The Democratic Paradox of Campaign Finance Reform Author(s): Daniel R. Ortiz Source: Stanford Law Review, Vol. 50, No. 3, (Feb., 1998), pp. 893-914 Published by: Stanford Law Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1229326 Accessed: 02/07/2008 11:04 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=slr. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org TheDemocraticParadoxof Campaign FinanceReform DanielR. Ortiz* Campaignfinance reformrests on a centralfear: thatpolitical actors will converteconomicadvantageintopoliticalpower. However,thisfear assumesa failure of normativedemocratictheory. If voters thinkthroughpolitical decisions in the way democratictheoryassumes-by exercisinginformed,careful, independentjudgment-economic inequalitiesamong candidatesshould make little differenceto the outcomeof elections. Reform,then,is premisedon doubt about voters'-or at least some voters'-civic capabilities. This is the democraticparadox of campaignfinance reform. Thisarticle reveals thisparadox and traces similaritiesbetweencampaignfinance reformand other types of regulationof thepoliticalprocess-some attractiveand some not. It concludes that the paradox is unavoidableand, althoughdiscomforting,should be made transparent.For onlyby confrontingour democraticshortcomingscan we hope to overcomethem. INTRODUCTION Seldom have so many workedso hardand so long to accomplish so little. Despite enduringpopularsupport,campaignfinance reformhas had, at best, mixed success. Congress has moved slowly, when at all,' and has often enacted changes that are either cosmetic, easy to circumvent,or practicallyunenforceable.2 If a reform should actually threatento matter,the courts, par* JohnAllan Love Professorof Law and ElizabethD. and RichardA. MerrillResearchProfessor, Universityof VirginiaSchool of Law. I would especiallylike to thankPamelaS. Karlan and VincentA. Blasi for theirhelpfuland kindcriticismof an early draftof this article. I would also like to thankErikPritchardforhis researchassistance. 1. On the nationallevel, variousgroupshave pushedcampaignfinancereformever since the end of the nineteenthcentury. Congress'responsehas alwaysbeengrudging.For a comprehensive E. MUTCH, history of federal efforts at campaignfinance regulation,see generally ROBERT CAMPAIGNS,CONGRESS,AND COURTS:THE MAKINGOF FEDERALCAMPAIGNFINANCELAW (1988). Fora brieferrecounting,see generallyAnthonyCorrado,Moneyand Politics:A Historyof Federal Campaign Finance Law, in CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM:A SOURCEBOOK 25 (Anthony Corrado,ThomasE. Mann,DanielR. Ortiz,TrevorPotter& FrankSoraufeds., 1997) [hereinafter CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM]. 2. See Corrado,supra note 1, at 27-32 (detailingfaults of pre-Watergatelegislation). The Federal Election Campaign Act Amendments of 1974, Pub. L. No. 93-443, 88 Stat. 1263, are the great exception to this statement. See Daniel R. Ortiz, The First Amendment at Work: Constitutional Restrictions on Campaign Finance Regulation, in CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM,supra note 1,at61. 893 894 LAWREVIEW STANFORD [Vol. 50:893 ticularlythe United States SupremeCourt,have been quick to strike, leaving in their wake a patchworkframeworkthat Congress never would have enacted and that makes little sense.3 And to the extent courts do leave something meaningful behind, the available enforcementmechanisms are underfunded,hamstrungby political interference,and designed to deadlock.4 The states have been only slightly more successful. Several states have passed real reform measures,5often through initiative, only to have their hearts struck out by the courts.6 And state administrativeenforcement mechanismssuffer from many of the same problemsas their federal counterparts.7 The only source of optimism in the reform saga is the remarkable (and perhapsfoolish) tenacity of reformers. Over and over they returnto the fray, only to be disappointedonce again. The usual villains in the campaign finance story are the legislators who depend on private fundraisingto run their campaigns, the larger private interests that fund them, and the courts,particularlythe United States Supreme Court. In fact, nearly every discussion favoring reformattacksBuckleyv. 3. Buckleyv. Valeo,424 U.S. 1 (1976) (percuriam),is thebest examplehere. In thatcase, the SupremeCourtheld, among otherthings, that Congresscould limit contributionsto a candidate fromothers,but not fromthe candidatehimself. See id. at 23-29, 51-54. It is doubtfulthatCongress wouldhave ever agreedto treatthe one type morefavorablythanthe other,since the effect is to give rich challengersa strong advantageover less rich incumbents. Similarly,the Court in contributions to a candidate,but not independent Buckleyheld thatCongresscould limitthird-party expenditureson thatsamecandidate'sbehalf. See id. at 23-29, 39-51. Figureson both sides of the campaignfinancedebatecriticizethis distinctionas makinglittle sense. See ColoradoRepublican Fed. CampaignComm.v. FEC, 116 S. Ct. 2309, 2325-28 (1996) (Thomas,J., concurringin the judgmentand dissentingin part) (arguingagainstthe constitutionalityof limitingcontributions); Buckley,424 U.S. at 241-46 (Burger,J., concurringin partanddissentingin part)(arguingagainst the constitutionality of limitingcontributions); id. at 259-62 (White,J., concurringin partand disof limitingexpenditures). sentingin part)(arguingin favorof theconstitutionality 4. For a generaloverviewof the FEC'sabilityto enforceits mandate,see generallyThomas E. Mann,TheFederal ElectionCommission:Implementingand EnforcingFederal CampaignFinance Law, in CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM,supra note 1, at 275, and source materials excerpted there. The most pressing criticismsof the FEC's various structuralflaws appearin BROOKS WHYTHEFEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION FAILED23-37 (1990). JACKSON,BROKENPROMISE: 5. See generally AnthonyCorrado& Daniel R. Ortiz, Recent Innovations,in CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM,supra note 1, at 335 (describing the recent flurry of state reform efforts). 6. See, e.g., Carverv. Nixon, 72 F.3d 633 (8th Cir. 1995) (holdingunconstitutional Missouri to $100 to $300 per electioncycle), PropositionA, whichlimitedindividualcampaigncontributions cert. denied, 116 S. Ct. 2579 (1996); ShrinkMo. Gov't PAC v. Maupin,71 F.3d 1422 (8th Cir. two Missouristatutesthatlimitedspendingin stateoffice electoral 1995) (holdingunconstitutional campaignsand that prohibitedcarry-overof contributionsfrom one campaignto another),cert. denied, 116 S. Ct. 2579 (1996);Day v. Holahan,34 F.3d 1356 (8th Cir. 1994) (holdingunconstitutional Missouricampaignfinancereformlaws); Vannattav. Keisling, 899 F. Supp. 488 (D. Ore. 1995) (holdingunconstitutionalan Oregonballot measurethat limited the amountof campaign contributionsthatcandidatescouldacceptfromout-of-district donors). 7. See generally THOMASGAIS& MICHAELMALBIN,THEDAY AFTERREFORM:SOBERING CAMPAIGN FINANCELESSONSFROMTHEAMERICAN STATES(forthcoming 1998). February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 895 Valeo8as posing the centraldifficulty to campaignfinance reform.9 Buckley, I agree, is wrong. But I think there is a deeperproblemhere. The majorobstacle to campaign finance reform is not that the Supreme Court misunderstands the role of money in politics nor, more fundamentally,misinterprets the First Amendment,as many who favor regulationargue. Rather,the arguments advancedby the reformersthemselves are internallyincoherent. In a deep sense, those who argue for campaignfinance reformappearto violate democratictheory in the name of defendingit. All arguments favoring reform regard the regulation of campaign spending as necessary to protect liberal democracy.'0 Without such regulation, the argumentgoes, differentfeaturesof democraticpolitics will suffer. As I will show, however, despite theirvery differentviews of which features need protection,reformargumentsall rest on a single fear: that, left to themselves, various political actors will transformeconomic power into political power and thereby violate the democratic norm of equal political empowerment.'1To me, this fearmakes sense. Nevertheless, in the name of protecting democracy, these theories all violate one of democracy'scentralnormativeassumptions: the idea that voters are civically competent.12To the extent Americansare the kind of people that democratictheory demands-i.e., engaged, informed voters who carefully reason throughpolitical arguments-we hardly need the kind of protection that campaign finance regulationaffords us. Even if one side of a political race dramaticallyoutspendsthe other,voters can be relied on to sort through the merits and ultimately decide on the right candidate or policy. Only if many of us do not make decisions this way need we worry about the dangers of overspending. In other words, the equality-protectingand other rationales underpinning most forms of campaign finance regulation are premised on doubts about voters' civic capabilities. This is the democratic paradoxof campaignfinancereform. In the first section of this article, I lay the ground for this paradox. I show how, despite their seeming differences, all four leading justifications for campaign finance reform rest on a single fear: that campaign spending 8. 424 U.S. 1 (1976) (per curiam). 9. See, e.g., CASS R. SUNSTEIN,DEMOCRACY AND THEPROBLEMOF FREESPEECH94-101 AND THE PROBLEMOF FREE SPEECH];CASS R. (1993) [hereinafter SUNSTEIN,DEMOCRACY SUNSTEIN,THE PARTIALCONSTITUTION 84-85, 223-24 (1993); Ronald Dworkin, The Curse of American Politics, N.Y. REV. BOOKS,Oct. 17, 1996, at 19. 10. See text accompanying notes 14-33 infra. 11. See JOHNRAWLS,POLITICAL LIBERALISM 360-61 (1993); MICHAELWALZER,SPHERES OF JUSTICE22 (1983); Cass R. Sunstein, Political Equality and Unintended Consequences, 94 COLUM.L. REV. 1390, 1391-93 (1994). 12. For a general discussion of this tension between the demands of democratic theory and the civic capacities of average citizens, see MICHAELX. DELLICARPINI& SCOTTKEETER,WHAT AMERICANS KNOWABOUTPOLITICS ANDWHYITMATTERS22-61 (1996). 896 LAWREVIEW STANFORD [Vol. 50:893 can converteconomicintopoliticalpower. In the secondsection,I explain how this centralconcerndisappearsif votersare civicallycompetentin the I focuson a powertheoryassumes.Inparticular, waynormativedemocratic ful argumentthat RonaldDworkinhas recentlymade that democracyreforpeople'svotesto makea difference, quiresnot only an equalopportunity but also an equalopportunity for peopleto persuadeothersto theirviews.13 to persuade" means,I showthatit By unpackingwhatan "equalopportunity is premisedon a particularview of how votersmakepoliticaldecisions,a view whichis at oddswithnormativedemocratic theory. The thirdsectionexploresthe pedigreeof this belief in voters'civic incompetence. The belief goes back very far and underliesmany historical electoralpractices,includingpropertyqualifications, pauperexclusions,poll of certainracialand gendergroups,and taxes, outrightdisenfranchisement literacytests. Justas all of these now discreditedmechanismswere once defendedas ways of makingsurethatthe vote was independently exercised those who were of or onlyby capable understanding sufficientlycaringabout finance reformreflectssuspicionaboutvoters'abilityto politics,campaign exerciseindependent politicaljudgment. Whilethe older,now discredited, meansworkedby denyingthe vote to peoplewhose civic capabilitieswere suspect,campaignfinanceregulationworksby limitingthenumberandtypes of appealsthatpeoplecan maketo thesevoters'attention.Only if you believe thatpeopledo not exercisethe vote in the way democratictheorydemandswouldyou fearunconstrained appealsto them. Althoughwe have now repudiatedall thesepractices,it is importantto realizewhy. We have rejectedthemnot becausewe have come to believe theiraim of ensuringthe independentexerciseof politicaljudgmentis not worthpursuing-farfromit. We haverejectedthemonly becausewe have come to thinkthatsome peoplehad misappropriated thesepracticesto unexclude that were as as the rest of us of exercising justly groups just capable thiskindof judgment.Theircentraldemocratic aimremainsuntarnished. Thefourthsectionexploresa moreflatteringanalogybetweencampaign financereformandprohibitionsagainstvote trafficking.As I show, these two typesof reformareanalogousonly if we againbelievethatvotersmake politicaldecisionsin a way thatconflictswithnormativedemocratictheory. Forreformersto drawsupportfromthisanalogy,theymustfirstquestionthe civic capacitiesof manyof thevoterswhosechoicestheyaimto protect. The final section of the articleoutlinesa new strategyfor defending campaignfinanceregulation.This strategysees reformas imperativeprecisely becausedemocratictheoryis, in somedeepsense,utopian. Sincewe do not live up to the demandsthatnormativedemocratictheoryplaceson us, 13. See Dworkin,supranote 9, at 23-24. February1998] FINANCEREFORM CAMPAIGN 897 we shouldstoppretendingthatwe do andinsteaddesigninstitutionalstructures,includingcampaignfinanceregulations,to overcome,not ignore,our weaknesses. Seen from this perspective,democracywould functionas a regulativeideal ratherthanas a descriptionof reality. As such, campaign financeregulationwouldbe defendedas a meansof copingwith our civic incompetenciesratherthanas a practicenecessaryto protectthe civically competentfrombeingpreyeduponby advertising.Sucha provocativedebut it is morerealisticand andcontroversial, fense maybe bothunflattering less internallyconflictedthanits predecessors.At bottom,reformersmust rejectthe two alternativeassumptionsthatunderliemuchof everydaydiscourseaboutdemocracy:thatwe do notcarehow votersmaketheirpolitical decisionsor that,if we do care, votersmake sufficientlyindependent,informedjudgments. I. THE EVIL AT THE ROOT OF ALL MONEY Four seemingly differentconcernsmotivatecampaignfinance regulation. First,somereformersadvocateregulationas a meansto improvethe day-today operationof legislative politics. Vincent Blasi, for example, has argued that the need to keep representatives'eyes on theirjobs justifies some important campaign finance restrictions.14 Since elected representativesfeel they need to spend much time that could otherwise be spent on lawmaking raising money to protect their seats from challenge, they will devote too muchof theirenergyto tasksotherthanthosetheirconstituentselectedthem to do.'5 In this view, fundraisingis a form of shirking, which impairs the quality of the voters' representation.Blasi believes that the state has an importantinterest in representativesavoiding such behavior, an interest which 14. See VincentBlasi, Free Speechand the WideningGyreof Fund-Raising:WhyCampaign L. REV.1281, 1282SpendingLimitsMayNot Violatethe First Amendment AfterAll, 94 COLUM. 83 (1994). 15. As Blasi putsit: As difficultas thegeneralsubjectof representation canbe, one doesnot needa sophisticated of eitherrepublican understanding theoryor moder interestgrouppoliticsto concludethat there is a failure of representationwhen candidatesspend as much time as most of them now do attendingto the task of fund-raising. This featureof moder representationshould trouble those who favor close constituentcontrol as well as those who favor relative independencefor legislators;those who favor an "aristocracyof virtue"as well as those with more populist ideals regardingwho should serve; those who conceive of representationas flowing exclusively from geographicconstituenciesas well as those who see a role for constituenciesdefined along other lines, be they racial, ethnic, gender, economic, religious, or even ideological. Whatever it is that representativesare supposedto represent,whetherparochialinterests,the public good of the nation as a whole, or something in between, they cannot dischargethat representational function well if their schedules are consumed by the need to spend endless hours raising money and attendingto time demandsof those who give it. Id. at 1304 (footnotes omitted). 898 LAWREVIEW STANFORD [Vol. 50:893 supportssome regulationof money in politics, particularlythe imposition of campaignspendinglimits.16 Second, many argue that regulatingmoney in politics can help improve the quality of political discussion and debate. The two most notable proponents of this view, J. Skelly Wrightand Cass Sunstein,believe that appropriate regulationcan refocus political discourse on substantiveideas. Wright, for example, argues that unregulatedspending leads to people voting according to what he calls "intensities."17 When candidates spend huge amounts of money on mass advertising, he argues, voters will follow the louder ratherthan more thoughtfulvoice.18 He also believes that restraining spending would improve discussion by encouragingretail ratherthan mass, wholesale politics.19 To his mind, such a shift would mean that candidates would individually engage and address voters ratherthan treating them as mass consumersto be targetedwith affective advertisements,the same way a deodorantmanufacturerinterestedin increasingdemandfor its productmight view them. Similarly,Cass Sunsteinhopes that campaignfinance regulationwill improve political debate, but he focuses on legislative rather than electoral politics.20 As he puts it: Politicsshouldnot simplyregisterexistingpreferencesand theirintensities,especially as these are measuredby privatewillingnessto pay. In the American constitutionaltradition,politics has an importantdeliberativefunction. The constitutionalsystemaspiresto a formof "governmentby discussion." Grants of cash to candidatesmightcompromisethatgoal by, for example,encouraging legislaturesto vote in accordancewithprivateinterestratherthanreasons.21 By lessening the legislator's incentive to serve contributorsratherthan constituents, regulation may improve the chance that the legislature will function throughdiscussion, reason-giving, and debate. Thus, according to Wright and Sunstein, campaign finance regulation is necessary to improve 16. See id. at 1302-09. 17. J. Skelly Wright,Politics and the Constitution:Is MoneySpeech?, 85 YALEL.J. 1001, 1019 (1976). 18. See id. at 1018-20. 19. For example,in rejectingthe view thatrestrictingcontributionsand expenditureswill reducethe overallamountof politicalspeech,he writes: Thegivingandspendingrestrictions andotherindividualsto relymore maycausecandidates on less expensivemeansof communication. Butthereis no reasonto believethatsucha shift in meansreducesthenumberof issuesdiscussedin a campaign.And,by forcingcandidates to put moreemphasison localorganizingor leafletingor door-to-door canvassingandless on therestrictions full-pageadsandtelevisionspotcommercials, maywell generatedeeperexplorationof theissuesraised. Id. at 1012(footnoteomitted). 20. See Sunstein,supranote 11, at 1392(statingthat"[c]ampaignfinancelaws mightpromote the goal of ensuringpoliticaldeliberationandreason-giving"in the legislature). 21. Id. February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 899 the quality of political decisionmakingon both the elective and representative levels of democraticpolitics. Third, even more reformersargue that campaign finance regulationprotects the political process from direct, quid pro quo corruption. This view, like Sunstein's, maintains that, without some forms of regulation, particularly limitations on individual direct contributionsto political candidates, candidates become so beholden to contributorsthat they follow the contributors' rather than the voters' interests.22 Everyone, including the Supreme Court, agrees that this is a serious danger.23 The pivotal questions concern how great a danger it actually presents24and how well alternative means of regulation,like briberylaws, can controlit.25 Fourth,and most controversially,many reformersarguethat regulationis necessary to maintain political equality.26 These writers all start with the belief that democracydemandsformalequality in the political sphere. Some voters' candidatesmay win, some may lose, but each voter should have an equal chance to affect the ultimate decision. This principle representsthe democraticnorm of equal political entitlementand is reflected in such legal rules as one person, one vote,27the Fifteenth and Nineteenth Amendments, and the Voting Rights Act of 1965.28 This principle is, by now, an almost universally accepted tenet of our political culture, although it is, of course, subject to certain well-known exceptions that reflect some individuals' inability to properlyexercise choice. For example, the best known and probably least controversialexception is thatdenying childrenthe rightto vote.29 To this last group of reformers,problems arise from democracy's tolerance of great economic inequality.30The dangeris that some of the rich will 22. The anticorruption rationalediffersfromSunstein'sview, however,in thatit does not see debateand reason-givingas necessarilyrepresentingthe voters' interests. Theirinterestsmightbe which Sunsteinmightdecryas privateinterestsheld in common. undeliberative, 23. See FECv. NationalConservativePAC,470 U.S. 480, 496-97 (1985). This, in fact, was the single reformgoal the SupremeCourtupheldin Buckleyv. Valeo,424 U.S. 1, 26-27 (1976) (per curiam). 24. See BradleyA. Smith,FaultyAssumptionsand UndemocraticConsequencesof Campaign FinanceReform,105 YALEL.J. 1049, 1067-71(1996). 25. See Buckley,424 U.S. at 27-28 ("[L]awsmakingcriminalthe giving andtakingof bribes only deal with the mostblatantandspecificattemptsof thosewith moneyto influencegovernmental action.");see also ColoradoRepublicanFed. CampaignComm.v. FEC, 116 S. Ct. 2309, 232829 (1996) (Thomas,J., concurringin thejudgmentand dissentingin part)(discussingthe Court's view of briberylaws in Buckley). 26. See Sunstein,supranote 11, at 1392. 27. See Karcherv. Daggett,462 U.S. 725 (1983) (in the contextof federalapportionment); Reynoldsv. Sims, 377 U.S. 533 (1964) (in the contextof statelegislativeapportionment). 28. 42 U.S.C. ?? 1973-1973gg-10(1994). 29. See, e.g., CAL. CONST.art. II, ? 2; N.Y. CONST.art. II, ? 1; VA. CONST.art. II, ? 1. 30. See BruceAckerman,Creditingthe Voters:A New Beginningfor CampaignFinance, 13 AM. PROSPECT 71, 72 (1993). LAWREVIEW STANFORD 900 [Vol. 50:893 try to stretchtheireconomicadvantageinto the politicalsphere. If the rich do converteconomicintopoliticalpower,theyviolatethe normof equalpoliticalentitlement.Manyreformersbelievethatcampaignfinanceregulation is necessaryto helpkeepthe inequalityacceptedin the economicrealmfrom infectingpolitics,whereinequalityis not so tolerated.31Proposalslimiting individualspending,for example,areoftendefendedas a way of preventing influenceon politics.32 thewealthyfromexertinga disproportionate thisgeneralposition. He sees blindness RonaldDworkinbestarticulates as the fundamental problemwiththe SupremeCourt'scasesrestrictingcamBuckley.TheCourtsimplyfails to see paignfinanceregulation,particularly roles. As Dworkinexplains: one of a citizen'stwo democratic Citizens play two roles in a democracy. As voters they are, collectively, the final referees or judges of political contests. But they also participate, as individuals, in the contests they collectively judge: they are candidates, supporters, and political activists; they lobby and demonstrate for and against government measures, and they consult and argue about them with their fellow citizens.... [W]hen wealth is unfairly distributed and money dominates politics, then, though individual citizens may be equal in their vote and their freedom to hear the candidates they wish to hear, they are not equal in their own ability to command the attention of others for their own candidates, interests, and convictions. When the Supreme Court said, in the Buckley case, that fairness to candidates and their convictions is "foreign" to the First Amendment, it denied that such fairness was required by democracy. That is a mistake because the most fundamental characterization of democracy-that it provides self-government by the people as a whole-supposes that citizens are equals not only as judges but as participants as well. ... [Of course, n]o citizen is entitled to demand that others find his opinions persuasive or even worthy of attention. But each citizen is entitled to compete for that attention, and to have a chance at persuasion, on fair terms, a chance that is now denied almost everyone without great wealth or access to it.33 To Dworkin,democracyrequiresnotjust thatwe eachhavean equalsay in choosingamongcompetingcandidatesand positions-that is, an equal vote-but also thatwe eachhavean equalopportunity to persuadeothersto our own views aboutthese candidatesand issues. Unregulatedspending for it allowsthe richto makemoreappeals violatesthis secondrequirement, on behalfof theirviews thancanothers. Theseseeminglydisparate justifications,however,ultimatelyreston one centralfear: that economicinequalitiesmight encroachon the political 31. 32. Finance, 33. See id. at 71. See Edward B. Foley, Equal-Dollars-Per-Voter: A Constitutional Principle of Campaign 94 COLUM.L. REV. 1204, 1204 (1994). Dworkin, supra note 9, at 23. February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 901 sphere. The concerns behind the first and thirdjustifications-for example, that elected officials will shirk theirjobs to do fundraisingand that elected officials will representcampaigncontributorsratherthan their own constituents-arise because candidatesthemselves perceive that money makes a big difference in their election prospects. If candidates thought that money would not make a large difference beyond a certain threshold, they would spend less time fundraisingand would be less inclined to accept contributions that might appearto bind them to particularinterests. In other words, it is belief in the power of money to influence politics that leads candidatesto shirk once in office and overvaluethe interestsof contributors. If candidates did not believe they could convert economic into political advantage,neither type of misbehaviorwould occur. The second concern-that money debilitatesreason-giving and deliberation-also grows out of this same belief. Sunstein's fear that money impairs legislative deliberationstems largely from his belief that elected officials will feel compelled to rewardtheir contributorslest they find themselves without money in the future. And Wright'sconcernthat money harmselectoralpolitics because it encouragesmass advertisingover face-to-face retail politicsand thus, to his mind, manipulatesaffect more than communicates ideasreveals how he believes economic power translatesinto political power. At bottom, then, whatever the particulardefense offered for campaign finance regulation, the fear is the same: Without regulation, the rich will convert their economic into political power. Shirking,debilitateddebate, corruption, and dangerouslyunlevel playing fields are all different manifestationsof a single problem. No matterhow it is expressed, the conversion of economic into political inequalityis the root of all evil in political money. II. DEMOCRACYAT WAR WITHITSELF The notion that people can transformeconomic into political power has such great common-sense appeal that few reformerseven bother to explain how it occurs. That speakerswith more money can make more appeals to voters than can those with less money seems obviously to violate equality, particularlythe equality of opportunityto persuade others, which Dworkin and others believe democracyrequires. But how does it do so? It is important to lay out the argumentbecause it entails somewhat troublingand "undemocratic"assumptionsaboutvoters' civic capabilities. Consider two different citizens.34 The first holds down a busy job, but still manages to read several newspapers, argue politics around the water 34. Theseportraitsare admittedlyquitestylized. Few of us completelyfit one portraitor the other. We arenearlyall some combinationof both. I knowI am. The caricaturesarehelpful,however, because they help bring into sharperfocus the assumptionsthat we make about ourselves whenwe describecertaindangersin politics. I employthemas heuristicdevices. 902 LAWREVIEW STANFORD [Vol. 50:893 cooler, and watch the talking heads on Sunday discuss the latest failings of the political process. The other holds down a busy job too, but spends very little time pursuingpolitics. Insteadof talking politics with others at work, the second goes as far as possible to avoid such conversations. This second citizen is fundamentallydisengaged from public affairs and may not even know how the candidatesstand on major issues or how they differ from one another. The little this second, "disengaged"person knows aboutpolitics all comes from the short commercialsthat are impossible to avoid while watching television. Perhapssome of these have made an impression and maybe this voter prefers a particularcandidatebecause she has more commercials than her opponent,all of which are visually stirringand full of general emotional appeal. The voter can favorablyrememberher name, moreover, because the commercialsappearsteadily, but not often enough to annoy. Both citizens vote in November. How might money have affected these two voters' choices? As to the first, money in politics represents-from a democraticand First Amendment perspective-a very great good. It allows the politically engaged voter to carefully consider more appeals from each candidate. Many of these appeals, of course, will fail to convey the kind of informationand argument that the voter cares about and, as such, will be wasted. In no way, however, should the presence of money worryus here. At worst, the money would be wasted trying to influence the engaged voter; at best, it would help this voter make a more informed choice at the polls. Thus, for the engaged voter, money cannot impair her political choice and may actually improve it. To say with respect to this voter, then, that campaign spending has converted economic into political power may be right-it has, after all, turned the voter's choice-but it is a "good" turn, one we should celebrate, not condemn. Money has, after all, enabled the engaged voter to betterjudge the merits of each candidate. It has improveddemocracy,not impairedit. But what about the second, disengagedvoter? This voter also feels good about his choice. He walks into the voting booth feeling certain about his decision. He may not know what the issues are or where the candidates really standon these issues, but from the numerouscommercialshe has seen, he feels better about one candidatethan the other. In this case too, the campaign has convertedeconomic into political power. The disengaged voter is, after all, choosing on the basis of commercials made possible by money. Money, then, has made a differencehere too, but is it, as before, a good difference? The reformersthink not, and their reason is interesting. Although they arguethatmoney allows the richercandidateto drownout the poorerone,35it 35. See SUNSTEIN,DEMOCRACY AND THEPROBLEMOF FREESPEECH,supra note 9, at 99 (criticizingH. Ross Perot'spresidentialcampaignfor "delug[ing]the mediawith advertisements" February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 903 is clear that, strictly speaking, the poorer candidate's views are not silenced.36 These views remainedavailable to interestedand inquiringminds such as that of the engaged voter. The drowning out occurrednot because opposing views could not be heard, but because the second voter was not interested in hearing them. Perhaps they were dull, or hard to follow, or maybe just thought to be irrelevant. To reformers,the real problem is that mass advertising produced an affective judgment, which the second voter acted on at the polls.37 As before, campaignspending influenced choice, but this time not in a positive way. It did not provide the voter with more concrete informationon which to base a decision. Instead,money sold the candidate the same way manufacturerssell their products: by appealing to a consumer's emotion ratherthan to his intellect. Thus, money produced a change in the vote, but on a basis many regardas inappropriate. In Dworkin's view, the two candidatesdo not have the same opportunity to persuadevoters. With respect to the civic slackers, the "disengaged"voters, the candidate with the greaterresources can conduct a more extensive and thus more effective advertisingcampaign. But it is importantto realize thatthe candidateslack an equal opportunityto persuadethe civic slackernot so much because of their inequality of resources-that was, after all, no problem with respect to the first voter-but ratherbecause of how the civic slacker makes political choices: by respondingto sheer advertisingstimulus ratherthan to issues.38 The inequalityof opportunityto persuade,then, ultimately rests on the civic slacker's disinterestin a politics of substantivepolicy argumentand ideas. With respect to the civic slacker, an equal opportunity to persuadedemands something akin to equal resources, but it also entails a particularlyundemocraticform of persuasion-sheer stimulus rather than convincing argumentation. Requiring equality of resources will give each side a fair shot at the civic slacker, but not on any ground traditional democratictheory recognizes as legitimate. One starkway of bringing this out is to show how our notions of equal opportunityto persuade in other decisionmakingcontexts depend critically on how we believe the particulardecisionmakermakes decisions. When a and "purchas[ing] his way into publicconsciousness");Wright,supra note 17, at 1018-20 (noting thatthe candidatewith moremoney is able to talk at higher"decibels"withoutcontributingmore ideas to the politicaldebate);Dworkin,supra note 9, at 22 ("Itseems perverseto sufferthe clear unfairnessof allowingrichcandidatesto drownoutpoorones."). 36. See Joel L. Fleishman& Pope McCorkle,Level-UpRatherThanLevel-Down:Towardsa New Theoryof CampaignFinanceReform,1 J.L.& POL.211, 244-45 (1984). 37. See note 35 supra. 38. The slackercouldrespondto eitherthe quantityor qualityof the stimuli,butin eithercase would not be respondingprimarilyto ideas. Such a notionunderliesmanyreformers'arguments. See David A. Strauss,Corruption,Equality,and CampaignFinance Reform,94 COLUM. L. REV. 1369, 1373 (1994) (arguingthat"makinga campaigncontributionis roughlyequivalentto delivering a certainnumberof votes to the legislator");Wright,supranote 17, at 1018-20. 904 LAWREVIEW STANFORD [Vol. 50:893 decisionmaker, like a judge, reasons to a decision after listening to both sides, an equal opportunityto persuadedoes not requireequal resources. If it did, our civil and criminaljustice systems would look much different. Legitimacy would demand not just court-appointedattorneys for indigents in most criminal cases,39but something akin to equal quality legal representation and equal investigative supporton both sides of a case. In the case of a diligent judge, we expect the decisionmakingprocess itself to mitigate some of the effects of inequalityof resources. On the other hand, if the decisionmakeremploys a lottery or other random decisionmakingprocess to preserve equality among applicantscompeting for a privilege or benefit, fairness does demand that applicants deploy equal resources. Imagine the uproarthat would accompany an announcement that people could file as many applicationsas they wanted-and could afford-in a lotteryto grantexemptions from compulsorymilitaryservice in wartime. Thus, whether someone has an equal opportunityto persuade depends less on whetherthatperson has been able to deploy as many resources as have others than it does on the methodology of the decisionmaker. If the decisionmakerrelies on careful reasoning, inequalityof resourcesposes less difficulty. In the campaign finance context, the reformers'assumptionthat equality of opportunityto persuade requires equal resources makes sense only if the reformers believe that voters-those being persuaded-do not carefully reason their way throughtheir decisions. In other words, the reformersmust believe that many of us resemble civic slackers more than we should. Moreover, with respect to the civic slacker, the situation may be worse than a lottery. If civic slackers respondedat randomto political candidates, their votes would in the aggregatecancel each other out, leaving the overall outcome of the election unaffected. In other words, they might introduce some noise or static into the system, but they would not change the bottom line; the final result would still reflect the choices of politically engaged voters. If, however, civic slackers respond in more predictableways to certain stimuli, like political advertising,then money can be spent to influence their choices more systematically and the overall outcome will no longer reflect the choices of the politically engaged. This seems to be the reformers'real worry. How does this affect Dworkin's argumentthat Buckley and its defenders misunderstandwhat democracy requires? Remember, Dworkin criticizes Buckleyfor ignoring one of a citizen's two roles in democracy: that of a persuader of others.40 But does it really? Can we separatea citizen's role as judge from that as persuaderas neatly as Dworkindoes? 39. See Gideonv. Wainwright,372 U.S. 335 (1963). 40. See Dworkin,supranote 9, at 22-24. February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 905 In someways,I thinknot. To the extentyourandmy relativeabilitiesto persuadeanotherpersondependon how that person makes choices, my complaintaboutinequalityaims at the rightnessof thatperson'sdecisional criteria.If you will alwaysbe thebettercandidatein a particular voter'seyes becauseyou aretall, blond,andblue-eyedandI am not, is my complaintof nothavinga fairshotat thatvoter'svoteaimedmoreat youradvantagesor at thevoter'smisguidedpoliticalcriteria? Dworkin'scomplaint,then,aboutsome havingless opportunityto persuadethanothersis, at bottom,a complaintaboutthe way manyof us evaluatepoliticalcandidates.Manyof us, he thinks,simplydo not exercisepolitical choice in the informed,deliberate,reasonedway he believesdemocracy requires.And he is right. SurveyaftersurveyshowsthatmanyAmericans makeuninformedpoliticalchoices.41But achievingequalityof persuasion by disrespectingthe ways some votersmakechoicesraisesvery thornyissues. For one thing,it appearsthatwe may be violatingdemocracyin the verynameof protectingit. In the last hypothetical,for example,imaginewhatit wouldmeanto respect my equalityclaim. To place me in an equalpositionwith my tall, blond,blue-eyedopponentwouldrequirethatall candidateshide theirfaces fromthe public. We wouldhave to deny thosevoterswho choose among candidatesin this particularway the informationthey deem relevant. But doingso amountsto imposingon themanunwantedpoliticaldecisionmaking calculus. Theywantto judgeon thebasisof looks. Theproblemis not that theymistakenlythinklooksarea goodproxyforpolicy. Dworkin'sargumentworks similarly. In his view, reformserves to limit-and thus to equalize-the availabilityof certainpoliticalstimulito which manyvotersrespond. But denyingthese votersexposureto stimuli they believe to be importantreallyrepresentsan attemptto disciplinetheir or at leastto mitigateits overallimpacton the outcomeof decisionmaking the election. Reform,in a deep sense, disrespectsthese voters' evaluative autonomy. It frustratestheirabilityto judge candidatesin the way they wouldotherwisejudge. The questionis whethersuch decisionaldiscipline promotesor underminesdemocracyand equalityoverall. Canwe preserve equalityamongvotersas personsby accordingunequalrespectto theirdecisionalcriteria?Thisis anotherformof the democraticparadoxof campaign financereform. III. SOME CHILLINGANALOGIES Whencampaignfinanceregulationis seen as minimizingthe influence of certainkindsof votes,it appearsless akinto unabashedly democraticrules 41. See CARPINI& KEETER,supra note 12, at 62-104. 906 STANFORD LAWREVIEW [Vol. 50:893 like one person, one vote and more akin to practices we now believe offensive to democracy, such as propertyqualifications,pauper exclusions, poll taxes, disenfranchisementof certain racial and gender groups, and literacy tests. Unlike these now discreditedpractices, campaign finance regulation does not formallybar certaingroupsfrom voting. But as I will show, it does share these practices' centralaim of minimizing the effect of votes resulting from disfavoreddecisional criteria. These analogies are meantto be provocative. By offering them, I do not mean to undercutreform through"guilt by association." Rather, I want to demonstrate,first, thatthe centralgoal of reform,as I have describedit, has a longstandingpedigree and, second, thatwe have repudiateddevices that have pursued this goal not because we. distrustedthe goal itself, but because the devices had been hijackedto serve other, quite troubling,and antidemocratic ends. Our rejection of these devices does not in fact reflect any belief that dependentand uninformedpoliticaljudgment is just as good as its opposite. Instead,it reflects the belief that the particulargroups these devices operated to exclude were just as capable as the rest of us of making independent,informed choices. But the question still remains: Should the partial resemblance between campaignfinancereformand these now discreditedpractices worry us? Is campaign finance reform itself susceptible to the same kind of misappropriationthatthese otherdevices suffered? To answer these questions, we must understandthe argumentsthat once favored these now discreditedpractices. Propertyqualifications, for example, limited the vote to owners of certainamounts of property.42Nowadays such limits seem designed only to favor one class, propertyholders, at the expense of others,and that was partof their originaleffect. Originally,however, propertyqualificationswere thoughtto promote a vital goal: ensuring that voters had a stake in political mattersand exercised independentpolitical judgment.43 People without property,it was feared, would not care sufficiently about the public realm to form political opinions worthy of respect44 and would be susceptible to pressure from those who controlled their income.45 In this view, only a propertyowner of sufficient means would care 42. At the time of the AmericanRevolution,all Americancolonies except South Carolina limited the vote to property holders. See ALBERTE. MCKINLEY,THE SUFFRAGEFRANCHISE IN THETHIRTEEN ENGLISHCOLONIES IN AMERICA478-81 (1905). South Carolina limited the vote to taxpayers.See id. at 481. 43. See RobertJ. Steinfeld,PropertyandSuffragein the EarlyAmericanRepublic,41 STAN. L. REV.335, 340 (1989). 44. See WILLI PAUL ADAMS, THE FIRST AMERICANCONSTITUTIONS:REPUBLICAN IDEOLOGY AND THEMAKINGOF THESTATECONSTITUTIONS IN THEREVOLUTIONARY ERA 211 (Rita Kimber& RobertKimbertrans.,Universityof NorthCarolinaPress 1980) (1973); SAMUEL ONTHERIGHTOFSUFFRAGE 109 (Boston, Otis, Broaders & Co. 1842). JONES,TREATISE 45. See Steinfeld,supranote 43, at 340-42. February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 907 sufficientlyaboutpublicaffairsandbe sufficientlyfree fromexternalinfluencesto exerciseindependent politicaljudgment.46 The secondrationale-freedomfrominfluenceby others-resemblesthe equalityof influencerationaleofferedby campaignfinancereformers.They, of course,do not fearthatdirecteconomiccoercionwill overbeara voter's judgment. Rather,reformersare concernedthatthe voterwill independent follow certainkindsof politicalstimulusand fail to exerciseindependent, deliberate judgment.Still,thebottomline is similar.Justas propertyexclusionswerethoughtto maintainequalityof influenceamongindependent votersby preventingone manfromdirectingthe vote of otherswho aredependent on him,47campaignfinanceregulationis thoughtto maintainequalityof influenceamongengagedvotersby preventingsomefromdirectingthe vote of otherswho aresusceptibleto massadvertising. of pauperexclusionsmadesimilararguments.As wage earnSupporters ersgainedthevote andpeoplecameto see a steadywageas ensuringa sufficient stakein politicalmattersand independenceof judgment,paupersbecamethe next disfavoredclass.48Not only did theynot supportthemselves, but they dependedon local governmentfor theirneeds. This dependence presentedobvious opportunitiesfor coercionof a particularlythreatening kind:49coercionby representatives of the stateitselfratherthanby otherprivate parties.50Pauperexclusionsthusworkednot only to preserveequality voters,but also to preventtyrannyat the handsof local amongindependent government. Racialand genderexclusionswere somewhatsimilarlyregarded. Althoughwe now view them, like propertyqualificationsand pauperexcluone social groupto another,these exclusions, as workingto subordinate * 171. 46. See 1 WILLIAM COMMENTARIES BLACKSTONE, 47. Blackstone makes explicit how disenfranchising one group was necessary to promote equality: The true reason of requiringany qualification,with regardto property,in voters, is to exclude such persons as are in so mean a situationthat they are esteemed to have no will of their own. If these persons had votes, they would be temptedto dispose of them undersome undue influence or other. This would give a great, an artful,or a wealthy man, a largershare in elections thanis consistentwithgeneralliberty.If it wereprobablethateverymanwouldgive his vote freelyandwithoutinfluenceof anykind,then,uponthetruetheoryandgenuineprinciplesof howeverpoor,shouldhavea vote in electingthose liberty,everymemberof the community, delegates,to whosechargeis committedthedisposalof his property,his liberty,andhis life. But,sincethatcanhardlybe expectedin personsof indigentfortunes,or suchas areunderthe immediate dominionof others,all popularstateshavebeenobligedto establishcertainqualifications;wherebysome,who are suspectedto haveno will of theirown, are excludedfrom whosewillsmaybe supposedindependent, morethorvoting,in orderto set otherindividuals, oughlyupona levelwitheachother. Id. at *171-72. 48. See Steinfeld,supranote42, at 335-37. 49. See id. at 344-48, 362. 50. See id. 908 LAWREVIEW STANFORD [Vol. 50:893 sions were oncejustifiedon two othergrounds:First,thatmembersof the disfavoredgroupssufferedincapacitiesof judgment,andsecond,thateven if theydidnot,theywereparticularly susceptibleto outsidecoercion. The first groundis depressinglyfamiliar.Manythoughtbothblacksandwomenwere incapableof properlythinkingthroughpoliticaldecisions.51Womensufferedunderan additionaldisability.Manythoughttheirspecialrole within the domesticsphereof home and familywas incompatiblewith politics.52 Underprevailingideologies,it was believedthatwomen were simplynot naturallysuitedto politicaldecisionmaking.Whitemen, on the otherhand, wereconsiderednaturalrulers.53Andshouldthe occasionalblackor woman actuallybe capableof exercisingjudgment,therewas a dangerthatothers would overbearit. Manybelievedthatfreedblackswere uniquelyvulnerable to their formermasters,54 or opportunistic whites,56and employers,55 51. See 56 CONG.REC. 784 (1918) (recording the statements of Congressman Clark that men who once supported woman suffrage "were forced to change their views by the force of unanswerable logic"); J.N. BRENAMAN,A HISTORYOFVIRGINIACONVENTIONS 80, 81, 88 (1902) (discuss- CHAPMAN CATT& ing Virginia'seffortsto eliminatethe electoralpowerof blackvoters);CARRIE ANDPOLITICS 279 (1926) (quoting former President NETTIEROGERSSHULER,WOMANSUFFRAGE Taftas saying,"Thelackof experiencein affairsandthe excess of emotionon thepartof womenin reachingtheirpoliticaldecisions[on certainissues] ... wouldlowerthe averagepracticalsense and self-restraint of the electorate ...."); WILLIAM THERIGHTTOVOTE:POLITICS ANDTHE GILLETTE, PASSAGEOF THEFIFTEENTH AMENDMENT 42, 89 (1965) (discussing the belief that blacks lacked the necessary characteristicsfor intelligentexercise of the vote); RICHARD L. MORTON, THE NEGROINVIRGINIAPOLITICS,1865-1902, at 151-52 (1918) (discussing the views during Virginia's 1901-1902Constitutional Conventionthatblackswerea "menacein politics"). 52. See 56 CONG.REC. 785 (1918) (recording the statements of Congressman Clark that the vote would bring women "discontent, sorrow, and pain"); LINDAK. KERBER,WOMENOF THE REPUBLIC:INTELLECT AND IDEOLOGY IN REVOLUTIONARY AMERICA235, 269-88 (1980) (dis- cussingthe nation'sgrudgingresponseto women'ssacrificesduringthe revolutionaryera);JUDITH THE QUESTFORINCLUSION 6-8 (1991) (noting that, although SHKLAR,AMERICANCITIZENSHIP: women "were said to be good more frequently than men,... they were not fit to be citizens"). 53. One commentator present during the battle over the Nineteenth Amendment described this position with regard to women: It maintainsthat woman is dependentwhethershe likes it or not, and all the laws that could be written never would alter the fact. In the plant, animal, and human kingdom alike, in all the fundamental,instinctive family relations,the female is bound in the very natureof things to be dependent. The tyrannyof man, the old common law of England, and acts of parliamentare not responsible for the fact that the male creatureis always the leader, the protector,and the rulerof his kind. An act of Congress, it maintains,will not alter the fact that women instinctively seek and glory in the protectionof men, that men will lead, will control and dominate and rule, and that normalwomen will be contentin the masterfuldominationof their men; that all the laws in Christendomcould not alterthese elemental instincts. It is not cruel legislation that has made the female of the species dependenteverywhere,among the flowers of the earth, the beasts of the field, the birds, the savages, and at the family hearth,and no amountof legislation can undo it. All the king's horses and all the king's men are helpless in the face of elemental instincts. INTHEUNITEDSTATES249-50 (1918). KIRKH. PORTER,A HISTORYOFSUFFRAGE 54. See id. at 83-84. 55. See GILLETTE, supra note 51, at 42. 56. See BRENAMAN,supra note 51, at 80-81. February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 909 womenwerethoughtto be easilyswayedby theirhusbands.57 In thisview, if blacksand womenwere allowedto vote, they wouldmore likely multiply theirmasters'or husbands'votesthanaddan independent voice of theirown. Racialand genderexclusionsthus sought,as campaignfinanceregulation does, to promoteequalityamongthosethoughtto be civicallyindependent andcapableof judgment. Poll taxeswere also defendedon similargrounds. Althoughpoll taxes were long employedto frustratesouthernblacksfrom voting,58they were also oncejustifiedas a safeguardto ensurethatall who voted caredabout publicaffairs.59If votingcameat a cost,the argumentwent,only thosewho caredwouldvote, andthe outcomewouldreflectsounderjudgment.60Thus, in theory,poll taxesworkedto promoteequalityamongcertainengagedcitizensby discouraging votingon a lark. Literacytests representperhapsthe best parallelto campaignfinance regulation.Althoughwe now thinkof literacytests as a shamefulmeansof excludingblacksfromthe vote-and, indeed,thatwas amongtheiroriginal purposesin some jurisdictions61-theytheoreticallyserved an important civic function. In theory,they ensuredthatall who votedcouldreadnewspapers and journals,the primarysourcesof political informationat the time.62 In otherwords,like the previousdevices,literacytests workedto disenfranchisethose who might well make politicaldecisionson inferior grounds,suchas a candidate'slooks,simplepartyaffiliation,or theadviceof andjudgment others,ratherthanaccordingto the voter'sown understanding of the issues. By exclusion,literacyteststhuspreservedequalitywithinthe limitedclassof engagedvoters. 57. See CAROLEPATEMAN,THESEXUALCONTRACT 39-57, 97-99, 168-72 (1988). 58. See BRENAMAN, supra note 51, at 89-90 (discussingVirginia'sdesire duringits 19011902 Constitutional Conventionto use the poll tax to limitsuffrage);see also FREDERIC D. OGDEN, THEPOLLTAX INTHESOUTH1-31 (1958). 59. See Harperv. VirginiaBd. of Elections,383 U.S. 663, 674, 677 (1966) (Black, J., dissenting); id. at 684-85 (Harlan, J., dissenting); A.F. THOMAS,THE VIRGINIACONSTITUTIONAL CONVENTION ANDITSPOSSIBILITIES 12 (1901). 60. Cf OGDEN, supranote 58, at 32 (notingthatsupportersof the poll tax believedthat"anyone who will not pay $1.00 fortheprivilegeof votingdoes not deserveto havethatprivilege"). 61. See BRENAMAN, supra note 51, at 89-90 (discussingVirginia'suse of literacytests and blackvotersduringits 1901-1902Constitutional poll taxesto disenfranchise Convention). 62. In examiningliteracytests,the SupremeCourthas stated: Yet in our society where newspapers,periodicals,books, and other printedmattercanvass and debate campaignissues, a State might conclude thatonly those who are literateshould exercise the franchise. It was said last centuryin Massachusettsthat a literacy test was designed to insure an independentand intelligentexercise of the rightof suffrage. Lassiter v. Northampton County Bd. of Elections, 360 U.S. 45, 52 (1959) (citations and footnote omitted); see also JONES,supra note 44, at 132-33 (stating that a person must be educated to properly vote). 910 STANFORD LAWREVIEW [Vol. 50:893 Now, of course,campaignfinanceregulationis differentfrom all of thesenow suspectpractices.It excludesno one fromthe votingbooth..Yet campaignfinanceregulationdoes frustratecertainvoters from exercising choice in ways they otherwisewould and minimizesthe overalleffect of theirvotes if they do.63 In a sense,then,campaignfinanceregulationis to is to outrightracialexclumanyof thesepracticesas racialgerrymandering sion. Likeracialgerrymandering, finance campaign regulationdoes not bar anyonefromvoting,butit doesdilutetheeffectof certainvotes: thevotesof thosewho respondto politicsin certaindisfavoredways.64Whereasracial worksby preventingracialgroupsfromeffectivelyaggregerrymandering their individual votes, campaignfinancelimitationswork by supgating pressingappealsto certainvoters'choice mechanisms.Regulationstarves these votersof the stimulusto whichthey are most likely to respondor at leastmakessurethatall the candidatescanmakea roughlyequalnumberof suchappeals. So therearetwo hopesin campaignfinancereform.First,insofaras reformdiminishessuchappeals,it will reducethe role of affectin votingand increasethe role of issues, arguments,policies, and ideas. correspondingly Second,insofaras campaignfinanceregulationequalizessuch appeals,it will limittheiroveralleffect. Thevotesof peoplewho respondin suchways to politicswill largelycancelthemselvesout. IV. A MORECOMFORTING ANALOGY Thereformers, of course,neverraiseanyof the foregoinganalogies.But on they mightrely anotheranalogythatresonatesmorepositively: the prohibitionagainstvotebuying. In one view, spendinggreatamountsof money on an electionlookslikebuyingit. If successful,thisanalogywouldbe quite helpfulto the reformers'case, for vote buyingis universallydiscreditedin ourpoliticalculture.65 Butdoestheanalogyreallywork? At first,vote buyingappearsto be a riddle.66It outlawsbehaviorthat seemsto benefitbothof the partiesdirectlyinvolved. Like any consensual trade,vote buyingmustimprovethe welfareof boththe buyerandthe seller in orderto occur.67Thebuyerandsellerwill tradeonly if the buyerprefers thevote overthemoneyandthesellerprefersthemoneyoverthevote. 63. See text accompanyingnotes34-41 supra. 64. See id. 65. See generallyPamelaS. Karlan,Not by Moneybut by VirtueWon?VoteTraffickingand the VotingRightsSystem,80 VA.L. REV.1455(1994) (discussingthe dangersof vote trafficking). 66. See id. at 1456-59(discussinghow antitrafficking laws can actuallyrestrictvoter autonomy). 67. See JAMESM. BUCHANAN& GORDONTULLOCK,THE CALCULUSOF CONSENT270 (1962). February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 911 Commentatorshave disagreed over how to describe the problem with vote buying. To some, the danger lies in the social vulnerability that alienability would create. Vote sellers would disproportionatelycome from marginal social groups.68 While selling their votes might improve their short-termprospects, it is likely to do damage in the long run.69 This is because selling their votes would impair their alreadymeager political power and therebyreinforcetheir social subjugation.70To some public choice theorists, on the other hand, the problem lies in the imperfectionsthat would inevitably infect the marketfor votes.71 These imperfections,they fear, would lead to stable coalitions of vote traders,coalitions which would systematically exploit people outside the tradingbloc.72 To others, the problem lies in the likelihood that vote buyers who succeed in the election will raid the public fisc to pay off their debts.73Finally, to those who worry about commodifying human personality,the problem might lie in the way one's vote is intrinsically connected to one's self. People holding this view might believe that the vote should be inalienablebecause it is so tied up with the voter's status as citizen. To allow a person to sell his vote would commodify a centralpartof his identity. Under none of these theoriesdoes vote buying seem closely analogous to campaign spending. If anything, increased campaign spending combats these dangers. By providingmore informationto interestedvoters, campaign spending (1) allows voters within marginal communities to better protect themselves; (2) destabilizes vote trading coalitions by providing members reasons to split from them; (3) provides informationthat may enable voters to punish officials who raid the treasury;and (4) allows voters to make more informedpolitical choices and thus better develop and exercise their identities. To the extent campaignspendingprovides more informationof interest to voters, it can only ease, as opposed to exacerbate,the various problemsof vote buying. Under anotherview, however, vote buying is closely analogous to campaign spending. Imagine A sells his vote to B; both A and B are happy. C, however, has a complaint against both. Although C may still cast a vote in the election-the same as before A and B traded-the vote means something different than before. It no longer representsa right to have equal influence over the outcome of the election because B now effectively votes twice. C's 68. See Karlan,supranote65, at 1458-59. 69. See id. at 1469 (arguingthat,once a politicianhas purchaseda vote, he may be temptedto thinkhe has dischargedhis dutyto the voter). 70. See id. at 1470-72. 71. See BUCHANNAN & TULLOCK, supranote 67, at 275. 72. See id. at 270-76. 73. See RichardA. Epstein, WhyRestrainAlienation?,85 COLUM.L. REV.970, 987-88 (1985). 912 STANFORD LAWREVIEW [Vol. 50:893 say countsonly half as muchas B's. So the valueof C's vote has changed even if the vote itself has not.74 C couldnot, of course,complainif A andB cast theirvotes independently and happenedto supportthe same candidate. C's rightis a rightto haveherjudgmentcountequallywithothers'in thevotingbooth,not a right to controlthe outcomeof the election. ThetradebetweenA andB, in other words,imposescosts on C not becauseC loses, butbecauseC's entitlement, the vote, is definedin termsof A andB exercisingindependentchoice. In thisview of votebuying,it is wrongforA to sell hervoteto B notbecauseof anyinjuryto A or B, butbecausetheirtradedilutesthevalueof C's vote. In economicterms,A andB's tradecreatesnegativeexternalitiesbecausethe valueof everyoneelse's vote is partlydefinedaccordingto the independence of A andB's voting. A's vote belongsto A, butall othervotershavea right in it belongingonly to her,just as A hasa rightin theirvotesbelongingonly to them. In otherwords,whenA sells her vote, she is not only alienating somethingthatis hers,but also givingawaysomethingthatdoes not belong to heralone: partof the valueof everyoneelse's vote. Democracy,to most eyes, doesnot allowherto alienateso much.75 Theprohibitionagainstvote buyingis, in this view, continuouswith all the now discreditedvotingpracticesdiscussedbefore. It seeks to ensureexerciseof pojustas thosepracticeswereoncebelievedto-the independent liticaljudgment. Thatwe cling to this prohibitionwhile repudiatingall the otherpracticesshowsthatwe do not questionthis goal, but do worryabout thesepractices'misappropriation. In otherwords,theproblemwithall these lies not in the were saidto pursue,butin theirperversion practices goal they to other,troublingends. If we conceptualizethe evil of vote buying in this way, campaign spendingis analogousundera particular descriptionof how votersmakepoliticaldecisions. To the engaged,activevoter,campaignspendingcanmake it fundspresentsno ideas, only a positivedifference.If the communication arguments,or information,the voterwill discountit. At worst,the added communication it provideswill provea distractionor minorirritant,but it will not impairthatvoter'spoliticalchoice. Moreover,to the extentit does provideideas,arguments,and information,it can only improvethe voter's decisionmaking.Forevenif thevoterdisagreeswithall the information presented,the speech will have bettertested the voter's opinionsand made 74. Cf BUCHANAN& TULLOCK,supranote 67, at 270 (describinghow vote selling changes the valueof a person'svote even thoughhe didnot participatein the exchange). 75. Cf Karlan,supranote 65, at 1466 (discussinghow thereis a dangerto the groupwhen individualsengagein vote trafficking). February1998] CAMPAIGN FINANCEREFORM 913 strongerthe voter'sjudgment.Whateverextracommunication moneymakes hurt cannot this of voter's possible,then, type decisionmaking.76 On the otherhand,to the unengaged,passivevoterwho neitherfollows nor caresfor ideas,popoliticalarguments,carefullyanalyzesinformation, liticaladvertisingmay indeedmakea negativedifference.77Remember,the fearhereis thatthe unengagedvoterwill respondpositivelyto sheeradvertising stimulus,thathe will vote for the candidatewho has the morelavish advertisingcampaign,regardlessof whetherthat campaignconveys informationaboutwherethe candidatestandson the majorissues. To the extent thattheunengagedvoterrespondsthisway,spendingresemblesvote buying. The engaged,activevoter'svote is dilutedbecauseanothervoterhas abdicatedproper,independent judgment.The civic slackercedes his vote to the candidatewith the betteradvertisingcampaign,just as the traditionalvote seller cedes his vote to the vote buyer. In both cases, followingsomeone else's politicaljudgmenthasthird-party effects. It devaluesthevote of those exercisingindependent judgment.78 that the analogybetweenvote buying and campaign Note, however, spendingdependson strongassumptionsabouthow some voters do and shouldbehave. It requires,descriptively,thata significantnumberof citizens-those analogousto vote sellers-be civic slackers:voterswho make politicaldecisionsin a somewhatcarelessway. It also requires,prescriptively, a strongnormativecommitmentto a particularconceptionof how people shouldvote. Afterall, accordingto the civic slacker'sown values, does not cause any followingpoliticaladvertisingwithoutdiscrimination it harm; only injuresfromtheperspectiveof engagedvoters. Forthe analogy to vote buyingto work, then, democracyitself must impose an engaged, normativeconceptionof decisionmaking.In otherwords,democracymust eschewpluralismamongdifferentconceptionsof howpeopleshouldvote. CONCLUSION: A NEW STRATEGY FORREFORNI Thus,the debateaboutcampaignfinanceregulationconcernssomething moreandvery differentthanis oftenthought.It is less aboutequality,pure and simple,and more aboutwhat the vote represents,whetherdemocracy requirespeopleto makepoliticaldecisionsin a particular way, andhow peomake choices. To not all ple actually reformers, political ways of making decisions are in their demands the indepolitical equal. Democracy, eyes, exercise of deliberate pendent politicaljudgment.Reformersaimto promote equalityamongthosewho vote this way by minimizingthe distortingeffect 76. See Dworkin,supranote 9, at 22. 77. See text accompanyingnotes 17-21supra. 78. See text accompanyingnotes26-33 supra. 914 LAWREVIEW STANFORD [Vol. 50:893 of votes that reflect other decisionmakingprocesses. In the end, to champion equality among the engaged citizenry, reformersmust disregardthe "rights" of civic slackers. The opponents of campaignfinance reform, on the other hand, promote equality of a differentsort: equalityamong voters who use differentkinds of decisional criteria. To opponents,the differentways in which civic slackers and engaged citizens make political decisions are entitled to equal constitutional respect. From this perspective,reformersappearelitist and suspicious of modem mass politics.79 All of this suggests a new strategy for reformers: honesty. Currently, their opponents, both on and off the Supreme Court, have the upper hand partly because their argumentis cleaner, more straightforward,and less internally conflicted. They assume either that voters are largely engaged, thoughtful, and civically responsible or that the law should equally respect all ways of making a political choice.80 Reformerscannot win under either of these assumptions. Under the first, reformerscannot argue that more advertising poses any dangerbecause the voters can be relied on to see through it. Under the second, advertising can pose no danger because we cannot normativelydistinguishamong differentvoters' differentuses of it. Reformers must move the public debateto differentgroundsandjoin argumentover how people should make political decisions and how they actually do. There is nothing shameful about this. On this issue, they must, moreover, frankly admit that they are not egalitarians. Democracy is a substantivenotion, demandingmuch, perhapstoo much, from its citizens. Although it sounds uncomfortablyelitist to say that not everyone's way of making political decisions should be equally respected, that is exactly what reformersmust do in order to make their argument,let alone win the debate. They must persuade us that democracy is, in this one sense, profoundly antiegalitarian,that it cannot equally respect all forms of decisional autonomy. We must come to see, in other words, that if we have mistaken democracyas egalitarian,it is only because we have flatteredourselves into believing thatwe are all the engaged citizens thatdemocracydemandswe be. The reformers'case is an unflatteringone, to be sure. It views many voters' civic capacities quite dimly. But if reformersare to make their case, they must force us to recognize our civic failings. For only by recognizing our failings can we ever hope to grapplewith and perhapseventually overcome them. 79. See L.A. Powe, Jr.,Mass Speechand the NewerFirst Amendment,1982 SUP.CT. REV. 243,274,283. 80. See Dworkin,supra note 9, at 22 (describingthe "individual-choice" argumentagainst campaignfinanceregulation).