1 Socrates Talks to Himself in Plato’s Hippias Major1 Halsten Olson §1 Socrates Meets His Match At Last It is almost a rule that the mature Socrates of Plato’s puzzle-raising dialogues never converses with a philosophical equal. But it is not quite a rule: the exception is an ongoing conversation with himself of which Socrates gives us fragments in the Hippias Major.2 From the fragments we learn that in talking to himself, Socrates is, while of course his own equal, also his own superior and his own inferior. He at once refutes his interlocutor and gets refuted. The central conversation of the Hippias Major is between Socrates and Hippias on the question, “What is the fine?”. But during his questioning of Hippias Socrates alludes to someone who has asked questions of Socrates. Socrates acts the part of this person, who is first presented as an annoying questioner, “not refined” (ou kompsos) and “rabblerubbish” (surphetos, 288d4), “a real plague” (mermeros, 290e4), who would try to give Socrates a thrashing if Socrates could not remember what question he was supposed to be thinking about, then as someone who takes pity on Socrates and occasionally makes a suggestion to help discussion along, then as the person Socrates would be most ashamed to make pretensions to, then as the “son of Sophroniscus”, and finally as “a close relative of mine”, who “lives in the same house”. Before the dialogue ends, readers realize that Socrates’ annoying questioner is none other than Socrates himself. The device of Socrates’ acting out these second-hand questions for Hippias somewhat insulates Socrates from seeming discourteous to Hippias. The questions he 2 relays from the third party can be more simple and straightforward than the questions which the self-admiring Hippias would expect Socrates to address to his face. For his part Hippias can more frankly grumble about the unadorned questioning of the absent third party than would be polite for Hippias to grumble directly to Socrates. Socrates’ acting out the annoying questioner’s questions in the Hippias Major may be compared to and contrasted with Socrates’ acting out speeches of the Laws of Athens in the Crito. In the conversation with the Laws Socrates imagines himself as speaking briefly (50c) contrary to fact, as though he proposed to escape from prison; he then speaks the Laws’ reasoning opposing escape. It seems that only one side of the discussion gives Socrates’ actual views.3 The Hippias Major’s conversation is different in that Socrates is narrator, questioner, and answerer.4 It may reveal Socrates’ own views better than Socrates’ narrations of his conversations with others.5 My deliberately chosen modality ‘may’ presents a revelatory possibility, not a certainty; for there is the further possibility that the depicted Socrates is, as we might say, ironic. What Socrates says on occasion may not be directly revelatory of anything. But I shall avoid the word ‘ironist’. Although it sounds like a straightforward translation and hence a synomym of the Greek ειρων, its relation to its Greek ancestor, which doesn’t have quite the flavor of our word ‘ironist’, is complicated and may be misleading. Since neither ‘ironist’ nor words related to it occur in the Hippias Major, rather than speak of irony, I will simply state what everyone would agree to -- that Socrates is not always depicted as saying flatly and directly what Plato intends us, Plato’s readers, to understand.6 3 The sort of self-conversation Socrates reports will be familiar to many of us who talk to ourselves and try out objections on ourselves. For example, the Socrates of the Theaetetus (189e) says that the soul’s carrying on a discussion (dialegesthai), questioning itself and answering itself, is what he calls ‘thinking’.7 Socrates’ report of what the annoying questioner has said to him, if we believe it, gives us a rich picture of Socrates as a self-questioner. The report tells us what the questioner has asked Socrates in the past (286d). The report tells us what the questioner is in the habit of asking (287c). The report predicts what the questioner will say (293d; 303e-304). But in so predicting, Socrates is making use of prediction to reveal a tendency, not just to point to an isolated future event. So even these future tense claims give some information about how Socrates has questioned himself. There is a complexity in the picture the dialogue gives us of Socrates as answerer, for Socrates sometimes assumes the part of Hippias to give answers in the conversation. For example, at 289c-d Socrates says, in effect, that if he said that the finest girl is shamefully ugly compared with the gods (as Hippias has just agreed), and is no more fine than shamefully ugly, then the annoying questioner would say that Socrates had only answered the question ‘What is both fine and shamefully ugly?’, instead of answering the question the questioner has asked. In this passage Socrates is not himself asserting the view which he has taken over from Hippias. He is just considering what the questioner would discover to follow if Socrates asserted the view of Hippias. So we need to separate Socrates’ genuine answers, in his own person, to his questioner from those answers that Socrates says he would give in the contrary to fact condition that he were to answer as Hippias does. When we make that separation, we find 4 that Socrates gives only a fragmentary picture of how, speaking for himself, he has answered the questioner. But the fragmentary picture is, if we trust what Socrates says, of great interest. I will, in fact, trust Socrates; I will take as a starting point that there is some, but not much, Socratic dissembling and indirection in Socrates’ report to Hippias. I will then ask in the rest of this paper what we learn about Socrates from his description of his conversation with himself. Others who take as a starting point the thought that there is a great deal of dissembling in Socrates’ self-description will not find the Hippias Major as informative as I do. My starting point that Socrates is reporting quite accurately how he talks to himself has this interesting consequence: the Hippias Major gives us Plato’s picture of how the most philosophically adept answerer responds to the most philosophically acute questioner. §2 Socrates, Self-Questioner, Asks ‘What is the fine?’ We learn from Socrates’ conversation with himself that Socrates questions himself in just the way he questions others in the short dialogues of inquiry. Socrates reports at 286c-d that the questioner has asked Socrates, “How do you know (pothen oistha) what sorts of things (hopoia) are fine and ugly?” and “Are you able to say (echois eipein) what the fine is?” At 287d, Socrates, who has proposed to question Hippias in the same way the annoying questioner questions Socrates, asks Hippias what the fine is. At 289c Socrates rephrases, asking, “Whatever is the fine itself?” Although Socrates does not use the word ‘definition’ here, I’ll say that Socrates is asking for a 5 definition in this sense: to ask what the fine itself is is to ask what it is for anything to be fine. That Socrates moves from the question “How do you know what sorts of things are fine and ugly?” to the question, “What is the fine itself?” shows the point of the latter, definitional, question. The answer to this definitional question will also give Socrates the answer to his initial question, “How do you know what sorts of things are fine?” The connection between a definitional question, such as the question what the fine is, and a question about knowledge, such as, ‘How do you know when something is fine?’, is straightforward to see in some cases. If a learner in an ordinary learning situation asks of an acknowledged expert the question, ‘How do you know that that figure is an octagon?’, the expert might answer, ‘Because the octagon itself -- that is, what it is to be an octagon -- is a figure with eight sides. And this figure indeed has eight sides.’ Here the person who knows that this is an octagon is able to say what an octagon is, or what it is to be an octagon. To say what it is to be an octagon is to cite the octagon itself in giving, as reasons for knowing that this is an octagon, what a teacher would say in teaching someone else what an octagon is. At the end of the dialogue, at 304d, after the failure of all their attempts to answer, ‘What is the fine?’, Socrates again makes the connection between ‘What is the fine itself?’ and ‘How do you know what is fine?’ There Socrates says that if he tries to converse (304d,dialegesthai) about fine activities when he is ignorant about what the fine itself is, his questioner will ask him, “How will you know (pôs su eisê(i)) whose speech or any other activity is finely presented or not, when you are ignorant of the fine?” 6 §3 Socrates Asks ‘What is the fine?’ When Hippias Commends Fine Actions to the Young We learn from Socrates’ self-conversation, as well as from Socrates’ conversation with Hippias, exactly what moves Socrates to ask about the fine by itself. Although previous to 286c Socrates has used the word ‘fine’ or close derivatives several times, and Hippias has used it once (282d6), these earlier uses have not moved Socrates to ask, in general, what is the fine. The turning point in the conversation occurs when Hippias uses ‘fine’ to make life-guiding recommendations about pursuits for a life, practices (epitêdeumata). At 285e10-286b5 there is this exchange. S: The Spartans enjoy you, predictably, because you know a lot of things, and they use you the way children use old ladies, to tell stories for pleasure.8 H: Yes, and by God, Socrates, about fine pursuits. Just now I made a great impression there speaking about the pursuits which a young man should take up. I have a speech about that that I put together really finely. ... My setting and the starting point of the speech are something like this: after Troy was taken, the tale is told that Neoptolemus asked Nestor what sort of pursuits (epitêdeumata) are fine (kala) -- the sort of pursuits that would make someone most famous if he adopted them while young. After that, the speaker is Nestor, who teaches him a great many altogether fine (pagkala) customs. Hippias’ speech presents the advice of Nestor, a Greek elder, to the young Neoptolemus, son of Achilles. The advice hints at an account of one type of fine 7 things, namely, “fine pursuits”, or, apparently equivalently, “the sort of activities that would make someone most famous if he adopted them while young”. That Hippias is, by telling his story, giving advice to the young is what moves Socrates to the general inquiry at 286c. Socrates recalls that the questioner has questioned Socrates precisely when Socrates has praised or found fault with speeches. The speeches that Socrates has in mind are the instruments of political advice, as his reference at the end of the dialogue to speeches and getting things done “in court or some other gathering” (304c8d1) implies. It’s a fine thing you reminded me. Just now someone got me badly stuck when I was finding fault with parts of some speeches for being shameful, and praising other parts as fine. He questioned me ..., ‘Socrates, how do you know what sorts of things are fine and shameful? Look, would you be able to say what the fine is?’ So it’s a fine thing you came now. Teach me enough about what the fine is itself, ... so I won’t be a laughingstock. Of course you know it clearly.(286c4-e3) At 287b5-8 Socrates emphasizes that what would provoke the questioner to ask the question about the fine itself is Hippias’ recommendation of fine pursuits. If you displayed that speech to him, the one you mentioned about the fine pursuits, he’d listen, and when you stopped speaking, he’d ask not about anything else but about the fine. When Hippias says that doing what will lead to becoming famous is a fine pursuit, Hippias is recommending conduct, or even a way of life, to his hearer. If you, the hearer, 8 believe that what Hippias says is fine is fine, you have some reason to undertake the commended activity yourself. But on the important topic of life-absorbing activities in which you will invest yourself, it seems a bad idea to trust in a recommendation of examples without having something to say about what explains why the examples of the fine are fine. For life-guiding recommendations you want, from someone who presents himself as an expert, a way to understand his examples. You do not want to take his word for one example after another. That is why Socrates asks Hippias how he knows. §4. Socrates Wants A Certain Kind of Explanatory Answer to “What is the fine itself?” We learn from Socrates’ self-conversation that he wants, from himself as well as from Hippias, a certain kind of answer to the question what the fine is. At 293d-294 Socrates gives for Hippias an example of an adequate answer to a different definitional question, ‘What is the large?’ The large, or that by which something is large, is the going-beyond. That is, if something goes beyond (some other thing), then it is a necessity that it is large (that is, larger than that other thing). What all large things are large by is by the going beyond. For by that, they are all large. ... If they go beyond... it is a necessity [anagke] for them to be large. (294b2-4) Socrates would ask himself, “All those things you say are fine, will they be fine if the fine itself is what ?” (288a6-10). He wants to know that by which or in virtue of which or because of which all fine things are fine. The answer to ‘What is the fine?’ will tell us something that necessitates being fine. The answer Socrates expects is what we would call a necessary truth that is somehow explanatory. 9 In giving his example of that by which or because of which things are large, Socrates does not here say what entitles his example to count as explanatory of why something is large. Examples that the Socrates of other dialogues has accepted as adequate definitions suggest that explanatory analyses are fuller, simpler, and more obvious than what they analyse. Theaetetus 147c tells us helpfully that mud is earth mixed with moisture. The Laches 192b tells us that quickness is the power of doing much in a short time. The Hippias Major’s account of the large as the going beyond does not, however, seem especially explanatory or helpful, although it is a necessary truth. ‘Large’ (or ‘big’) is a part of our vocabulary so basic that we all learn it as toddlers, before we learn much else. It is then difficult to see what could be simpler and more obvious than it. (And thus it is understandable that Phaedo 102 analyses in the other direction, apparently explaining going beyond by being large.)9 So some questions remain about what counts as explanatory. We can nonetheless see how an analysing answer to the question ‘What is the fine?’ would be a helpful step in the direction of answering the question ‘How do you know what is fine?’. The answer to ‘What is the fine?’ would be helpful because it would give the answer to two further questions which in turn help with answering ‘How do you know?’. First, it would answer, ‘What is the reason why you believe that such and such is fine?’ But second, it would answer ‘What is the reason why it is true that such and such is fine?’ Compare our answer to ‘What is an octagon?’ Our answer gives reasons why someone might believe that something is an octagon which also explain why it is true that that something is an octagon. 10 Not all answers to ‘What is the reason why you believe that that is fine?’ answer ‘What is the reason why it is true that that is fine?’. Answers such as ‘Someone I trust told me’ or ‘Experts on the fine have recommended it’ might explain why you believe that something is fine, but do not explain why it is true that that thing is fine. Socrates’ example reveals that Socrates wants reasons to believe which are also reasons why what is to be believed is true. §5 Socrates Worries about “Nothing But the Truth”, But Says Some False Things We learn from Socrates’ conversation with himself that he is after the truth about the topic at hand. At 288d5 Socrates says of the questioner, “He cares about nothing but the truth.” But this seems odd. Socrates, as questioner of Hippias, seems actually to say some false things. Since the Socrates who questions Hippias is also that annoying questioner who questions Socrates, if the latter cares only for the truth, so should the former. So how can Socrates consistently say false things to Hippias? An example of what is arguably a Socratic falsehood about himself is at 286c7-8 where Socrates reports that the questioner asks questions of Socrates “quite insultingly” (286c7-8 mala hubristikôs). However, Socrates’ reports of the questioner’s questions give us no details which would be evidence that the questions ‘How do you know?’ and ‘Are you able to say?’ were asked in an insulting manner. Socrates does say things to himself later which are insulting -- at 298d, “millstone, with no ears and no brain”. The questioner would hit Socrates with a stick if Socrates gave certain answers (292a-b). So the questioner is insulting to Socrates. But all Socrates gives us to initiate the central 11 discussion with Hippias is the bare questions. And the questions by themselves obviously are not insulting. Socrates offers the qualification “insultingly” without more details because he knows Hippias will accept it. Hippias would think the questions insulting. To ask Hippias, ‘How do you know that what you said is fine is fine?’ would challenge, improperly, as Hippias doubtless thinks, his claims to expertise and authority (282d, 286 a-c). But Socrates takes these questions to be important and appropriate. Socrates accepts the questions as proper for himself (291a: “It’s nothing much for me”). Having been challenged with these questions does not strike him as insolent treatment to complain about. Instead of taking offense at the questions, Socrates reproaches himself (286d-e) for his inability to answer them. These are the challenges -- ‘How do you know?’ and ‘Say what it is!’ -- that Socrates expects himself to be able to answer if he is going to commend and hence recommend life-absorbing activities as fine to others. So Socrates speaks falsely of himself when he says the questioner asked insultingly. In addition, Socrates speaks falsely of Hippias; for example, at 286e Socrates says of Hippias, “You know it clearly”, and Socrates then implies that Hippias will teach Socrates how to avoid being refuted. Is Socrates’ uttering such falsehoods compatible with Socrates’ interest in the truth? If Socrates is interested in arriving at the truth, should he not be saying true things? Not necessarily. For one thing, uttering truths would not serve an interest in the truth in the circumstance of discussion with Hippias. If Socrates said truths about himself such as, ‘I am asking useful questions’, or if Socrates said truths about Hippias such as, ‘You might make better progress if you were humbler’, uttering such truths would not advance either Socrates’ or Hippias’ progress toward the truth. Hippias is depicted as 12 having a conceit and self-satisfaction that make him impervious to such accurate descriptions.10 And Socrates does not need them. Yet the false descriptions, which encourage Hippias, thus help to keep the conversation going. So the answer to our question about consistency is that Socrates’ making false statements actually serves his interest in truth about the fine itself as it bears on life conduct, because it keeps the truth-seeking conversation going. But this answer raises a new question: what is the use of sustaining a conversation with Hippias at all? How would a conversation with anyone like the depicted Hippias serve an interest in the truth in the first place? §6 Talking with Hippias Is Training for Socrates From a consideration of that question we learn something more about Socrates as self-questioner and self-answerer. At 287a 2-5 Socrates wants to learn by questioning Hippias so that Hippias will give him the most training (me ekmeletêsês): Socrates says he already has experience as an answerer.11 We readers are not familiar with Socrates as answerer. Other dialogues show us Socrates mostly as questioner. Socrates’ saying here that he has experience as answerer then seems an allusion to that practice of being answerer to himself as questioner of which the Hippias Major gives us a small glimpse. I take the statement that Socrates wants to get training as a partly accurate description; it is not a description tailored simply to fit Hippias’ point of view. Taken as a sincere statement, it tells us that Socrates expects some benefit from questioning Hippias. At the end of the dialogue Socrates says that he has been benefited both by conversation with Hippias and by conversation with his questioner. 13 Yet if Hippias, as depicted, is completely self-satisfied and utterly incapable of considering any new thoughts that challenge his current picture of himself, he is unlikely to have any insights into how to live to bring into the conversation. For the same reasons, Socrates cannot be expecting to benefit Hippias by inspiring any thought in Hippias. Further, Socrates is not trying to benefit any onlookers to the conversation, since the Hippias Major mentions no onlookers within the drama. So it looks as though there is no answer to our question in what direction Socrates could be expecting benefits from the conversation to flow. The question is a serious one. Someone might propose the answer that Socrates likes to amuse himself by watching pompous people make fools of themselves. I do not think so. A person taking care to live his life best would hardly waste time in that way.12 Our own observations of Socrates in conversation may of course benefit us as readers. But that only explains why Plato might have written a dialogue with Hippias for readers to observe. It does not explain why Socrates, as depicted,would engage in a private unobserved conversation with Hippias. It looks as though Socrates could more profitably just have talked to himself, as he does in the conversation with the annoying questioner that he reports to us. Why was that not enough? A possible answer is this. Here again I suggest a possibility, not a certainty. But I have heard no better offers, and the proposal above is certainly worse. Suppose that Socrates is interested in finding out the effects of self-satisfaction. Well, either Socrates is self-satisfied or he is not. If he is not, then conversation with himself will not show him the bad effects of self-satisfaction, since the effects will not ensue. If he is selfsatisfied, then again, talking to himself will not show him the bad effects of self- 14 satisfaction: for a person does not easily see his own self-satisfaction, and in fact selfsatisfaction blinds one to its bad effects. It stands in the way of one’s being self-critical. (Love is blind, and self-love the blindest.) So in either case, for assessing the effects of self-satisfaction it would not be useful for Socrates to talk to himself. But it might be useful for Socrates to talk to someone else who is self-satisfied. In another person Socrates can observe more clearly the bad effects of total self-satisfaction. So we have learned that Socrates has reason to converse with Hippias.13 §7 Socrates Is Always Tempted to Give A Certain Sort of Answer About Socrates the self- answerer we learn that he is always tempted by a certain sort of answer to the question ‘What is the fine?’ At 293e, Socrates reports that his annoying questioner has suggested candidate definitional answers to Socrates. Apparently out of pity for Socrates, who has been unable to come up with answers, the questioner has suggested such answers as that the fine might be the appropriate. Socrates does not say whether the questioner has offered the exact suggestion that the fine is the appropriate, or whether the questioner’s suggestions have been other than that, but similar in some way to it. Whatever the questioner’s suggestions have been exactly, Socrates says that he is “in the habit of (eiôtha) agreeing with such things (ta toiauta) every time (hekastote), because I don’t know what to say.” Apparently Socrates always falls for the type of account the questioner, trying to be helpful, suggests. A noticeable feature of the suggestion that the fine is the appropriate, the feature that perhaps “such things” as Socrates is inclined to agree with all have, is that the appropriate has more than a very good chance of being necessary and sufficient for the 15 fine. ‘Appropriate’ is a very general adjective of commendation, just as ‘fine’ is. It is therefore very plausible that it is, as we might say, a necessary truth that something is fine if and only if it is appropriate. Perhaps such statements as Socrates has been “every time” agreeing with are those that not only give necessary and sufficient conditions but that are also necessary truths. But the questioner has then gone on to refute all such helpful suggestions to which Socrates has agreed. §8 Socrates Has Always Refuted Himself in the Past About Socrates the self-answerer we learn that he regularly gets refuted by his questioner. Socrates has gotten “badly stuck” (286c: eis aporian; 286d: êporoumên); he thinks that is because he was totally worthless (dia tên emên phaulotêta). He does not want to be refuted (286e: exelegtheis) a second time, that is, by a second person. One of the points of learning what the fine itself is is that “no one will ever refute me again” (286e). His critic is “that man who has always (aei) been refuting me” (304d). The point is worth dwelling on. Socrates as questioner has refuted himself, and regularly; he has been at an impasse (aporia); he has driven himself into contradiction. I think we are given a clue to one sort of argument that has refuted Socrates in the past. The clue is Socrates’ own arguments, now given as he takes on the role of questioner in his own person to Hippias. Here he does not quote the annoying questioner as he argues against the questioner’s imagined helpful suggestion that the appropriate is the fine. Though Socrates does not quote the questioner, it is quite natural to suppose that 16 Socrates’ argumentative moves against the helpful suggestion are ones that he has learned from the annoying questioner. Although there are several arguments against candidate definitions that occur toward the end of the dialogue, after Socrates has referred to “the man who is always refuting me”, all of which strike me as subtle and important, I choose to explore here as part of my inquiry into how Socrates has been talking to himself only two arguments against the proposal that the fine is the appropriate. The arguments do not strike only against the proposed definition. Rather, they show that given certain other premises to which Hippias agrees, the appropriate cannot be the fine. The first of the two arguments from 293e11-294e9 is a simple two-premise argument. First Premise: The appropriate makes things seem fine when they are not fine. Second Premise: What makes things seem to be fine even when they are not fine cannot be the fine. Conclusion: The fine is not the appropriate. (294a7-8: “It wouldn’t be what we are looking for” and 294e6, “It wouldn’t be the appropriate.”) The first premise is given when Socrates says that the appropriate makes things seem finer than they are and it won’t let them be seen as they are.14 Socrates is recording Hippias’ assertion at 294a4-5 that the appropriate makes things be seen to be fine; when someone puts on appropriate clothes and shoes, he looks finer, even if he is ridiculous. I think this amounts to my shorter formulation that the appropriate makes things that are not actually fine --they may even be ridiculous -- seem fine. They of course then seem 17 finer than they actually are. I take the word “makes” here to have the same perfectly ordinary role it has when we say that its eight sides make this an octagon. Hippias’ example shows that he has in view a shallow notion of the appropriate. His notion amounts to something like the fashionable or the superficially attractive. But given his notion, we can understand the example from which Socrates gets the first premise. The second premise comes from 294b6-8, where Socrates again uses the comparative ‘finer’ as Hippias did in his contribution. The appropriate cannot be the fine, what fine things are fine by, because the appropriate “makes things to be finer than they are ... and it won’t let things be seen to be as they are.” Again I think that the point may be put more simply, without the comparative. This argument decisively defeats the proposal that the fine is the appropriate when that proposal is combined with Hippias’ thought that the appropriate can make things seem finer than they are. This first argument would, of course, defeat any candidate definition of the fine whose candidate definiens might also be cited as the explanation of why something, like the ridiculous figure in becoming clothes, seemed fine when it was not fine. That is, it would defeat any candidate definiens which picked out a feature not actually coextensive with the fine but which someone might mistake for a fine-making feature. It is useful to consider why argument of the pattern above would not work against a good definition. For example, the argument would not work against the analysis of an octagon as a figure having eight sides. That something has eight sides, though presumably it is often an important part of the explanation why that thing seems to be an 18 octagon, could not be an explanation why that thing seems to be an octagon when it is not in fact a octagon. So, so far, the first argument Socrates gives here against the proposal that the fine is the appropriate seems a long-winded way of saying that the appropriate -- conceived of, as Hippias inadequately conceives of it here, as the fashionable -- is not coextensive with the fine.15 Hippias now changes his mind and proposes that the appropriate makes things both be and be seen to be fine when it is present. Hippias, thus retracting his example about the ridiculous (and hence not actually fine) figure who looks finer in appropriate clothes and footwear, reveals another assumption of his which he cannot hold in conjunction with the proposal that the fine is to be defined as the appropriate. Socrates’ second argument, against this new configuration of Hippias’ premises, is another short one. First Premise. The appropriate makes things both be fine and be seen to be fine, when it’s present. (Hippias’ proposal at 294c3-4) Second Premise. The fine by itself (or perhaps the fine, itself) could not make things both be and be seen to be fine (294e2-4) Conclusion. The appropriate has been seen to be something other than fine. (294e8-9)16 Socrates argues for the second premise. He gets Hippias’ assent that there is disagreement about fine things, e.g. fine customs and pursuits (294c8-9), even when they really are fine. Hippias concurs that the presence of the fine in the case of fine things does not 19 always make them seem fine. Fine things often go unrecognized: “They are unknown.” (294d4) Guthrie comments on this second argument. (Guthrie’s translation uses ‘beautiful’ instead of ‘fine’.) “[The suggestion that the fine is the appropriate] is finally dismissed by an argument using the distinction between reality and appearance. This is a very curious argument, for it would apply not only to appropriateness but to whatever else might be alleged to be a definition or description of beauty. Does the appropriate make things to be beautiful or only to appear so? It cannot do both, for otherwise everything that possesses that attribute (i.e. if appropriateness =beauty, everything that is beautiful) would both be and appear beautiful, and there could be no difference of opinion about what is beautiful.”17 Guthrie says further of Plato, “Presumably ... he was aware that it disqualified not only ‘the appropriate’ but anything else one could think of, from consideration as a definition of beauty.’18 What Guthrie says is instructive, though wrong: contrary to what Guthrie says, the argument does not disqualify every possible definition. Rather, the argument disqualifies the conjunction of any proposed definition with an assumption like Hippias’ new first premise. That new first premise asserts the wrong sort of connection between on the one hand possessing the attribute that falls under the analysans and on the other hand seeming, or being seen, to fall under the analysandum. Hippias has asserted that possessing the analysans-attribute always makes for seeming to possess the analysandum 20 -attribute. Hippias’ proposal requires, unacceptably, that the presence of what the analysans of the fine describes should make it unmistakeably obvious that whatever falls under the analysans falls under the analysandum . Consider again the octagon. Though having eight sides is what makes a plane figure an octagon, having eight sides does not always make such a figure seem, or be seen, to be an octagon. Some octagons are entirely unobserved. And some observers are inattentive. Someone who fails to notice the presence of eight sides as he observes a plane figure will not take even the first step toward recognizing it as an octagon, even if he has firmly in mind the analysis that an eight-sided figure is an octagon. Even possession of an analysis cannot protect us against errors of inattention. That is the simplest case which vividly shows that Socrates has a decisive argument against the current candidate definition plus Hippias’ extra assumption. This simplest case reminds us that between the presence of the analysans -attribute and the being seen to fall under the analysandum -attribute there intervenes a person to whom seeming occurs or fails to occur.19 Moreover, there are some less simple cases in which the presence, even the recognized presence, of an analysans -attribute will not guarantee recognition of the presence of the analysandum-attribute. Imagine a geometer-in-training who antecedently believes that eight-sided figures are definitely not octagons. Turning his attention to what he sees to be an eight-sided figure, he will think that it is not an octagon. Granted, his confusion is maximal. But such confusion is one possible source for a disconnection between the recognition of an analysans -attribute and the recognition of an analysandum 21 -attribute. Our error can stand in the way of our matching up an analysans -attribute with what it analyses. Here is another way in which even recognizing the presence of an analysansattribute can fail to trigger recognition of its analysandum -attribute. Imagine a person searching for a definition of justice who believes strongly in advance that nothing just could greatly inconvenience him or that nothing just could disrupt traditional familiar social arrangements. Suppose he is even contemplating the correct, but at present unrecognized by him to be correct, analysans of justice, whatever that may be. Suppose he notices that if that were what just is, it would follow that freeing his slaves would be just. He is already convinced that freeing his slaves cannot be just, since it would be obviously inconvenient. So he will conclude that the (analysans-) attribute he is dwelling on cannot be justice. Socrates’ argument against Hippias’ way of connecting the proposed analysans of the fine with what makes things seem to be fine is a stimulus to reflection on the ways in which we can fail to make the connection between analysans and analysandum. We can fail because related convictions impede us. The finest analysis will not strike the otherwise unreceptive. §9 Socrates Omits to Mention a Possibility If this argument against the proposal that the fine is the appropriate has its source, as I am supposing, in Socrates’ self- questioning, consideration of that argument teaches us a further detail about Socrates the self-questioner: he thinks it important to explore 22 one’s assumptions about being seen to be -- which includes seeming -- as one tests a definition, but he omits to consider a certain possibility. It is Socrates who introduces the topic of seeming into the discussion in the first place when he offers Hippias some alternatives: does the appropriate make things “be seen to be fine, or be fine, or neither” (293e11-294a2)? It is not strange that Socrates and Hippias do not go on to consider the alternative “neither”, since they agreed earlier that the fine itself is what makes things be fine (287c8-d3), and they will agree so again: (294b4-6) “The fine is what all things are fine by, whether or not they are seen to be fine” (similarly 294b8-c1)). It is strange, however, that they test only two alternatives: first, that the appropriate makes things seem (and merely seem) fine and second, that the appropriate always makes things be seen to be, as well as be, fine. It is strange also that as the conclusion of this phase of their discussion, Socrates again offers Hippias the meager choice ( 294e4-5), between saying that the appropriate is what makes things be seen to be fine, or saying that the appropriate is what makes things be fine. Hippias chooses the former, and the topic of the appropriate is then abandoned. But why did Socrates not give Hippias another choice? Why did Socrates not ask Hippias to consider some more complex connections between being made to be, and being made to seem, fine? There is at least a third possible connection between the analysans -attribute and the recognition of the analysandum -attribute that Socrates is omitting. The appropriate, properly understood (although this might have been beyond the depicted Hippias) as the genuinely appropriate instead of the merely superficially appropriate, might always and only make things be fine and yet might merely sometimes, 23 but not always, make things seem fine to us. (Our receptivity to recognition will of course also enter in.) Would Socrates also have an argument against that more complex suggestion? The more complex suggestion seems initially more promising. For very general evaluative predicates such as ‘fine’, ‘good’, or ‘valuable’ it seems a strongly important truth about what is good, fine, or valuable that someone somewhere appreciates something good or otherwise valuable. Whatever is the correct analysis of the good or the fine, that analysis, which says what makes things good or fine, should bring out that strongly important truth. The correct analysis, whatever it might be, should bring out somehow the appeal of the good, that is, to its seeming good or fine to us. Whatever makes things good should make good things somewhere, sometime, seem good -- appeal -- to us. Being good or otherwise valuable is then rather different from being a rock or a galaxy or an octagon; there might be rocks, galaxies, and octagons without their ever getting noticed in the history of the universe. But if no sentient being could ever appreciate anything, there would be no fine things. (Any particular fine thing, though not all of them, might nevertheless escape the notice of all of us for all time.) Hippias’ inclination to connect his attempted analysis of the fine with what makes things seem fine is, to give even the depicted Hippias some credit, natural.20 I think that Socrates’ omission of any more complex proposal for the relation between the appropriate and what seems fine must mean something. It may simply mean that it is too much to expect Hippias to understand a more complex proposal. Or the omission may mean that Socrates in his self-questioning has not so far defeated that sort of proposal. Or the omission may mean that Socrates, or even Plato, is not yet ready to 24 talk about such a proposal. Perhaps the lesson is that the connection is a hard one even for an acute philosopher to articulate clearly.21 §10 A Major Lesson of Socrates’ Self-Questioning From Socrates’ depiction of his ongoing self-conversation, we learn what strikes me as an especially important thing about him. Socrates presents his conversation with himself as a conversation between people who are utterly focussed on the topic, who are utterly serious and plain speaking, who are utterly open to the severest criticism, but who yet arrive at no grand positive concluding statements. It is of course Plato who depicts Socrates as so depicting himself. I have put it previously that in Socrates’ self-conversation we are given Plato’s picture of the most philosophically acute questioner examining the philosophically most adept answerer. I would like to emphasize as strongly as possible the sort of picture Plato has drawn, and the importance I think he must have attached to it. I am tempted to try to make comparisons to other legendary contests; I think of matches that stand out in the history of boxing or of chess. Casting about for comparisons to convey the magnitude that I believe Plato saw in Socrates’ conversation with himself, I think also of mythic combatants locked in struggle. I imagine perhaps Fafner vs. Godzilla. But though that fantasy would approach a suitable magnitude, it is in other ways not appropriate. One reason is that Socrates’ self-conversation is not a battle. It is part of his customary search for the truth about how to live. So, after all, the barest statement is best. The conversation gives us Socrates facing Socrates. That says enough about the importance that Plato saw in this ongoing conversation of which he gives us fragments. It says, in fact, that we are 25 here given Plato’s picture of what we might call the Platonic ideal of a philosophical examination.22 So we learn something also about Plato from Socrates’ conversation. We learn that as Plato imagines an examining-conversation between the best possible philosophical equals, he imagines a conversation in which the participants do not put knowledge on display.23 The conversation, so far as we are told, may be only humbling.24 § 11 A Condition That Repels Socrates Finally, and most importantly, we learn from Socrates’ self-conversation just how very seriously he takes discussion of the fine. He thinks it shameful to discuss the fine under certain conditions. Socrates tells us at at 304 d how, as self-questioner, he reproaches himself. When I go home (epeidan oun eiselthô oikade) to my own place (eis emautou) and he hears me saying those things, he asks if I’m not ashamed that I dare discuss (dialegesthai) fine activities when I’ve been so plainly refuted about the fine, and it’s clear I don’t even know at all what that is itself! ‘Look’, he’ll say, ‘How will you know whose speech -- or any other action -- is finely presented or not, when you are ignorant of the fine?’ The final question which Socrates reports from the questioner is (304e1-2), Whenever you are in a state like that (hopote houtô diakeisai) do you think it is any better (kreitton) for you to live (zên) than to die (tethnanai)? It is a rhetorical question. I take it that Socrates would answer, ‘No, I think it is not any better for me to live than to die when I am in a state like that’. In 26 contrast to other dialogues in which Socrates as questioner gives no clues to his own beliefs, here we may confidently ascribe the answer to the depicted Socrates, who is answerer as well as questioner.25 The putative answer bears some scrutiny. I take it that the answer would not be merely a report on Socrates’ state of mind. It would convey something about the value of a certain way of life: when Socrates is in a state like that, it is no better for him to live than to die. We may then treat as a direct assertion from Socrates the statement, Whenever I am in such a condition, it is no better for me to be alive than dead. The statement is riveting, despairing, and puzzling. There are rare circumstances in which someone might seriously say of a person that life is no better than death for that person. But such circumstances -- for example, extreme permanent suffering or permanent criminality-- do not seem to be present here.26 Gregory Vlastos says of the statement, “the gravity of the denouement ... has never been properly appreciated in the scholarly literature.”27 He then comments and paraphrases thus: At the last moment the comedy turns tragic. Socrates sees the failure of the definitional search as his personal disaster: if he has no viable answer to the question, “What is the fine?”--and the long preceding discussion has shown that he hasn’t--his life has lost its value, he might as well be dead.(p.71) 27 Socrates sees catastrophe. He says that if this is to be his condition -- that of not knowing what is the fine and, therefore, not knowing if any particular action whatsoever is fine -- he might as well be dead: his life is worthless. We know what would make life worthless for Socrates: forfeiture of virtue. Thus Socrates is implying that since he cannot know if any particular action is fine so long as he has no definition of the “fine”, he will be unable to tell if any action whatever, be it the noblest deed or the foulest crime, is fine or foul: all his practical moral judgements will be at sea; so he will be unable to make correct moral choices in his daily life and thus to act virtuously. He is morally bankrupt. (p. 72) Vlastos says that “Socrates’ critic tells him that not knowing” if any particular action is fine “would spell moral disaster”. (p. 73) I think, however, that that is not what Socrates’ critic tells him. Although Socrates’ statement has as much gravity as Vlastos claims, its gravity is different in kind from what Vlastos finds. To explain its gravity I will ask here: what, exactly, are the conditions under which Socrates might as well die as live? I look again at the passage in which the questioner asks if Socrates is not ashamed: When I’m convinced by you and say what you say, that it’s much the most excellent thing (polu kratiston) to be able to present a speech well and finely (kalôs) and get things done in court or any other gathering, I hear every insult from that man. ... When ... he hears me saying those things, he asks if I’m not ashamed that I dare discuss (dialegesthai) fine pursuits 28 (kalôn epitêdeumatôn) when I’ve been so plainly refuted about the fine, and it’s clear I don’t even know what that is itself! ‘Look,’ he’ll say, ‘How will you know whose speech -- or any other action -- is finely presented or not, when you are ignorant of the fine? And when you’re in a state like that, do you think it is any better for you to live than die?’ (304c-e) I take it that here for Socrates to say that a certain speech was presented finely amounts to his saying that the action of presenting the speech was a fine thing to do. Ordinarily, saying ‘That’s a fine speech’ is distinct from saying ‘Your giving that speech is a fine action’. But I gather that Socrates does not want to make that distinction here, since he reproaches himself also in the passage for having discussed “fine pursuits” (or, in Woodruff’s translation, “fine activities”). That is, the annoying questioner locates as the source of shame that Socrates “dares” to say that activities such as getting things done in court are fine although Socrates cannot answer ‘How will you know what is fine?’; Socrates has no answer to ‘What is the fine?’, to give to someone else. I am uncertain whether Socrates is conveying that he actually at some time did say that presenting a speech or getting things done in court was a fine thing to do. However, it seems to me unlikely that Socrates is here confessing to an inclination to make such an observation. It seems to me more likely that Socrates is conveying to Hippias the conditional thought that if Socrates were to say such a thing, the annoying questioner would tell Socrates that that was shameful.28 29 Our question is: what is the gravity here? why would it be shameful enough to render life no better than death to ‘dare discuss’ fine activities or pursuits without an answer to the question, What is the fine? It is helpful here to look back at what prompted Socrates to ask ‘What is the fine?’ in the first place. What prompted him was Hippias’ mentioning his speech about fine pursuits. Hippias was in effect recommending a way of life to young men. Socrates’ challenge to Hippias suggests that Socrates has this objection: it would be shameful if Socrates were to recommend to others, as fine, certain life pursuits without being able to answer ‘What is the fine?’ Such recommendations about a fine way to live, without a supporting definition, would not help the hearer to arrive at his own reasons to believe -which are also reasons that explain why it is true -- that the recommended way of life is fine. Since a way of life is the most important thing that the hearer can endorse as fine, such a recommendation may in fact be damaging to a hearer if it inspires him to follow a pursuit but does not help him to explore his own reasons for it. In contrast, Socrates shows that he is not troubled that he recommends pots or soup ladles as fine without having a very general account of the fine. He can still give perfectly good reasons, specific to pots, why something is a fine pot, as he does at 288e: If the pot should have been turned by a good potter, smooth and round and finely fired, like some of those fine two-handled pots that hold six choes, very fine ones -- if he’s asking about a pot like that, we have to agree it’s fine. How could we say that what is fine is not a fine thing? It does not occur to Socrates to ask here what, in general, the fine is as a preliminary to talking about fine pots. They are not as important or as far reaching a topic as fine 30 pursuits for a life. (And there are pot experts, such as the good potter Socrates alludes to. This potter no doubt has no general definition of the fine, but Socrates is untroubled in getting his fine pots, and his fine pot standards, from the good potter.) My understanding of the condition under which Socrates would be ashamed is confirmed by 298b7-c1. Hippias had suggested that some answers Socrates finds flawed might “slip right past” (paralathoi) the questioner, that is, that they might not get tested. But Socrates says, emphasizing that it would be bad for him to put up a façade of knowing when he did not know, not past the person I’d be most ashamed to babble at or pretend (prospoioumenos) to say something when I’m not saying anything. ... He wouldn’t easily let me say those things without testing them, any more than he’d let me talk as if I knew what I didn’t know.29 The question might now be raised if Socrates is not, in talking to Hippias, doing just what Socrates says is shameful. Is Socrates not making recommendations to Hippias by calling pursuits fine and shameful (the opposite of fine) in the absence of a definition of the fine? I think the answer is that Socrates is not. He is definitely not urging Hippias to avoid doing the thing that Socrates would be most ashamed to do. In fact Socrates, in his last response to Hippias in the dialogue, congratulates Hippias, of course archly, that Hippias knows the things a man ought to practise (epitêdeuein: 304b8). But, Socrates says, when he himself repeats what Hippias says, and hence makes recommendations to others, Socrates’ self-questioner asks Socrates if Socrates is not ashamed. Socrates’ reproaches seem to be confined to himself. 31 There is one surprising thing about Socrates’ self-reproach which I note. The questioner asks Socrates if Socrates is not ashamed to converse -- dialegesthai-- about fine pursuits when he has been so plainly refuted about the fine 304d5-8). The verb dialegesthai can refer, very broadly, to conversing of all kinds. It can also refer, more narrowly, to the exchanges of short questions and short answers, the examining discussions, in which Socrates customarily engages. It would seem odd for Socrates to object to himself for engaging in these questioning discussions in the absence of a definition, since it is the absence of a definition that gets the conversations going in the first place; the point of the conversations is often to search for a definition. Socrates could hardly object to himself for looking for a definition when he does not have a definition. So perhaps ‘converse’ in its wider sense is the appropriate translation for dialegesthai here. Or perhaps we are to gather that Socrates is indeed, and not surprisingly, at least raising the reflexive and self-critical question whether he should be having examining conversations at all if they in fact presuppose some ability to classify things as fine and shameful. The question of what Socrates thinks he should be ashamed of is worth more thought. I conclude, however, that Socrates does not represent mere ignorance of definitions as moral disaster. He might even be thinking that such ignorance is the normal moral condition. His concluding response of the dialogue is not that simply because of not knowing what the fine is, it would be as well for him to die as to live. Rather, Socrates’ actual concern is somewhat less self-centered than a concern about his own acting in ignorance of definitions. He is looking outward at the effect of ignorant recommendations on ignorant others when, revealing the most serious insight of his self- 32 conversation, he paints the conditions under which he might as well die as live. The condition that repels Socrates is not ignorance. It is ignorance plus pretension, that is, fraud.30 University of Minnesota, Twin Cities Minneapolis, MN 55455 33 BIBLIOGRAPHY Benson, Hugh 1990. ‘Meno, the Slave Boy, and the Elenchus’. Phronesis 35: 128-158. Benson, Hugh 1996. ‘The Aims of the Socratic Elenchus’ 21-33 in Lehrer. Burnet, John 1903. Platonis Opera vol III. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Brickhouse, Thomas C. and Smith, Nicholas 1994. Plato’s Socrates. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Freeman, Kathleen 1959. Companion to the Presocratic Philosophers. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Frede, Michael 1992. ‘Plato’s Arguments and the Dialogue Form’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Supplementary volume IX: 201-219. Guthrie, W.K.C. 1986. A History of Greek Philosophy vol IV. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hyland, Drew 1995. Finitude and Transcendence in the Platonic Dialogues. Albany: SUNY Press. Inglessis-Margellos, Cécile 1994. ‘Socrate et Son Double’. Revue des Études Grecques 105: 85-106. Lehrer, K. et al., eds. 1996. Knowledge, Teaching, and Wisdom. Philosophical Studies Series vol 67. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. McGinn, Colin 1983. The Subjective View. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Miller, Mitchell 1996. ‘The Arguments I Seem to Hear: Argument and Irony in the Crito’. Phronesis 41: 121-137. Moreau, Joseph 1941. ‘Le Platonisme de L’Hippias Majeur’ Revue des Études Grecques 54: 19-42. 34 Palmer, John A. 1999. Plato’s Reception of Parmenides . Oxford: Clarendon Press. Prior, William J. 1997. ‘Why Did Plato Write Socratic Dialogues?’ Apeiron 30: 109123. Saunders, Trevor J. 1987. Plato’s Early Dialogues. New York: Penguin. Sedley, David 1998. ‘Platonic Causes’ Phronesis 43: 114-132. Smith, Angela M. 1998. ‘Knowledge and Expertise in the Early Platonic Dialogues’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. 80: 129-161. Szlezák, Thomas Alexander 1985. Platon und die Schriftlichkeit der Philosophie. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Tarrant, Dorothy 1976. The ‘Hippias Major’ Attributed to Plato. New York: Arno Press, reprint of 1928 edition of Cambridge University Press. Tarrant, R.S. 1994. ‘The Hippias Major and Socratic Theories of Pleasure’ in Vander Waert 1994: 107-126. Teloh, Henry 1986. Socratic Education in Plato’s Early Dialogues. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Tigerstedt, E.N. 1977. Interpreting Plato: Acta Universitatis Stockholmiensis 17. Uppsala: Amquist and Wicksell. Vander Waert, Paul A. 1994. The Socratic Movement. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Vlastos, Gregory 1991. Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Vlastos, Gregory 1994. Socratic Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Waterfield, Robin 1987. Translation of Hippias Major in Saunders 1987. 35 Whitaker, Albert Keith 1998. Plato’s ‘Parmenides’. Newburyport, MA: Focus Publishing. Woodruff, Paul 1982. Plato: ‘Hippias Major’: Translated with Commentary and Essay. Indianapolis: Hackett. 1 I use the translation of Woodruff 1982, and I have benefited from the commentary and essays. I have occasionally made a change in the translation, using the edition of Burnet 1903. At 294e3 I would keep Burnet’s reading. 2 Hyland 1995, p. 5 proposes an even more sweeping rule: “It is instructive, as others have observed, that Plato never presents a dialogue between two mature philosophers, much less between two ‘wise’ people.” Whitaker 1998 p. 2 says, “The Parmenides is the only example we possess of a conversation between Socrates, albeit a very young Socrates, and another philosopher.” Socrates’ conversation with himself in the Hippias Major is an exception, though a very brief one. Noticing the same thing as Hyland and Whitaker do, but describing it more accurately, even given the Hippias Major’s self-conversation, Prior 1997 p. 116 says, “Philosophy, for Socrates in these [early and middle] dialogues, is a way of life. In the dialogues written before the Parmenides, Socrates is the only representative of that way of life.” 3 There seems still to be some reasonable controversy here about what Socrates believes. A study of the speeches of the Laws in the Crito by Miller 1996 raises the question whether Socrates’ enactment of the Laws’ speech tells us Socrates’ own views, or whether these remain unspoken. For more complexities of the Crito, see Inglessis-Margellos 1994. 36 4 The conversation in the Hippias Major then is also a counter-example, but a special and not quite threatening one, to the thesis on p. 146 of Smith 1998: “Socrates’ interlocutors all claimed to be experts”. Socrates of course famously claims not to be an expert. This essay will explain why he interrogates himself anyway. 5 Tarrant 1994 suggests that neither of the two representations of Socrates is quite the real Socrates. Tarrant describes Socrates (p. 113) in the Hippias Major with “the surface Socrates having neither the urgent desire for truth nor the guts to ask tricky questions for himself, and the alter ego being all too hostile in his interrogations.” That I object to Tarrant’s description will become clear later. 6 There is a thought-provoking discussion of irony in Vlastos 1991. Vlastos says that when we speak today of a comment as ironic, we have in mind that its falsity will be obvious to its audience. But, he claims, the ancient Greek eirôn, ‘ironist’, as explained in e.g. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, conveys deliberate lying and the aim of deceiving the audience. I do not entirely agree with Vlastos that we today think that irony must be obviously false to its audience, since I don’t think he takes into account that there may be more than one audience for the same irony, and some audiences may be obtuse, and be known to be. But the matter is complicated, and I will anyway avoid the word ‘irony’. Tigerstedt 1977 p. 95 says, “We can seldom be absolutely sure that Plato is not speaking ironically.” (Presumably by ‘Plato’, he means ‘certain characters in Plato’s dialogues’.) I appreciate the difficulty of discerning when a statement in a dialogue is or is not ironic. But it seems appropriate, and even necessary, to ask ourselves what follows if certain statements -- such as the questions and comments of Socrates in his self-conversation in the Hippias Major-- are taken seriously. 7 The Editor reminds me that Socrates talked to himself after he was told what the Delphic Oracle had said about him. 8 Woodruff points out that athetizers of the dialogue have said that Hippias is “mercilessly ridiculed” in a way that is uncharacteristic of Plato’s Socrates (p.97). Woodruff replies that the Socrates of the Hippias Major, “sharp, ironic, and not without a streak of cruelty” is consistent with the goading and irritating Socrates elsewhere portrayed by Plato (p. 97). But Woodruff’s example of the “streak of cruelty” is solely what he calls the “naked insult at 286a” (p. 119). There Socrates says to Hippias that the Spartans use 37 Hippias “the way children use old ladies, to tell stories for pleasure.” Woodruff’s note 42 compares the remark to a Thrasymachean insult in the Republic . But it seems to me that at 286a Socrates is giving a mild barb: the Spartans have located Hippias in the wrong performance genre. I would need more evidence that Socrates or Hippias has the degree of total contempt for old ladies and children’s stories that would render Socrates’ description a positive cruelty. 9 Woodruff, p. 65 note 119 comments on the relation to the Phaedo passage. In contrast, Sedley 1998 p. 128 sees the Phaedo passage as defining large via going beyond (or exceeding), that is, as giving the same analysis as the Hippias Major, and notes that the same account is given at Parmenides 150c-d. 10 The character of Hippias as portrayed in this dialogue as self-satisfied is, so far as I know, universally acknowledged. Tarrant 1976 comments, “His first words breathe self-importance and he continues to boast without shame,” and she speaks of his “arrogant self-confidence” (p. xxix). Guthrie 1986 p. 176 says that the dialogue is “a burlesque of Hippias as an insensitive and stupid man with an impenetrable complacency and an insatiable appetite for flattery.” I don’t think that Hippias is stupid, although he is often wrong; but I won’t discuss that point here. Teloh 1986 p. 179 says, “Hippias’ ignorance is matched only by his confidence and insolence.” See also Freeman 1959 p. 389 –390. Hippias’ character is unchanged two days later in the conversation depicted in the Hippias Minor. Some readers of this paper have expressed sympathy for the actual Hippias, but I obviously do not take a stand on what he was like. 11 Here with a personal object ekmeletêsês means “train”. Woodruff translates “practice”, which is the translation Liddell-Scott gives for the verb with a non-personal object (to practice something, to study it), as at 286d6, which Woodruff translates “study”. 12 Prior p. 117, makes a similar point about why Plato wrote descriptions of conversations with such people as Hippias. “The interlocutors don’t fail because they are stupid, though commentators often allege this. Plato was not interested in writing works that simply made fun of foolish views and the people who held them.” 13 Compare Aristotle’s saying that we can contemplate our neighbors better than ourselves and their actions better than our own. (Nicomachean Ethics Bk IX ch 9 1169b33-34). Compare also Socrates’ observation in 38 Alcibiades Major (133a) that an eye looking into another eye will see itself, which precedes his suggestion that if a soul is to see itself, it should look at a soul (133b). 14 The verb I am rendering ‘seem’ [phainesthai] has an important ambiguity between ‘is plainly’ and ‘is apparently’, as Woodruff points out note 80, p. 54. Woodruff renders it “to be seen to be” in order to preserve the ambiguity. I have mostly used ‘seem’ here to emphasize that that is the force that is important in this argument. The argument points out that appropriateness can give the mere appearance of being fine. 15 On this point I am indebted to Gale Justin for comments on a shorter version of this paper that I presented at the Pacific Division Meetings of the American Philosophical Association in April 1999. She made it clear to me that the genuinely appropriate -- the appropriate in that sense of ‘appropriate’ in which it is a perfectly general word of commendation - is different from Hippias’ understanding of the word. The argument that Socrates gives here works only against Hippias’ rather shallow conception of the appropriate. Teloh p. 178, puts it: “Hippias operates only at the level of superficial appearances and public opinion.” Hippias’ example of shoes and clothes as appropriate suggests that for him the appropriate is the fashionable. 16 One might also state the conclusion, “The appropriate is plainly something other than fine.” Translating the verb ephanê, from phainesthai, by ‘is plainly’, is warranted by the following participle, on. 17 Guthrie p. 185. 18 Guthrie, p. 185. 19 Woodruff, p. 64, also thinks, in contrast to Guthrie, that Socrates’ argument is a good one, but he identifies the flaw that the argument reveals in Hippias’ proposal differently. Woodruff says, “The argument would discredit any definition of the fine that was intended to suffice for some other definiendum as well. Two different things cannot have the same logical cause . . . unless the two always occur together. ... So the argument is not a trick; it serves to show that Hippias himself conceptually separates the appropriate from the fine.” Woodruff’s principle about logical cause seems unobjectionable, but I think it is especially of interest to notice that the argument is calling attention to the connection between being and seeming. 39 20 Robin Waterfield, p. 249 in Trevor J. Saunders, ed., Plato: Early Dialogues (Penguin: New York 1987) comments on the argument by which Socrates disqualifies Hippias’ second proposal in a way that makes, but I think somewhat too simply, the important connection between seeming and being fine. “The argument is neat, but flawed, from our point of view, because we want to say that fineness is an aesthetic quality; it lies in the eye of the beholder. There seems to be little sense in the notion that something is fine, if in fact no one recognizes it as such -- but what has universal recognition got to do with it? However many people see X as fine, X is fine for them; if no one sees X as fine, X is not fine for them.” Because Socrates is especially concerned about fine activities, I think it is clear that he is not interested in what is fine for some particular individual. Socrates, unlike Waterfield, could say that a particular fine thing might go universally unrecognized. 21 For some complicated ways of stating the connection that are ultimately discarded, see McGinn 1983 pp. 145-155. 22 Palmer 1999 p. 63 suggests the possibility that Socrates the questioner and Socrates the answerer “make crucially different assumptions about the definitional project.” It will be clear that, in taking the conversation of which Socrates reports fragments to be a serious conversation of Socrates with himself, I disagree with that. 23 On this point I disagree strongly with Szlezák 1985 ch. 7, “Hippias maior: Sokrates und sein Doppelgänger”. According to Szlezák, when Socrates “splits” into two, one of the results of the split, the questioner, is someone whose speech “betrays knowledge of the ideas”; the other result is the unknowing answerer. But in the Hippias Major the knowledge of the fine itself that is sought is first of all an analysis of the fine. I see no evidence that Socrates the questioner has that analysis. Talking about the fine itself shows an interest in a definitional question. It does not show a grasp of the answer. Moreover, if Socrates the answerer were to answer the questioner by mentioning “the ideas” in the sense of a realm of transcendent beings graspable only by a few people who had special access to them, my impression of Socrates the questioner is that he would get out his cudgel in earnest. Socrates objects to Hippias’ advice to make yourself famous by making speeches not because Hippias cannot reinforce his advice by speaking of the 40 theory of ideas in this latter sense. Rather, Socrates is objecting that Hippias gives no straightforward reasons to believe that the advice is good advice. Plato hints that Hippias’ advice is not good by making that advice originate with Nestor, who has some character flaws that may indicate his untrustworthiness. (The Oxford Classical Dictionary credits Nestor with “platitudes”.) On the point that the questioner is somehow alluding to the theory of ideas, I disagree also with the helpful though athetizing article of Moreau 1941. Moreau finds that the questioning Socrates (pp. 4142) asks questions in a way that only “initiates of Platonism” will see the point of. If “initiates of Platonism” need to do more than to understand what it is to ask for an analysis, I disagree. There is room for dispute whether or not Plato moved -- and if so, how much -- from this picture of the ideal conversation about philosophy in other works. I do not take up that question here. 24 The conversation in the Hippias Major provides a corrective worth dwelling on to a statement of Prior p. 117. Prior says, “The dialogues are unhappy encounters between the philosopher and non-philosophers, and the point of the encounters is to show the incompatibility between the life of philosophy and that lived by non-philosophers.” Socrates’ self-conversation in the Hippias Major is an encounter also somewhat unhappy -- in that no positive answer to the main question is arrived at. But it is an encounter between a philosopher and a philosopher. The Hippias Major might then have another point: to show that a life of philosophy involves pretty constant self-questioning and pretty constant failure to define the most important things. Waterfield 1987 p. 226 raises the question why, “if the dialogue is scarcely informative on the nature of fineness, ... did Plato write it?” Waterfield pp. 226-228 gives some reasons to find the dialogue useful. Prior’s idea gives another answer to the question: the encounter between Socrates and Hippias shows the incompatibility of their two ways of life. Adding to Prior’s idea the thought that the dialogue displays the encounter between Socrates and himself gives another answer to Waterfield’s question. 25 In most dialogues the dialogue form prevents us, as, for example, Frede 1992 points out, from finding direct evidence for any views to ascribe to Socrates the questioner, let alone to Plato. We only have what the answerer believes in a question and answer discussion. In Alcibiades Major Alcibiades states this. Socrates asks, (112e- 113a) “Do you see again, Alcibiades, how you aren’t saying that well... that I am 41 saying these things? ...Concerning these things, surely, it’s not that I, the one questioning, am evidently saying [them]; rather, [is it] you, the one answering?” Alcibiades responds, “The one answering, it seems to me, Socrates.” But here in the Hippias Major, if Socrates would answer ‘No’ to the question, we have the view of Socrates the answerer, who happens also to be the questioner. 26 Other passages in which what Socrates says seems to have the implication that under certain conditions it would be better to die than to live are discussed in Brickhouse and Smith 1994, pp. 201-212. An anonymous referee has made the thought-provoking and correct comment that there is some room for dispute about what Socrates’ response would be. Suppose, as is possible, that Socrates’ response would be, ‘No, I do not think that it is any better for me to live than to die when I am in a state like that.’ That response is logically different from, and milder than, the response, ‘I think that it is not …’. The response, ‘I do not think…’ would be a report simply about the content of Socrates’ thoughts. It would not be a comment on the value of a certain way of living. It would be a further report of Socratic ignorance. Socrates’ putative response would not then be as riveting as I find it to be later on in this essay. I don’t see a way to settle this dispute definitively. At the moment I am more inclined to believe that Socrates’ answer is intended as a comment on the value of a way of life, not just as a comment about the contents of his thought. 27 Vlastos 1994, p. 72. 28 It would also be relevant to look at passages in other dialogues in which Socrates says (and not ironically) that someone has said something fine. For example, at 19e in the Apology Socrates says that he thinks it is a fine thing if someone is able to teach people, as Gorgias, Prodicus, and Hippias profess to do. Is this statement the sort of recommendation that the Socrates of the Hippias Major would be ashamed to make in the absence of an account of the fine? I think that the answer is ‘No’, but I will not pursue that question here. Gale Justin has suggested that since Socrates mentions ‘court or any other gathering’, Socrates has in mind the sort of recommendations he would put himself in the position of making if he were to go into politics. 42 29 Benson 1990 p. 152 also objects to Vlastos’ account of 304d5-e3, but differently from the way I have objected. “To read the Hippias Major passage ... as ... a message of the futility of the quest for knowledge is, I think, to seriously misread it. [It] is of a piece with those passages in which Socrates testifies to the value of eliminating one’s conceit. It is just another passage in which Socrates exhorts others toward philosophy. Once one recognizes one’s ignorance, one must recognize that a life in such a state is not worth living.” Benson relates the Hippias Major passage to the Apology’s claim that the unexamined life is not worth living for a man. I think Benson’s account is compatible with my account. The Hippias Major passage, as I’ve explained it, says only that the pretentious or fraudulent life is not worth living. The connection with the unexamined life is perhaps that an unexamined life leads to self-satisfaction; selfsatisfaction may lead to pretension and fraud. Self-examination may help Socrates ward off selfsatisfaction. But the connection is worth more exploration. 30 I thank two anonymous referees and the Editor for very thought provoking comments. I thank my colleague, Elizabeth Belfiore, for informing me about Nestor and for convincing me that Socrates is genuinely insulting to himself. I thank my colleague Norman Dahl for reminding me that making objections to oneself about one’s current philosophical projects is a very ordinary thing to do. I thank Constance Meinwald and Marie Pannier for helpful reactions and comments, and I especially thank Hugh Benson and Gale Justin for some objections. I thank John Wallace and my sons John and Peter for their encouraging attention to a very early draft of this.