Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity Kuo-Kuei Kao Abstract This essay argues an imaginary mode of suicide at work in Giddens’ discourse of late-modernity. First, Giddens’ early study of suicide is read as a mediator behind his transition from the theory of structuration to that of reflexive modernity, given the problematic status of agency. Moreover, this claim will be demonstrated by Giddens’ revolt against Durkheimian sociology. On the one hand, he coins the type of “attempted suicide” to reverse Durkheim’s sociology of suicide, thereby overturning a structural theory of society into a risk-taking theory of action. On the other hand, he reappropriates Durkheim’s political sociology to forge a link between suicide and reflexive agency. In this sense, Giddens’ early theory of suicide is the disavowed truth of his late theory of reflexive modernity. Accordingly, the problem with Giddens’ theory of society is that the preconditioned notion of attempted suicide plays with the suicido-generic simulation of death, hence avoiding the destructive force of real death. As such, suicide in the sense of a form of challenge to the production of social structure as such is re-totalized as the agential reproduction of social structures. In effect, the politics of reflexive modernization reveals Giddens’ adaptation to a neo-liberal society of the undead, a worldless society of individuals linked by the terror of death without death, imaginary suicide without suicide. Keywords: recursivity, reflexivity, attempted suicide, imaginary suicide, adaptation Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 1. 1 A passage from recursivity to reflexivity Giddens’ work reveals a theoretical transition from the recursive structuration of society to the reflexive modernization of the self.1 This divide has been seen by commentators as a problematic dislocation of methodological perspective from agency/structure to reflexive system.2 The central argument of Giddens’ structuration theory is to reconcile a series of oppositions between agency and structure, structure and system, and further reproduction and change within the recursive realm of “everyday life”. 3 Meanwhile, he is interested in the so-called “critical situations” to represent the systemic instability of human psyche. 4 Radicalizing the Durkheimian line, he adduces Le Bon’s analysis of mob behavior and Bettelheim’s study of Nazi concentration camps to upset the status quo of routinization. The social psychological realm opened up here could be less abnormal than general in late-modernity. The generalization of abnormal social phenomena favours the systemic perspective to that of everyday structuration. Notwithstanding bounded by his recursive theory of society, multiple social realities could be better explained through a non-linear logic of reflexivity. To be exact, he theorizes two facets of reflexivity: one is on the side of agency and the other system. On the one hand, the agential notion of reflexivity is known throughout his work as “reflexive monitoring of action,” in which elements, such as the unconscious and anxiety in the motivational structure and unintended consequences of action, are mentioned in passing because of their functional value to reproduce social practice by knowledgeable agents. 5 On the other hand, the systemic aspect of reflexivity appeared first in the two explicit formulae of “interdependence of action” and “reflexive self-regulation” in Central Problems in Social Theory. 6 Then, it faded out nearly all together in The Constitution of Society where the notion of system was simultaneously 2 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ marginalized due to the central plot of agency, structure and change. Finally, it resurfaced in The Nation-State and Violence and particularly from The Consequences of Modernity onwards.7 In light of this, the latter two pieces of work could be regarded as the empirical and theoretical manifestos of latemodernity with a distinctive approach to reflexive global systems. Examined closely, Giddens presents, first, a historical-sociological study of nation-states. His argument consists of two theses, which are industrialization/ pacification of war and globalization/ internationalization of nation-states. Giddens’ rich historical narrative demonstrates the systemic reflexivity of knowledge/ power from rule to government. Meanwhile, the meaning of systemic reflexivity is deprived of the reflexive monitoring of action, but further loaded with the dialectic of control, given the evolution of military industrialism and international diplomacy. In short, systemic reflexivity becomes dominant at the outset of nation-states’ building. Second, this institutional turn is radicalized in The Consequences of Modernity. Novel themes like late-modernity, globalization, and risk take up the central argument along with system and reflexivity. Ironically, reflexivity here implies more about the unintended consequences of action, relegating in the meantime the enabling aspect of reflexive monitoring to a purely functional value. Given the case, the social mechanism of reflexivity is altered from agential power to knowledge/ power. Accordingly, the embodied sense of an institutionalized system defined in the structuration theory as “recursively organized practices” is undermined. The upshot is a risky world of “abstract systems.” In the prevalence of extra-ordinary critical situations, trust, anxiety and ontological security become urgent issues to be addressed prior to power and agency. Giddens’ theoretical transition can be construed as delineating a social transformation from the logic of recursivity to that of reflexivity since the Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 3 ambivalent logic of reflexivity may account better for the individual psychopathology subversive to social systems. Therefore, Giddens proposes a reflexive project of the self to counteract social insecurity and anxiety brought about by institutional reflexivity. The project culminates in his theory of intimacy and self-identity as “the democratization of personal life,” life politics as the ideal habitat of the third way politics. 8 Giddens’ utopian realism here concerns the ambivalent nature of reflexivity which reflects upon itself and hence splits up from within. Reflexivity comes as the blessing as well as the peril of our uncertain times. In consequence, Giddens’ reflexive worldview induces a boomerang effect that “we are surrounded by areas where we don’t really know what we have done to existing order of things and what the consequences will be.”9 Seized by the abyss of thought, late-modern agents including Giddens himself who are supposed to “act” on the calculation of future risk and trust turn out to be “narrating” a science fiction of the future as “scenario futures” in “a number of alternative possible worlds.” 10 Gradually, the Giddensian agent has become entangled in his own riddle of tying and untying the tension between recursivity and reflexivity. 2. An elective affinity between a theory of late-modernity and a theory of suicide A. The birth of Giddens’ theory of suicide Given this reflexive turn, we might conduct a counterfactual genealogy, tracing a virtual event of “what could have happened” had Giddens early research on suicide been extrapolated as an early referential frame to his late theory of reflexive modernity. To begin with, Giddens developed his study of suicide from 1964/5 with ad hoc methods and concepts in fragmentary notes and essays. His work 4 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ targets an “attempted type” of suicide in cases where attempted suicides or suicidal threats act as “a form of social sanction against those towards whom the individual has a grievance” and “function independently as mechanisms of social sanctions.”11 For Giddens, the attempted type of suicide should have a theoretical meaning in its own right beyond circumstantial considerations. Exploring the perceived meaning of situational factors of a suicide, such as the failure of attempts due to the method, time and place, are usually deemed as fruitful to the post-Durkheimain empirical study of suicide. 12 Classical examples are Stengel’s Suicide and Attempted Suicide (1964) and Douglas’ The Social Meanings of Suicide (1967). Giddens, by contrast, stresses the ritualized and deliberative dimensions in this type of suicide as an “accepted method of bringing pressure to bear upon others” and “an attempt bound to be saved”.13 In a short note, he enumerates nearly a dozen anthropological examples of attempted or verbal threats of suicide used by aboriginal cultures, all of which aim to expiate crime through public protest or settle matrimonial disputes. However, the frame of analysis remains incoherent, flirting with the anthropological concept of ritual (“social sanction”) and psychological notions of superego (“pressure on others”), ego (“induce feelings of guilt and concern”) and the unconscious (“desire to influence others”). However, the attempted suicide finds no place in Durkheim’s typology. This is due to Giddens’ ambiguity as he singles out the attempted suicide from egoistic and anomic types of suicide. Nonetheless, it is conceived as an exceptional case of altruistic suicide because the attempted type shares the “ritualized elements” with the altruistic type. Hence, “there does exist another form of suicide, of a rather different type from ‘altruistic’ suicide, which is part of a wider social system of punishment and sanction in some societies.” 14 Giddens’ methodological position went through a transition from anthropology to social-psychology during this early period. 15 In fact, the Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 5 focus is on the “interrelationship between personality and social structure.” 16 This social-psychological method is applied in his social-historical study of the suicide problem in Durkheim’s France. 17 He argues that Durkheim’s contribution to the problem of suicide should be credited for his theoretical rather than empirical originality. Moreover, a historical interpretation of suicide should incorporate individual personality (using the method of casehistory) into social structural analysis. Giddens discusses sociological as well as psychological models in order to expose the “misconceived ontological dichotomy” in the Durkheim-Tarde divide and to construct a dualistic relation between social types and particular individuals. 18 The plot thickened as Giddens focused on egoistic and anomic suicides in his subsequent study of ‘typology of suicide’, later substantially revised as ‘a theory of suicide’.19 In his ‘typology of suicide’, only egoistic and anomic suicides are elaborated. Giddens justifies them as “modern” types that apply only to “‘industrial’ societies.”20 The manifest aim is to challenge Durkheim’s structural model from a different empirical and theoretical view. Specifically, he discusses Durkheim’s ideas of egoism and anomie through two short case reports (attempted suicide by self-poisoning and suicide by hanging) as well as long theoretical digressions (mostly Freudian). The outcomes are two explanatory flowcharts routing possible causal paths in precipitating the two types of suicide. Curiously, this essay ends in a convoluted passage. 21 First, Durkheim’s altruistic suicide is dismissed as a traditional type. Nevertheless, a subtype of altruistic suicide is retained, while “the anthropological evidence” is mentioned in passing to discredit the existence of altruism all together even in traditional societies. With this move, the distinction between modernity and tradition is suspended in order to bring all suicide cases forward into the modern types of egoism and anomie. Then, following Halbwach, sacrifice is 6 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ severed resolutely from suicide in order to arrive at an example of the monk’s suicide (who “consigns himself to the flames in a public and deliberate altruistic fashion”), which again is one “in other cases” distinguished from both altruism and sacrifice, but is nevertheless found in “a less open form” in primary modern types. Here it is difficult to pin down what Giddens tries to capture. But it’s certain that he endeavors to coin an “attempted type” inside egoistic and anomic types without the need to build another type to designate what he needs to articulate. In the meantime, he wants to differentiate this attempted type from sacrifice and altruism, and yet without losing the sacred share of altruism. The central theoretical thesis, methodological operation, and empirical data in the typology article reappears in ‘a theory of suicide,’ where the “attempted type” becomes fully developed. Apart from the methodological integration of Durkheim and Freud, Giddens’ theory of suicide requires alternative sources to clarify the uncertain nature of the attempted type. These sources include Stengel, Douglas, Masaryk and Halbwachs. First, Stengel and Cook’s Attempted Suicide (1958) serves the springboard for Giddens’ interest in the attempted type since references to them began since the 1964 note. However, Giddens’ reviews of Stengel’s and Douglas’ studies on suicide remain critical 22 . He holds that Durkheim’s approach deserves a merit of social explanation. In ‘a theory of suicide,’ Durkheim and Douglas are both under a barrage of criticisms. This double negative move leads Giddens to assimilate “meaning” with “causality” in the conception of suicide. Specifically, he revises Douglas’ perception of suicide as an action having situated meanings, as well as Durkheim’s conception of suicide as “an act carried out by an individual that results in his death, where he knows that his act will have that result.”23 Just as the causality of meaning is broadened up to include non-intentional knowing, so the meaning of causality is narrowed Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 7 down to agential causality. 24 In result, the “psychological dynamics of suicide” can be tied up with “social condition” regarded now as the “outcome of rationalized processes of action.”25 As such, he acknowledges that suicide is “probably almost universally preceded by” depression although not every case of depression leads to suicide. 26 Also, egoistic and anomic suicides are reduced to true types of suicide as “particular types of individual inter-action” rather than “types of social condition.” 27 In this regard, Giddens’ modernist presumption of individualized isolation can be traced to Masaryk and Halbwachs. In his introduction to the 1970 English translation of Suicide and the Meaning of Civilization written by the Czech philosopher-king Thomas Garrigue Masaryk, Giddens outlines a longterm change of mentality about suicide in Masaryk’s time from Greco-Roman societies onwards, further contextualizing Durkheim’s science. As a whole, the generations of Masaryk and Durkheim were preoccupied with the problem of suicide is because it represents the by-product of civilization in decline of religion and morality.28 In fact, Giddens concurred early on with Halbwachs’ dissolution of Durkheim’s typology in a more inclusive concept, “way of life” (genre de vie), which in modern times corresponds to “social isolation of the individual.”29 The factor of isolation occupied only a partial place in Giddens’ typology of suicide, referred only to egoistic suicide; however, isolation turns into a master concept in his theory of suicide, capable of explaining both types. Besides, an ambiguous discussion about the relation between Halbwachs’ “isolation” and Durkehim’s “egoism” in the concluding passage of “the suicide problem in French sociology” published twice in 1965 and 1971 was deleted in the 1977 revised version. At bottom, Giddens accepts unreservedly Halbwachs’ analysis that “the social conditions implicated in the causation of suicide have to be closely bound up with the motivated, purposive character of human behaviors.” 30 Therefore, Giddens’ 8 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ theory of suicide finds its anchor in Halbwachs’ theory of civilization as an “isolated way of life” in contradistinction to tradition as ritualized “collective memory.”31 Bearing the historical-theoretical concept of isolation in mind, one can finally appreciate the significance of the “attempted type.” Previously, we have seen the elaborate concluding argument in ‘a typology of suicide.’ The distinction of an attempted suicide from a completed one suggested in the only two case histories was unclear, while the attempted suicide couldn’t find any manifest form within the two modern types of suicide. This awkward situation was largely due to the lack of theoretical and methodological frameworks. In the final passage of ‘a theory of suicide,’ by contrast, suicide and attempted suicide become the subtitle and the central argument after a risk-taking element in all suicidal behaviors has been acknowledged. The aim is to open up the “contingent event intervening between the attempt itself and its outcome.” 32 This “contingency” feeds paradoxically on the general “normativity” of the attempted type under egoism and anomie. The two modern types of suicide are then rooted in the isolated character of suicidal actors within the system of interaction. Thus, “the social or moral isolation of the actor…helps to create his own social milieu at the same time as he is created by it.” 33 By implication, isolation is no longer a vice of social morality, but turns into a theoretical-historical condition of possibility for risk-taking actions. The manifestation of modern suicides in the attempted type plays around the as if, simulative character, which guarantees the active performance almost “bound to be saved.” B. A political theory of late-modernity contra Durkheim Giddens began his study of suicide since 1964/5 with methods and concepts still in a sketchy development. It transformed into the sophisticated Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 9 methodology and theory of suicide in 1971, and then went through a major reversal of Durkheim’s structural model into a risk-taking theory of action by 1977/8. Meanwhile, the reversal was strengthened by Giddens’ ethical-political interpretation of Durkheim’s thought. The reshaping of Durkheim’s oeuvre along this line commenced in two seminal essays on political sociology and moral individualism published in 1971, crystallized in the 1978 textbook on Durkheim, and matured in the 1986 edition of Durkheim’s political texts. The appreciation of Durkheim’s ideas of moral individualism and socialist state paved the way to his subsequent multivolume critique of Marxian historical materialism. 34 Therefore, the trilogy to recapture Marx’s critical spirit appeared soon after his radicalization of Durkheim’s thought.35 Eventually, sufficient conditions of possibility were set for the reflexive turn around 1990. Advocating change by evolution instead of revolution, Giddens’ form of politics “beyond left and right” is a result of his appreciation of Durkheim. 36 In fact, later Giddens’ political agenda in a tripartite alliance of reflexive individualism, systemic nation-states and global governance is an updated application of Durkheim’s ethical-political horizon, a horizon based on a particular history of the French dialogical moral-state in contradistinction to the German militant power-state. Moreover, a higher purpose is to solve the tension in the two Durkheims thesis with such ethical politics. Simply put, Giddens refutes the two Durkheims thesis by highlighting Durkheim’s Bordeaux courses in the years around 1895, the period of his controversial transition from science to religion. 37 According to the two Durkheims thesis, Division of Labour in Society (1893) and The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (1912) are supposed to be set apart. For Giddens, however, Durkheim’s lectures delivered in the transitional period functions to link the gap between science 10 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ (social change) and morality (religion) through practice (politics and education), since they deal with problems of authority and sanction in practical themes such as socialism, family, education and religion. Giddens’ proposal is to put forward a “coherent Durkheim thesis,” as we call it, to falsify the two Durkheims thesis invented by Parsons, a consensus still dominating the Durkheimains, regardless of their positivist, structural and cultural divisions.38 On the other hand, it is important to stress the fact that Durkheim in his transitional period between 1895 and 1897 was not only interested in the issue of politics but also the problem of suicide. In short, Giddens introduces an elective affinity between the political and the suicidal images of Durkheim’s social theory in order to turn the schizophrenic conservative into a rational radical. Given the case, a reflexive significance comes out of Giddens’ consecutive reworking of the Durkheimian issues of suicide and politics. His own transition toward reflexive modernity is produced out of this reflection upon the transitional period of Durkheim’s thought. A greater potential lying behind Giddens’ research of suicide is its potential to politicize the connection between suicide and agency. Theoretically, his new theory of suicide could be easily transposed to agency in a Sysyphusian claim for power: [P]ower relations are two-way. This accounts for the intimate tie between agency and suicide. Self-destruction is a (virtually) alwaysopen option, the ultimate refusal that finally and absolutely cancels the oppressive power of others; hence suicidal acts themselves can be understood as concerned with the exercise of power. 39 The doubling of suicide and agency explains why there were no direct Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 11 commentaries by Giddens on the problem of suicide since 1979 onwards. Strictly speaking, already noted in his new rules of sociology, the Durkheimian problem of suicide was criticized as a positivist exercise entrapped by the interplay between theoretical and common languages, unable to capture subjective experiences via objective observation. 40 As the concept of agency surfaced, suicide further lost its once prominent legitimacy in the 1979 checklist of sociological central problems, as if the classical case of suicide had been closed and done with except for the function of display in the first year sociology textbook. However, this is only the literal disappearance of completed suicides. Living the consequence of modernity, the attempted suicide is retained in the counterfactual permutations of everyday human struggle for identity and intimacy. In the late-modern lifeworld where erotic seduction is superseded by sexual conquests, the transvitalist élan suicidé thrives on the grand narratives of sexualized love and gendered identity through post-familial couples who cope with codependence, letting-go addictively and tightening-up compulsively at the same time.41 As intimacy is measured by the principles of democracy, selfidentity is tested by the precipice of “fateful moments”.42 The tragic acts of “completed suicide” have been displaced by the contingent plays of “suicidal agency” when reflexive agents strive to maintain and reverse adverse circumstances in the hours. 3. Misrecognize the modality of suicide In view of the elective affinity between Giddens’ theory of late-modernity and the theory of suicide, three critical comments can be made. First, associating the suicidal and political images of Durkheim-in-transition, he comes to endorse the culture of individualization in itself. Giddens bids farewell to all collectivist ideas of culture, ranging from cybernetic 12 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ integration to symbolic effervescence. His whole intellectual enterprise can be seen as developing a counter-sociological interpretation of reflexive individuals. Constructing the theory of reflexive modernity by the secret route of the theory of suicide, Giddens has to terminate the logic of duality in his own structuration theory. Since the conceptual efficacy in the duality of structure does not only rely on agency but also on the symbolic repression of the suicidal abyss of agency, passing to a reflexive logic blows the whole social magic. When the suicidal madness behind agency is liberated, the errant trajectories of reflexive modernity are unfolded. This is largely due to the abnormal social fact that each and every individual can claim authenticity for him/herself, and nothing but the truth of the self without exterior sources of sanctity, authority and legitimacy. Severing the umbilical cord from classical dualism, Giddens “suicides” the sociological discipline long established in Durkheimian sociology like an intellectual terrorist. 43 In consequence, Giddens’ social theory shares a deep-seated complicity with “the implosion of the social” in Baudrillard’s sense insofar as he endorses a reversal of Durkheim’s “elementary forms” from the sui-generis of the social to the suicido-generis of late-modern individuals. Second, the kernel issue concerns the modality of suicide presupposed in Giddens’ formulation of reflexive modernity. His implicit identification of the attempted suicide with reflexive modernity posits an imaginary mode, since the attempted type of suicide must be sustained by the hypothetical projection about the future consequences of action or, in Žižek’s words, by “the imagined scene of the effect his or her act will have on posterity, on it witness, on the public, on those who will learn about it.” 44 Biographically, it is plausible to argue that Giddens’ wage on the imaginary modality of suicide only rewinds the memory of his personal experience of “the cult of the self,” as Foucault would say, in the late 1960s California. A vivid image of the Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 13 imaginary suicide can be seen from Spike Jonze’s 2002 tragic comedy Adaptation, a sequel to his 1999 Being John Malkovich, in which the manicdepressive character finds himself becoming an ouroboros’ form of life.45 Given the case, he misrecognizes the forward modality of the real suicide for a backward modality of the imaginary suicide. Insofar as the characteristics of the real suicide regard “the subject’s full and direct identification with the object,” “the frame that falls into what it frames,” and eventually “the exact opposite of the death drive,” the suicidal subject experiences a fetishist pleasure. 46 As such, the imaginary suicide and the real suicide share a phenomenological homology: both modalities present themselves away from the completed acts of suicide, aiming instead at late-modern strategies of simulation, survival and adaptation. In light of this, Giddens’ existential displacement of Durkheim’s structural theory of suicide fails to see through the hyper-reality of reflexive modernity. In effect, Giddens’ misrecognition of the modality of suicide in reflexive modernity guarantees his constant falling back on the adaptation to the world that adapts to itself - because in this virtual world, imaginary suicide reigns death through a self-referential monitoring of risks and catastrophes; also because in this worldless world, late-modern individuals are less “united” by the true love of the social than “connected” by the real terror of death. From a historical view, finally, Minois demonstrates that the Western consciousness of liberty and suicide have always been a close couple from the Renaissance to the Enlightenment. Hamlet’s ghostly, ethical selfquestioning has been silenced since the coming of social sciences in the nineteenth century.47 As such, the “extreme case of euthanasia” signifies a contemporary challenge of the “thanato-ethics” of cruelty to the bioethics of suffering.48 14 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ Notes 1 A certain endogenous tension had been picked up by the discordant descriptions of Giddens’ structuration theory as eclecticism and revisionism during the 1980s. See for example, F. Dallmayr, The theory of structuration: a critique, in A. Giddens, Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory, 1982, London, Macmillan, pp. 18-27; P. Hirst, The social theory of Anthony Giddens: a new syncretism, Theory, Culture and Society, 1(2), 1982 : 78-82; M. Gane, Anthony Giddens and the crisis in social theory, Economy and Society, 11, 1983: 368-398. Afterwards, his reflexive turn provoked polarized interpretations in the 1990s: it could mean a radical fragmentation into “theoretical omelettes” on the one hand, and a classical “last modernist” defense of social order on the other. See I. Craib, Anthony Giddens, London, Routledge, 1992; S. Městrovic, Anthony Giddens: The Last Modernist, London, Routledge, 1998. 2 C. Shilling, The Body and Social Theory, London, Sage, 1993, pp. 200-202; D. Layder, Understanding Social Theory, London, Sage, 1994, pp. 138-142. 3 See A. Giddens, The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1984. Here the structure/agency debate in contemporary theoretical sociology fails to capture the complexity of Giddens’ social theory. I am referring to Lockwood’s famous article first published in 1964 on social and system integrations, and later developed into various hypotheses from M. Archer’s dualism and J. Habermas’ first-degree perspectivism to N. Mouzelis’ second-degree perspectivism and A. Giddens’ duality. In retrospective, the debate of agency/structure ended up laying the foundation for a legible genre of British theoretical sociology to emerge out of the American domination with a positivist micro-macro problematic. But this misleading approach fails to account for the fact that Giddens’ application of Lockwood’s thesis operates at the conceptual interface between structure and system instead of between agency and structure. After all, the dual relation between structure and agency has been conjoined through a skillful mixture of structuralism and ethnomethodology as the building block towards structuration theory. See A. Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory: Action, Structure and Contradiction in Social Analysis, London, Macmillan, 1979: pp. 49-73; p. 66; 77. 4 A. Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, pp. 123-130. 5 A. Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, pp. 53-59; The Constitution of Society, pp. 5-14; 41-45; 78-83. 6 A. Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, p. 78. 7 For a formal definition of systemic reflexivity in the sense of a reflexive self-regulation by knowledge, see A. Giddens, The Constitution of Society, Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 15 p. 376. This is a neutralized interpretation (more Weberian than Marxist) of Foucault’s idea of social scientific knowledge, which is exemplified in a case of educational reform to underlie “the two most pervasive types of social mobilization in modern times: the legal-rational social organization and the secular social movement.” See A. Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, p. 79. 8 A. Giddens, Modernity and Self-Identity: Self and Society in the Late Modern Age, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1991; A. Giddens, The Transformation of Intimacy: Sexuality, Love and Eroticism in Modern Societies, Cambridge, Polity, 1992; A. Giddens, Beyond Left and Right: The Future of Radical Politics,Oxford, Polity Press, 1994. 9 A. Giddens & C. Pierson, Conversations with Anthony Giddens: Making Sense of Modernity, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1998, p. 114. 10 A. Giddens in The Contemporary Giddens: Social Theory in A Globalizing Age, edited by C. Bryant & D. Jary, Basingstoke, Palgrave— then Macmillan, 2001, pp. 244-245. 11 A. Giddens, Suicide, attempted suicide, and the suicidal threat, Man: a Record of Anthropological Science, 64 (article 136), 1964, p. 115. 12 S. Taylor, Durkheim and the Study of Suicide, London, Macmillam, 1982. 13 A. Giddens, Suicide, attempted suicide, and the suicidal threat, p. 116. 14 A. Giddens, Suicide, attempted suicide, and the suicidal threat, p. 115. 15 A. Giddens, The present position of social psychology, British Journal of Sociology, 16, 1965, pp. 365-372; A. Giddens, Suicide, British Journal of Sociology, 16, 1965, pp. 164-165; Theoretical problems in the sociology of suicide, Advancement of Science, 21, 1965, pp. 522-526. 16 A. Giddens, The present position of social psychology, p. 171. 17 A. Giddens, The suicide problem in French sociology, British Journal of Sociology, 16, 1965, pp. 3-18, reprinted in The Sociology of Suicide: A Selection of Readings, edited by A. Giddens, Cass, 1971, pp. 36-51. 18 A. Giddens, The suicide problem in French sociology, pp. 44-45. 19 A. Giddens, A typology of suicide, Archive Europeénes de Sociologie, 7, 1966, pp. 276-295, reprinted in The Sociology of Suicide: A Selection of Readings, edited by A. Giddens, Cass, 1971, pp. 97-120; A. Giddens, A theory of suicide, substantially revised from A typology of suicide to be printed in Studies in Social and Political Thought, edited by A. Giddens, London, Hutchinson, 1977, pp. 297-321. 20 A. Giddens, A typology of suicide, p. 116. 21 A. Giddens, A typology of suicide, pp. 116-117. 22 A. Giddens, Suicide, p. 164; Review of Douglas, The Social Meanings of Suicide, Princeton NJ, Princeton University Press, Sociology, 3, 1969, p. 266. 23 A. Giddens, A theory of suicide, pp. 301-304. 16 Giddens’ Adaptation: Imaginary Suicide in Reflexive Modernity _______________________________________________________ 24 A. Giddens, Durkheim, London, Fontana, pp. 118-119. 25 A. Giddens, A theory of suicide, p. 312. 26 A. Giddens, A theory of suicide, p. 308. 27 A. Giddens, A theory of suicide, p. 312. 28 A. Giddens, Introduction to T. Masaryk, Suicide and the Meaning of Civilization, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1970, p. xli. 29 A. Giddens, Foreword to M. Halbwachs, The Causes of Suicide, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978, pp. xvi-xx; A. Giddens, The suicide problem in French sociology, p. 47. 30 A. Giddens, Foreword, p. xx. 31 A. Giddens, Foreword, p. xvi; A. Giddens & C. Pierson, Conversations with Anthony Giddens, p. 128. 32 A. Giddens, A theory of suicide, p. 321. 33 A. Giddens, A theory of suicide, p. 314. 34 A. Giddens, Durkheim’s political sociology, Sociological Review, 19, 1971, pp. 477-519, reprinted in Studies in Social and Political Thought, edited by A. Giddens, London, Hutchinson, 1977, pp. 235-172; A. Giddens, The individual in the writings of Emile Durkheim, Archive Europeénes de Sociologies, 12, 1971, pp. 210-228, reprinted in Studies in Social and Political Thought, London, Hutchinson, edited by A. Giddens, 1977, pp. 273-290. 35 A. Giddens, A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism, vol. 1, Power, Property and the State, London, Macmillan, 1981; A. Giddens, A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism, vol.2, The Nation-State and Violence, London, Polity Press, 1985; A. Giddens, Beyond Left and Right. 36 Durkheim on Politics and the State, edited by A. Giddens, London, Polity Press, 1986, pp. 1-31. 37 A. Giddens, Durkheim, pp. 16-19; 49-50; 63-64; 80-82. 38 The Cambridge Companion to Durkheim, edited by J. Alexander & P. Smith, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005, pp. 1-31. However, this is not to say that Giddens “solves” the problem of suicide, much less the Durkheimian issue of transition. Nor does this imply that Durkheimians have been ignorant of the problem of suicide in Durkheim’s thought. See M. Gane, On Durkheim’s Rules of Sociological Method, London, Routledge, 1988. There is likely an unbridgeable void in Durkheim’s thought a-voided by both parties in the two Durkheims thesis. In particular, this void causes the enduring attraction of Durkheim’s problematic of suicide more than one century later, regardless of Giddens’ shrewd proposal. See Durkheim’s Suicide: A Century of Research and Debate, edited by W. S. F. Pickering & G. Walford, London, Routledge, 2000. Kuo-Kuei Kao _______________________________________________________ 17 39 A. Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, p. 149. 40 A. Giddens, New Rules of Sociological Method: A Positive Critique of Interpretative Sociologies, 2nd edn, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1993, pp. 138-141. 41 A. Giddens, The Transformation of Intimacy, pp. 49-110. 42 A. Giddens, Modernity and Self-Identity, pp. 109-143. 43 See J. Baudrillard, The Spirit of Terrorism and Other Essays, London: Verso, 2003, p. 65. 44 S. Žižek, The Fragile Absolute, or Why is the Christian Legacy Worth Fighting for? London, Verso, 2000, p. 28. 45 Compare J. Baudrillard, The Intelligence of Evil or The Lucidity Pact, Oxford, Berg, 2005, p. 59; S. Žižek, The Fragile Absolute, pp. 50-54. 46 S. Žižek, The Fragile Absolute, pp. 21-24; 28-29. 47 G. Minois, History of Suicide: Voluntary Death in Western Culture, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999, p. 325. 48 G. Minois, History of Suicide, p. 328. Kao, Kuo-Kuei (Pascal) is conducting his PhD research in the Department of Social Sciences, Loughborough University, United Kingdom. His thesis is about the genealogy of sociology and love.