, they must be individuated causally or architecturally: not just as sets of mental states but in terms of the kinds of relationships between those mental states that are afforded by a particular neural structure. In particular, within a single psychological framework, there should be a rich pattern of direct interaction (in the sense of “direct” defined earlier). In the case of a human subject’s psychological framework, the interaction should also sustain person-level activity like (especially conscious) believing, desiring, and experiencing. 17 8. Three possible modifications of Tye’s account Our split-brain subject S possesses two psychological frameworks, and the possession of these two frameworks helps explain S’s behavior with respect to the pipe during the split-brain experiment. If Tye is correct that “With each different PF, there is a different person” (141), then S must also be associated with two persons, a right hemisphere person who believes he held a pipe and a left hemisphere person who doesn’t. Some who have studied the split-brain phenomenon have argued (with varying degrees of explicitness and seriousness) that split-brain subjects are associated with two persons apiece—a right hemisphere person and a left hemisphere person. (See for instance Schiffer (1998), Dimond (1980), Bogen (1990), Rey (1975), Sperry (1974, 1990), and, most famously, Puccetti (1981, 1989).) Such “duality advocates,” however, have also accepted a further conclusion, one that directly contradicts a fundamental commitment of Tye’s. They have accepted that the evidential link Tye draws between acting in a unified fashion and being a single person can be broken, since split-brain subjects do generally behave in a unified fashion. Duality advocates see questions about counting minds and persons not as questions about behavior first and foremost, but rather as questions about the deep structure of the mental forces responsible for human behavior. This leaves them open to the possibility of discovering surprising things about the nature, and the number, of these structures. An alternative is to identify persons with organisms or animals, rather than with psychological frameworks or with the parts of animals that realize those frameworks. Such an account could say that a person is an organism or animal that possesses at least one psychological framework, and that S is a single person possessing two psychological frameworks. At first glance this option might seem to require us, again, to face a logical contradiction in order to provide a realistic explanation of S’s behavior during the split-brain experiment; for a single person still can’t both believe and not believe that P. But this account could simply make parts of persons, rather than persons themselves, the proper subjects of psychological frameworks; 18 persons would possess these frameworks without being their subjects, strictly speaking.12 Hence both the belief that P and the lack of a belief that P can be used to explain S’s behavior, because one of S’s hemispheres does not believe that P. Tye might object to this second alternative that identifying persons with whole organisms can’t account for another population he discusses, subjects with dissociative identity disorder (DID).13 If persons are whole organisms, then subjects with DID are single persons also; yet their behavior is disunified (at least across time). This objection is easily met, however. Though persons aren’t the proper subjects of psychological frameworks on this alternative, persons still possess (one or more) PFs, and these frameworks play a primary role in our explanations of behavior. A person with two PFs that are very similar (in terms of the types of mental states and contents they include) will exhibit more unified behavior than a person with two PFs that are very different. So we can still explain disunified behavior wherever we need to. Of course, accepting this modification to his account would still require Tye to give up something significant: it would require him to give up the connection between persons and coherent sets of psychological states. For, according to the account of persons now being considered, a person can, broadly speaking, possess incoherent pairs of mental states, by virtue of 12 Dainton has suggested something similar: “If the relevant mental capacities are grounded in only a small part of the animal, and this small part is, at least in principle, detachable from the remainder, then can we not say the following. Yes, animals have mental capacities, but strictly speaking, the whole animal does not possess these capacities, only a part of the animal possesses them; so in saying that ‘Animals have mental capacities’, what we are really saying—or would say on reflection—is that ‘Animals have mental capacities by possessing a part which has these capacities’” (Dainton 1998: 681-682). Dainton says this in the context of defending a kind of psychological account of persons; he suggests identifying the part of the animal that has these capacities with the person. This suggestion would be equivalent to the first possible modification of Tye’s account, which maintains that persons are the subjects of psychological frameworks and therefore accepts that a split-brain subject is associated with two persons. The alternative modification I’m suggesting here is that we identify the animal with the person—a person who possesses two cerebral hemispheres, each of which believes, experiences, and so forth. 13 While the basics of the split-brain phenomena are fairly robust, dissociative identity disorder (DID) is somewhat of a minefield diagnostically and theoretically. It remains a controversial diagnosis, with skeptics insisting that a better explanation of DID behavior can be given in terms of hysteria, amnesia, repression, and more common and mundane forms of dissociation. I remain agnostic on DID as a diagnosis in this paper and here confine myself to explaining why identifying persons with whole organisms does not leave us without the means to explain the 19 possessing multiple psychological frameworks whose contents do not cohere with each other. For this reason, this second alternative may be thought more extreme than the first, even though the first identified S with two persons. But persons may well be surprisingly complicated. Numerous cases of mental pathology, from blindsight to agnosia, suggest that all those activities that make up Tye’s “coherent psychological frameworks”—belief, perception, experience—are built up and break down in pieces. Such cases involve damage to particular areas and pathways of the brain, damage to particular physical parts of organisms, resulting in partial but not full loss of desire, experience, memory, and belief. Arguably the split-brain cases are so fascinating, and even disturbing, from the standpoint of personal identity, precisely because they bring into sharp relief the fact that we do in some sense see and desire and believe with parts of ourselves, and not with our whole being. When some of these parts stop perceiving and desiring and believing, it isn’t clear what happens to us. Identifying persons with animals means saying that we remain single persons even when our psychological aspects are deeply divided. A final possible modification to Tye’s account of personal identity would both respect the strong evidential weight that account puts on behavioral integration, and keep something like a rough psychological coherence condition for the individuation of persons, while still dissociating persons from psychological frameworks. According to this third alternative, a human organism with multiple PFs might still be a single person, so long as those PFs were psychologically similar to each other, particularly with regard to those psychological properties that most matter to us about persons: character and personality traits, values, long-term memories, emotional attachments, and deeply felt desires and dreams. The psychological properties we would pay most attention to, then, to determine whether a human being was one or more persons, would be intentional (and historical) first and foremost. Going this third route could mean saying that splitbrain subjects are single persons, since their two frameworks appear composed of significantly overlapping types of mental states and events, while saying that subjects with dissociative identity disorders are multiple persons. (Indeed a patient with DID might be multiple persons even if she had only a single psychological framework, depending on the architecture and behavior of subjects diagnosed with DID, or even without the means to accommodate the essentials of that diagnosis 20 contents of that framework.)14 According to this third possible modification of Tye’s account, while the individuation criteria for persons differ from those for psychological frameworks, the individuation criteria for persons are still psychological. Thus this third alternative allows Tye his conclusions about personhood in the two kinds of “hard cases” he discusses, and retains that aspect of his account of personal identity that grounds personhood in (some) psychological facts. But it rejects that aspect of his account of personhood that says that there is a unique person associated with each psychological framework, since different sorts of psychological facts will be relevant depending on whether it is persons or PFs being individuated. Note that this third alternative does not ground the individuation of persons in the findings of (scientific) psychology or neuroscience. (The second alternative doesn’t either, but it may ground the individuation of persons in biology.) This may be wise; Nagel (1971) suggested long ago that our notions about persons may be incompatible with the results of ongoing psychological and neuroscientific discovery. It is possible, then, that to the degree that Tye presents his account of persons as grounded in scientific psychology, he does so unwisely. For the interests we have in persons may well be largely “forensic,” as Locke once said (1690), and therefore not closely tied to the outcome of any scientific debate. In fact I myself am sympathetic to such a view of personhood, and suspect that while some findings in some areas of psychology will be relevant to our beliefs about persons, “person” will not survive in, nor have any terminological descendent in, the vocabulary of a developed scientific theory. This is not surprising, because, again, our interests in persons are largely moral, social, and simply personal in nature. Against the background of such interests, split-brain subjects may be single persons not simply because their behavior is usually so unified outside of experimental situations, but because even that behavior of theirs that is “disunified” does not usually reflect, and the division between the two hemispheres is not founded on, differences in values, temperament, character, or if in fact it is real. 14 While I am reluctant to say much about DID at this point in time, I do think that there is some evidence to suggest that there may be a kind of deep functional unity underlying the apparently oppositional “alters” of such subjects. We might identify a DID subject with one PF but with multiple persons, however, given the type of interests we tend to have in persons. 21 history. Nagel commented, and Tye repeats, that the friends and family of split-brain subjects relate to them as if they were single persons; this manner of relating to them seems not just natural but fully rational, regardless of what scientists discover about the deep structure of their mental lives: for the two hemispheres share not just a body, but a personality and a history. These three options I’ve just described all amount to the same thing in one crucial respect: they all attribute to S two distinct psychological frameworks. Accordingly, any of the three possible modifications of Tye’s account of personal identity will require Tye to change not just what he says about split-brain subjects, but also what he says about persons: the links between being a single person, having a single psychological framework, and behaving in an integrated fashion must be broken somewhere. My deepest criticism of Tye’s account of personal identity as applied to split-brain subjects is not that he identifies them with single persons. His intuition that split-brain subjects are single persons is quite understandable. But in order to defend this intuition Tye is forced to claim that split-brain subjects have single PFs, because of the account of personal identity he adopts. My deepest criticism of Tye’s account, then, concerns his treatment of PFs. Psychological frameworks, or something like them, I take it, are constructs of a (developing) scientific psychology, and accordingly will be individuated by reference to intentional properties, but also to both cognitive architecture—to the types of relationships possible between mental tokens of various types—and the underlying neural structure sustaining that architecture. So individuated, a unique PF is associated with each hemisphere of a split-brain subject: each is even the bearer of person-level properties and activities such as believing, perceiving, feeling, desiring, and remembering.15 Moreover, the interaction that occurs between them largely supervenes on behavior or environmental events, or on internal events not describable as mental. Ironically, individuating psychological frameworks architecturally, instead of (largely) behaviorally or by content type, would actually allow Tye to provide better behavioral explanations than he is currently able to. Since he takes S’s generally unified behavior to be 15 Note that this does not appear to be true of any smaller part of a human brain: no part smaller than a whole hemisphere is a believer and a desirer and a perceiver, etc. Nagel’s (1971) worry that if we identify each hemisphere with a mind we will soon have to identify the visual system alone with a mind, for example, is not warranted; there is no slippery slope here because the visual system alone is not a candidate for being the subject of an entire PF. 22 overriding evidence that S has a single PF, he is forced to resort to an unconvincing psychological explanation of S’s behavior during the split-brain experiment. Locating psychological frameworks at a deeper level gives us a better understanding of the psychological mechanisms responsible for split-brain subjects’ behavior and, accordingly, a better explanation of that behavior. References Bayne, T. (2005.) Divided brains & unified phenomenology: An essay on Michael Tye's Consciousness and Persons. Philosophical Psychology 18: 495-512. Boatman, D., Freeman, J., Vining, E., Pulsifer, M., Miglioretti, D., Minahan, R., Carson, B., Brandt, J., and G. McKhann. (1999). Language recovery after left hemispherectomy in children with late-onset seizures. Annals of Neurology 46: 579-586. Bogen, J. (1990). Partial hemispheric independence with the neocommissures intact. In C. Trevarthen (Ed.) Brain Circuits and Functions of the Mind (pp. 215-230). Cambridge University Press. Bogen, J. (1998). Physiologic Consequences of complete or partial commissural section. In M. Apuzzo (Ed.) Surgery of the Third Ventricle (pp.215-230). Williams and Wilkins. Bogen, J. (1985). The callosal syndromes. In K. Heilman and E. Valenstein (Eds.) Clinical Neuropsychology, 2nd Edition (pp. 295-338). Oxford University Press. Bogen, J., & Vogel, P. (1975). Neurologic status in the long term following cerebral commissurotomy. In F. Michel and B. Schott (Eds.) Les Syndromes de Disconnexion Calleuse Chez L'Homme (pp. 227-251). Hopital Neurologigue. 23 Burkland, C. and A. Smith. (1977). Language and the cerebral hemispheres. Neurology 27: 627633. Corballis, M. (1995). Visual integration in the split brain. Neuropsychologia 33: 937-959. Corballis, M., & Forster, B. (2003). Water under the bridge: Interhemispheric visuomotor integration in a split-brain man. In E. Zaidel and M. Iacoboni (Eds.), The Parallel Brain: The Cognitive Neuroscience of the Corpus Callosum. Bradford/MIT Press. Dainton, B. (1998). Review of Eric Olson’s The Human Animal: Personal Identity without Psychology. Mind 107: 679-682. Dimond, S. (1980). Neuropsychology: A Textbook of Systems and Psychological Functions of the Human Brain. Butterworths. Franz, E., Eliassen, J., Ivry, R., & Gazzaniga, M. (1996). Dissociation of spatial and temporal coupling in the bimanual movements of callosotomy patients. Psychological Science 7: 306310. Gazzaniga, M. (2005). Forty-five years of split-brain research and still going strong. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6: 653-659. Gazzaniga, M. (2000). Cerebral specialization and interhemispheric communication: does the corpus callosum enable the human condition? Brain 123: 1293-1326. Gazzaniga, M. (1985). The Social Brain. Basic Books. Gazzaniga, M. (1970). The Bisected Brain. Appleton-Century-Crofts. 24 Gazzaniga, M., & LeDoux, J. (1978). The Integrated Mind. Plenum Press. Gott, P. (1973). Cognitive abilities following right and left hemispherectomy. Cortex 9: 266-274. LeDoux, J. (2002). Synaptic Self: How Our Brains Become Who We Are. Viking Press. Locke, J. (1690) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding: Book 2, Chapter 27. (Many editions now available.) Lockwood, M. (1989.) Mind, brain and the quantum. Basil Blackwell. Marks, C. (1980). Commissurotomy, Consciousness, and Unity of Mind. Bradford Books. Nagel, T. (1971). Brain bisection and the unity of consciousness. Synthese 22: 396-413. Ogden, J. (1989). Visuospatial and other “right-hemispheric” functions after long recovery periods in left-hemispherectomized subjects. Neuropsychologia 27: 765-776. Olson, E. (1997). The Human Animal: Personal Identity without Psychology. Oxford University Press. Parfit, D. (1995). The unimportance of identity. In H. Harris (Ed.) Identity (pp. 13-45). Oxford University Press. Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press. Puccetti, R. (1989). Two brains, two minds? Wigan’s theory of mental duality. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40: 137-144. Puccetti, R. (1981). The case for mental duality: evidence from split-brain data and other 25 considerations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4: 93-123. Rey, G. (1975). Persons and personalities. Presented at the Colloquium on Personal Identity at the 72nd Annual Meeting of the American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division. Rey, G. (1977). Survival. In A. Rorty (Ed.) The Identities of Persons (pp. 41-66). University of California Press. Schechter, E. (forthcoming). Individuating mental tokens: The Split-Brain Case. Under review. Schiffer, F. (1998). Of Two Minds. The Free Press. Schiffer, F., Zaidel, E., Bogen, J., & Chasan-Taber, S. (1998). Different psychological status in the two hemispheres of two split-brain patients. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology, and Behavioral Neurology 11: 151-156. Smith, A. (1969.) Nondominant hemipherectomy. Neurology 19: 442-445. Smith, A. (1966.) Speech and other functions after left (dominant) hemispherectomy. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry 29: 467-471. Sperry, R. (1990). Forebrain commissurotomy and conscious awareness. In C. Trevarthen (Ed.) Brain Circuits and Functions of the Mind (pp. 371-386). Cambridge University Press. Sperry, R. (1974). Lateral specialization in the Surgically Separated Hemispheres. In F. Schmitt and F. Worden (Eds.), The Neurosciences: Third Study Program (pp. 5-19). MIT Press. Sperry, R. (1968). Hemisphere deconnection and unity in conscious awareness. American Psychologist 23: 723-733. 26 Sperry, R., Zaidel, E., & Zaidel, D. (1979). Self recognition and social awareness in the deconnected minor hemisphere. Neuropsychologia 17:153-166. Trevarthen, C. (1974a.) Analysis of cerebral activities that generate and regulate consciousness is commissurotomy patients. In S. Diamond and J. Beaumont (Eds.). Hemisphere Function in the Human Brain (pp. 235-61). Elek Science. Trevarthen, C. (1974b.) Functional relations of disconnected hemispheres with the brain stem, and with each other: Monkey and man. In M. Kinsbourne and W. Smith (Eds.) Hemispheric Disconnection and Cerebral Function (pp. 187-207). Charles C. Thomas. Tye, M. (2003). Consciousness and Persons. MIT Press. Wiggins, D. (1976). Locke, Butler and the stream of consciousness: And men as natural kind. In A. Rorty (Ed.), The Identities of Persons (pp. 139-174). University of California Press. 27