Piketty's laws and logic - BI Norwegian Business School

advertisement
Working Paper Series 7/14
PIKETTY’S LAWS AND LOGIC
Torgeir Høien
SKAGEN Funds
August 2014
Centre for Monetary Economics
BI Norwegian Business School
ISSN 1503-3031
CENTRE FOR MONETARY ECONOMICS
Piketty’s laws and logic
Torgeir Høien
August 2014
ABSTRACT:
Thomas Piketty’s Capital in the Twenty-First Century is a valuable contribution to the history of wealth and
income distribution. But Piketty’s theory about wealth and income distribution as encapsulate in his laws of
capitalism leaves much to be desired. One of the laws is devoid of substance, the others are convoluted
reformulations of relationships that have been known for a long time. And neither of them have any
bearing on the distribution of wealth and income. Also, Piketty’s use of logical terms is at times obscure, as
when he talks about “contradictions” in capitalism. Thus, Piketty’s laws are irrelevant for his predictions,
and his logical vocabulary is deceptive.
Portfolio Manager, SKAGEN Funds, Stavanger, Norway. I’ve benefitted from Debray Ray’s transparent discussion of
Piketty’s book in his «Nit-Piketty», New York University, May 23 2014. Thanks to Arne Jon Isachsen, Espen Henriksen
and colleagues for commenting on an earlier draft of the note. Errors and omissions are my responsibility.
Contents
The laws
.................................................................................................................
3
The logical vocabulary ...............................................................................................
7
Conclusion .................................................................................................................
9
The laws
In Capital in the Twenty-First Century Thomas Piketty states three “fundamental laws of capitalism”.
What do these laws say and imply?1
The first law says that the ratio of capital income to national income equals the rate of return on the
capital stock multiplied by the ratio of the capital stock to national income. (p. 52).
National income is GDP minus depreciation plus net foreign income during a period, e.g. 2014. The
capital stock is the market value of all potentially marketable wealth. That is, capital goods, land, houses,
and net financial claims on foreigners, at a point in time, e.g. Dec. 31 2013.2
The rate of return on the capital stock is capital income/capital stock. Hence, the first law states that:
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘
=
∙
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒
Simple fractional algebra reduces this equation to 1 = 1. Now, while it might be useful to be reminded of
the Aristotelian law of identity, only a disciple of Ayn Rand might be tempted to assert that capitalism
rests on the fact that, ontologically speaking, a = a, i.e. “a thing is what it is”. And it’s not my impression
that Piketty is a Randian.
The second law says that in the long run the ratio of the capital stock to national income equals the ratio
of net savings rate to the growth rate of national income. (p. 166).
Net savings is the addition to the capital stock between two points in time, e.g. the capital stock on Dec.
31 2014 minus the capital stock on Dec. 31 2013. That is, it is gross savings minus depreciation.
Ignoring capital gains, as Piketty does, the net savings rate equals the capital stock growth divided by
national income, e.g. savings in 2014 is: 3
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2014 − 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014
The growth rate of national income is national income one year minus national income the previous
year divided by national income the previous year, e.g. the growth rate in 2014 is:
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014 − 𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013
1
Strictly speaking: two laws and a “fundamental contradiction of capitalism”. See below.
While Piketty includes houses, he excludes other consumer durables, like cars and television sets – presumably
because one does not pay taxes on such durables after they are purchased and such goods are not counted as
wealth in national accounts.
3
I ignore the fact that the capital stock grows continuously during the year, not just on the last day of the year.
This has no implication for the results.
2
3
Assume we are in the long run, i.e. when the economy has adapted to any shocks, and Piketty’s second
law applies. Using the definitions above, the second law states that: 4
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
=
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2014 − 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014 − 𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013
Now, if both sides are multiplied by (national income 2014/capital stock Dec. 31 2013), the second law
becomes:
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2014 − 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
1=
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014 − 𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013
Multiply both sides by (national income 2014 – national income 2013)/national income 2013. Piketty’s
second law can then be written as:
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014 − 𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2014 − 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
=
𝑛𝑎𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2013
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
In other words: Piketty’s second law states that in the long run the growth rate of national income = the
growth rate of the capital stock. And that’s it.
There is nothing new here. The second law has been a standard prediction of economic models since
Solow’s seminal 1956 paper on economic growth. Note that this equation does not imply that the
growth of national income is determined by the growth of the capital stock, or vice versa.
The third law, which Piketty doesn’t call a “law” but “the central contradiction of capitalism” – more on
this later – says that the rate of return on capital is higher than the growth rate of national income. (p.
351).5
The return on capital is capital income. The rate of return on capital is capital income/capital stock. Since,
according to the second law, the growth rate of national income equals the growth rate of the capital
stock, this inequality says that:
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2014 − 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
>
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
If both sides of the inequality are multiplied by capital stock Dec. 31 2013, the inequality becomes:
𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑖𝑛𝑐𝑜𝑚𝑒 2014 > 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2014 − 𝑐𝑎𝑝𝑖𝑡𝑎𝑙 𝑠𝑡𝑜𝑐𝑘 𝐷𝑒𝑐. 31 2013
Here I’ve benefitted from Ray’s illumination of the second law.
This is also a standard prediction of established models of economic growth, as noted by Ray and other
commentators.
4
5
4
In other words, Piketty’s “central contradiction of capitalism” says that capital income during a period is
higher than net savings. Since capital income is net of depreciation, this implies that a part of capital
income is consumed.
That the rate of return on capital is higher than the growth rate of national income is, as noted by Ray
and other commentators, a prediction of established economic theory. Hence there is nothing new in
Piketty’s inequality.
Why do standard models predict that the rate of return on the capital stock is higher than the growth
rate of national income? Without going into the detail: if the rate of return on capital is lower than the
rate of growth of national income, the economy uses too many resources to accumulate new capital.
Consumption now and in the future can then be increased by saving less. With a slower growth rate of
the capital stock, the marginal productivity of capital services rises, lifting r above g.
Some commentators have hailed Piketty’s “central contradiction of capitalism” as the Holy Grail of new
political economy. Professor Gudmund Hernes compares Piketty’s “central contradiction of capitalism”
to Einstein’s E = MC². This, to put it mildly, is an exaggeration. Piketty is no Einstein. But, as Rays writes,
Piketty’s inquiry has established that a standard prediction of economic theory has been correct over
long time spans – but with the past century as an exception. Thus, Piketty and his collaborators might, if
we are generous, be compared to Arthur Eddington who, during a total solar eclipse in 1919, confirmed
one implication of Einstein’s general theory of relativity – that the sun deflects light.
How does all of this underpin Piketty’s main thesis, which states that we are at the dawn of a new area
of high and growing inequality?
The first law is obviously irrelevant for anything. The second law implies that the capital stock in the long
run will not grow faster than national income, i.e. that the ratio of the capital stock to national income
remains constant. This does not have any bearing on the distribution of the capital stock or national
income. The third law, known as r > g, with r for the rate of return on capital and g for the growth rate of
national income, also does not have any repercussions for the distribution of the capital stock or
national income. If anyone thinks otherwise it must be that they read r > g as implying that the growth
rate of capital income is higher than the growth rate of national income.
That’s not the case; r is the rate of return on capital, not the growth rate of capital income. In fact, r > g,
implies constant labor and capital shares of national income. How large the shares are, however,
depends upon the size of the gap between r and g. Thus, contrary to what Piketty claims, r > g does not
lead to growing inequality. Inequality only spirals if the difference between r and g continuously
increases – and if the distribution of labor and capital income is uneven among households.
An example might clarify:
Suppose that national income in Petitistan was USD 97.09 in 2013. Capital income was USD 29.13 and
labor income was USD 67.96. Suppose that Petitistan’s capital stock on Dec 31. 2013 was USD 600.
Assume that r is 5 and g is 3 during 2014, i.e. the rate of return on the capital stock is 5 percent in 2014
5
and the growth of national income is 3 percent from 3013 to 2014. How does capital income then evolve
relative to labor income?
5 percent of USD 600 is USD 30. Thus capital income increases 3 percent from 2013 to 2014, the same as
national income, which is USD 100 in 2014. Labor income in 2014 is USD 100 minus USD 30, i.e. USD 70,
a growth rate of 3 percent. Despite that r > g, therefore, both capital and labor income grow at the same
pace as national income, i.e. 3 percent.
Whatever happens to the stock of capital depends upon savings.
According to Piketty’s second law, and standard economic theory, the growth rate of capital is equal to
the growth rate of national income. 3 percent of USD 600 is USD 18. Thus the stock of capital increases
to USD 618 on Dec. 31 2014. This satisfies the condition we got by combining the second and third laws,
that capital income is greater than savings. If r remains at 5 and g remains at 3, the story repeats itself in
2015. The return on capital is USD 30.9, an increase of 3 percent. National income rises to USD 103.
Labor income is USD 103 minus USD 30.9, i.e. USD 72.1 – an increase of 3 percent.
But what if r rises to 6 in 2015 while g remains 3? Then capital income in 2015 is USD 37.08, an increase
of 23.6 percent. With national income at USD 103, labor income drops to USD 65.92, i.e. a 5.8 percent
decrease. Thus the functional distribution of income is altered in favor of capital income and to the
detriment of labor income. Suppose that thereafter the capital stock grows at the same rate as national
income. Then the capital stock is USD 636.54 on Dec. 31 2015. What if both r and g remain at 6 and 3 in
2016? Capital income increases to USD 38.19 in 2016, an increase of 3 percent, which is equal to the
growth rate of national income. Thus labor income also rises 3 percent in 2016.
Importantly, therefore, the year after the shift in the capital and labor share of national income when
the gap between r and g widens, the functional income distribution is constant.
The effect is equivalent if g drops for a given r. One only gets a one-time level effect on the distribution
of income from a change in the r > g inequality. Contrary to what many seem to think, Pikettys “central
contradiction of capitalism” does not predict a continuously decreasing labor to capital income ratio.
In order to get a workers’ dystopia, where laborers get a continuously smaller pie of national income, the
gap between the rate of return on the capital stock and the growth rate of national income must widen
constantly – and only capitalists must save.
Admittedly, while Piketty does not state the third law this way, his predictions for this and the next
century rest on assumptions that the rate of return on capital gradually rises and that the rate of growth
of national income gradually falls. (pp. 356-357). Whether these assumptions, which are not grounded in
a coherent theory, are reasonable, is beyond the remit of this paper.
I don’t quarrel with Piketty’s forecasts about income distribution if the future. My point is that his laws
have no bearing on his predictions, implying that they are no more than speculations.
6
Piketty, who laments the use of mathematics in economics, should have dropped two equations and
one inequality from his mighty tome. To support his main thesis he needs a different theory than what’s
encapsulated in his laws. Piketty’s verbal reasoning might contain the gist of such a theory. But his laws
and his “central contradiction in capitalism” are likely to share the fate of Keynes’ “fundamental
equations”. Keynes put forth these equations, which purported to explain national income and the price
level in his two-volume A Treatise of Money in 1930. They quickly dropped in economists’ memory hole.
The Keynesianism we remember is the one he formulated in his General Theory of Employment, Interest,
and Money in 1936.
The logical vocabulary
As mentioned, Piketty refrains from calling his third law a “law”. He instead refers to it as the “central
contradiction of capitalism”. On page 571 he writes “this inequality [r > g] expresses a fundamental
logical contradiction”.
This is an idiosyncratic use of the word “contradiction”, derived, probably, via Piketty’s reading of Marx
from the scribbling of Hegel. In logic a contradiction is a statement, or a theory, that’s necessarily false,
i.e. false no matter how the world works. Piketty clearly does not mean that r > g is necessarily false. On
the contrary, he thinks that the inequality is correct and that it has dire consequences for capitalistic
income distribution. It’s these consequences, which might undermine the public support for capitalism,
which he misleadingly refers to as a “contradiction”.
Capitalism is not a theory, it’s an economic system. There might be a flurry of contradictions in theories
about capitalism, but to claim that capitalism as an economic system is contradictory just breed
confusion. The same sort of confusion Ludwig von Mises sowed when he, three years after the Bolshevik
revolution, said that “socialism was impossible”.6
Piketty’s first law is the identity 1 = 1. Viewed semantically, i.e. as a proposition, it is the opposite of a
contradiction. It’s a statement, or a theory, which is necessarily true no matter how the world works.
Logicians call such propositions tautologies.
Piketty himself describe his first law is tautological. But it “should nevertheless be regarded as the first
fundamental law of capitalism, because it expresses a simple, transparent relationship among the three
most important concepts for analyzing the capitalist system: the capital/income ratio, the share of
capital in income, and the rate of return on capital”. (p. 52). I think it is just the opposite. Writing α = r x
β instead of 1 = 1 alienates more than in illuminates.
Tautologies do have their place in logic and mathematics, where all valid theorems, no matter how hard
they are to prove, are tautological. Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead, when they deduced
6
In fairness to von Mises: that «socialism is impossible» is how his phrasing is usually remembered. What he
actually wrote in 1920 was that ‘’rational economic activity is impossible in a socialist commonwealth’’.
7
mathematics from logic in Principia Mathematica, arrived at the “occasionally useful” proposition that
“1 +1 = 2” on page 86 in volume two.
Outside of logic and mathematics, however, the usefulness of tautologies is limited. Tautologies are
used when a new empirical or theoretical phenomenon is given a name, as when the existence of a new
elementary particle, subsequently named the Higgs boson, was suggested in 1964. But such definitions
are of course never elevated to the status of scientific laws.
I’m not sure if Piketty has a clear notion of what a tautology is. He criticizes the role of time preference
in the standard theory of the rate of return on capital for being tautological, writing that “this ‘theory’,
like many theoretical models in economics, is somewhat tautological (one can always explain any
behavior by assuming that the actors involved have preferences – or ‘utility functions’ in the jargon of
economics – that lead them to act the way).” (p. 359).
But this does not describe the way economists use the concept of preferences, whether it’s preferences
for goods during a period, or preferences for goods in one period relative to the next, to explain
behavior. On the contrary, since preferences are unobservable, economists assume that preferences are
constant. Economists then predict altered behavior when observable parameters, like prices, change.
Since Paul Samuelson and Milton Friedman wrote about economic methodology in the late 1940s and
early 1950s, this conception of economics has been mainstream.
Moreover, even if a change in behavior were to be is explained by a change in preferences, one would
not thereby engage in tautological reasoning.
Asserting that an increase in the rate of return on the capital stock is due to an increased preference for
goods now relative to later, for example, is not tautological since the two concepts don’t have the same
meaning. The problem is rather that since time preferences are unobservable, such a prediction cannot
be checked against empirical evidence. Economists, therefore, abstain from such explanations.
Interestingly, Piketty himself violates this methodological norm when he discusses the rise of labor
income among top managers. Dismissing the idea that increased compensation is due to higher marginal
productivity, he asserts that top managers lay claim on a larger share of national income due to altered
social norms. (pp. 332-333).
It’s difficult to define social norms without referring to common preferences for acceptable behavior.
Thus explaining increasing wage inequality by referring to altered social norms is, as I understand it, an
explanation in terms of shifting preferences. Admittedly, Piketty writes that in order to explain a change
in social norms one has to draw on expertise outside of economics. But he does not elaborate on how
evidence from such expertise supports his thesis. Anyway, while Pikettys explanation of higher wages to
top managers doesn’t follow established economic methodology, I wouldn’t characterize his reasoning
as tautological. Not all problematic aspects of economic analysis boils down to tautological thinking.
The notion of laws, let alone “fundamental laws” in economics, that Piketty exposes, is also dubious.
8
Logically, science attempts to produce novel and falsifiable hypotheses that correctly predict empirical
phenomena. Repeatedly non-falsified, but falsifiable, hypotheses might gain the status of scientific laws
in fields like physics. But since it, due to a lack of controlled experiments among other things, typically is
beyond the reach to conclusively test hypothesis in the social sciences, one should refrain from calling
an economic hypothesis – or any hypothesis about human behavior – a law.
Even the best candidates for economic laws fail. The existence of Giffen goods falsifies the law that
demand is a decreasing function of price. At best, economics can establish statistical generalizations that
normally hold, like the proposition that r > g.
Conclusion
While there is much to admire in Pikettys voluminous book, especially his data-driven discussion of
wealth and income inequality in previous centuries, his attempt to predict the evolution of inequalities
in this century and the next is unconvincing. Hence when Paul Krugman, in his review of the book said
that Piketty “offers what amounts to a unified field theory of inequality”, he engaged in hyperbole.
Piketty’s theoretical framework, upon closer inspection, turns out to be a castle of sand, at least to the
extent the theory is capsuled in two equations and one inequality. If there is more to Pikettys theory
than these three mathematical expressions exposes, and there might be, then he should do what
Keynes did after his failed 1930 book, and write a new, more convincing one.
By claiming to have discovered the two fundamental laws and the central contradiction of capitalism in
three convoluted mathematical expressions, and by his idiosyncratic use of logical vocabulary, Piketty
exemplifies simultaneously what Jon Elster respectively has called hard and soft obscurantism. Is this
what happens when a French intellectual has a stint as a professor at a “university near Boston” (p. 31)?
9
Working Paper Series
1/10
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Finanskrisen – Konsekvenser for USA
2/10
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Korrupsjon i Kina – Kommet for å bli?
3/10
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Om spekulasjon i valutamarkedet
4/10
Steigum, Erling
Norsk økonomi etter 1980 – fra krise til suksess
5/10
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Fortellinger om samfunnet
6/10
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Hva Kina vil
7/10
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Kinas makt
1/11
Børsum, Øystein
Exchange Rate Risk in the Government Pension Fund Global
2/11
Isachsen Arne Jon
Penge- og valutapolitikk i Kina
3/11
Alstadheim Ragna
Om nye virkemidler i pengepolitikken – avgrensning mellom pengepolitikken og
finanspolitikken
4/11
Isachsen Arne Jon
Økonomi er risikosport
5/11
Steigum Erling
The Norwegian Banking Crisis in the 1990s: Effects and Lessons
6/11
Isachsen Arne Jon
Felles valuta krever felles vaner
1/12
Isachsen Arne Jon
Is China Falling Apart?
2/12
Isachsen Arne Jon
På vandring
3/12
Nerheim, Reidun Grue
Investeringsstrategien for statens pensjonsfond utland
4/12
Steigum, Erling
Sovereign wealth funds for macroeconomic purposes
1/13
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Bollinger champagne
CME
Centre for Monetary Economics, BI Norwegian Business School
Office Manager: Siv Bjercke
Address: Nydalsveien 37, N-0484 Oslo, Norway
Phone +47 46 41 07 91. Fax +47 46 41 08 01.
E-mail: cme@bi.no
http://www.cme.no
ISSN 1503-3031
Working Paper Series
2/13
Mork, Knut Anton
Etter oljen: Utfordringer for norsk økonomi
3/13
Andersen, Torben M.
Finanspolitik og den økonomiske og monetære union
4/13
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Bank og Finans – Hva har hendt? Og hva har vi lært?
5/13
Utne, Amund
EØS-avtalen
6/13
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Stabilt eller robust?
7/13
Bjørnland, Hilde C. and Leif Anders Thorsrud
Ringvirkninger
Norsk økonomi og olje
8/13
Isachsen, Arne Jon
De gamle er eldst
1/14
Steigum, Erling and Øystein Thøgersen
A crisis not wasted – Institutional and structural reforms behind Norway’s strong
macroeconomic performance
2/14
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Ulikhetens pris
3/14
Høien, Torgeir
Nibor-mysteriet
4/14
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Noen betraktninger om Oljefondet
5/14
Isachsen, Arne Jon
Bank og pølsebod – Hva er forskjellen?
6/14
Aamdal, Kyrre
NIBOR – Intet mysterium
7/14
Høien, Torgeir
Piketty’s laws and logic
CME
Centre for Monetary Economics, BI Norwegian Business School
Office Manager: Siv Bjercke
Address: Nydalsveien 37, N-0484 Oslo, Norway
Phone +47 46 41 07 91. Fax +47 46 41 08 01.
E-mail: cme@bi.no
http://www.cme.no
ISSN 1503-3031
Norges Bank Watch Report Series
No 1/2000
Hamilton, Carl , Øystein Thøgersen, Marianne Andreassen
og Harald Magnus Andreassen
Norsk pengepolitikk, Norges Banks rolle og bankens gjennomføring av
pengepolitikken i 1999 og første del av 2000
No 2/2001
Andreassen, Harald Magnus, Paul De Grauwe, Haakon Solheim
and Øystein Thøgersen
A review of inflation targeting, the Norwegian monetary regime and its
institutional arrangements and Norges Bank’s actual monetary policy and
communication
No 3/2002
Svensson, Lars E. O., Kjetil Houg, Haakon O. Aa. Solheim
and Erling Steigum
An Independent Review of Monetary Policy and Institutions in Norway
No 4/2003
Ekeli, Thomas, Anne Kari Haug, Kjetil Houg and Erling Steigum
An Independent Review of Monetary Policy in Norway.
No 5/2004
Bjørnland, Hilde C., Thomas Ekeli, Petra M. Geraats and Kai Leitemo
An Independent Review of Monetary Policymaking in Norway.
No 6/2005
Dørum, Øystein, Steinar Holden and Arne Jon Isachsen
An Independent Review of Monetary Policymaking in Norway.
No 7/2006
Dørum, Øystein and Steinar Holden
An Independent Review of Monetary Policymaking in Norway.
No 8/2007
Goodfriend Marvin, Mork Knut Anton and Söderström Ulf
An Independent Review of Monetary Policymaking in Norway.
No 9/2008
Juel Steinar, Molnar Krisztina and Røed Knut
An Independent Review of Monetary Policymaking in Norway.
No 10/2009
Bergman Michael, Juel Steinar and Steigum Erling
Monetary Policy and the Financial Turmoil.
No 11/2010
Bjørnland Hilde C., Clarida Richard, Holvik Elisabeth and Steigum Erling
An Independent Evaluation of Monetary Policy in Norway.
No 12/2011
Bjørnland Hilde C. and Wilhelmsen Bjørn Roger
An Independent Evaluation of Monetary Policy in Norway.
No 13/2012
Torvik Ragnar, Vredin Anders and Wilhelmsen Bjørn Roger
An Independent Evaluation of Monetary Policy in Norway.
No 14/2013
Boye Katrine Godding and Sveen Tommy
An Independent Evaluation of Monetary Policy in Norway.
No 15/2014
Mork Knut Anton, Freixas Xavier and Aamdal Kyrre
An Independent Evaluation of Monetary Policy in Norway.
CME
Centre for Monetary Economics, BI Norwegian Business School
Office Manager: Siv Bjercke
Address: Nydalsveien 37, N-0484 Oslo, Norway
Phone +47 46 41 07 91. Fax +47 46 41 08 01.
E-mail: cme@bi.no
http://www.cme.no
ISSN 1503-3031
Download