Judith Butler and corporeal vulnerability : A new perspective on the public dimension of education Joris Vlieghe Centrum voor wijsgerige pedagogiek K.U. Leuven In this paper I would like to reflect upon the connection between the public and critical dimension of education on the one hand and our condition as corporeal and vulnerable beings on the other hand. In particular I will explore this issue within the framework that Judith Butler offers in her most recent writings1. This is of great importance to this year’s conference theme as it might help to elucidate why social problems can be interpreted (and therefore institutionalized) as social problems. This question presupposes that there is some dimension within education that is social, relational and public. So the problem remains how to conceptualise this public dimension. Therefore it seems interesting to deal in the following with Judith Butler’s statement that “the body has its invariably public dimension” (PL 26). How are we to understand the specific meaning of this body and why is it precisely our bodily incarnation that obligates us to take responsibility for others and for the community we belong to? Before turning to Butler’s position I will first discuss shortly why it’s nowadays not evident to speak about the public or critical possibilities of education. This will help to understand the importance and originality of Butler’s contribution in thinking about critical pedagogy. She argues that the experience of not being able Butler, J. (2004), Violence, Precarious Life. The Powers of Mourning and Violence, Londen (Verso) [abbreviated as PL] and Butler, J. (2005), Giving an Account of Oneself, New York (Fordham University Press) [abbreviated as GAO] to ground ourselves as autonomous, self-transparent and rational beings is an experience that grants the possibility to assume critical responsibility. This experience is inextricable bound to the corporeal condition of susceptibility, so she argues. Consequently critique towards the existing (pedagogical, societal, political) order should have to do more with an attitude that refers to an experience of radical finitude than with the typical modern (Kantian, Habermasian) definition and positioning of the self as autonomous transcendental subjectivity. I think I should mention here that my interest shall mainly go to Butler’s most recent writings, especially Giving an Account of Oneself and Precarious Life. This is rather exceptional. When one considers the bulk of articles in the field of educational theory and philosophy which are inspired by Butler, one will find only scarcely references to these texts. Butler has of course become one of the major referents when dealing with problems of social emancipation and more specifically with gender-related issues and the possibility of minorities to resist/revolt against institutionalized practices and discourse. So it is generally accepted to refer to her important studies of the 90’s, such as Gender Trouble, Bodies that Matter and Excitable Speech2. Time and again one invokes Butler’s interpretation of the key notions “performativity” (Austin) and ”iterability” (Derrida). Butler is mainly appreciated for her argument that subjectivity is dependent upon linguistic categories which are not of our own making: they define who we are and fix our identities, because it concerns expressions with performative qualities. We really are nothing else than the social categories we verify in our daily life. Butler’s point at issue is a double one: (1) we have to perform what we are in a culturally prescribed way in order to exist socially, but (2) in a sense it is pointless to speak here about a “we”, because there exists no 2 Butler, J. (1990), Gender Trouble:Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, New York (Routledge); Butler, J. (1993), Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of sex, New York (Routledge); Butler, J. (1997), Excitable Speech: a Politics of the Performative, New York (Routledge). subjectivity prior to the formative power of the pre-existing discourse. The dependency upon a given order of meaning constitutes singular subjectivities in the first place. So Butler shows that it is pointless to invoke an immaculate core of subjectivity that would exist independent of the given identities which are mandatory under a specific social and political regime. Consequentially political resistance that pretends to act on behalf of such repressed essence of mankind is doomed from the start, as it will assume a fiction that only serves the existing order of things. Fixing man’s essence, even when trying to find a ground for resistance, is always an act of reinstalling an arbitrary order of significations that exercises power and forms our very subjectivity. Nevertheless Butler also argues that societal and political order only exists by repeating consolidated meanings. Performativity is dependent upon ritual rehearsal, which in its endlessness is undeterminable. So precisely here, in this process of “citation”, in re-enacting given identities, a possibility is disclosed to contestate the existing regime. In the current discourse’s dependency on individuals who still have to perform some prescribed identity lies at the same time the very possibility of refusal. This line of thought has unmistakingly been fruitful within the field of pedagogy and particularly in thinking a “no nonsense approach” towards criticality, resistance and genuine social change. Now, my approach departs in a double way from this current appreciation of Judith Butler: firstly I will concentrate on her more recent writings, which I think have as yet not met the attention they deserve. In these texts one can find a conception of corporeality which exceeds the Austinian and Derridian framework that is dominant in Butler’s writings of the 90’s. Secondly I will try to broaden the critical perspective she offers in the direction of a more general consideration with the possibility of critique and resistance, particularly in reference to corporeal vulnerability. But let me first offer a sketch of the issue I think this latest work of Butler might help to elucidate. Why is the critical dimension of education a problem today? For a long time pedagogy has been formulating as its central aim the education of (young) people to become critical and enlightened citizens. This classic ideal of Bildung (edification, cultivation) came down to the idea that the main objective of education is the critical inquiry of the existing social order3. Students were expected to become initiated in a cultural heritage and to acquire the competencies needed to become bearers of social and political progress. So one looked at the gebildeter Mensch as an autonomous citizen, who develops her internal potentialities as far as possible so that she is willing to take the responsibility for the optimal functioning of society, for the continual strive for a better, more equal and harmonious community4. This continuous striving for an ideal society ascribed a prominent critical role to the gebildeter Mensch: she, more than anyone else, was expected to assume a critical position5. Crucial to this ambition is the very possibility of (and willingness to) changing oneself. This point of view is today no longer tenable. To understand what has happened, we can find support in Adorno’s thesis that in the modern world Bildung has become Halbbildung. Christiane Thompson comments on this idea as follows6: 3 See: Masschelein, J. (2004) How to conceive of a critical theory today?, Journal of Philosophy of Education”38 (3), p. 351-367 4 See Biesta, G. (2006), Beyond Learning. Democratic Education for a Human Future (Boulder, Paradigm), p. 2-4 5 For a more radical interpretation that situates the project of Bildung from its very beginning within the existing power apparatus, see: Masschelein, J., Ricken, N. (2003), Do We (Still) Need the Concept of Bildung? In Educational Philosophy and Theory 35 (2), p. 139-154. 6 Thompson, C. (2006), Adorno and the Borders of Experience: The Significance of the Nonidentical for a ‘different’ Theory of Bildung, Educational Theory 56(1), p. 69-87. In this article the author tries to “the experience of Bildung or learning does not predominantly change the students and their points of view anymore. Rather, the prospective experiences are intended to enhance the students’ spectrum of assets. […] Bildung has been transformed into a measure of the individual’s capacity for adaptation. […] What is learned is ‘no longer significant for one’s own life but forms a knowledge that is helpful for our survival.”7 We are no longer changed by the educational process. The only thing that happens to us is that our position gets confirmed and strengthened. We are never out of position, so to speak. This analysis is of course I line with many studies within the framework of governmentality-studies, which time and again show how under the current regime of quality and efficiency educational subjects come to identify themselves as “entrepreneurs of their own lives”, as investors who are obsessed by a will to strive for a strengthening of their own position. This has important consequences for the critical dimension of education. There exists no longer a possibility to take a distance to present society and its demands8. Of course, one could respond that the acquirement of “critical competencies” was never before so important as today. More and more the cornerstone of a good educational project appears to be: giving to pupils and students capabilities that have to do with self-reflection and critical inquiry, instead of filling their heads with contents and erudition9. Yet these so called “critical attitudes” imply in no way distancing oneself from existing societal order. By developing these capabilities pupils and students only see themselves once more in terms of the will to strive for a more excellent position in our current information society. There exists a persistent will in all of us to be critical which makes us to develop a new and actual relevant concept of Bildung, starting from Adorno’s remarks on aesthetic experience. 7 O.c., p. 73-74. 8 See also: Masschelein (2004). 9 One could relate this to the recent shift from the traditional “language of education” towards a “language of (life-long) learning”. See Biesta (2006), p. 13-24. define ourselves constantly as investors of our own lives. While exercising “critique” we therefore fail to distance ourselves from the current regime. So it is difficult to see how we could still be critical at all or what it could mean for education to have a “public” voice. The question is therefore where to look for a critical alternative that has no reference to the reinforcing of our own position as so called critical subjects. Perhaps we should try to assume a critical attitude, as Foucault would suggest, rather than a position. This kind of attitude is granted by what he refers to as “limitexperience”, i.e. an experience in the most passive sense of this word10: being vulnerable, being prepared to be exposed to something that obliges us to change our lives. By invoking the register of experience Foucault tried to think about a form of criticality which eludes the pitfall of contributing to the existing regime. Only an experimental alternative counts as a real alternative. So the experience of one’s own limits, the vivid confrontation with the existing discourse one lives with but which is usually not put into question, grants the experiencing of distance towards the existing societal and political order. Therefore it all comes down to an existential move, rather than to the taking of a firm position. Judith Butler on (corporeal) vulnerability It’s precisely here that we can fall back on the thinking of Judith Butler, who (at least partly) claims to be loyal to this Foucaultian stance. What links Butler’s most recent writings to the aforementioned discussion is her critique to a prevailing line of thought in western philosophy concerning the possibility to assume critical responsibility towards one’s own life, the life of others and the life of community. 10 Foucault, M. (1984), What is Enlightenment?, in Rabinow, P. (Ed.) The Foucault Reader. New York: Pantheon, pp.32-50. For a similar argumentation see also: Butler, J. (2002), What is Critique? On Foucault’s Virtue, in Ingram, D. (Ed.), The Political, Oxford (Blackwell), p. 212-226 She states that traditionally criticality rests upon the assumption” to give a full account of oneself”. This is because traditionally critical distance is defined in terms of the autonomy of a critical and rational subject that seeks for an ultimate justification for her actions. Trying to legitimate our moral obligations towards others and the community, we tend to found these in a kind of positive essence of what it means being human or belonging to a community. One can think here of the Kantian or Habermasian definition of transcendental (inter)subjectivity that serves as the starting point to legitimize a critical position towards the existing social, political or educational order. Butler on the contrary argues that it is precisely the negative experience of our own radical lacking of such a ground that constitutes moral and communal bindings. Moral agency is granted by the experience that we never reach the ground of our own origins. Being dependent upon conditions that we cannot fully control constitutes us as moral and accountable beings. The fundamental “opacity” that results from our constitution as singular creatures turns us into responsible moral subjects11. “I find that my very formation implicates the other in me, that my own foreignness to myself is, paradoxically, the source of my ethical connection with others.” (PL 46). Consequently, without any reference to an anthropological essence or to a transcendental ground, it becomes possible to speak in an alternative way about moral obligations12. Through the limit-experience of our own finitude we are confronted with a world and with others that charge us with responsibility. Thus the 11 See GAO p. 36-40. See also PL 20 and PL 48. 12 It could be discussed whether she succeeds in this ambition. Butler formulates her critical position by referring to a tradition that reduces valid speaking to epistemological founded discourse. According to her we have to recognize the impossibility hereof: we have to know that we don’t know. So perhaps her philosophy remains within the framework she tries to escape. The imperative “to know thyself” (in our unknowingness) stays an undisputed starting point. The later Foucault precisely criticised this, opening a radical different line of thinking, starting from the problem of “caring for oneself”. See: Gros, F., Le souci de soi chez Michel Foucault. A review of ‘The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-1982’, Philosophy and Social Criticism 31, 5-6 (2005), p. 697-708 awareness of non-transparency does not privatize us: the strangeness within us doesn’t make us prisoners of ourselves, but confronts us with a public dimension, namely that we cannot escape our relations with the other13. It should be noted that this is not a plea for a relational ontology (our essence = our relations to the others), but on the contrary the defence of a philosophy of radical finitude. Our “essence”, if it is still possible to use this terminology, should better be described as a void. Not in the Sartrian sense of the nothingness of absolute freedom, but as the exposure to a transcendence that forces us to relate to the other in a non gratuitous way14. In her essay Violence, Mourning and Politics Butler substantiates her argument by evoking some convincing examples. I will deal with two of these here15. The first case is the experience of losing someone whom one was attached to. This confronts us with the brute fact that we are but who we are, thanks to our dependency upon a particular other. What singularises us has to do with the uncontrollability of our social relations. The significance of mourning, a central theme in this essay, is that we become aware of something that escapes our own meaning-giving control. “[O]ne mourns when one accepts that by the loss one undergoes one will be changed possibly forever. Perhaps mourning has to do with agreeing to undergo a transformation (perhaps one should say submitting to a transformation) the full result of which one cannot know in advance.” (PL 21). Such an experience could have important pedagogical consequences: we might learn to 13 See PL p. 22 14 Cfr.: “Although I am insisting on referring to a common human vulnerability, one that emerges with life itself, I also insist that we cannot recover the source of this vulnerability; it precedes the formation of ‘I’. This is a condition, a condition of being laid bare from the start and with which we cannot argue.” (PL 31). 15 The third example is that of (sexual) desire: we can never give conclusive reasons why we desire the person we long for (PL 24). Similar arguments are developed in Beside Oneself: On the Limits of Sexual Autonomy in Butler, J., Undoing Gender, New York (Routledge) [abbreviated as UG], p. 17-39. forsake what Adorno calls moral narcissism (GAO: 103). This narcissistic attitude presupposes that moral obligations should be founded in the loyalty to our own essence as rational and autonomous beings, as self-transparent and sovereign lawgivers of ourselves, as Kantian or Habermasian transcendental subjects, as “entrepreneurs” who reposition ourselves, when acting ethically. Butler on the contrary thinks that the experience of loss and mourning reveals the possibility of an alternative moral responsibility and sense of community: we may find ourselves obliged to others because of the impossibility to give a full account of who we are, because of the impossibility to be our own ground. The striking point here is that Butler links this to the body: “grief contains within it the possibility of apprehending the fundamental sociality of embodied life, the ways in which we are from the start, and by virtue of being a bodily being, already given over, beyond ourselves, implicated in lives that are not our own” (UG 22, italics supplied). Before analysing the reasons to link opacity, community and corporeality, I will first deal with the second example she attends to. This concerns the passionate resistance one may experience belonging to a political marginalised minority. In this case one can be outside oneself with anger and indignation. Butler makes it clear that it is wrong to reduce political engagement to the desire for a society that safeguards the possibility for every individual to be respected in her own subjective rights. This liberal and legalist vision, commonly shared by feminists and advocates of homosexual’s emancipation movements, is according to Butler very unwise. Because the longing to justice in the situation of oppressed minorities is “[a] disposition of ourselves outside ourselves [which] seems to follow from bodily life, from its vulnerability and its exposure.” (PL 25). In the last quote we find again this very important remark: the public sense of resistance against the existing social order is not founded in a rationalist or individualistic morality, but refers to the experience of human vulnerability. This susceptibility is further described as an exposition that has to do with our bodily incarnation, with the “precariousness of life”. Or as she states is: “the body has its invariably public dimension” (PL 26). This is a most innovative insight. Butler departs from the traditional (Arendtian) definition of the “public” realm as a space of visibility, which grants autonomy to every citizen and the possibility to defend her own rights. This commonly shared vision “fails to do justice to passion and grief and rage, all of which tear us from ourselves, bind us to others, transport us, undo us, and implicate us in lives that are not our own, sometimes fatally, irreversibly.” (UG 20) This alternative conception of “political community [which] is wrought from such ties” (ibidem) refers to our corporeality: “to be a body is to be given over to others” (ibidem). The bodily vulnerability one experiences constitutes the public and “opens up a different conception of politics” (UG 21). The connection between vulnerability and the body The question I would like to bring to the fore is why this experience of exposure should refer to a corporeal type of vulnerability. Butler states time and again that the susceptibility that serves in her philosophy as the starting point for an alternative speaking about critique and moral obligation is the susceptibility of our bodies. I am never fully myself, as far as my body is never my own body. In the following I would like to explore why we should accept this bold but very fascinating statement. This reference to corporeality is a major theme in Butler’s oeuvre16. Inspired by the thoughts of Althusser and Foucault on subjectivization (assujettissement), she repeatedly states that subjectivity is the effect of some discourse. We are but who we are thanks to the identities ascribed to us (and spontaneously accepted by 16See for instance: Butler, J. (1993), Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of sex, New York (Routledge) us) according to a given order of meanings. Power “subjectivates” in the double sense of this word: (1) we become singularized beings (2) by relating to ourselves in terms that are dominant within a given regime of truth. This is the manner in which Butler actualises Foucault’s thesis that subjectivity can be analysed as the result of a double bond between totalising and in individualising forms of power: we gain our identity in subjection (in the sense of submission). Of course this view is equally dependent on Lacan’s theory of symbolic identification. Now, as a feminist thinker, Butler is strongly sensitive for the way power works through our bodies. We become somebody through the acceptance of arbitrary meanings such as the definition of masculinity and femininity. In her more recent writings she tries to extend this insight beyond the problems of gender studies and queer theory, in order to use this paradigm of “subjectivation-through-the-body” as a point of departure to state something about moral and social reality in general. This is a rather defiant line of thinking. I should mention beforehand that Butler’s considerations on this issue are not consistent. I will only point briefly here at some ambiguities in her thoughts on corporeality, not so much as to question the internal coherency of Butler’s philosophical position, but in order to find a more nuanced concept of bodily susceptibility17. (1) On the one hand she sometimes considers our corporeal condition as a mere biological given. On repeated occasions she seems to adhere to what she calls herself a “spinozistic” position, stating that we are all fundamentally driven by a desire to persist in our own being. This preoccupation with our own survival should explain why we become attached to identities that are arbitrary posed upon us as inhabitants of a certain power regime: “to persist in one’s own being means to be given over from the start to social terms that are never fully one’s own. […] Only by 17 I hope to elaborate these ambiguities further in article I am preparing persisting in alterity does one persist in one’s “own” being. Vulnerable to terms that one never made, one persists always, to some degree, through categories, names, terms, and classifications that mark a primary and inaugurative alienation in sociality.” (PLP 28)18. (2) On the other hand Butler frequently tracks human finitude back to the non-transparent social and cultural conditions that constitute us as singular individuals. In the constitution of our subjectivities we are dependent upon and therefore exposed to others who “called us into being” (Althusser), to social meanings and norms that we must use to be intelligible for ourselves and to others, etc. Using the expression invented by Lacan, we could term this dimension of strangeness-within-us “extimité”: I can never control or appropriate that what appears to be the most proper to myself. To become aware of this attachment to uncontrollable social and cultural preconditions is then an experience of exposition and dispossession (because we realise we didn’t and cannot ground the meaning of our own being). “[I]f the very production of the subject and the formation of [its] will are the consequences of a primary subordination, then the vulnerability of the subject to a power not of its own making is unavoidable.”19 Needless to say that this opposition cannot be found literally in Butler’s oeuvre: this is a reconstruction for which I am responsible. Nevertheless I am convinced that this ambiguity exists within Butler’s philosophy and that it deserves the attention I give it here. Both approaches of vulnerability are not easily 18 Similar positions, in connection with Foucault, are defended by Mourad, R., After Foucault. A new form of right, Philosophy and Social Criticism 29 (4), p. 451-481 and Olssen, M. , Foucault and the Imperatives of Education. Critique and Self-creation in a Non-foundational World, in Studies in Philosophy and Education 25 (2006), p. 245-271. Mourad e.g. speaks of the human condition of “contention”: “Under this conception, the human being is thrust into a world largely adverse to it and much more powerful.” (p. 466). In spite of the omnipresence of power, it is precisely the unavoidable fragility of the flesh that grants the motivation to resist to power. 19 Butler, J. (1997), The Psychic Life of Power, Stanford (Stanford University Press) [abbreviated as PLP], p. 20. harmonised. Moreover each approach has to deal with specific difficulties. Let me start with the last remark: (1) If one identifies susceptibility in terms of the individual’s will to survive, one reduces subjectivity to a kind of biological substance. This is quite problematic, because in this case Butler falls back on a transcendental principle in the name of which adherence to or, for that matter, the contestation of the existing order gets a justified ground. But, as I just mentioned, it is precisely her ambition to think of responsibility and criticality without this kind of presuppositions. Furthermore, this position could be described as a case of bio-politics: this Foucaultian term refers to the modern regime of power that owns its effectiveness to the interest for our own survival. Therefore the assumption that we are all fundamentally obsessed with the will to persevere in our own being can itself be analysed as the effect of a (typical modern) power regime. We are asked to relate to ourselves as spinozistic subjectivities. But we might realize that there is no necessity in this anthropological self-definition. And it is precisely the experience hereof that could open a critical distance. So perhaps we should just refuse to be obsessed with self-perseverance (as a normative criterion, that is). In this light Butler’s argument in terms of conatus essendi seems to legitimize exactly the position she wants to criticize. (2) If one treats susceptibility in exclusively cultural or linguistic terms – Butler speaks in Excitable speech of “linguistic vulnerability”20 – I think it is difficult to see why she keeps referring to human corporeality. As I said before, the connection between cultural code and our bodily incarnation is evident in the case of gender identity. But what have other aspects of culturally formed subjectivity to do with our body? So, I find it a defiant thought to state that there is no vulnerability 20 Butler, J. (1997), Excitable Speech: a Politics of the Performative, New York (Routledge). “Linguistic vulnerability” refers here to the possibility of being hurt by hate speech as a result of our formative dependency upon a socially and linguistically constituted order. Butler states clearly that this dimension of being hurt by hate speech is analogous to physical vulnerability, but not identical to it. outside of our corporeal condition, but I don’t think Butler makes it clear enough why all experience of human finitude necessarily refers to the body. Moreover, the linking of all sorts of vulnerability and the body becomes especially difficult when she tends to treat corporeality as a purely biological given. So for instance I find it very difficult to comprehend why the vulnerability which is disclosed in mourning refers to our own desire to survive. Therefore I think it is indispensable to reflect anew upon corporeality within a broadened Butlerian framework. In her most recent book, Giving an Account of Oneself, which is a reworking of her famous 2002 Adorno Lectures, I think we can find some relevant clues that point in new direction. Vulnerability as anonymity of the flesh Although she repeats in this book some of the positions I criticized, she also argues that we should think of human finitude not solely as an effect of our initiation in the symbolic order, but first of all as related to the fact that humans come into being as premature beings. As Jean Laplanche, a not well known psychoanalytic who was a critic of Lacan, showed, the human being is born as a radical fragile creature that is handed over to the care of others. As a newborn I find myself in “a condition in which I am prior to acquiring an ‘I’, a being who has been touched, moved, fed, changed, put to sleep, established as the subject and object of speech. My infantile body has not only been touched, moved and arranged, but those impingements operated as tactile signs that registered in my formation. These signs communicate to me in ways that are not reducible to vocalization. They are signs of an other, but they are also the traces from which an ‘I’ will eventually emerge, an ‘I’ who will never be able, fully, to recover or read these signs, for whom these signs will remain in part overwhelming and unreadable, enigmatic and formative.” (GAO 70). From the very beginning of its life the newborn child is delivered to the care of the other, because of it being an embodied subject. As such our existence is fundamentally marked by a dimension of radical passivity and inescapable susceptibility that relates to the frailty of our body rather than to our dependency on the order of language. The condition of being a premature being makes that our body has “its invariably public dimension” (PL 26). This ontogenetic account of the impossibility to have full control of our own existence gives Butler indeed a way to depart from the Lacanian anthropology. She works this intuition out in dialogue with Levinas and particulary in relation to his analysis of the subjectivity, which is revealed in the ethical encounter. So, whereas Laplanche gives a historical account of finitude, the same dimension is analysed by Levinas in more structural terms: an ungraspable attachment that predates all meaning-giving intentionality but that constitutes time and again who we are at this very moment of speaking. Subjectivity can’t utterly be identified with the intentionality of the subject, but refers to a deeper dimension of passiveness that constitutes our own individualities. This dimension is first revealed when we are appealed by the question the naked face of the other poses to me (and not to someone else). So, in Butlers latest work the philosophy of Levinas appears as a source of inspiration to rethink moral responsibility in terms of dispossession of ourselves. I think she is particularly interested in his position because within Levinas’s perspective the starting point for morality has to do with the vulnerability of the flesh. It seems to me that she uses Levinas here first of all because of his very powerful description of this state of vulnerability, rather than as a companion in the search for a ground in the name of which responsibility becomes legitimate. Vulnerability rather refers to an experience of not being able to find this kind of grounding principle. It even commits us to the abstinence of longing to search for such a transcendental principle. We become deaf to this concern. In the experience of corporeal susceptibility we may come to relate to ourselves in a way that we forsake the will to ground our own being and the desire to find a definitive justification for the right kind of ethics or pedagogy. The experience of bodily susceptibility moves us literally out of position. In this light the body isn’t to be described as a metaphysical principle or primordial force in the name of which one should criticize existing forms of life and could ground an alternative way of living. Thus the experience Butler refers to comes near to the concept of limit-experience I described above: exposure through the body is not about the finding of a (forgotten or repressed) positive essence, but confronts us with a void, with a difficulty we cannot escape and where we nevertheless have to relate to. “If I am wounded, I find that the wound testifies to the fact that I am impressionable, given over to the other in ways that I cannot fully predict or control.” (GAO 84) We cannot deny that something happens to us, that something is disclosed in spite of ourselves. In the same experience we feel a kind of commitment we cannot justify. So, this (possible) commitment doesn’t depend on the acceptance of a firm ground: in this sense it is really a desubjectivizing experience. This insight is well captured in the citation of Blanchot that Butler quotes to introduce her chapter on Levinas in Giving an Account of Oneself: “Levinas speaks of the subjectivity of the subject. If one wishes to use this word – why? But why not? – one ought perhaps to speak of a subjectivity without a subject: the wounded space, the hurt of the dying, the already dead body which no one could ever own, or ever say of it, I, my body” (cited in GAO 84). I think that Blachot’s remark is very much to the point. At issue is how to interpret it. As I see it, one might give the following readings of his quote: (1) In her own consideration of Levinas in Giving an Account of Oneself Butler seems to fall back on the biological vision of subjectivity, i.e. the “spinozistic” anthropology I criticised earlier. Consider the following quote: Violence […] delineates a physical vulnerability from which we cannot slip away, which we cannot finally resolve in the name of the subject, but which can provide a way to understand that non of us is fully bounded, utterly separate, but, rather, we are in our skins, given over, in each other’s hand, at each other’s mercy” (GOA 101). The experience of dispossession that should awaken in us an alternative sense of responsibility seems here to become reduced to the mere physical or biological sense of vulnerability. For reasons I will not repeat here, this seems rather problematic. (2) One could of course, as Thomas Keenan does in his study Fables of Responsibility, stress that Blanchot means with this anonymity first and for all a radicalized version of Levinas’s figure of “the hostage”: the tragedy of the election by the other is that I am not special or unique, as I realise that anyone else could have been made responsible. Only because I was at the right place at the right time I was addressed. The cry for help from the other was thus not specifically “addressed to me in particular, not to anyone in particular, but to me as anyone”21. It’s precisely this anonymity which implicates me as responsible subject. The problem with this line of thought is of course that any reference to corporeal vulnerability is missing. (3) Therefore I would like to give another interpretation of this quote of Blanchot, stressing the anonymity of the body in question. What I offer here is only an intuition which should be explored much more in depth. In this reading I am very much indebted to the brilliant analyses of corporeal reality Alphonso Lingis offers e.g. in his book “The Imperative”22. Firstly one might link this anonymity with Levinas’s phenomenological analyses of pain and suffering in his earlier writings: contrary to Heidegger, he argues that pain and the experience of approaching death 21 Keenan, T. (1997), Fables of Responsibility. Aberrations and Predicaments in Ethics and Politics, Stanford (Stanford University Press) 22 Lingis, A. (1998), The Imperative, Bloomington (Indiana University Press). don’t awake in us a strengthened sense of singularity; these experiences rather depersonalize us. Pain immobilizes us, we cannot react, we are the passive witness of our own disability to react in a meaningful way. At the same time suffering gets a political significance – as Butler would also claim : “To look upon someone who is in pain is to know what it is. We do not simply see the pallid surfaces, the contorted hands and fingers; we feel a depth of pain. […] Suffering is a bond with others. One does not suffer without understanding that others suffer, understanding how others suffer. […] We are repelled but also drawn to the pain another suffers. It awakens in us a will to struggle with that pain. […] Then we understand that the passivity and prostration and depersonalisation of suffering that mires me in my own substance do not isolate me. If I suffer as one suffers, as anyone, everyone suffers, it is also true that the others are there, to act, to help, to heal, or to stay with me when no healing is possible.”23 I wonder whether one could relate this bodily anonymity with Merleau-Ponty’s concept of the “flesh of the world” and his characterization of human relationality as intercorporeality24. Of course one should refrain from falling back on these concepts as transcendental principles in the name of which “the right kind of pedagogy” could be legitimised. 23 Lingis, A. (2000), “To Die with Others”, Diacritics 30 (3), p. 106-113: p. 110. 24 Butler makes this link with Merleau-Ponty herself, e.g. in an endnote in one of her most recent texts (UG: 15, endnote 7). Although she criticised Merleau-Ponty, especially in her earlier work, for his essentialist and masculine conception of the body, he seems to stay one of Butler privileged, though not often mentioned, dialogue partners. Merleau-Ponty states, in opposition to the Cartesian view of man, that our body isn’t a mere instrument consciousness uses to relate to the world. We are our body, in the sense that all meaningful phenomena are constituted in accordance with a particular bodily perspective and its habitual schemes. This however doesn’t mean that we have a full grasp of our body. And because we are our body, it is this corporeal condition that constitutes us as nontransparant creatures. Opacity resides in the body. Furthermore this condition grants the possibility of intersubjectivity, as we are all in our very existence dependent upon what “the flesh of the world”. I have no place to elaborate this considerations further here, but hope to do so in another article. See also: Meyer-Drawe, K (1984)., Leiblichkeit und Sozialität. Phänomenologische Beiträge zu einer pädagogischen Theorie der Inter-Subjectivität, München (Wilhelm Fink Verlag). To conclude my reflections, I would like to relate all this to the problem of the public dimension of education. Granted that we should look for critical possibilities which do not relate to the strengthening of or own position, I think a more elaborated description of corporeal vulnerability in experiential categories, and more particular in terms of the anonymity of the flesh (or intercorporeality), might help us to look in another way to the public dimension of education. In any case it could contribute to a concept of “the public sphere” which is no longer to be thought of in reference to subject-positions, be it my own position that has to be protected at any price, or be it the position of the other which should at all cost be safeguarded. Consequentially it might also offer an alternative for a discourse which is very popular nowadays: thinking of criticality in terms of the unconditional will to respect the other in her otherness, in terms of the opening of ourselves to the alterity of the vulnerable other (the child, the stranger, etc.). “The public” that is at issue in Blanchot’s quote and which seems for Butler to be a most relevant alternative for commonly accepted theories of (inter)subjectivity, seems to refer to a dimension of vulnerability which first of all has to do with the experience of a “subjectivity without a subject” which is experienced in the anonymity of the flesh. References Biesta, G. (2006), Beyond Learning. Democratic Education for a Human Future, Boulder (Paradigm) Butler, J. (1990), Gender Trouble:Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, New York (Routledge) Butler, J. (1993), Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of sex, New York (Routledge) Butler, J. (1997), Excitable Speech: a Politics of the Performative, New York (Routledge) Butler, J. (1997), The Psychic Life of Power, Stanford (Stanford University Press) Butler, J. (2002), What is Critique? On Foucault’s Virtue, in Ingram, D. (Ed.), The Political, Oxford (Blackwell), p. 212-226 Butler, J. (2004), Violence, Precarious Life. The Powers of Mourning and Violence, Londen (Verso) Butler, J., (2004) Beside Oneself: On the Limits of Sexual Autonomy in Butler, J., Undoing Gender, New York (Routledge) Butler, J. (2005), Giving an Account of Oneself, New York (Fordham University Press) Foucault, M. (1984), What is Enlightenment?, in Rabinow, P. (Ed.) The Foucault Reader. New York: Pantheon, pp.32-50. Gros, F., Le souci de soi chez Michel Foucault. A review of ‘The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-1982’, Philosophy and Social Criticism 31, 5-6 (2005), p. 697708 Keenan, T. (1997), Fables of Responsibility. Aberrations and Predicaments in Ethics and Politics, Stanford (Stanford University Press) Lingis, A. (1998), The Imperative, Bloomington (Indiana University Press) Lingis, A. (2000), “To Die with Others”, Diacritics 30 (3), p. 106-113 Masschelein, J., Ricken, N. (2003), Do We (Still) Need the Concept of Bildung? In Educational Philosophy and Theory 35 (2), p. 139-154 Masschelein, J. (2004) How to conceive of a critical theory today?, Journal of Philosophy of Education”38 (3), p. 351-367 Meyer-Drawe, K (1984)., Leiblichkeit und Sozialität. Phänomenologische Beiträge zu einer pädagogischen Theorie der Inter-Subjectivität, München (Wilhelm Fink Verlag) Mourad, R., After Foucault. A new form of right, Philosophy and Social Criticism 29 (4), p. 451-481 Olssen, M. , Foucault and the Imperatives of Education. Critique and Self-creation in a Nonfoundational World, in Studies in Philosophy and Education 25 (2006), p. 245-271 Thompson, C. (2006), Adorno and the Borders of Experience: The Significance of the Nonidentical for a ‘different’ Theory of Bildung, Educational Theory 56(1), p. 69-87