CHAPTER2 Action Phasesand Mind-Sets P E T EM R . GOLLWITZER Forschung f ür psychologische Max-Planck-/nstitut The focus of this chapter is on the course of action, which is understood to be a temporal, horizontal path starting with a person's desires and ending with the evaluation of the achieved action outcome. The phenomena of choosing an action goal, initiating the appropriate actions, and executing these actions are assumed to be situated in between. This comprehensive perspective conceivesof the course of action as a number of consecutive, distinct segments or phases. It raises questions concerning how people choose action goals, plan and enact their "mind-set" is employed to execution, and eaaluate thek efforts. The concept of find answers to these questions in terms of the cognitive processesor orientations that allow for easy completion of the different action phases. A PHASEMODELOF ACTION Goal Settingand Goal Striving "Being motivated" implies a number of different phenomena. But how many distinct aspectsof being motivated to pursue a desired goal are there? Kurt Lewin (Lewin, Dembo, Festinger, & Sears, 1944) made a major distinction between goal "Goal striving" is behavior directed toward existing striving and goal setting. "Goal goals, and thus addressesquestions of moving toward the chosen goal. setting," on the other hand, addressesthe question of what goals a person will choose, and thus considers the expected value of the available choice options. Noticing the unique nature of both of these problems, Lewin adopted a distinct theoretical perspective for each of them. He referred to an expectancy X value model when goal setting was at issue-for instance, when he and his colleagues were attempting to explain people's changes in aspiration level (Lewin et al., 1944).Issues of goal striving, however, were explained in terms of his theory of tension systems (Lewin, 1926), through which he tried to discover the forces that move a person toward a chosen goal. Lewin considered the strength of these forces to be related not only to the valence of the chosen goal, but also to the individual's perceived distance from the goal. By introducing the variable of t3 54 and Self-Control Part I. Selt'-Regulation porency, Lewin (1936) tried to explain which of the many goals people entertain at a given time actually guide their behavior in specific situations. German researchersstudying goal-oriented beha'rior before Lewin devoted themselves solely to the issue of goal striving by studying the initiation and execurion of actions serving chosen goals or instructions given by others. This re"wii1 psychology"; its rnost search tradition has become known as the German prominent figure was Narziss Äch (1905, 1910, 1915). Researchersin this tradition fiercely disagreed on the key questions of will psychology, such as whether intentions specifying an appropriate opportunity to act favor smooth action initiation, regardlessof the importance of the respective superordinate goal (Ach, 1935; Selz, 1910). Nevertheless, they unanimously considered goal striving "battle of motives." to be different from goal setting, which they referred to as the For German will psychologists, it was clear that people's goal setting depends primarily on their desires, needs, and interests, whereas a host of additional variables determines whether and how people act on their chosen goals.It was the latter that they tried to identify and that they explored in their theories. Researchersstudying goal-oriented behavior after Lewin shifted their attention from goal striving to goal setting. Stimulated by Lewin's as well as Festinger's work on shifts in the level of aspiration (Festinger,1942; Lewin et al., 1944), Atkinson (19t7) presented a formal model of risk taking that made it possible to compute the motivational tendency to choose tasks representing various difficulty levels. Like Lewin, Atkinson considered goal setting and goal striving to be the two major problems requiring solution in any psychology of motivation: The first problem is to accountfor an individual'sselectionof one path of action among a set of possiblealternatives.The secondproblem is to accountfor the amplitude of the action tendencyonce it is initiated, and for its tendencyto persistfor a time in a given situation.(1957,p. 359) However, Atkinson hoped that the two distinct problems could be reduced to one and thereby could be accounted for by a single theoretical model. In his view, the theory best suited to accomplish this purpose was the risk-taking model (Ätkinson, 1957) or a modified version of it (Atkinson & Reitman, 1956). This model implies that the motivational tendency that makes a person choose a certain task will also account for the effort the person exerts when working on the chosen task and for the quality of the achieved performance. Empirical studies investigating this implication sometimes observed the predicted performance-enhancing effects of motivation, but more often failed to "now you see it, do so (see Atkinson,1974, for a review). Atkinson attributed the "overmotivation" (and its now you don't" character of this effect to what he called "undermotivation"). (Yerkes & Referring to the Yerkes-Dodson law opposite, tendency Dodson, 1908), he postulated that there should be an ideal motivational for each individual task. Tasks differ with respect to the amount of motivation that leads ro most efficient performance: Low levels of motivation are more Chapter 2. Action Pbasesand Mind-Sets 55 appropriatefor some tasks,whereasmedium or high levelsare more appropriate for others.Sincewhich tasksbelong to which categorywas unknown, Ätkinson suggestedestablishingthis classificationempirically. Once it was known what level of motivation is ideal for a given task, researcherswould finally be able to developvalid predictionsof task performance,basedsolelyon their knowledgeof the individual'smotivation. Äs comparedto this empirical Sisyphus-likework, a more theoreticalsolution to the troublesomemotivation-perfcrmanceissuecertainly exists.That is, one can re-establishthe old distinction betweengoal setting and goal striving. Eric Kling er (7977) recognizedthis possibilitywhen he introducedhis conceptof "current concerns."He pointed out (1977, pp. 22-24, 329-)30) that expectancy X value theories have been only very modestly successfulin predicting vital aspectsof goal striving, such as work effort and quality of performance.Consequently, his theory of current concernsfocusessolely on issuesof goal striving. This theory has no difficulties in accountingfor the commonly observedinvigoration of acrivityin the faceof obstaclesen route to a chosengoal-a phenomenon that cannot be explained by expectancy-valuetheories,becausethe setbackmust be assumedto reducethe expectancyof achievingthe goal and thus the individual's motivation to work for it. Kuhl (1983) also re-establishedthe classicdistinction by introducing the "control "choice motivation." In his opinion, models motivation" and conceptsof of choice motivation relate to goal setting, and he saw Atkinson's risk-taking model and its many reformulationsand extensions(e.g.,Feather, 1967; Heckhausen,I9l7;Raynor, L969;\7einer,1974)as more or lessvalid examplesof such models.Kuhl noted alackof theorieson goal striving and offered his own model, "control theory" (Kuhl, 1984). Stimulated by Atkinson and which he labeled Birch's (I970) assumptionthat a person is alwaysaffectedby numerousmotivational tendencies,all in constant flux, Kuhl saw effective goal striving as dependent on people'sefforts to shield it from competing action tendencies.Accordingly, whether people make progresswith respectto a chosengoal is no longer seen as dependentoniy on the motivation that originally made them choosethis people shield (control) the goal. Rather, it is also a questionof how successfully actions that lead to goal achievement. The Rubicon Model of Action Phases "Rubicon model" of action phases (Heckhausen,1987b; Heckhausen& The Gollwitzer, 7986, 1987) goes beyond the useful conceptualdistinction between goal setting and goal striving. Although the model keeps these two problems of both within a single theoretical goal-orientedbehaviorseparate,it encompasses model, thus permitting them to be analyzedin relation to each other. Furthermore, it provides a temporal perspectivethat begins with the awakeningof a person's wishes prior to goal setting and continues through the evaluative thoughts entertained after goal striving has ended. 56 and'Selt''Control Part l. Self-Regulati.on Separating the sequenceof events occurring within this comprehensive time frame into discrete phenomena, the model posits four distinct phases: first, the predecisional phase; second, the postdecisional but still Preactional phase; third, ihe uctional phase; and iast, the postactional phase. These phases are seParatedby three clear boundaries or transition points: the makin gof a decision,the initiation of respective actions, and the conclusion of these actions. But what distinct phenomena ^re associatedwith each phase? PredecisionalAction Phase People'smoby wishingand deliberating. The first phaseis characterized tives (McClelland,1930)producecertainwishes:For instance,a personwith a srrong power motive and a weak affiliation motive is expectedto experiencemore wishes related to power than to affiliation. However, people cannot act on all of their wishes but must chooseamong them, becausesome wishes may contradict each other, others are roo difficult to implement, and life is simply too short to follow all of one's wishes. People have to deliberate over which of their many wishesthey prefer to Pursue. They may employ the criteria of How can peopleestablishsuchpreferences? feasibility and desirability. S7ith respect to feasibility, people may contemplate whether they can obtain the outcomeimplied by a given wish through their own activity and whether the situational context they face is facilitating or impeding. Accordingly, they should also becomeconcernedwith questionssuch as whether they will find enough time to strive for the desired outcomes and whether the necessarymeans or oPPortunitieswill be available. The desirability of the wanted outcome is determined by reflecting on its expectedvalue. The expectedvalue is derived by estimating the pleasantnessorrpl.uruntness of potential short-term and long-term consequencesand by assessing the probability that achieving the desired outcome will lead to these consequences.Such consequencesinclude the following: a positive or negative self-evaluarion,a positive or negative evaluation by significant others, Progress toward some important life goal, or some pleasant or unpleasant side effects unrelated to the specific wish that initially started the person's striving (Heckwith the processof achievingthe hausen,1977).In addition,incentivesassociated desired ourcome (e.g., joy experienced while trying to establish the desired outcome) should also be relevantwhen the desirability of a given wish is deliberated. of the feasibilityand desirabilityof a given wish, however, Proper assessment with requiresthat this wish be seenin relation to other wishes.A wish associated many atractive consequencesmay suddenly appear less desirable when scrutinized in the light of a superordinatewish (e.g.,the wish to dine in fine restaurants becomeslessdesirablewhen it conflictswith the wish to buy a house).Or it might becomemore feasible when contemplatedin connection with the realization of other wishes (e.g.,u busyperson'swish to learn to play tennis may aPPearmore feasible when it is contemplated together with the wish to take an extended vacation). Chapter2. Action Phasesand Mind'-Sets 57 Makinga Decision and the PreactionalPhase high desirabiiityand feasibilityand thus is Evenwhen a wish is accorded given highest preference,the model of action phasesassumesthat wish fulfillmenr further demandstransformingthe wish into an intention. Phenomenologically,thistransformationis characteizedas a resolutionresulting in a feeling of that one will act determinationto fulfill the wish (or at leasta feelingof assurance on rhe wish at hand; Michotte & Prüm, 1910).The goal stateor desiredoutcome specifiedby the wish thus becomesan end state that the individual feels committed to achieve.The model describesthis senseof obligation in stating that the "goai intention." To catch the flavor of this transition individual has acquireda from the fluid state of deliberation to a firm senseof commitment, Heckhausen "crossing the Rubicon." (1987b)employedthe metaphor of After forming a goal intention, people move to the preactional phase.The phenomenon associatedwith this action phase is planning. Planning is often necessarybecausenewly formed goal intentions cannot be implemented immediately if the individual is engagedin alternative activities that first need to be completed or if relevant opportunities to act are not yet available.In addition, most goal intentions specify goal states (e.g., to graduate from college) that cannorbe achievedin a single step. Consequently,the individual is interrupted (or must pause) repeatedly and is forced to await future opportunities to work towardsthis goal. The model of action phasesassumesthat people do not usethesetime breaks of goal achievement; or pausesto weigh the positive or negative consequences rather, the feeling of obligation associatedwith the goal intention makespeople cöncernedwith the issueof how to promote achievingthe chosen goal. Accordingly, they should addressquestionsof.wben anduhere to start acting,bow to act, and bout long to act. STheneverpeople anticipate difficulties with respectto any of these implementational issues,they should commit themselvesto one of the many possibleways of initiating, executing,and terminating a relevant courseof action. Committing oneself to a particular implementational course constitutes forming behavioralintentions. These behavioralintentions (i.e., initiation intentions, execution intentions, and termination intentions) focus on a person's behaviorin pursuing the chosengoal. The model distinguishesbehavioralintentions from goal intentions, since the latter focus on desired goal states.In line with the ideas of German will psychology (Ach, 1935), it is assumed that behavioralintentions promote the smooth initiation, execution,and termination of activitiesin pursuing a person'sgoal intentions. Action lnitiation and the Actional Phase When does a goal intention lead to initiating relevant actions?It primarily depends on the goal intention's volitional strength-that is, how stron gly a person is committed to implementing the chosengoal. The genuine amount of volitional strength is consideredto be a positive function of the goal's desirability and feasibility as perceivedprior to choosing this goal. However, this volitional 5B Part I. Self-Regulationand Self-Control strength may vary, depending on a person's experienceswith attempting to initiate relevant actions.If a person repeatedlyignores good opportunities to initiate relevantactions,volitional strength may decreaseover time. On the other hand,volitional strength may spontaneouslyand momentarily increasewhen the individual encountersobstacles. More importantiy, goal intentions and their effects on the initiation of without consideringthat many different goal relevantactionscannotbe discussed intentions may compete for implementation at any given point in time. One the intention with the comparatively would expectthat under thesecircumstances highest volitional strength would prevail. However, the situation at hand may not be equally conduciveto implementing all of these competing intentions; it may favor implementing some of theseintentions more than others. In addition,for someintentions the situationat hand may be better suitedfor smooth implementation than any future situation for which the individual hopes.Consequently,the individual may be very eagerto take the opportunity at hand and to postpone the implementationof competingintentions,even if these intentions are associated with comparatively higher volitional strength. To summarize: SThether a given goal intention leads to the initiation of relevant actions depends on its volitional strength (as compared with that of other competing goal intentions) and on how favorablethe situation is for readily initiating the particular goal intention (as compared with initiating competing goal intentions and as comparedwith relevant furure opportunities one hopes to encounter).Finally, a goal intention that has been furnished with initiation intentions during the postdecisional(preactional)phaseshould havean additional advantageover competing goal intentions, given that the opportunity specifiedby the initiation intention is present. In this case,the opportunity to act should be more easily recognizedand, once recognized,should elicit a specialimpulse to start acting on it. Action initiation is the demarcationline signaling the transition to the actionalphase.The phenomenoncharacteristic of this phaseis actingtoward goal achievement.A person'sefforts to pursuea goalintention arc againassumedto be related to the goal intention's volitional strength. The amount of volitional strength servesas a kind of threshold value for the individual's effort exertion. This threshold, however, may be spontaneouslymoved upward if hindrancesare encountered, thus allowing f.or a reactive, momentary increase in volitional strength. Spontaneousnonconsciousincreasesin effort exertion were originaliy reportedby German will psychologists(Ach, 1935;Hillgruber, \9I2), who interpreted these reactiveresponsesof the individual as attempts to hold on to one's goal commitment. These ideas should not be confusedwith considerationsexpressedby models of effort calculation.For example, Brehm, \7right, Solomon, Silka,and Greenberg(1983),Kukla (1972),and Meyer (1973) specifiedhow the reflective appraisal of perceivedability, perceiveddifficulty, and subjectivevalue of goal attainment determine a person's effort exertion. Heckhausen(1987a) assumedthat the courseof action is directedby the mental representation of the goal, and that determination to achieve a goal Chaater2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 59 originates from the mental goal representation even when the goal itself is outside of conscious awareness.The goal may be defined at various levels of abstraction (i.e., at the lowest level to the intricacies of the actions to be executed, at an intermediate level to the intended outcome, and at the highest level to the conseqlrencesthat this outcome is expected to mediate), depending on the difficulties the person encounters when acting on it. In line with Vallacher and \Tegner's (1987) action identification theory, goals are assumedto be defined on low levels of abstraction (i.e., necessaryimplementational steps as compared to the intended outcome and its desired consequences)when smooth goal pursuit is thwarted. Coal Achievementand the PostactionalPhase The phenomenon associatedwith the final action phase is evaluating the question of whether one's goal striving has succeeded.\X/hat criteria govern this evaluation? Two successiveevaluative questions must be answered by the individual. First is the question of whether the intended outcome has been achieved,so that the individual may stop acting and await the desired consequences. This question is easily answered whenever the outcome is a discrete performance (e.g., to send a birthday gift to a friend). It becomes a problem difficult to solve and full of uncertainty whenever the intended outcome can be continuously improved or extended (e.g., to prepare well for a mathematics test). In the latter case, the "I will work through the individual may resort to termination intentions (e.g., "I practice examples twice" or will stop when I succeed in solving every other practice problem"), thus defining clear standards regarding when the intended outcome is achieved. Second, the individual must address the question of whether the actual value of the goal striving matches its expected value. This implies that the individual must wait for the desired consequences of the achieved outcome before this question can be answered. Only then will the individual be in a position to compare the actual value with the desired value, regardless of whether the desired consequencesare a positive self-evaluation, positive evaluation by others, progress toward some superordinate goal, or some pleasant side effects. In reality, the actual value may not measure up to the expected value as assessed during predecisional deliberation. The desirability of the goal may have been overestimated because certain negative consequenceswere neglected or underestimated, whereas positive consequenceswere overestimated. Future predecisional deliberation should benefit from such evaluations; that is, the estimation of expected values should become more accurate. In this sense, postactional individuals look not only back into the past, but also to the future. Postactional evaluation may not only benefit future deliberation, but may also help a person's future planning. \Whenever the individual recognizes that the achieved outcome does not meet the intended standards or that the achieved outcome is not good enough to lead to the desired consequences,the individual may furnish the goal intention with new initiation and execution intentions, thus improving the chances of successful implementation. Or the person may lower 60 Part l. Self-Regalationand'Self'Control the standards related to the quality of the outcome or the attractiveness of its consequences.If such measuresare not taken or if all of these efforts fail, the goal intention may linger on without successfulimplementation. \Thenever a situation is encountered that could be perceived as conducive to implementing the goal intention, it still should become activated, although chances to implement it are rather slim. Since this acivation occupies cognitive capacity, it may even hinder t|e implementarion of competing goal intentions, thus turning the individual into a procrastinator who keeps failing to act on his or her intentions. Summaryand Discussion temporal(horiThe Rubiconmodelof actionphasestakesa comprehensive zontal) perspectiveon the courseof action, and thus differs from most current modelsof action.The latter are of a strict vertical,hierarchicalnature (e.g.,Carver & Scheier,1981;Gallistel,1980,1985;FIacker,1985;Semmer& Frese,1985);they assumethat the individual, when executing a courseof action, advancesfrom a concern with abstract,superordinate,higher-level goals to concrete,subordinate, lower-level goals. The temporal dimension of action is addressedsolely with respect ,o ,h. organizationof single acts or action units within the course of action (von Cranach,1982). by the model of actionphaseshasso The horizontalperspectiveassuggested far not been very popular in psychology.The German philosopher and psychologist Christoph Sigwart (1889) introduced this perspectiveprior to the heydayof will psychology.Although his work did not stimulate any systematicresearch,it at le"si prevented German will psychologistsfrom confounding problems of goal setring (which they referred to as problems of motivation) with goal striving (which they referred to as problems of willing or volition). Recently,Heckhausen and Kuhl (1985) employed a horizontal perspectivewhen they reflected on the long way from a person's wishes to the execution of relevant actions.Although their primary focuswas on the mental examinationsthat wishes must passbefore winning accessto a person's behavior, they made a strong distinction between pr.- unä postinrentional processes,which they also referred to as motivational respectively. and volitional processes, The Rubicon model of action phasesincorporatesthis distinction; however, insteadof focusingon a person'smental efforts (or blocks) in turning a wish into relevant action, it artempts to delineate distinct phenomena of goal-oriented behavior whose functioning obeys distinct principles. In temporal order, these phenomena are deliberating, planning, acting, and evaluating. The Rubicon model may lead ro a number of misconceptions if taken too literally. These misconceptionsare as follows: 1. The model doesnot imply that every single initiation of action is directly precededby deliberation of the desirability and feasibility of the underlying goal and the forming of a goal intention. Many initiations of action are simply resumprionsof activitiesthat were started some time before; forming the underlying goal intention anew is therefore unnecessary.The same is true for action initiations postponed becauseof a lack of opportunities to act. Finally, people Chapter2. Action Pbasesand,Mind-Sets 61 entertaingoal intentions that imply superordinate,identity-relatedgoals,suchas becoming a psychologist.These identity intentions (Gollwitzer, 1987) lead to initiating relevantactionswithout prior reflectionon the desirabilityand feasibility of the underlying goal; the individual needsonly to checkwhether a given opportunity is conduciveto pursuing this goal. 2. The model doesnot imply that forming a goal intention is necessarily followed by intense planning concerningwhere, when, how, and how long to implement the chosengoal.It is rather assumedthat suchconcernsoriginateonly when smooth implementationof the goal intention is threatened.Initiation may or means are required that be cumbersome(a) wheneverspecialcircumstances still needto be developedor created;(b) wheneverthe critical opportunity may be missedbecauseit is difficult to recognize,happensinfrequently, or presentsitself only for a short moment; and (c) when competing goal intentions continue to block implementing the critical goal intention. Execution is hampered when the courseof action runs into difficulties becausethe individual does not possessthe necessarycompetenciesor fails to focus attention on the goal pursuit when consciouscontrol of the activity is needed.Finally, termination of the implementational activities becomesproblematic whenever it is unclear exactly what suffices as the intended outcome.In all of these casespertaining to the initiation, execution,and termination of implementational actions,planning that results in the formation of the respectivebehavioralintentions is to be expected. 3. The model of action phases doesnot exclude the possibility of overlap betweenactionphases.In the predecisionalphase,deliberationof wishesconcerning a goal can easilybe interrupted so that actions in the serviceof other already chosen goals may be planned, initiated, completed, or evaluated.Also, in the postdecisional(preactional) phase,the individual may deliberatevarious wishes and evaluatesome completed goal pursuit while waiting for the opportunity to act on a chosen goal; the individual may even act on some other goal when theseactionsdo not demandmuch cognitive capacity(i.e.,when they are automatized). Similarly, during the execution of goal-related actions, individuals may deliberatewishes, ready themselvesfor implementing other goals, or evaluate some terminated goal pursuit as long as executing the critical actions is largely automatized. 4. The model of action phases doesnot ignore the fact that goal striving is hierarchicallyorganized.This is most evident in the model's distinction between goal intentions and behavioralintentions. Behavioralintentions are supplements to goal intentions and serve to promote the implementation of goal intentions. Accordingly, the formation of a goal intention precedesthe formation of behavioral intentions, and the latter are justified by the former. But not all of the intentions formed subordinatelyto some goal intention must be behavioralintentions. People frequently form goal intentions in the serviceof other (superordinate) goal intentions (e.g.,when a personwho has decidedto becomea psychologist makesup his or her mind to go to schoolabroad).In this case,the formation of the subordinate goal (i.e., going to school abroad) should be precededby a concernnot only for the feasibility of this goal, but also for its desirability. 6Z Partl. Self'Regulationand'Self'Control describeforming 5. The modelusesrhe metaphorof crossingthe Rubiconto point of no a goalintention.The allusionis not so much to havinggone beyonda that ..,orr. as it is to putting incessantdeliberationto a rest' The model assumes "babble of competing inner voices" $ones & making a goaldecisionsrops the to the initiation Gerurd, 1967,p.18i). After the decisionhas beenmade,but prior goal is of actions,.ro d"liberation of the pros and cons relative to the chosen implemenexpectedto occur;rather,the individualis assumedto exploreefficient ,uiio' of the chosengoal (Beckmann& Gollwitzer, L987). Still, the model *ro*", that making a goaldecisioncfeatesa rather durabie do not commitmenr to pufsue this goal, so that hindrancesto one'sgoal pursuit to conquer leadto immed.iateretfear.Rather, the individual is expectedto attemPt increasingeffort, employingdifferent means'taking hindrancesby spontaneously taking more time to overcomethese hindrances,or trying to get around them by alternativefoutes to goal achievement(Gollwitzer & \Ticklund, 1985)'Obviously, phasesis the concept of co*m-itment employed by the Rubicon model of action of dissimilar to commirment notions that link commitment to the execution action, as conceivedby dissonanceresearchers(Brehm & Cohen, 1962; \Ticklund and Rusbult & Brehm, 7976),u.ri ulso by Brockner and Rubin (1985), Farrell (1981),Kiesler (1971),andSalancik(1977).since behavioris lessrevocablethan thoughts $ones & Gerard, 1961),the latter concePtualizationfurnishes committhe action .rr.n, with a point-of-no-fetufn quality. Contrary to this approach, a goal' as phasesmodel iorr..p,rrulizes commitment in terms of an obligation to 798ö; portruy.d in researchon maintaining relationships(Kanter'1972; Kelley, (Buchanan, Lond.,1985;Rosenblatt, \977),on identificationwith an organization on self1974;Mowday, Porter, & Steers,1982;O'Reilly & Chatman,1986),and (Emmons' defining goals (Wicklund & Gollwitzer, 1982) or personal strivings 1989). the At the core of the Rubicon model of action phasesis the assumPtionthat (deliberating' realm of goal-orientedbehavior comprises various phenomena is it planning, äctirrg,evaluating) that are ruled by different principles' But how In possibleto ,p..iiy theseprinciples so that one may test postulateddifferences? an the next section, I show that employing the concept of mind-set provides interesting solution to this problem. THECONCEPTOF MIND-SET the Rubicon If we assume that the phenomena associated with each phase of the tasks to be model are efforts at solving distinct tasks, we may try to specify phase, the solved at each of the four lhases of the model. In the predecisional action goals, pefson's task is to make the best possible choice between potential promote the irh.r.u, in the postdecisional (preactional) phase the task is to the actional initiation of actions that imply moving toward the chosen goal' In the phase the person faces the task of efficiently executing such actions, whereas determine to task in the postactional phase may best be described as trying Cbapter2. Action Pltase:and Mind-Sets 63 whether the intended outcome and its desiredconsequences actually accrued.\7e may further assumethat involvementin these taskscrearesa congruent"mindset"-that is, a phase-typicalcognitiveorientation that promorestask completion (Gollwitzer,7990).This implies that analyzingthe task demandsof each action phaseshouldleadto hypothesesaboutthe uniquequalitiesof the respectivemindset. Beforethis analysisis attempted,however,a historical review of the concepr of mind-setis presented. Historical Background In 1904 Oskar Külpe, the founder of the \würzburg school (see Boring, 19i0, pp. 401-406;Gibson, 1947;Humphrey,1951, pp. 30-131), reported his experiments on what he called"abstraction."Subjectsviewedpicturesof four nonsense syllables,eachwritten in a differentcolor.The letterscomposingthe syllables,the positioning of the colors,and syllablesthemselveswere varied over rrials. Most importantly, Külpe also varied instructionsprior to each picture presentation. Subjectshad to attend to a particular aspect of the stimulus display (e.g., the frequencyof a certain letter, the positioning of the colors, the figure represented by the positioningof the syllables,or the kind of letters composingthe syllables). Immediatelyafter eachstimulus presentation,lasting 0.125second,he requested the subjectsto report the solutionsto the tasks;in addition, he askedthem to recall the other aspectsof the stimulus display, of which they had not been instructedto take notice.The results showeddrastic effectsof instruction: $7henever the experimenter'squestionswere related to the instructions prior to viewing the display(e.g.,subjectswere askedto attend to the positioningof the colors and then asked to recall it), subjectswere highly accurarein their answers; however,wheneverthere was a mismatch (e.g.,subjectswere askedto attend to the positioning of the colors but had to report on the different letters composing the four different syllables),subjectswere exrremely inaccurate. In a very similar experiment, Chapman (L932) observedcomparativelymore accuratereports when the instructions given prior to srimulus presentation matched the inquiry posed after stimulus presentation.ITatt (1905), another representativeof the Sfürzburg school of thought, used particular words to talk about sucheffects,speakingof the instructions prior to stimulus presentation as constituting an Aufgabe (task), which createsin the individual who acceptsit a corresPondingEinstellung (mind-set). This mind-set in turn should "prepare" the individual so that the stimulus material presented should be analyzedefficiently, resulting in proper task completion. Mind-Sets Related to Action Phases In earlier papers stimulated by the Rubicon model of action phases,two distinct mind-sets or states of mind were postulated (Gollwitzer, !987; Heckhausen, 1987b; Heckhausen& Gollwitzer, 1986, 1987). The predecisionaland postactional phaseswere seenas being similar, becausein both phasesthe desirability 64 and Self'Control PartI. Self-Regulation and feasibilityof a goal^re atissue.Becausethis issueis the mastertheme of the modern psychologyof motivation (Ätkinson, 1964),we referred to theseaction "motivational." Likewise,the postdeciphasesani the ^iiociuted mind-setsas sio.rul(preactional)phaseand the actionalphasewere seenasbeing similar, since in both phasesimplementing the chosengoal is at issue.Becausethis was the mindsets masrertheme of *ill psychology,theseactionphasesand the associated "volitional." Moreover,the motivationalmind-setwas said to were referredto as "reality orien121i6n"-1hat is, an orientation be characterizedby a so-called unbiasedmanner. On toward processingavailableinformation in a nonselective, by a so-called the othJr hand,the volitional mind-setwas saidto be characterized "realization orientation"-that is, an orientation toward processingavailable information in a selectivemanner biasedin favor of attaining the chosengoal' This original conceptualization,however,createdconfusion.For instance,it can be urgo.J (Kornadt, 1988) that not only predecisionalbut also postactional individuais try to achieve(realize) something-namely, to make Pfoper decisions or to developcorrect evaluations,respectively.Therefore, realization orientation shouldalsobe presentin the latter actionphases.Similarly,people in the process of planning or executing an intricate courseof action have to scrutinize available situational information rather realistically,and thus should also evidencea strong reality orientation. ihis original conceptualizationalsofailed to exploit the theoreticalpower of the concepro1mind-set. Applying the mind-set concePtto the action phases,first of all, requirescritically aialyzingthe tasks individuals set for themselvesin the various uition phases.Seco.rd,having discoveredthe characteristictask demands, one is finally in a position to form hypotheses about the unique cognitive orientation of the reipective mind-sets. Our original conceptualizationdiscouraged this approach beca.rseit lumped the predecisional and the postactional piur., ,og.,h.r, banning the idea that different tasks are solved in these action -phur.r. Tte sume was done with the postdecisional(preactional) phase and the -actional phase.Moreover, the characterizationof the cognitive characteristicsof the delineatedmind-setswas either extremely general (reality orientation) or did not even relate to a cognitive orientation, but rather to the task expectedto elicit the mind-set (realizationorientation).In the following discussion,our original conceptualizationis abandoned.Instead, an analysisof the tasks to be solved at each lction phase is presented. As a result, four distinct mind-sets (i.e., the deliberativ., implemenlal, actional,and evaluativemind-sets) afe posnrlated,and their distinctive cognitive orientations are spelled out' Deli ber ative M i nd-Sets \When reflecting on rhe task to be solvedin the predecisionalphase,one has to keep in mind that predecisionalindividuals deliberatein order to determine which of their wishes ur. ,ro, only most desirablebut also feasible' Solving this task requiresthat an individual be primarily concernedwith information relevant of a given wish's outto the positivity-negativity of the expectedconsequences Chapter2. Action Pbasesand.Mind.-Sets 65 comein order to estimateits desirability.In addition,information that aliows the individualto assessthe chancesof achievingthis outcomeseemscrucialin determining its feasibility. Reliable estimates should be favored when all of the relevant information for assessingdesirabilityand feasibility is discoveredand processed.Since it is unciear at the outset which pieces of information or knowledge may be relevant to assessingdesirability and feasibility, a general open-mindedness toward processingincomingor storedinformation seemsbeneficiaL Finally, being concernedwith information that addresses(or potentially addresses) the desirabilityof the wish under scrutiny will not do much good if deliberation is not conductedin an impartial manner. Ignoring negative consequencesor overemphasizing positive consequencesmay make the deliberated wish appear more desirablethan is actuallyjustified. Similarly, if information pertaining to the feasibility of the wish under scrutiny is not analyzedina manner that favors accurate assessments,the individual may overestimate his or her capabilitiesto implement the desiredwish, and thus may judge its feasibility to be higher than it actually is. Accordingly, the mind-set that clearly facilitatesthe task of the predecisional phase (i.e.,to choosethe most desirablewish that is also feasible)should evidence the following characteristics:First, there should be cognitive tuning toward information relevant to the issuesof feasibility and desirability. Second,there should be an orientation toward accurateand impartial processingof such information. And finally, there should be an open-mindednessor heightenedreceptiviry to information in general. This deliberativemind-set should originate whenever people becomeintensely involved with deliberating their wishes. lmplemental Mind-Sets The task to be solved by the postdecisional(preactional) individual is planning when, where, and how to act in order to promore action initiation. Solving this task effectively requires the individual to be primarily concernedwith information related to these questions.Moreover, task solution is facilitated whenever the individual commits himself or herself to a certain favorable opporrunity to act-that is, forms an initiation intention. In this way attention is focused on a specifiedopportunity to act, and the probability that the individual will forego this opportunity is reduced. Flowever, all.of these concerns will fail to benefit action initiation if the individual starts to questionthe desirability or feasibiliry of the chosengoal. Accordingly, any suchdoubts should be counteredby the individual's boosting the desirability and feasibility of the chosengoal, thus maintaining persistencein initiating actions ro reach the chosengoal. Therefore, the mind-set that facilitatessolving the task of the posrdecisional (preactional) phase should evidence the following characteristics:First, there should be cognitive runing toward information relevant to when, where, and how to act-Second,there should be closed-mindedness in the senseof concentraringon information that helps to promote the chosengoal. And finally, there should be a partial and optimistic analysisof information related to the chosengoal's desira- 66 and.Self-Co.ntrol Partl. Self-Regulation bility and feasibility,respectively.This implemental mind-set should originate wheneverpeoplebecomeintenselyinvolvedwith planning the implementationof their goal intentions. ActionalMind-Sets The task of the actionalphasemay be describedas acting toward the goal so that goal achievement is promoted. Solving this task requires one to avoid disruftions, becauseany halting of the flow of action postponesgoal achievementof what The mind-setrhat facilitatesthis shouldthereforeevidencecharacteristics "flow experience"and Wicklund (1986) labeled Csikszentmihalyi(L975) called "dynamic orientation." The individual no longer reflectson the qualitiesof the goul ,o be achieved,on his or her capacitiesto achievethe goal, or on alternative itrategies on goal achievement;nor does the individual form behavioral intentions iegarding when, where, and how to act.Rather, the individual is completely caught up in the actionscurrently being executed.Accordingly, only those aspects of Ä. self and the environmentthat sustainthe courseof action are attendedto, whereasany potentially disruptive aspects(e.g.,self-reflectivethoughts, comPeting goal intentions,disiractiveenvironmentalstimuli) are ignored.Therefore,the mind-set that facilirates rhe promotion of goal achievement is one of closedmindednessto informarion that could trigger a re-evaluationof the goal that is pursued,a re-evaluationof the chosenroute toward goal attainment, or any self"Can I be proud of my performance?Am I suited for this evaluation (e.g., activity?"). Raiher, the actionalmind-set should evidencecognitive tuning toward internal and external cuesthat guide the courseof action toward goal attainment. It should originate whenever people move effectively toward goal attainment. Evaluative Mind-Sets The task to be solved in the postactionalphase is evaluating outcomesand of goal striving in order to discoverwhether the intended outcome consequences have been obtained. Solving this has been reacheJand its desired consequences task, therefore, requiresthe individual to be primarily concernedwith the quality Task of the outcome (siandards)and the actual desirability of its consequences. solution should be facilitated when the individual simply compares what is achieved(outcomes) and obtained (consequences)with what was intended and desired when the goal intention was formed. This comparison should benefit from a correcr assessmentof the quality of the outcome and an objective,impartial view of the desirability of its consequences. Accordingly, the mind-set that facilitatesthe task of evaluationin the postactional phase should evidencethe following characteristics:First, there should be cognitive tuning toward information relevant to assessingthe quality of the Second,there shouldbe achievedourcomeand the desirabilityof its consequences. an orientation toward accurateand impartial processingof this information- And finaily, there should be a comparativeorientation; that is, the intended outcome should be comparedwith the actualoutcomeand its and the desiredconsequences consequences.This evaluative mind-set should originate whenever people be- Cbapter2. Action Phasesand M.ind-Sets 67 come intensely involved with evaluatingourcomesand consequences of goal striving. S u mma ry The various action phasesof the Rubicon model differentiatefour distinct phenomenaof goal-orientedbehavior:deliberating,plannin g, acting,and evaluating. Sinceeachof thesephenomenaimpiies solving a distinct task,it is inferred that different mind-setsevolvewheneverone is involved in theseparticular tasks. For each of these distinct mind-sets (i.e., deliberative,implemental, actional, evaluative),the associatedcognitive orientation is specifiedby analyzingconcrere task demands. MIND-SETS AND COGNITIVE FUNCTIONING: RECENT FINDINGS So far, we have concentrated our empirical efforts on testing the cognitive orientations postulated for the deliberativeand implemental mind-sets. Our experimentshavefocusedon three key issues:(1) the postulatedcognitive-tuning effects; (2) the distinct way of processinginformation related to feasibility and desirability;and (3) the postulateddifferencesin open-mindedness. Mind-Setsand CognitiveTuning S7e hypothesized that both the deliberative and the implemental mind-sets achievecognitive tuning toward task-congruousinformation. The deliberative mind-set should lead to cognitive tuning toward information related to the feasibility of the intended outcome (action-outcome expectancy) and to the desirability of the expectedconsequences(expectedvalue), whereas the implemental mind-set should evoke cognitive tuning toward information related to actioninitiation (when, where,and how to ger started).How doesone test these hypotheses?In principle, there are two possible approaches.The first approach focuseson the subjects'thoughts while they are in a deliberativeor implemental mind-set; it is expectedthat congruousthoughts will be experiencedmore frequently than incongruousthoughts.The secondapproachfocuseson the subjects' readinessto encodeor retrieve task-congruousinformation; here it is expected that congruous information will be encodedand retrieved comparatively more effectively. Thought Sampling The first approachled us to conductthree different but related experiments. In the first experiment (Heckhausen& Gollwitzer, L987,Study l), experimental subjectschose between two different sets of test material designed ro measure creativity,one set consistingof black-and-whitepictures and the orher set consisting of color pictures.Subjectswere told that they would later write a creativestory 68 and,Self-Control Partl. Self-Regulation about whichever set of pictures they chose.The reasongiven for offering a choice was rhat somepeoplemore easilyreachtheir full creativepotential when working with color pictures,whereasothersperform better with black-and-whitepictures. Subjectswere encouragedto avoid snap choicesbetween test materials,but to engageinsteadin full-fledgeddeliberation.For this Purpose,we had subjectsview a seriesof samplepictures (six black-and-whiteand six color pictures). S7einterrupted one group of subjects90 secondsafter they had viewed the samplepictures(the predecisionalgroup), while still undecidedas to which set of test material they wanted to choose.In a thought-sampling task, they were requestedro reporr their thoughts experiencedduring the 90-secondtime period, starring with the last sample picture up to the point of interruption. To increase the validity of this self-report,we proceededas follows: Subjectsfirst were to write down their most recent thought, and then the secondmost recent thought. Next, the first thought was to be reported, and then everything they had thought of in between.According to Ericssonand Simon (1980), this procedureshould produce valid self-reports becausesubjectscan retrieve the most recent thought from short-term memory. \Triting down the most recent thought should then facilitate recall of the thoughts experienced immediately before, since these should be connectedthrough episodicassociationsin long-term memory. Another group of subjectswas not interrupted until a decision had been made and subjectshad spent 90 secondswaiting for the test material they had chosen (the postdecisionalgroup). These postdecisionalsubiectsreported their thoughts experienced during the 90-second time period starting with having made a decisionup to the point of interruption. Finally, we employed two groups of control subjects.Both groups were simply assigneda set of test material (yoked with the pre- and postdecisional subjects'choices).One of these groups was interrupted before this assignment (the preassignmentgroup) and the other group afterwards (the postassignment group). The time periods on which control subjectshad to focus when reporting their thoughts were closely matched to those of the respective experimental subjects. Content analysisof subjects'reported thoughts revealedthat thoughts re"Being a cfeative Person is important") and lated to expected values (e.g., "I thoughts related ro action-outcomeexpectancies(e.g., would do better with the color material") were much more frequent in predecisionalsubjectsthan in any of the other three groups of subjects.The frequency of implementation-related thoughts (i.e., considerationsand expressedintentions about what kind of story would be told and how this should be done) was elevatedin both the postdecisional and postassignmentgroups. However, hardly any implemental thoughts were reported by predecisionaland preassignmentsubjects. If it is assumedthat predecisionalsubjectsengagedin intensive deliberation and thus developeda deliberativemind-set, the observedpredominanceof taskcongruousthoughts in predecisionalsubjectssupports our cognitive-tuning hypothesis.Similarly, becauseboth postdecisionaland postassignmentsubjectswere planning to write a crearivestory on the test material, both of these groups of Cbapter2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 69 subjectsshould have developedan implemental mind-set. Observingcomparativeiy more implemental thoughts in these two groups again suPPortsour hycognitivetuning. pothesisof task-congruous Distance from Making a ChangeDecision One could argue that the findings describedaboveare rather trivial, because subjectssimply entertainedthose thoughtsthat they were told to entertain.One has to remember,however,that we did not tell predecisionalsubjectsto think of issuesrelatedto action-outcomeexpectanciesand expectedvalues;nor did we tell postdecisionalsubjects to stop thinking about such issues and to turn their attention to implementationalissuesinstead.A still more convincingtest of the cognitive-tuning hypothesismay be performed if the independentand dependent variables are exchanged-that is, if one asks people who harbor a Personal, unresolvedproblem pending a changedecisionto engagein exactly those mental activities hypothesized to be associatedwith a deliberative mind-set. If our hypothesisof mind-set-congruouscognitive tuning is correct,one should exPect thesesubjectsto becomelost in deliberation and therefore to feel predecisionalthat is, far from making a changedecision.But if suchpeople are askedto engage in mental activities that we believe to be associatedwith an implemental mindset, they should becomeintensely involved in the postdecisionaltask of planning the implemenration of the change decision not yet made. Consequently,they should feel postdecisionaland thus closer to making a changedecision. To test these ideas, the following experiment was conducted (Gollwitzer, Heckhausen,& Ratalczak,1990). Subjectsfirst named an unresolved personal problem that was pending a change decision. They named problems such as "should move away from home?" "should I switch my major?" or "Should I I break up with my boyfriend?" In order to measuresubjects'perceiveddistance from making a changedecision,we askedsubjectsat the outsetof the experiment how determined they felt at that very moment, how much resolution it would still take them to arrive at a changedecision,and how far awaythey felt from the act of making a change decision.Next, one group of subjects(the deliberation group) was askedto estimare the expectedvalue of making the change decision.They and the delayedpositive and negative listed the potential immediateconsequences and they estimated the probability of these consequences'occurconsequences, the chancesof achievingthe resPectiveoutcomes. ring. In addition, they assessed Another group of subjects (the implementation group) was asked to plan the implemenration of the not-yet-made change decision by listing a number of difierent activities that could servethe purpose of implementing it. Subjectsthen had to decideon a courseof action and to imagine themselvesexecutingthis planS7hen subjects were asked again about their perceived distance from a changedecision (employing the three items listed above), deliberation subjects continued to describe themselvesas undetermined and irresolute-that is, far from making a changedecision.Implementation subjects,however, indicated an increasein determination and resolution-that is, perceivedthemselvesas closer to making a changedecision.An analysisof the potential mediators of this effect 70 Part I. Self-Regulationand Self-Control but instead pointed to having ruled our an increase in desirability or feasibility, plan as the critical variable' In committed oneself to a certain implementational strongly contributed to apother words, forming behavioral intentions most proaching the change decision' ? r 1r r:.r-^-^ far, I would like to point out In summa rizirJgthe two studies reported thus more thoughts rethe following: Pred-ecisionalsubjects showed comParatively values, and when (undecided) lated to action-outcome exPectanciesand expected they felt strongly predecisional' people were made to entertain such thoogÄts, comParatively more implePostdecisional subjects, on the other hand, showed were made to entertain such mental thoughts, and when (undecided) people to the act of decision' These thoughts tn.! i.tt less predecisional-thatls, closer produces cognitive tuning toward findings suggest that a deliberative mind-set and expected values' whereas the thoughts related to action-outcome expectancies how to achieve a chosen goal' implemental mind-set tunes o.r. ,o*ird issuesof Writing FairYlales and implemental The most conoi.rcing demonstration that delibefative by the findings of the mind-setsentail congfuous"thoughtproduction is provided L989,Study 1)' First' foliowing e"perimeit (Gollwitzer, Heckhausen'& Steller, implemental mind-set by subjects1"r" placed either into a deliberativeor an problem pending a change being asked to deliber ate an unresolved personal resPectively'Again, decisionor ro plan a personalproject pending realization, projects of their choice; subjectswere ilo*ed to *ork o., p.rrorral problems or with apIifestyle-related,unä interpersonalissueswefe named career-related, grouP receivedthe same proximately equal fäqo.r.y. The deliberativemind-set experiinstructions as describedabove in the distance-from-a-change-decision instructed to list five ment. subjectsin the implemental mind-set grouP were proiect they had implementational stePs required to complete the intended themselvesas to when' named.For each of thesestePs,subjectshud to commit did not receiveany where, and how they plann.d ,o executeit. The control grouP mind-set maniPulation. presented with the In the secondpart of the experiment, subjectswere askedto continue these tales beginnings of threeiiff.r.rr, fairy tales and were point where the main with three sentenceseach.All oi these tales ended at a story' for example' a character of the story faced a goal decision. In the first at home to Protect his widowed king faced tlre choiceof going to war or staying of whether deliberative beloveddaughter.The senter.., *-.r. scotedon the basis verbs.relating to the or implementational efforts were imputed to the king: Äny in the predeciking were classifiedaccordingto whethef the king was engaged task of implementing goalsor the postdecisional sionaltask of choosingbetween "The king ,u.k"d Äis brain wondering what to do"' for a chosengoal. The phrase king, whereas the instance,*u, ,.orä as imputittg u a.[berative effort to the 'iTh. king ordered a trusted officer to stay at home at the castle and phrase ^p.o,.., effort' his daugliter" was scoredas imputing an implementational Chafrter2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 71 Äs expected,subjects'mind-sets affected their flow of creative thought when completing their fairy tales.Deliberative mind-set subjectsimputed more deliberative efforts to the king than implemental mind-set subjects, with control subjects' imputations faliing between those of the other two groups. An analogous congruency effect was observed with imputing implementational efforts. The implemental mind-set group scored higher than the deliberative mind-set group, and the control group again scored in between these rwo groups. Telling fairy tales follows a certain story grammar (Rabkin t979; Rumelhart, 1975, l9l7): Only when a solution is found to the problem introduced at the beginning may the story come to an end. Since these solutions come about more easily if the main character takes action, ascribing implementational efforts to the king should have been the more common response. This was actually the case in the controi group: Subjects imputed about 10 times as many implementational efforts as deliberative efforts to the king. However, although telling a f.airy tale strongly favors producing implementational thoughts, the deliberative mind-set weakened this preorientation and the implemental mind-set strengthened it. It seems important to note that these mind-sets had been elicited when subjects meditated on quite different issues (i.e., unresolved personal problems or intended projects related to career,lifestyle, or interpersonal issues),and that some minutes had passed before subjects proceeded with the fairy tales. Cued Reca/l of Mind-Set-Congruous lnformation Deliberative and implemental mind-sets not only should make congnrous thoughts more readily available,but also should allow for more effective processing of congruous information. That is, people operating within a deliberative mind-set should be particularly effective in processing information related to outcome expectancy and expected vaiue, whereas people operating within an implemental mind-set should be more adept at processinginformation related to when, where, and how to act on a chosengoal. Demonstratingpotent mind-sets implies, in addition, that this prediction should hold true not only for information relevant to the meditated unresolvedproblem that has led to the deliberative mind-set, or for information relevant to the planned project that has led to the implemental mind-set. Rather, these mind-sets' cognitive-tuning effects should transfer to unrelated deliberativeor implementational information. To explore this supposition, we asked subjects to view a series of slides (Gollwitzer et al., 1989,Study 2). Each of the eight slides depicteda different person said to be experiencinga personalconflict of the following kind: Should I do X or not? The accompanyingslide specifiedthis conflict (e.g.,"should I sell my apartment or not?") and presented thoughts presumably entertained by the person depicted.Two of thesethoughts were related to the expectedvaluesof the changedecision("It would be good because. ."; "Ir would be bad because. ."), and two were related to the questionof how to initiate relevant actions,given that the changedecision had been made. One of these latter two was related to the timing of relevant actions ( "If I should decide to do it, then I won't . . . before 72 PartI. Self-Regulationand Self-Control . . ."), and the other to rhe sequencingof reievantactions("If I should decideto d o i t , t h e nI w i l l f i r s t . . . a n d t h e n . - . " ) . S7ecreateddeliberativeand implementai mind-setsby employing the choice paradigmintroducedabove(i.e.,the first studyreported).The choiceofferedwas b.,*..r, materials for a creativity test that required constructingcollagesfrom material cur out of newspapers.Two sets of collagesegmentswere said to be available,one set consistingof black-and-whiteelementsand the other of color elements.Subjectswere told that people could reachtheir full creativepotential only if they chose rhe type of material (black-and-white or color) they found personally most appealing. One group of subjectsviewed the slides and had to recall the information depictedon the sidesprior to making a decision.Another group receivedand recalledthe information af.tera decision had been made. If mind-set-congruous information is processedmore effectively, predecisional subjects should have recalledinformation relatedto expectedvaluesbetter than implemental information, whereas rhe reverse should have been true for postdecisional subjects. Finally, we employed a group of control subjectswho receivedand recalled the same information without either expecting to make a decision or having made one. performance(the beginningsof the sentencesas Control subjects'cued-recall listed abovewere provided as recall cues)was the samefor expected-value-related information (positive and negative consequences)and the implementationrelated information (timing and sequencingof relevant actions).Predecisional information than with subjects,however, did better with expected-value-related implementation-related information, whereas the reversewas true for postdecisional subjects.This pattern of recall performance strongly suggeststhat mindser-congruousinformarion is processedmore effectively than incongruousinformation. The present study should not be confusedwith experiments designedto explore whether there is differential recall of information that is consistentwith or contradictoryto rhe decisionmade (Dellarosa& Bourne,7984).In the present study, the informarion provided was not even relevant to the choice to be made, neither supporting nor undermining subjects'decisions. S7hat kind of memory processesaccountfor the Present finding that mindser-congruousinformation is recalled comparatively more effectively? If we assume that subjects' retrieval attempts necessitateconstructing descriptions of what they are trying to retrieve (Bobrow & Norman,l97l; Norman & Bobrow, I976, 1979), it seemspossible that mind-sets provide perspectives(Bobrow & \Tinograd,1977) that allow for the easyconstructionof specificdescriptions.The deliberativemind-set, for insrance,should favor descriptionsphrased as pros and cons,benefits and cosrs,hopes and fears, all tied to the specific conflicts of the depictedcharactersgiven as retrieval cues.In other words, the deliberativemindset makes for the ready construction of descriptionsthat specify expected-valuereiated information, whereasthe implemental mind-set helps constructingdescriptions that specify implementation-relatedinformation. As Norman and Bobrow (1979) point our, quick consrructionof specificdescriptionsat the time of Chapter2. Action Phatesand Mind'-Sets 73 retrieval further successfulretrieval. Norman and Bobrow also assume that wheneverthe descriptionof the information sought matchesthe elaborationof this information at the time of encoding,recall performance is particularly enhanced.It seemspossible,then, that deliberativeand implemental mind-sets favor congruousrecall via congruouselaboration at the time of encoding and via the ready construction of congruousdescriptionsat the time of retrieval. Summary The results of the four experiments reported show that deliberative and implemental mind-sets tune people's cognitive functioning so that congruous and congruousinformation is processedeffecthoughts becomereadily accessible tively. Most interestingly,both mind-setspossesssome stability over time and generalizeacrosssituations (the third and fourth studies reported). Mind-Sets and Biased Inferences The studiespresentedaboveprimarily addressthe questionsof what types of thoughts or information are congruouswith the deliberative and implemental mind-sets,whether congruousthoughts are more pervasive,and whether congruous information is processedmore effectively.However, both mind-sets can also be assumedto differentially affect the way in which congruous or incongruous information is handled. S7ehypothesizedthat information related to feasibility and to desirability arc analyzedin a distinct manner. Whereas in a deliberative impartially, assessment mind-set information related to desirabiiityis assessed mind-set. Älso, feasibility partialto the chosengoal is expectedin an implemental is expectedto be assessedrather accuratelyin a deliberative mind-set, whereas optimistic assessmentsthat overestimate the actual feasibility of the intended outcome are expectedin an implemental mind-set. !7e conductedtwo studieson eachof these issues.The first two studieswere thought-sampling studies related to predecisionalindividuals' assessmentof desirability. The second two studies used the illusion-of-control paradigm (Alloy & Abramson, 1982) and related to assessingfeasibility when a deliberativeor implemental mind-set has been createdexperimentally. The Cou nterplea Heuristic Is there an impartial analysisof expectedvalue in individuals with a deliberative mind-set? To answer this question,we (Gollwitzer & Heckhausen,1987, Study 2) askedfemale university studentsto name an unresolvedpersonal problem for which they wished resolution but that for some reason they had not " " "Should "Should I switch my major? resolvedyet (e.g., I move from home? "Should I studyabroad?").Then we askedsubjectsto achieveclarity with respect to whether they wanted to make a changedecision;we expectedthis instruction to trigger intensive deliberation and to create a deliberative mind-set. \7e also askedsubjectsto report back to the experimenterwhen they felt that further mentation would not achievegreater clarity. 74 and Self-Control Partl. Self-Regulation Subjectswere rhen given the thought-samplingquestionnaire(described above),becausesubjects'answersto this questionnaireallowed us to study the temporal order of the flow of consciousthought. $7e scoredsubjects'thoughts accordingto a coding schemethat differentiatedbetweenpositive and negative of having achievedthe desiredoutcome as implied by a change consequences were pondered decision.First, v/e noticedthat positiveand negativeconsequences with equalfrequency.More interestingly,when we put the thoughtsreportedinto the correcr temporal order, we discoveredthat deliberationfoliowed a certain partern. Deliberation started with reflection on the positive incentivesof wish fulfillment (e.g.,having moved from home). However, subjectsdid not indulge in but immediately turned toward reflecting on negathese positive consequences, tive incentives.It seemedthat thesedeliberatingpeople playedtheir own devil's advocate:Their initial enthusiasmaboutthe positiveaspectswas temperedwith a counterpleapointing to negativeconsequences. S7etried to replicatethis observedpattern of meditating on positive and with a different sampleof subjects-that is, male students negativeconsequences at a military academy(Gollwitzer &. Heckhausen, 1987, Study 2). Älthough these "Should I acquire a students named rarher different unresolvedproblems (e.g., " "Should " "Should I learn how to I buy new skiing equipment? flying license? hang-glid€?"), the same temporal pattern of thinking about the positive and negarive consequencesemerged. Obviously, people who become intensely involved with deliberatingan unresolvedpersonalproblem attemPt an impartial are Even though the positive consequences analysisof potential consequences. most salient at the beginning, negativeprospectsare quickly compiled in order to with potential negativeconsequences. contrast the desiredpositive consequences are pitted against those that are feared; therefore, Thus, desiredconsequences there is no partial analysisfocusing exclusivelyor primarily on desiredconsequences. The issueof impartial information processingprior to making a decisionis nor new. Festinger (1964) reported a number of studies that addressedthe cognitive functioning of predecisionalsubjects.All of these studiesassumedthat an impartial analysiswould not affect the initial divergence of attractiveness between choice alternatives(Davidson & Kiesler, 1964;Jecker, 7964; Walster & Festinger,1964). Other studiesdefined impartiality as an equal amount of attention paid to eachof the choicealternatives,as measuredby looking time (Gerard, 1967),listeningtime (Brockg Balloun,1967),or more recentlyin terms of recall performance (Beckmann& Gollwitzer, 1987). Flowever, these different approachesto predecisional impartiality do not capture the individual's analysisof decision-relevantinformation. An impartial analysisdoesnot necessarilyleavethe divergenceof attractivenessbetweenchoice alternativesuntouched,and a partial analysismay be conductedeven when the amenrionpaid to choicealternatives(as measuredin terms of encodingtime or recall performance) is about equal. Not surprisingly, then, conflicting findings have been reported by studiesthat adhereto these operationalizationsof impartiality (e.g.,Janis& Mann, 1968;Mann,Janis,& Chaplin,1969). Therefore,the Chapter2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 75 somewhat old-fashioned thought-sampling technique we employed may actually provide the most valid data on the question of whether predecisional deliberation is impartial, becauseit captures subjects' actual thought processes. \Wehave not yet used our thought-sampling technique to test the hypothesis that the implemental mind-set leads to a partial analysis of expected-value-related information. But rather unambiguous support for such partial information processing after a decision is available elsewhere (Wicklund & Brehm, 1976). Researchers in the tradition of dissonance theory observed that postdecisional subjects increased the attractivenessof the chosen alternative and decreasedthe attractivenessof the nonchosen alternative (Brehm, 1956).In addition, postdecisional individuals were found to selectively seek information that potentially supported their choice and to actively avoid nonsupportive information (Frey, 1986). These findings have been interpreted either in terms of justifying one's decision in order to fulfiil a need for consistency (Insko, ITorchel, Folger, & Kutkus, 1975) or in terms of justifying one's decision for the purpose of arriving "unequivocal action orientation" that precludes further deliberation of the at an choice alternatives $ones & Gerard, 1967; l7icklund & Frey, 198i). This latter interpretation of postdecisional partiality is similar to our perspecrive that an implemental mind-set yields a pafüal analysis of expected-valuerelated information in order to promote immediate and persistent implementation of the chosen goal. The minor difference between the two perspectives may be the following: The mind-set perspective suggests that doubts about the actual desirability of the chosen goal arc first of all avoided by concentrating on the implementation of the chosen goal. Only when this fails are postdecisional individuals assumed to resort to justifying their choices by increasing their expected desirability. Illusionof Control How do the deliberative and implemental mind-sets affect the analysisof information related to the issue of feasibility?Our hypothesis was that the deliberative mind-set should spawn ail acclrrateassessmentof the probability of achieving a certain outcome, whereas the implemental mind-set should \7e tested these hypothesesin two lead to inaccurate,optimistic assessments. experiments employing an illusion-of-control paradigm (Gollwitzer & Kinney, 1989). In the contingency learning task designedby Alloy and Abramson (1919), subjectsperform numerous trials on a single-stimulus apparatus. In this task, subjectsare askedto determine to what degreethey can influence the onset of a target light (outcome) by choosing to press or not to press a button (alternative actions).By observingwhether or not the target light turns on, subjectsestimate how much influence or control they have over the target light onset. The experimenter can vary the actualdegreeof control by manipulating the frequency of light onset associatedwith eachof the two action alternatives (pressingor not pressing). The smaller the difference between these two frequencies,the less objective control subjectshave over target light onset. 76 and Selt''Control PartI. Selt''Regulati'on review, see Alloy & Än extensivebody of research(for a comPfehensive Ä b r a m s o n , 1 9 8 8 ) h a s r e v e a l e d t h a t n o n d e p r e s s e d i n d i v i d uactions' a l s c l a iwhenmtoPossess subiects' on ,ron.ontingent ur" that control over desiredoutcomes (e.g.,in a75-1.5 problem, where the target ever theseourcomesoccurfrequently responses)as light comeson rn 75% of fressing ;d 15!.of .nonpressing problem)' \7e hypothesizedthat the comparedto infrequently (e.g.,in uiS-ZS (action-outcomeexpectancy)found inaccurate,optimistic iudgmentsof control problems should be attenuated in with noncontingent but frequent outcome in implemental be aggravated deliberativemind-setsubjects,and that they sirould mind-set subiects. 1989, Study 1), we modified the In our first study (Gollwitzer & Kinney, a secondaPParatusand by asking Älloy and Äbramron ir9z9) paradigm by adding ."u-tt a deliberativemind-set'we told subjectsto work on five ,.., of 20 tiials.'To of the experimentwas to decide(after subjectsthat their obiectivein the first part two availableapparatusesthey wanted completing the firre ,.ts; on which ol irr. To allow for an informed to work during the second part of the experiment' between the two aPparatuses'\7e decision,subjectswere "r,.oo-rug.dto alternate by askingsubjectsto decideon the attemptedro createan implemental mind-set *ith 'espect to all five setsof trials sequenceof alternation between aPParatuses tfy to produce as many light onsets as before starting the first set, and then to possible. T w o p r o b l e m c o n d i t i o n s w e r e e s t a b l i s h e d ' , a 7 5 _ T 5 p r o b l efrequent manda2'.2' noncontingent pfesented-either aPparatuses both problem. Äccordingly, light' \ühen target light onset or noncontingent infrequent onset of tü. target tittd-tet subiectsreportedinacwas frequent (the 7t-75 problem), implemenäl whereas deliberative mind-set curately high, illusionary iudgments äf .on,.ol, Apparently, the deliberativemind-set subjectsshowedmodest.orr,rol iudgments. optimism; that is' they recogprevents people from being lured into illusionary is not necessarilya valid indicator of nize that high frequencyof a desiredoutcome \(ith respectto the 2t-25 problem' one's degreeof lnfloer,ceover the outcome' judgments' This indicates that both mind-set groups showed modest control of reality' They do not implemen.* *äa-r.t subiectsdo adapt to the constraints over target outcomes' but rather blindly perpetuare an impression of control many failures are encountered' acceprthat they have little control when too grounds' First' one could This experiment may be criticized on two different may havebeen reluctant to tell the afgue thar the implemental mind-set subiects alternation between aPPafatuses; experiment., thu-t they made a bad choice of judgments simply to keep up a consequently,.i.y *uy huo. inflated their control reported an illusion-of,BarrySchwartz (1983) "tt*ly good impression-'secood on a button-pushing task that control experiment where he pretrained subiects ta'k, he either establisheda rule offered only two buttons. In ihe pretrainin! which sequeocesof button discovery orientation (subjects nua to determine problems) or a reward pressing led to reinforcement in three different sequence in any order' on eachof the orientation (subjectswere reinforced for four pushes, illusion of control than reward two buttons). Rule discoverysubiectsshowed-less Chapter2. Action Pbasesand Mind-Sets 77 subjectsin a subsequentÄlloy and Abramson type of contingencylearning task. One could argue that our deliberativemind-set manipulation was acruallya rule discoverymanipulation,sincesubjectswere instructedto determine on which of the two apparatusesthey would do better, whereasthe implemental mind-set manipulation was a reward orientation manipulation, since subjectswere instructedto produceas many rarget light onsetsas possible. Both problems can easilybe avoided,however,when a mind-set manipulation is employed,as describedin the fairy tale experiment above.Accordingly, we ran a secondstudy (Gollwitzer & Kinney,1989, Study2) where one-third of the subjectsmeditatedon an unresolvedpersonalproblem requiring a changedecision by carefully deliberating the expected value of making a change decision (deliberativemind-set).Another third made specificplans for implementing an intended project by delineatingexactly when, where, and how they wanted to initiate relevant actions (implemental mind-set). Once both groups of subjects had finishedthesementations,they were askedto work on a contingencyproblem that presentedfrequent noncontingenttarget outcomes(a 75-75 problem). The instructionsfor completing this task were identicalfor both groups of subjects; that is, they had to discoverhow to producetarget light onset.A set of 40 trials was offered.I7e also addeda control group (the last third of the subjects)that did not receive any mind-set manipulation, but worked only on the contingency problem. Deliberative mind-set subjectsagainshowedthe most accuratejudgments of control; that is, their control judgmentswere lower than those of control and implemental subjects.Implemental mind-set subjectsevidencedcontrol j"dgments that were even (albeit not significantly) more illusionary than those of control subjects.Supportingour mind-set interpretationof thesefindings, deliberative mind-set subjects'judgments of control correlated negatively with the "personal reported importance" of the problem pondered during the predecisional mentation. Apparently, the more involved subjects'deliberation was, the more realistic their subsequentjudgments of control were. Ä parallel finding was observedfor implemental subjects.F{ere, judgments of control were positively related to subjects' anticipated frustration if the project should (for whatever reason)fail to be implemented. The present findings not only support our hypothesis that a deliberative mind-set spawnsaccuratecontrol judgmentswhereasthe implemental mind-set favorsillusionary optimism, but also offer a new perspectiveon the phenomenon of illusion of control. It seemspossiblethat illusion of control is generally based on an implemental mind-set. That is, whenever subjectscommit themselvesto achievinga desiredoutcome,they are likely to experienceillusion of control. Data from Martin, Abramson, and Alloy (1984) and Vazquez(1987) support this line of thought: \Thenever it was made difficult for subjectsto commit themselvesto achievingthe target outcome,subjectsfailed to evidenceillusion of control. Also, when Langer (1975) introducedthe conceptof illusion of control, she discovered that variousfactors making a luck task (i.e.,random outcomes)appear to be a skill task manageto produceillusion of control. Viewed in the context of our theoreti- 7B Part I. Self'Regulationand Self-Control cal framework, the presence of skill-related aspectsin a task may induce subjects to commit themselves ro the goal of achieving the desired outcome, even though its appearanceis solely determined by chance.In other words, a goal commitment emerges that allows for the development of an implemental mind-set. Finally, our mind.-setconceptualization also provides a new framework from "depressive realism" (i.e., the observation that depressedpeople do which to view not experience illusion of control when noncontingent outcomes appear freqoently;. Conceivabiy, depressives find it particularly difficult to set for themselvesthe goal at hand (e.g.,to maximize target light onset) becauseof pervasive negative beliefs about themselves-that is, their abilities, past performances, intelligence, and strengths (Beck, 1961, 1976). Such beliefs should generate doubts concerning the attainability of the given goal and thus should hinder goal commitmenr. Consequently,no implemental mind-set may evolve, and depressed people thereby remain insusceptible to feelings of illusionary optimism. Summary The findings of the last four experimentsreportedsuggeststrongly that deliberativemind-set subjectsdo analyzethe positive and negativeconsequences of a prospectivegoal impartially.In addition,they make rather accurateestimates of action-ourcomeprobabilities.The latter is definitely not true of implemental mind-setsubjects:They overestimatetheseprobabilities,thus showing illusionary optimism. One wonders whether the deliberative mind-set favors accurateprobability judgments in general, and not only when action-outcome expectanciesare at stake.\When wishes are deliberated,the probability (certainty) that the desired outcomemay be reachedis an important concern.Clearly, part of the answer to this questionis relatedto action-outcomeexpectancy(i.e.,how certainPeopleare that they can conrrol the desiredoutcome).However, there are other possible answers.The more general answer relatesto people'sbeliefs that they possess of relevantcompetencies);the relevantaction potentials (i.e.,their self-concepts more specific answer relates to beliefs associatedwith specific coursesof action (i.e.,how cerainis it that doing X will leadto the desiredoutcome).Certaintyis of relevance again when an individual ponders the probability that the achieved To answer this question,the individourcomewill lead to a desiredconsequence. ual must estimatethe probability that certain eventswill occur.As we know from decisionresearch(Baron, 1988; Slovic,Lichtenstein,& Fischhoff,1988),people havedifficulty with deriving accurateestimates.They employ numerousheuristics to easethis task (Nisbett & Ross,1980;Tversky& Kahneman,1973,1974),b:ut more often than not go astray(e.g.,the gambler'sfallacy,the conjunctionfallacy). In particular, they are overconfident when estimating the probability of desired evenrs(Hoch, 1985)or frequentevents(Fischhoff,Slovic,& Lichtenstein,1977). In add,ition,they cling ro an initial estimateevenwhen evidenceaccruesthat urges correction;in other words, people generallyfail to aPplyBayes'stheorem (Birnbaum & Mellers,1983). Chapter 2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 79 Should deliberativemind-set subjectsdo better in all of these probability judgments? Or do improvements in probability judgments generally require instructionin statistics(Nisbett,Fong,Lehman,& Cheng,1987)? For someof the above-reportedfailures in assessingthe probability of certain events correctly, intensiveinstruction in statisticsseemsnecessaryto achievenoticeableimprovements (e.g.,when the applicationof the Bayesiantheoremis calledfor); however, for other failures,such as the overconfidencephenomenon,benefit may result from a deliberativemind-set.\fith respectto probabilityjudgmentsrelatedto the feasibility of the desired outcome, however, one would expect that all relevant judgments should becomemore accuratein a deliberativemind-set. Moreover, one wonders whether the deliberativemind-set may also reduce shortcomings people evidencewhen analyzing the desirability of a choice. Äs decisionresearchershave repeatedlyobserved(Baron, 1988;Slovic et al., 1988), people ignore minor differencesbetweenoptions; they employ simplified strategies (e.g.,elimination by aspects);they avoidtradeoffsbetweenequailyimportant they weight negativeconsequences differently from positive conseconsequences; quences,thus falling prey to framing effects; and they overweight consequences that are absolutelycertain (the certaintyeffect).Moreover,many potential consequencesare not even considered,and relevant values,attitudes,and goals that are ignored (in particuallow one to estimate the attractivenessof consequences lar, those that are contradictory).Again, one may raisethe questionof whether people need explicit training to avoid theseshortcomings.So far, no researchhas been conductedto explore whether a deliberative mind-set reducesthese shortcomings. Researchconductedin the realm of person memory suggeststhat this may be possible.During impressionformation, people give greater attention and processingto relatively infrequent behaviorsthat do not match the overall picture of the target person (i.e., are inconsistentor contradictory).However, once an impressionhasbeenformed,it is the consistentinformation that is preferentially encodedand better remembered(for reviews,seeHiggins & Bargh, L987;Ruble & Stangor, 1986). Apparently, as soon as one is ready to act on an impression formed (implemental mind-set), the thorough analysisof the information at hand (associatedwith the deliberative mind-set during impression formation) vanishes. Mind-Sets and Open-Mindedness S7ehypothesizedthat the deliberativemind-set increasesa person's receptiveness to a broad range of incoming information, whereas the implemental mind-set decreases suchreceptiveness.$7ethought that two different structural qualities of a person'sinformation processingmight accountfor this. First, the more heeded information (i.e., information to which individuals are attending) people can encodeinto short-term memory, the higher their receptivity should be. Second, people should show higher receptivity if their allocation of attention is very B0 Part l. Self-Regalationand Self'Control mobile and flexible, becausethat should allow them to pick up peripheral information. Accordingly, we conductedexperiments that measured amount of heeded information encoded and allocation of attention in deliberative and implemental mind-sets. Noun Span As pointed out by Dempster (1981) and others (Case,Kurland, & Goldberg, 7982; Chi, L976), the width of a person'snoun span is a good indicator of the amounr of heeded information a person successfullyencodesinto short-term memory. In a typical noun span experiment, subjectsare read a list of words presentedlessthan 1 secondapart.\7hen the experimenterhas pronouncedthe last word of the list, subjectsare requestedto immediately rePeatall of the words in the order presented. For our experiment,we (Heckhausen& Gollwitzer,1987,Study2) prepared a whole set of word lists, including lists consistingof five, six, and sevenonesyllable nouns. S7eread a first block of word lists to subjectsto obtain baseiine scoresof their noun span.Then subjectswere given the cover story of the first experiment reported above,which offered subjectsa choicebetweentest materials for a creativitytest (Heckhausen& Gollwitzer,1987,Study 1). The subjectswere interrupted either prior to making a choice of test material (the deliberative mind-setgroup) or shortly thereafter(the implemental mind-setgroup). Immediately after the interruption, another block of word lists was read to the subjects. The words on the lists for the baselinemeasureand the critical secondtest were irrelevant to making a choicebetweentest materials.\7e also employed a control group that was never offered a choice between test materials, but still took the baselineand critical noun span test. \7hen computing the noun spansvia a classicproceduredescribedby \7oodworth and Schlosberg(1954,p. 696),we found that deliberativemind-setsubjects showed a broader span in the second,critical assessment,as compared to their baseline scores. Their noun span increased after they had moved from the ordinary test situation (testing sessionfor baselinedata) into a deliberativemindset associatedwith contemplating the choiceof test material. This increasednoun span was also significantly elevatedas compared to both the first and second assessmentsof the control group. For the implemental mind-set group, no significant decreasein noun span was observedbetween the first and second possibly,the task of planning one's performanceon the chosen assessments; creativity rest was just not complex and involving enough to createa Pronounced implemental mind-set. It might be suggestedthat the superior performance of the deliberative mind-set subjectson the noun span test may have been rooted in an increasein nonspecificactivation causedby disrupting deliberation.Flowever,the resultsof a further study (Heckhausen & Gollwitzer, 1986, Study 3) do not support this explanation. This study employed exactly the same paradigm as the noun span experimenr, except that subjectsworked on simple arithmetic tasks instead of recalling lists of nouns.I7e thought that performing highly routinized and nearly Chabter2. Acti.onPhasesand Mind.-Sets 81 informationless mental tasks such as these should profit from an increasedlevel of activation. Accordingly, if performance on such tasks was not facilitated when these tasks were solved within a deliberative mind-set, nonspecific activation was unlikely to have produced the increase in noun span. As it turned out, no differences in performance were observed between the groups. Mobile Allocation of Attention The last study to be presentedhere suggeststhat a deliberativemind-set involves a greater receptivity to incoming information, becausecomparatively more heededinformation is encoded.But there should be a secondsourceof greaterreceptivity-that is, an increasedreadinessto encodeperipheral,incidental information. Flexible, mobile allocation of attention should enhance the individual'schancesof encodingsuch information, whereasallocatingattention solely to information that is alreadyheededshould reducethem. \Weconductedthe following experiment (Gollwitzer &. Heckhausen,1987, Study 1) to explore whether the deliberativemind-set increasesflexible allocation of attention and the implemental mind-set reducesit. The idea underlying this study drew on researchdone by developmentalpsychologistsinterested in the developmentof attentional processesin children (Hagen & Hale, 1973).Much of "centralthis research(e.g.,Miller & S7eiss,1981) has involved the so-called incidental learning task," in which children are askedto remember the location of certain objects designatedas central while other objects designatedas incidental serveas potential distractors.At the end of this task, children are unexpectedly asked to recali the incidental objects in addition to the central objects; this determines whether attention was also allocatedto the incidental information. $7emodified this task so that adults would also find it involving. In our task, the central information was a short story consistingof factualstatementsabouta small university in northern Germany. This story was presentedsentenceby sentence,and subjectswere told to memorize it for later recall. The incidental information took the form of single, unrelated two-syllable nouns placed next to each sentence.These nouns also were irrelevant to the decisionalproblem that was used to create deliberative and implemental mind-sets (see below). After presentation of the stimulus material, a rccognition test for the incidental information was applied. Recognition of the incidental material seemed a more appropriate measure than recall, becauserecall speaks to the accessibilityof information in memory, whereas the availability of the incidental information was at issue here. The latter is more sensitively captured by a recognition procedure(seeBargh & Thein, 198); Srull, 1981, 1984>. Subjectsviewed the information and had to recall it either prior to making a decision (deliberativemind-set group) or shortly thereafter (implemental mindset group). In the control group, subjectsworked on the central-incidental task, neither having made nor expecting to make a decision.The decisionthat subjects had to make was embeddedin the following cover story: Subjectswere to play the part of a personnel manager. The problem at hand was to hire one of two applicants for the position of a product manager. Part l. Self-Regalationand Selt''Control 82 Deliberative mind-set subjectsrecognized the incidental information significanrly better than implemental mind-set subjects,with control subjectsshowing a recognition performance that tended to be better than that of the implemental minä-set subjects and worse than that of the deliberative mind-set subjects. In addition, there was no difference among these three grouPs with respect to how certain they felt about the correctness of their judgments. Äccordingly, the hypothesis that the motivational mind-set is characterizedby more mobile allocation of attention than the implemental mind-set finds suPport in this pattern of data. Summary The last two experimentspresentedsuggestthat deliberativemind-set subjectsare more recepriveto availableinformation than are implemental mind-set subjects.This is becausedeliberativemind-setsubjects(1) encodecomParatively more heededinforrnation into short-term memory, and (2) show more mobile allocation of attention. The conductedexperiments suggestthat the deliberative mind-set enhancesreceptivity via encoding of heeded information and that it tends to do so via mobile allocation.\7ith respectto the implemental mind-set's postuiated reduction in receptivity, our findings are much weaker. There is no reduction in terms of encoding,and only a tendencywith respectto allocation of arrention. Possiblywe failed to create strong implemental mind-sets in both experimenrsreported. Subjectsmay not haveexperienceda full-blown implemental mind-set, and this may have been the reason why we did not observe any significant reductions in receptivity. AND MECHANISMS THEIRCORRELATES MIND.SETEFFECTS: Not ail mind-sets influence cognitive processingto an equal degree;some are more potenr than others. \ü7hat are the correlates (variables) that accompany these differences?These variablesshould be different for each of the actionrelated mind-sets outlined at the beginning of this chapter (the deliberative, implemental, actional.,or evaluativemind-set). But all of these variables are related to the individual's involvement with trying to solve the task associated with the respecriveaction phase (the predecisional,preactional,actional, or postactionalphase). For instance,in the predecisionalphase the task is to determine which of one's wishes is most desirablebut still feasible.\Whether intensive task involvement (i.e.,intense deliberation)will actuallyoccur dependson the wish that is scrutinized,the surrounding environment, and various personal attributes.Inrensedeiiberation should be hindered when the individual's freedom of choice is restrictedby others (e.g.,superiorswho make the final decision);when habit or need intervenes(i.e., there is no questionwhich wish will be chosen);or when aheadychosen superordinate goals determine which subordinate wish will be implemented (i.e., goal-closeddecisions;Toda, I976). It should be stimulated Chapter2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 83 wheneverconflict existsbetweenwishesthat appearequallydesirableor between feasibilityand desirabilityof a given wish. Other variablesthat should stimulate intense deliberationare the accountabilityand irreversibility of the individual's choiceand the amount of information available.A number of potentially relevant personalattributes,suchascertaintyorientation (Sorrentino& Short, 1986),state orientation (Kuhl, 1984), sensitizationcoping style (Olson & Zanna, 1979), failure threat and depression(Pietromonaco& Rook, 1987), and the state of (Wicklund & Ickes,1972),may all favor intense deliberaprivate self-awareness tion. Finally,it alsoseemspossibleto intensify deliberationthrough self-instructions and through instructionsgiven by the experimenter (seeMischel's[1983] work on self-regulation). All of these variablesdeterminehow involved a person may becomewith deliberatingwishes,and thus have to be consideredas potential correlateswith the potency of the deliberative mind-set. Similarly, becoming intensely involved with the task of promoting the initiation of actions(implemental mind-set),the effectiveexecutionof goal-directedactivities(actionalmind-set),and the proper evaluationof the effects of one's goal striving (evaluativemind-set) should all dependon the specificqualitiesof the problem at hand, the situationalcontext, and variouSpersonality attributes.I havetried to specifythesevariableselsewhere (Gollwitzer, 1990);as it turns out, there are different correlateswith the potency of eachof thesemind-sets.I do not repeatthis analysishere,but insteadraisethe question of what types of mechanismsproduce mind-set effects. The classicdefinition of mind-set (Einstellung) advancedby the Wörzburg schoolsuggeststhat the mechanismsmediating mind-set effectsare locatedin the cognitiveprocessesadvancingthe solution of the task that stimulatedthe mindset. In the presentedresearchon deliberativeand implemental mind-sets,we observedthat mind-sets affectedsubjects'thought production, the recall of congruous information, the analysis of desirability-relatedinformation, the inferencesmade on the basis of feasibility-relatedinformation, and finally the attentional processeswhen irrelevant information had to be encoded.It appears,then, that deliberativeand implemental mind-sets make any knowledge that helps to Part of this knowledge is categoricalor solve the respectivetask more accessible. episodicand relatesto the specificproblem at hand (i.e.,the decisionto be made or the project to be planned). The other part is procedural and relates to how wishesare deiiberated(deliberativemind-set) or how projectsare planned (implementalmind-set) in general.It is this latter part that we found to transfer to subsequent,unrelated tasks. In this sense,the observedmind-seteffectsare most similar to the cognitivetuning effects originally analyzedby Zajonc (1960) and extended by Brock and Fromkin (1968),Cohen (1961),Leventhal(1962),and most recentlyby Higgins, McCann, and Fondacaro (7982). This researchemploys a paradigm in which subjectsare assigneddifferent tasks.Half of the subjectsare told to transmit their impressionof a target personto others,whereasthe other half arc told to receive others' impressions of the target person. Subsequently,how subjects organize information on the target personand what kind of information is suppressedare 84 and Self'Control Partl. Selt''Regulation analyzed.Clearly,thesestudiesalso demonstratethat different task assignments may act as steering mechanismsfor organizingpresentedinformation. The researchreported here expandson this ideaby stating that the taskspeople faceat the various action phasescreatedistinct mind-setsthat tune people'scognitive functioning. The observedmind-seteffectsshouldnot be confusedwith researchfindings "New Look" in perception (Bruner, \957; reported under the heading of the "category Bruner & Goodman, L947). This researchintroduced the notion of accessibility."It is assumedthat the easewith which a given stimulus input is codedin terms of a given categorydependsnot only on the match between the featuresof the stimulus and of the category;other factors,such as expectancyand needstates,can alsoincreasethe likelihood that a particularcategoryrather than an alternative will be applied to the input. More recently,it has been demonstrated that simply activating (priming) a concept in one task is capableof increasingthe accessibilityof that construct in an unrelated subsequenttask where subjects are asked to categorizea target person's behavior (Higgins, Rholes,&Jones, 1977;Srull * $(yer, 1979).In general,this researchfocuseson so that it influencesthe interpretahow a certain categoryis mademore accessible tion of availableinformation in its own terms. Our mind-set research,on the other hand, exploresthe effectsthat becomingintensely involved with the task of deliberating or planning has on the accessibilityof appropriate cognitive procedures.In this sense,our researchis more similar to recent attempts to delineate effectsof goals or roles on the elaboration and organizationof availableinformation, as reported by Srull and \Wyer(1986) and Zukier (1986), respectively. Also, there is the question of whether mind-set effects are basedon active, consciousprocessesinvolving deliberate strategies and control, or on passive, unconsciousprocessesthat occur automaticallyand are uncontrolled (Higgins & King, 1981; Posner& S7arren, 7972) . As Bargh ( 1989) pointed out, these aspects of being an intentional (active) processcharacterizedby awarenessand control may nor always come in the two configurations described (i.e., all three are presentor all three are absent),as seemsto be the casewith our subjects.First, our subjecrswere not awareof the mind-set effectswe observedin the illusion-ofstudy (i.e., subjects'cercontrol study or in the mobile-allocation-of-attention tainty ratings were high and did not differ betweengroups). Second,however,if we had made subjectsawareof them (and this is also true for the fairy tale study), subiects could have easily halted (controlled) them. Finally, deliberative and implemental mind-set effects would not occur in the absenceof an explicit intention to deliberate an unresolved problem or to plan a chosen project, respecrively.So it appearsthat mind-setscarry more of the qualities of activesets than of passivesets (Higgins & King, 1981). Finally, how do we accountfor the observedtransfer of the cognitive processesstimulated by deliberatingor planning to subsequentunrelated tasks?This effect reminds of Luchins's (1942) problem-solvingexperiments,in which he demonstrated that when subjectsrepeatedly solved a given type of arithmetic Chapter2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 85 problem suggestinga certain strategy,they then applied this strategyto subsequent arithmetic problems even when other ways of solving the problem were possibleor necessary. Obviously,practicedmental operationsmay transfer frorn the training context to subsequentcontexts to which they do not immediately aPply. The questionsof what featuresof the subsequentcontext enhancethis effect, how much time may pass before such effects vanish, and what exactly happens to mental proceduresduring practice remain open. Recent researchby J. R. Anderson on the acquisitionof cognitive skill has begun addressingthese issues(Anderson,1982,1,987;in the realm of socialcognition,seeSmith, Branscombe,& Borman, 1988;Smith & Lerner, 1936). GENERAT SUMMARYAND CONCLUSION The starting point of this chapter is the questionof whether the courseof events associatedwith goal-oriented behavior is homogeneous. Although early researchers(e.g.,Narziss Ach, Kurt Lewin) studying goal-oriented behavior vehemently argued against such a view by suggesting that goal setting and goal striving are ruled by different principles, this insight was widely ignored in later researchon motivation (e.g.,in researchstimulated by Atkinson's risk-taking model). S7eintroduceda model of action phasesin a renewedattempt to delineate the various distinctive phenomena of goal-orientedbehavior.These phenomena are consideredto be deliberatingwishes (potential goals),planning the implementation of chosen goals, acting on these goals, and evaluating one's goal striving (i.e.,the outcomeand its consequences). Under the assumptionthat thesephenomenapresent themselvesto individuals engaged in goal-oriented endeavors as tasks that need to be solved in succession,the conceptof mind-set has been introduced.It has been argued that being involved with these tasks leads to characteristic cognitive orientarions (mind-sets) that are beneficial for solving these tasks efficiently. The cognitive orientations related to eachof these tasks (or phenomena) have been spelledout. Finally, a number of experiments have been reported that empirically tested the cognitive orientations postulatedfor the deliberativeand implemenral mind-sets. This researchhas shown that the deliberativemind-set is characterizedby cognitive tuning toward outcomeexpectancyand expected-value-related thoughts and information, by an accurateanalysisof outcome-expecrancy-related information and an impartial analvsisof expected-value-related information, and by a heightened general receptivity to availableinformation. The implemental mind-ser, on the other hand, is characterizedby cognitive tuning roward the implementational thoughts and information, and by an optimistic analysisof expecrancy-related information. These findings strongly suggestthat researchersof motivation should question the still-common view that goal-orientedbehavior is a homogeneousphenomenon. It seemsmore appropriate to conceiveof goal-oriented behavior as a 86 and Self-Control Partl. Self-Regulation of distinctivephenomenathat are ruled by their own principles.The succession very recentrevival of interest in goal concepts(Pervin, i989) and in the issueof commitment (Brickman, 1987) seemsbasedon this vievrBut the presented findings are also important in their own right. They suggestthat the individual's cognitive apparatusreadily adjuststo the various demandsof goal-orientedbehavior,and they thus stimulatea new persPectiveon common topics in the psychologyof motivation (e.g.,illusion of control), clinicai psychology(e.g.,depressiverealism),decisionmaking (e.g.,certaintyjudgments), and socialcognition (e.g.,impressiontesting vs. impressionformation). Finally, they imply interestinganswersto the questionof how peoplecan more effectively rurn their wishes into action. Acknowledgments I arn gratefulto John This chapteris dedicatedto the memoryof Heinz Heckhausen. Bargh,Tory Higgins,ChristineLiu, RichardSorrentino,and RobertWicklundfor their comments on an earlier draft. References Ach, N. (190r). Über d,ie \Y'illenstätigkeitund das Denken [\Tilling and thinking]. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck* Rupprecht. Ach, N. (1910).Über den \Y/illenvkt and.dat Temperamenr[Temperamentand the act of willing]. Leipzig:Quelle& Meyer. Ach, N. (1935).Analyte des \Y'illens[The analysisof willing]. Berlin: Urban & Schwarzenberg. Alloy, L.8., & Äbramson,L. Y. (1979).Judgmentof contingencyin depressedand nondepressed students:Sadderbut wiser?Journalof ExperimentalPsychology:General,108,44I-485. depressionand the illusion of control. Alloy, L. B., & Abramson,L. Y. (1982).Learnedhelplessness, Journal of Personality and'Social Psycb ologit, 42, 1114-1126. In L. B' Alloy, L. B., & Abramson,L. Y. (1988).Depressiverealism:Four theoreticalperspectives. Alloy (Ed.), Cognitiaeprocertesin depretsioo(pp.22i-265). New York: Guilford Press. Reuieu, 89,369-406. Anderson,J. R. (1982).Acquisitionof cognitive skill.Psychological Anderson, J. R. (1987). Skill acquisition: Compilation of weak-minded problem solutions. Psych ological Reaieu.,,94, I92-210. Atkinson,J.\7. (1957).Motivationaldeterminantsof risk-takingbehavior.PrychologicalReuiett,64, 4\g-17) Atkinson,J. If. (1964). An introduction to motiaation. Princeton, NJ: Van Nostrand. Atkinson,J. W. (1974). Strength of motivation and efficiency of performance. InJ. \7. Atkinson and V. H. STinJ. O. Raynor (Eds.), Motiaation and.achieaentent (pp.193-218). \Tashington, DC: ston. Atkinson, J. S7.,& Birch, D. (1970). Tbe d.Tnatnicsof action. New York: ITiley. Atkinson, J. W., & Reitman, !7. R. (i956). Performance as a function of motive strength and expectancyof goal attainment. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychologlt, 53,36I-366. Bargh, J. A. (1989) Conditional automaticity: Varieties of automatic influence in social perception and cognition. InJ. S. Uleman &J.A Bargh (Eds.), Unintended thought (pp.3-5t). New York: Guilford Press. Bargh, J. A., & Thein, R. D. (1985). Individual consrruct accessibility,person memory, and the recalljudgment link: The case of information overload. Journal of Pertonality and. Social Prychology, 49, 1L29-1146. Baron, J. (1988). Thinking and.decid.ing.New York: Cambridge University Press. Chaöter 2. Action Pbases and Mind-Sets 87 Beck, A. T. (1967). Depression: Clini.cal,experimental, and theoretical aspectr. New York: Hoeber. Beck, A. T. Q976). Cognitioe therapy and the emotional dhorders. New York: International Universities Press. Beckmann,J.,& Gollwitzer, P. M. (1987).Deliberativeversusimplemental statesof mind: The issueof impartiality in pre- and postdecisional information processing. Social Cogniti.on, 5,2t9-279. Birnbaum, M. H., & Mellers, B. A. (i983). Bayesianinference:Combining baserates with opinions of sourceswho vary in credibility. Journal of Personality and. Soc.ialPsycbologjt,45,792-804. Bobrow, D. G., & Norman, D. A. (197t). Some principies of memory schemata.In D. G. Bobrow & A. Collins (Eds.), Representationand.understanding (pp. 131-149). New York: Academic Press. Bobrow, D. G., & \7inograd,T. (1977). An overview of KRL, a knowledge representation language. Cognitiue Science,1, 3-46. Boring, E. G. (i950). A history ol experimental psychologT.New York: Appleton-Cenrury-Crofts. Brehm,J. \7. (1956). Postdecisionchangesin the desirability of alternatives.Journal of Abnormal and. Social P ry cbolo gy, 52, 384-389. Brehm, J. W., & Cohen, A. R. (1962). Explorations in cognitiue d.issonance.New York: I7iley. Brehm, J. W., \Wright, R. 4., Solomon, S., Silka, L., & Greenberg, J. (1983). Perceived difficulty, energization, and the magnitude of goal valence.Joarnal ot' Experimental Social Psycbologlt, 19, 2r-48. Brickman,P. (1987).Comnzitrzent,cont'lict,and.caring.EnglewoodCliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Brock, T. C., & Balloun,I. L. (1967).Behavioralreceptivity to dissonantinformation. Journal of Abnormal and SocialPsychology,6, 413-428. Brock,T. C., & Fromkin, H. L. (i968). Cognitivetuning set and behavioralreceptivityto discrepant information.Journal ot' Personality,36, 108-125. Brockner,J.,* Rubin,J. Z. (L985).Entrapmentin escalatingconflicts:A socialpsychologicalanalysis. New York: Springer. Bruner,J. S. (1957).On perceptualreadiness. Psychological Reuiett,64,I23-1r2. Bruner,J. S.,& Goodman,C. C. (1947).Valueand needasorganizingfactorsin perception.Journalof Abnormal and,SocialPsychology, 42,13-44. Buchanan,B. (I974). Building organizationalcommitment:The socializationof managersin work organizations. Ad.minbtratia e ScienceQuarterllt, 19, 133-546 Carver,C. S., & Scheier,M. F. (1981). Attention and selt'-regulation: A control-theoryapproacbto ltuman behaaior.New York: Springer. Case,R., Kurland, D. M., & Goldberg,J. Q982).Operationalefficiencyand the growth of short-term memory span.Journalof ExperimentalChild.Psychologlr, 33,386-404. Chapman,D. W. (1932). Relative effectsof determinateand indeterminateAufgaben.American Journal of Prychologt, 44, 763-174. Chi, M. T. H. (1976).Short-term memory limitations in children: Capacttyor processingdeficits? Memoryand Cognition,4,559-572. Cohen,A. R. (1961).Cognitivetuning asa factoraffectingimpressionformation.Journalof PersonalitJl,29,235-24r. Csikszentmihalyi, M. (T97t). Beyondboredomand.anxiety.San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Davidson,J. R., & Kiesler,S. B. (T964).Cognitivebehaviorbeforeand after decisions.In L. A. Festinger (Ed.), Conflict, d.ecision, and dissonance(pp. 45-6I). Stanford,CA: StanfordUniversiry Press. Dellarosa,D., & Bourne,L. E. (1984).Decisionand memory:Differential retrievabilityof consistent and contradictoryevidence. Journalof VerbalLearningand.VerbalBehaaior,23,669-682. Dempster,F. N. (1985). Short-term memory developmentin childhood and adolescence. In C. J. Brainerd (Ed.), Basicprocesses in memory deuelopment(pp.209-248). New York: Springer. Emmons,R. A. (1989).The personalstriving approachto personality.In L. A. Pervin (Ed.), Goal conceptsin personalityand.socialpsychology(pp. 87-126).Hillsdale,NJ: Erlbaum. Ericsson, K. A., & Simon,H. A. (1980).Verbalreporrsas data.Psycbological Reuieut,87,2l5-25I. Farrell,D., & Rusbult,C. E. (1981).Exchangevariablesaspredictorsof job satisfaction,job commitment,and turnover:The impactof rewards,costs,alternatives,and investments.Organizational Bebaaiorand Human Performance, 28, 78-95. BB Part l. Self-Regulationand Self-Connol Feather, N. T. (1967). Valence of outcome and expectation of successin relation to task difficulty and perceived iocus of control. Journal of Personality and.Social Psychologjt,7,372-186. Festinger, L. A. (1944. A theoreticai interpretation of shifts in level of aspiration. Psychological R e u i e t u ,4 9 , 2 3 > - 2 t 0 . Festinger, L. A. (Ed.). (1964). Conflict, d.ecirion,and dissonance.Snnford, CÄ: Stanford University Press. Fischhoff, B., Slovic, P., & Lichtenstein, S. (1917). Knowing with certainty: The appropriateness of extreme confidence. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Hurnan Perception and. Performance, 3 ,t 5 2 - 5 6 4 . Frey, D. (1936). Recent researchon selectiveexposure to information. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),Adaances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 19, pp. 4i-80). Orlando: Academic Press. Gallistel, C. R. (1980). The organization of action: A new rynthesb. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Gallistel, C. R. (198t). Motivation, intention and emotion: Goal-directed behavior from a cognitiveneuro-ethological perspective. In M. Frese * J. Sabini (Eds.), Goal-directed behaaior: The concept ot' action in psycbologlt (pp. 48-65). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Gerard, H. B. (1967). Choice difficulty, dissonance,and the decision sequence.lournal ot' Personality, 35.9r-r08. Gibson, I. I. Q94T). Ä critical review of the concept of set in contemporary experimental social psychology. Psy ch olo gical Ball et in, 3 8, 7 8I -817 . Gollwitzer, P. M. (1987). The implementation of identity intentions: A motivational-volitional perspective on symbolic self-completion. In F. Halisch * J. Kuhl (Eds.), Motiaation, intention and a olition (pp. 349-169). Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Gollwitzer, P. M. (1990). Abuägen und. Planen ab BewuJ3tseinslagenfDeliberating and planning as mind-sets]. Göttingen: Hogrefe. Gollwitzer, P. M., & Heckhausen, H. (1937). Bread,th of attention and the coanrerplea bearistic: Further eaid.enceon tbe motitational and aolitional nzind'-setdistinction Unpublished manuscript, Max-Planck-Institut für psychologischeForschung, Munich. Gollwitzer, P. M., & Heckhausen,H., & Ratajczak,H. (1990). From weighing to willing: Äpproaching a change decision through pre- or postdecisional mentation. Organizational Behaaior and Haman De cision Procesle t, 45, 41 -65. Gollwitzer, P. M., & Heckhausen, H., & Steller, B. (1989). Deliberatioe and implemental mind-tets: Cognitiae tuning toward congruou thoughtt and. information. Unpublished manuscript, MaxPlanck-Institut für psychologischeForschung, Munich. Gollwitzer, P. M., & Kinney, R. F. (1989). Effects of deliberative and implemental mind-sets on illusion of control. Journal of Personality and' SocialPsitchologt, 56,53I-542. Goliwitzer, P. M., & N7icklund, R. A. (1985). The pursuit of self-defining goals. In J. Kuhl & J. Beckmann (Eds.), Action control: From cognition to behaaior (pp. 61-85). Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Hacker,Iü. (1985). Activity: A fruitful concept in industrial psychology. In M. Frese &J. Sabini (Eds.), Goal-directed behauior: Tbe concept of action in psychology @p.262-283). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. l{agen,J.\7., & Hale, G. A. (1973). The development of attention in children. In A. D. Pick (Ed.), Minnetota Symposiam on Child. Psychology (Vol. 7, pp.Il7-1,40). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Heckhausen,H. (T977). Achievement motivation and its constmcts: A cognitive model. Motiaation and.Emotion, 1, 283-329. Heckhausen, H. (1987a). Intentionsgeleitetes Handeln und seine Fehler [Action slips]. In H. Heckhausen, P. M. Gollwitzer, & F. E. I7einert (Eds.), Jeueits d.es Rubikon: Der V'ille in den Hunt anuit senscbat'ten (pp. 143-\7 5 ). Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. In H. HeckHeckhausen, H. (1987b). \7ünschen-\üählen-S7olien fWishing-weighing-willingl. hausen, P. M. Gollwitzer, & F. E. I7einert (Eds.), Jenseits des Rubikon: Der lY/ille in d'en Hunzantaissenscb aften (pp. 3-9) Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Heckhausen,H., & Gollwitzer, P. M. (1986). Information processing before and after the formation of Cbapter 2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 89 an intent. in F, Klix & H. Hagendorf (Eds.), In m.ertoriam Hermann Ebbinghaus: Symposium on tbe stractareand function of buman ntemorl (pp. 1071-i082). Ämsterdam: Elsevier/NorthHolland. Heckhausen, H., & Gollwitzer, P. M. (1987). Thought conrenrs and cognitive functioning in motivational versus volitional states of mind. Motiuation and.Emotion, l1, r0r-r20. Heckhausen,H., & Kuhl,J. (1985). From wishes to action: The dead ends and short-cutson the long way to action. In M. Frese & J. Sabini (Eds.), Goal-d.irected, behaaior: The concept of action in psychology (pp. i34-159). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Higgins, E. T., & Bargh, J. A. (1987). Social cognition and sociai perception. Annual Reuieu of Prych olo gy, 3 8, 369-425. Higgins, E. T., & King, G. (1981). Accessibiiity of social constructs: Information-processing consequences of individual and contextual variability. In N. Cantor & J F. Kihlstrom (Eds.), Personality, cognition, and social interaction (pp.69-T2r). Hiilsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Higgins, E. T., McCann, C. D., & Fondacaro, R. (1982), The communication game: Goal-directed encoding and cognitive consequences. SocialCognition, 1,2L47. Higgins, E. T., Rholes, N7.S., &Jones, C. R. (1977). Category accessibiliryand impression formation. Journal of Experimental Social Psycbologjt, 13,l4l-I54. Hillgruber, A. (1912). Fortlaufende Arbeit und N7illensbetätigung [Continuous work and willing]. Untersucbungen zur Psychologie und. Philosopbie, 1(6). Hoch, S. J. (1985). Counterfactual reasoning and accuracyin predicting personal events. Journal of Exp eriment al Psych olo gy : Learnin g, Menzory, and. Cognition, 1 l, I Ig -7 jI. Humphrey, G. (19t1). Thinking. London: Methuen. Insko, C. A., \7orchel, S., Folger, R., & Kutkus, A. (1975). A balance theory interpretation of dissonance.Prychological Reaieut, 82, 169-I83. Janis, I. L., & Mann, L. (1968). A conflict theory approach to attitude change and decision making. In A. Greenwald, T. Brock, & T. Ostrom (Eds.), Psychologicalfoand.ations of attitudes (pp.327360). New York: Academic Press. Jecker,J. D. (1964). The cognitive effects of conflict and dissonance.In L. A. Festinger (Ed.), Conflict, d.ecision,and.d.issonance(pp.2l-10). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Jones, E. E., & Gerard, H. B. (1967). Found.ationsof social psychology. New York: STiley. Kanter, R. M. (1972). Commitment and contmunity: Cornmunes and.utopias in sociologicalperspectiae. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kelley, H. H. (1983). Love and commitment. In H. H. Kelley, E. Berscheid, A. Christensen, H. J. Harvey, T. L. Huston, G. Levinger, E. McClintock, L. A. Peplau, & D. R. Peterson (Eds.), Close relationship: (pp.26)-314). San Francisco: \7. H. Freeman. Kiesler, L. A. (1971).Tbe psychology of commitrzen. New York: Academic press. Klinger, E. (L977). Meaning and. aoid: lnner experience and. tlte incentiues in people's liues. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Kornadt, H. J. (1988). Motivation und Volition: Anmerkungen und Fragen zur wiederbelebten $TillenspsychologiefMotivation and volition: Comments on the revived psychology of willing]. Archia für Psychologie, 140, 209-222. Kuhl, J. (1983). Motiuation, KonfliAt und. Hand.lungskontrolle. fMotivation, conflict, and action controll. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Kuhl, J. (1984). Volitional aspects of achievement motivation and learned helplessness: Toward a comprehensive theory of action control. in B. A. Maher (Bd.), Progrets in experimental personalitT researcb (Vol. 13, pp. 99-U1). New York: Academic Press. Kukla, A. (1972). Foundations of an attributional theory of performance. Psychological Reuieu,,,79, 454-470. Langer, E. J. (1971). The illusion of control. Joarnal of Personalityand SocialPqtcbolog4, 32,31L-328. Leventhal, H. (1962). The effects of set and discrepanry on impression change. lournal of Personality, 30,r-tl. Lewin,K. (1926).Vorsatz,S7illeund Bedürfnisflntention, will, and need].Prychologische Forscltung, 7, 330-385. 90 Part l. Self-Regalation and Self-Control New York: McGraw-Hili' Lewin, K. (19i6). Principlet ot' topologicalpsYcholog\' InJ. M' Hunt (Ed'), i. 4., & Sears,P. S. (1944).Levelof aspirationLewin,K., Dembo,T., Festinger, (pp. 3i3-178). New York: Ronald Press' personalit\and.the bebaaiord.isorders Monographs,54,1-95' solving.PsTchological problem in Luchins,A. S. (7942).Mechanization for predictingcontinuityof scales Lund,M. (198t). The developmentof investmentand commitment 2,3-23' s. Journalof Socialand PersonalRelationships, personalreiationship informationon forthcoming of anticipation of Mann, L., Janis,I. L., & Ciaplin, R (1969).Effects 11,10-16' Journal of Personalityand SocialPtychology, predecisionaiprocesses. Y., & Älloy,L. B. (1984).illusionof controlfor selfandothersin depressed Martin,D. J.,Abramson,L. r25-l'36' collegestudents.Journalof Personalityand SocialPsycbologL,46, and nondepressed social and' personality ot' (Ed.), Reoietu McClelland,D. C. (1980).Moiiu. dispositions.In L. Irheeier psychology(Vol. 1, pp. i0-41). BeverlyHills, CA: Sage' uon Erfolg and'MilSert'olglAchievement U.y"f \7. U. (1973). Leisiungsrnotiuund' [Jrsachenerklärung and failure]. Stuttgart:E. Klett. motive and attributionsfor success volontaireet sesant6c6dents Michotte, A. E., & Prüm, E. (1910).f,tude e*p6rimentalesur le choix 10,lI9of ,h. act of choice).Archiaesde PsYchologie, imm6diats.[The immediateantecede.r,, )99 allocation, understanding of attention' and H., & Süeiss, M. G. (1981). Children's attention 'perf6r.rru.r.. on the central incidental learning task.Child Deaelopment,52, 7183-1190' variable in development'In Mischel, W. (1933). Delay of gratification as processand as person perspectiue D. Magnusson& v. P. Allen (Eds.), Huntan deuelopnent: An interactional (pp.149-16>).New York: AcademicPress' linkages:Tbe psychologT Mowday,R. T., Porter,L. W.,& steers,R. M. (1982). Emplo4ee-organization and.tarnoaer.New York: AcademicPress. ot' commitment,absenteeism, reasoning.science,238, Nisbett, R. E., Fong,G. T., Lehman,D. R., & cheng, P. W. (1987).Teaching Miil.;; 625-61r. shortcomings of social judgment' Nisbett, R., & Ross, L. (i980). Human inference: Strategies and Englewood cliffs' NJ: Prentice-Hatltr, pfocessesln Plerception and n ,no role of active a*ive memory Norman, D. A., & Bobrow, D. G. (1976). On the (pp. 1i4-132)' san Francisco' cognition. In c. N. cofer (Ed.), The structure of hurnan fTremory \7. H. Freeman. stage in memory retrievai' Norman, D. A., & Bobrow, D. G. (1979). Descriptions: Än intermediate Cognititte Psychology, I 1, 701-123' p. (1919). A new look at selectiveexPosure'Journal of Experimental Social Olson,J. M., &,Zanna, U. Psycbologit,15,l-1r. and psychological attachment: o'Reilly, c. o., ]|I, & chatman, J. (1986). Organizational commitment prosocial behavior' Journal of The effects of compliance, identification, and internalization on Applied P sycbology, 71, 492-499. psycholog'Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum' Pervin, L. A. (Ed.). (198t1. Goal conceptsin personality and social contribution of perceived risks Pietromonaco, P., & Rook, K. (1987). Decision style in depression:The vs. benefits. Journal of Pertonalit\ and Social Ps|cbology, 52,399-408. In A' \7' Melton & Posner,M. I., & $Varren,R. E. (1972). Traces,concePtsand consciousconstructions' \Tashington, Dc: v' H' E. Martin (Eds.), cod.ing processesin human 7ltefnory @p.25-44). \7inston. Oxford University Press' Rabkin, E. S. (1979). Fantastic tt,orld.s:Myths, tales and stories' Oxford: An elaboration of the O. (1969). Future orientation and motivation of immediate activity: Raynor,J. ' 606-610. th.o.y of achievement motivation. Ps\chological Reuiew, 76, In G' Levinger g H' L' Rausch Rosenblatt, P.C. (1977).Needed researchoo commitment in marriage' Ämherst: (Eds.), close relatiouhips: Perspectiaes on tbe meaning of intimacY Gp' 73-86)' University of MassachusettsPress. from developmental and Ruble, D. N., & Stangor, c. (1986). Stalking the elusive schema: Insights -26I' social psychological analysesof gender schemas.social cognition, 4,221 Chapter 2. Action Phasesand Mind-Sets 91 Rumelhart,D. E. (197i). Notes on a schemafor stories.In D. G. Bobrow & A. M. Collins (Eds.), and understanding Repre:entation Gp.2LI-236), New York: AcademicPress. and summarizingbrief stories.In D. LaBerge&J. Samuels Rumelhart,D.E. (1977).Understanding (Eds.),Basicprocestesin readi.ngand.comprehension(pp.265-303). Hillsdale,NJ: Erlbaum. Salancik,G. R. (i977). Commitment and'the control of orgaoizationalbehaviorand belief.In B. M. in organizationalbehaaior(pp. i-54). Chicago: Staw& G. R. Salancik(Eds.),Netu d.i.rections St. Clair Press. Schwartz,B. (1988).The experimentalsynthesisof behavior:Reinforcement,behavioralstereotypy, and problem solving. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychologyot' learning and motiaation: Adaancesin researcltand theory (YoL.22, pp.93-li5). New York: AcademicPress. Selz,O. (1910).Die experimentellelJntersuchungdesWillensaktes.Zeitschrift für Ptychologie,j7, 24r-270. In M. Frese&J. Sabini(Eds.), Semmer,N., & Frese,M. (1985).Action theoryin clinicalpsychology. psychology (pp. 296-310). Hillsdale, NJ: behaaior: The concept ot' action in Goal-directed. Erlbaum. Sigwart,C. (1889).Der Begrit'fdes\Y/ollentund tein Verbähnitzum Begrift'der UrsachelThe concept of willing vs. the conceptof motivel. Freiburg:J. C. B. Mohr. Slovic,P.,Lichtenstein,S.,& Fischhoff,B. (1988).Decisionmaking.In R. C. Atkinson, R. J. Hernstein, G. Lindzey,& R. D. Luce (Eds.),Steuent'handbookof experimentalpsycbologjr:Learningand cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 673-738).New York: S7iley. Smith, E. R., Branscombe, N. R., & Borman,C. (1988).Generalityof the effectsof practiceon social judgment tasks.Journalof Personalityand SocialPsychologjt, 54,385-395. Smith, E. R., & Lerner, M. (1986). Developmentof automatismof social judgments.Journal of Personality and Soci.alPsych ology, 50, 246-259. Sorrentino,R. M., & Short,J. (1986).Uncertaintyorientation,motivation, and cognition.In R. M. of social Sorrentino& E. T. Higgins (Eds.),Handbookof motitation and cognition:Found.ations bebaaior(Vol. 1, pp.179-403). New York: Guilford Press. Srull,T. K. (1981).Personmemory:Sometestsof associative storageand retrievalmodels.Joarnalot' ExperinzentalPsychology: Human Learning and.Memory, 7, 440-463. Srull,T. K. (1984).Methodologicaltechniquesfor the studyof personmemoryand socialcognition.In R. S. S7yer* T. K. Srull (Eds.),Handbookof socialcogni.tion(Vol. 2, pp.I-72). Hillsdale,NJ: Erlbaum. Srull, T. K., & \7yer, R. S. (1979). The role of categoryaccessibilityin the interpretation of information about persons:Some determinantsand implications.Journal of Perconalityand gy, 37, 1660-1672. SocialPsycholo Srull, T. K., & \7yer, R. S. (1986).The role of chronic and temporary goals in socialinformation processing. in R. M. Sorrentino& E. T. Higgins (Eds.),Hand.bookof motiuationand cognition: Foundationsof socialbebaaior(Vol. 1, pp.503-549).New York: Guilford Press. Toda,M. (1976).The decisionprocess.Ä perspective.lntemationalJournalof GeneralSystenu,3,19-88. Tversky,4., & Kahnemann,D. (I97j). Ävailability:A heuristicfor judgingfrequencyand probability. CognitiuePrychologt, 5, 201-232. Tversky,4., & Kahnemann,D. (1974).Judgmentunder uncertainty:Heuristicsand biases.Science, 185,tt24-tt3r. Vallacher,R. R., &'$7egner,D. M. (1987).Sfhat do peoplethink they'redoing?Psyc.hological Reaiew, 94.3-r5. Yazquez, C. V. (1987). Judgments of contingency: Cognitive biases in depressed and nondepressed subjects. Journal of Personality and. Social Psycholo g1t,5 2, 419-431. von Cranach, M. (1982). The psychological study of goal-directed action: Basic issues. In M. von Cranach & R. Harr6 (Eds.), Tbe analysis of action (pp. 35-13). Cambridge, England: Cambridge Universiry Press. \Walster,E., & Festinger, L. (T964). Decisions among imperfect alternatives. In L. A. Festinger (Ed.), Cont'lict, d.ecision,and,d.issonance(pp. I3l-l4t). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. 92 Part L Self-Regalation and, Self-Control Beiträgezu einerTheoriedesDenkensfExperimentson a theory \üatt, H. J (190t). Experimentelle of thinkingl.Archiu t'ilr d.iegesanttePsychologie,4,289-436. rnotiuation and.attributiontheory.Morristown,NJ: GeneralLearning \7einer,B. (I974).Achieaement Press. with humanpotential. Wickiund,R. Ä. (1986).Orientarionto the environmentversuspreoccupation In R. M. Sorrentino& E. T. Higgins (Eds.),Hand.bookof rnotiuationand cogni.tion:Found.ations of socialbehaaior(YoI. I, pp. 64-95).New York: Guilford Press. Hillsdale,NJ: Erlbaum. on cognitiued.issonance. \Ticklund,R. A., & Brehm,J.\7. (1976).Perspectiues \Ticklund, R. 4., & Frey, D. (1981). Cognitive consistency:Motivational versusnon-motivational on euerydayunderstand,ing perspectives. I. J.P. Forgas(Ed.), Socialcognition: Perspectiaes (pp. 141-163).London:AcademicPress. Sficklund,R. A., & Gollwitzer,P. M. (1982). Sym.bolicself-completion.Hlllsdale,NJ: Erlbaum. exposure on predecisional \0ickiund,R. A., & Ickes,\7. J. Q972).The effectof objectiveself-awareness 8,378-i87. SocialPsychologT, to information.Journal ot' Exper'i.mental H. (1954).Experimentalpsychology.New York: Holt, Rinehart & lToodworth,R. S.,& Schlosberg, \7inston. Yerkes,R. M., & Dodson,J. D. (1908).The relation of strength of stimulus to rapidity of habit Neurologyand PsycholoBI,18,459-482. formation.Journal of Conaparatiae (1960). The processof cognitivetuning in communication.Journal of Abnormal and Zajonc,R. B. SocialPsychology, 61, L59-I61. Zukier, H. (1986).The paradigmaticand narrativemodesin goal-guidedinference.In R. M. Sorrenot' social tino & E. T. Higgins (Eds.),Hand.bookof motiration and cognition: Found,ations behaaior(Vol. 1, pp. 465-502).New York: Guilford Press. HANDBOOKOF MOTIVATIONAND COGNITION of SocialBehavior Foundations VOLUME2 Edited by E.TorYHiggins Columb'ia IJnia er si'ty RichardM. Sorrentino [JniaersitYof \VesternOntario THEGUILFORDPRESS New York ' London