Sidgwick’s Methods, page 1 Sidgwick on Moral Theories and Common Sense Morality Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics deservedly enjoys a prominent place in the history of ethics.1 Its influence extends even to the fashioning of terms used to distinguish ethical theories today: It was in commentaries on Methods that C. D. Broad suggested distinguishing theories as deontological and teleological, and Elizabeth Anscombe introduced the term “consequentialism.”2 Yet surprisingly Sidgwick scholarship is barely beyond its infancy.3 Its slow progress may be attributed at least partly to the difficulty of reading it. As J. B. Schneewind, in the most authoritative single work to date on Methods, notes: 1 Unless otherwise indicated, references are to and quotations are from the seventh edition of The Methods of Ethics (London: Macmillan, 1907; Indianapolis: Hackett reprint, 1962), hereafter Methods. Other editions were published in 1874, 1877, 1884, 1890, 1893, and 1901. 2 G. E. M. Anscombe, “Modern Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy (January 1958), 1– 19; reprinted in Ethics, Religion and Politics, Vol. 3 of The Collected Philosophical Papers of G. E. M. Anscombe, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1981), 36; C. D. Broad, Five Types of Ethical Theory (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1930), 206. 3 In a letter to the author dated July 6, 1994, Marcus G. Singer says that he is not sure that he agrees with my describing Sidgwick scholarship as being in its infancy; he thinks it might perhaps be “at the kindergarten stage.” Sidgwick’s Methods, page 2 The book does not have the surface difficulties found in Kant or in Hegel, but its argument is intricate, and the very care with which it is elaborated tends to obscure it…. It has become common to think that there is no overall argument in the Methods…. Broad reinforces the common view, since he examines only selected positions defended in the Methods and does not try to show their connection with any unified argument. The reader is thus not encouraged to look for more in Sidgwick than isolated insights and analyses: he thereby misses what is central to Sidgwick’s own view of his work, and perhaps to what is most permanently valuable in it.4 Others besides Broad have concentrated on only portions of Methods. Admittedly, as a work in four parts, it is hard to read for “any unified argument,” but the unity is there. In Book I Sidgwick introduces terms crucially important for a correct understanding of Methods; in particular note “principles” and “methods” (Chapter 6), and “egoism” (Chapter 7) and “intuitionism” (Chapter 8)—two of the three methods of Methods, and “the good” (Chap. 9). Books II, III, and IV deal with the egoist, intuitionist, and utilitarian methods respectively. With Book II the reader faces the difficulty of understanding why Sidgwick gives such a high degree of respectability to egoism, when he seems only to want to discard it by Book IV. Then in Book III there is the extended and highly approving treatment of intuitionism—this by one who is usually classified with Bentham and Mill 4 J. B. Schneewind, Sidgwick’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon, 1977), 2. The reference to Broad is to the last chapter of his Five Types, 143– 256. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 3 as a utilitarian.5 And when the reader who is determined to make her way through from beginning to end finally reaches the utilitarian Book IV, with its insistence on the theoretical dependence of rightness on the good of universal happiness, it is hard to remember that its author is also the author of the intuitionist Book III, who agrees with common sense moralists that agents need not resort to any notion of goodness in order to act rightly. These points contribute to the difficulty of seeing the work as a whole, and philosophers continue to miss the work’s essential unity. That unity depends on the following neglected fact about Methods: It is the thorough and systematic examination of a single moral theory. Sidgwick presents three methods in detail—egoism, intuitionism, and utilitarianism—because prima facie they are parts of that single complex moral theory. Sidgwick did not choose that moral theory (xii, 338): it is the one he found or thought he found in common sense morality. My purpose here is to demonstrate that there is just this one moral theory in Methods, and that the requirements of that theory are entirely dictated by Sidgwick’s understanding of common sense morality. I begin with a summary of Sidgwick’s explanation of common sense morality (I). Next I discuss his view of the relationship of moral philosophy to common sense morality (II). This clears the way for me to set out what Sidgwick means by a moral theory in general (III, IV), and the moral theory of Methods 5 Sidgwick does say, when agreeing with Butler that conscience claims authority, that his conscience “was a more utilitarian conscience than Butler’s” (xx), but he also says that he is an intuitionist: “And I had become, as I had to admit to myself, an Intuitionist to some extent” (xxi). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 4 in particular (V, VI, VII). I conclude with some typical ways philosophers have misunderstood Methods (VIII). I The passage closest to a definition of common sense morality is the one in which Sidgwick distinguishes it from positive morality:6 It only requires a little reflection and observation of men’s moral discourse to make a collection of general rules, as to the validity of which there is apparent general agreement at least among moral persons of our own age and civilization, and which would cover with approximate completeness the whole of human conduct. Such a collection, regarded as a code imposed on an individual by the public opinion of the community to which he belongs, we have called the Positive Morality of the community: but when regarded as a body of moral truth, warranted to be such by the consensus of mankind,—or at least of that portion of 6 Another passage illuminating what Sidgwick means by common sense morality is the following: In considering the relation of Utilitarianism to the moral judgments of Common Sense, it will be convenient to begin with the former element of current morality, as the more important and indispensable; i.e., with the ensemble of rules imposed by common opinion in any society, which form a kind of unwritten legislation, supplementary to Law proper, and enforced by the penalties of social disfavor and contempt. (80) Common sense morality is common because of its wide acceptance. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 5 mankind which combines adequate intellectual enlightenment with a serious concern for morality—it is more significantly termed the morality of Common Sense. (214–215) Although common sense morality sometimes parallels the positive morality of the society in which it is found, it is distinct from it. Common sense morality is most often described as a set of rules, but it includes “habits and sentiments” (475). Comparing the common sense morality of one time or place with that of another often reveals “remarkable discrepancies,” though in at least one respect, to be discussed presently, they are “strikingly correlated” (426). Common sense morality, then, is a set of rules of a particular culture and the habits and sentiments attending them, distinct from and complementary to the written law of that culture, and accepted by its members, or just those who are the most reliable.7 It is imposed on individual members under pain of social disapproval. II 7 The majority is almost certainly not reliable: The majority of human beings spend most of their time in labouring to avert starvation and severe bodily discomfort: and the brief leisure that remains to them, after supplying the bodily needs of food, sleep, etc., is spent in ways determined rather by impulse, routine, and habit, than by a deliberate estimate of probable pleasure. It would seem, then, that the common sense to which we have here to refer can only be that of a minority of comparatively rich and leisured persons. (152) Sidgwick’s Methods, page 6 Common sense morality provides the subject matter for the moral philosopher, who examines it much as a scientist examines data. Sidgwick makes this comparison explicitly in his brief and justly famous history of ethics: Ethical truth, in [Aristotle’s] view, is to be obtained by a careful comparison of particular moral opinions, as physical truth is to be obtained by induction from particular physical observations.8 Methods is Sidgwick’s attempt to do for his time what Aristotle had done for his, as he tells us in the account of the development of his thought given in the preface to the sixth edition: What [Aristotle] gave us … was the Common Sense Morality of Greece, reduced to consistency by careful comparison: given not as something external to him but as what “we”—he and others—think, ascertained by reflection. And was not this really the Socratic induction, elicited by interrogation? Might I not imitate this: do the same for our morality here and now, in the same manner of impartial reflection on current opinion? (xxii) The task of Methods is to examine the multifaceted bulk of common sense morality to see if it is justified—that is, to see if its imprecise rules can be made over into precise ones or if there is some valid moral theory underlying it. The moral philosopher seeks “to throw the Morality of Common Sense into a scientific form” (338). Sidgwick’s goal is similar to that of the common sense philosopher Thomas Reid, whom Sidgwick criticizes not for having failed to reach his goal, but for having failed to realize that he did not 8 Outlines of the History of Ethics, (London: Macmillan and Co., 1902; reprint, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1988), 58. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 7 reach it.9 As we shall see, Sidgwick thought that no one could reach it—at least not the common sense morality of his time. Common sense morality is not itself a moral theory since it fails the test of scientific precision; the demands of scientific precision leap out on almost every page of Methods. We turn now to what Sidgwick means by a moral theory. III The goal of the moral philosopher is to examine the rightness of moral rules in terms of the good that following such rules brings about: “… [W]ithout being disposed to deny that conduct commonly judged to be right is so, we may yet require some deeper explanation why it is so” (102). A moral theory supplies this deeper explanation. Here is a first approximation of what Sidgwick has in mind. A method is a procedure for the generation of rules of right conduct, a principle is a statement of the good that is actually achieved by agents’ following those rules, and a moral theory is the explanation of the relationship of the two. Readers of Methods have failed to notice or failed to give sufficient weight to the fact that moral theories are complex combinations of methods and principles. For the most part they have not noticed that in a single, coherent, and justified moral theory, a method of one sort might be matched to a principle of another, or that in the same theory more than one method might be attached to a single principle. So the end the agent thinks she is achieving by following the rules she has set for herself might not 9 See “The Philosophy of Common Sense,” in Lectures on the Philosophy of Kant and Other Philosophical Lectures and Essays, (London: Macmillan, 1905; Kraus reprint, 1968), 428–429. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 8 be the same as the end ultimately achieved, or might not be the only or most important end actually achieved. Now we can take a closer look at Sidgwick’s account of moral theories in terms of methods and principles, to see why their distinctiveness and relationship is so important. Sidgwick defines a method of ethics in the first sentence of Methods:10 The boundaries of the study called Ethics are variously and often vaguely conceived: but they will perhaps be sufficiently defined at the outset, for the purposes of the present treatise, if a method of Ethics is explained to mean any rational procedure by which we determine what individual human beings ‘ought’—or what it is ‘right’ for them—to do, or to seek to realise by voluntary action. (1) The method or “rational procedure” is the system of moral rule generation; as such, a method involves an intention, aim, or motive of a certain sort, though not necessarily the one the agent has at the time of acting.11 Note that by following a method agents bring about some end; although “we” might realize they are bringing about some end and what that end is, they might not. According to one variety of intuitionism, agents might 10 Virtually the same definition is given in the sixth chapter of Book I (p. 78), in the context of the difference between a method and an ultimate reason. 11 On a matter also touching on the relationship between aims and ends (the possibility of altruism), Neven Sesardic noted in a recent issue of Ethics that although the jury is still out with respect to the extent to which human goals tend to be realized as intended, surely intentions are not “wholly impotent and disconnected from reality” (“Recent Work on Human Altruism and Evolution,” Ethics 106 [October 1995], 135). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 9 (indeed, must) have no “end” at all, unless the rightness of the action itself can be called an end (4). Although an agent might not have an end in mind, Sidgwick does not allow a non-end-referenced criterion of rightness to be a moral theory. By following the rules generated by the method, the agent may or may not reach the goal she aimed at; she may reach another goal. If she reaches the goal she aimed at, it may not be the only one or the ultimate one. Such is the case for a single agent, a group or agents, or even all agents. For example: Some rule about keeping promises may have been formulated from the agent’s intention to do what is right; but in acting according to this aim, she contributes to her own moral perfection, and several agents’ following this rule contributes to universal happiness. What agents aim at when acting is one thing; what end they ultimate achieve is (or could be) another. Although Sidgwick explicitly gives a definition of a method, it is regrettable, as Schneewind notes, that Sidgwick “nowhere gives a … general account of what a principle is.” But Schneewind is not correct when he says that “it is not hard to see what he had in mind.”12 Sidgwick is unclear about what he means by a principle, and Schneewind himself fails to see what he has in mind. But the unity of Methods requires that a principle be defined as above, as the statement of the ultimate end actually achieved in a world in which agents have whatever conscious aims and moral rules they have. The part of a moral theory that Sidgwick calls the principle is that part which names the actually-achieved and ultimate goal. The best moral theory correctly names the ultimate good. Even in an ideal society, it may be that only some agents are conscious of 12 Schneewind, Sidgwick’s Ethics, 194. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 10 the ultimate good actually achieved; that is, perhaps only some agents are using a method of a certain sort that is matched to a principle of the same sort. A moral theory is complicated, then, in these two ways: the agent might not have the aim or end of the method in mind at the time of acting, and even if she has it in mind, that end might not be the one ultimately achieved.13 Now one task of the moral philosopher is to study common sense morality for what moral rules people are following (or, more realistically, to which they are giving lip service), to find out what agents seek to realize in so acting. Another task is to uncover what goal is actually achieved if agents so act—keeping in mind that different agents might have different sets of rules. If and only if all these parts fit into a coherent, single moral theory can common sense morality be said to be justified. In a successful moral theory the combination works: agents acting from rules generated by a certain aim do achieve the goal named in the principle. The best moral theory is the one with the best or most precise rules and the best or correctly-named ultimate end. A moral theory fails if the rules are so vague that they fail to give sufficient guidance, or if the goal the agent thinks she is achieving is not achievable by acting as she does, or if the goal achieved is not the one right ultimate goal, or if—in case there is more than one right ultimate goal— the several goals cannot be achieved, either concurrently or successively. Whether or not 13 For example: “It is obvious that such an exposition [of egoist reasons given to the irreformable egoist for why he should follow utilitarian-end-generated rules] has no tendency to make [the egoist] accept the greatest happiness of the greatest number as his ultimate end; but only as a means to the end of his own happiness” (420). In this case, following the rules generated by the utilitarian method is a means to the egoist end. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 11 the end aimed at is the same as the end ultimately achieved, in a satisfactory moral theory the connection between the aim and the end is, as Sidgwick says, “logical” or “plausible” (78, 83). A moral theory is “valid” (84) just in case the connection it asserts between method and principle—between the rules and the end—in fact obtains. Although the agent’s goal might be the end achieved, it need not be. And if it is, it need not be the only or ultimate end. It is crucial to understanding Sidgwick’s notion of a moral theory to see (to put the point in terms of methods and principles) that a method of one sort can be paired with a principle of another: Not all the different views that are taken of the ultimate reason for doing what is concluded to be right lead to practically different methods of arriving at this conclusion. Indeed we find that almost any method may be connected with almost any ultimate reason by means of some—often plausible—assumption. (83) Sidgwick himself finds, as he hopes others do, that almost any method may be matched to almost any principle. Sidgwick makes this point again—that aims and ends may differ—in his first discussion of egoism: It must, however, be pointed out that the adoption of the fundamental principle of Egoism, as just explained, by no means necessarily implies the ordinary empirical method of seeking one’s own pleasure or happiness. A man may aim at the greatest happiness within his reach, and yet not attempt to ascertain empirically what amount of pleasure and pain is likely to attend any given course of action: believing that he has some surer, deductive method for determining the conduct which will make him most happy in the long-run. (121, second emphasis added) Sidgwick’s Methods, page 12 Here Sidgwick clearly claims that what is aimed at need not be what is achieved—that a method of some sort can be matched with a principle of another sort. Toward the end of Methods, Sidgwick makes this same point more strongly, claiming that it is a philosophical mistake to suppose that the egoist method and the egoist principle must be connected: But lastly, from the universal point of view no less than from the individual, it seems true that Happiness is likely to be better attained if the extent to which we set ourselves consciously to aim at it be carefully restricted. (405) Not only is it possible for there to be a difference between an aim and an end, egoism and utilitarianism (theories of individual and universal happiness, respectively) demand that there be a difference. And what is true of these ends might be true of others. In the following passage, Sidgwick clearly detaches an aim, which might be simply conformity to a rule, from an end: Such a belief [in moral rules’ having been planted by Nature or revealed by God, but leading to happiness] implies that, though I am bound to take, as my ultimate standard for acting, conformity to a rule which is for me absolute, still the natural or Divine reason for the rule laid down is Utilitarian. On this view, the method of Utilitarianism is certainly rejected: the connection between right action and happiness is not ascertained by a process of reasoning. But we can hardly say that the Utilitarian principle is altogether rejected: rather the limitations of the human reason are supposed to prevent it from apprehending adequately the real connexion between the true principle and the right rules of conduct. The Sidgwick’s Methods, page 13 connexion, however, has always been to a large extent recognised by all reflective persons.” (85; second emphasis added) Another complication, besides the one whereby a method can be matched with a different principle, is that a method might have more than one form, depending on what it is at which the agent aims.14 In the direct form of the egoist method, for instance, agents achieve happiness by aiming at happiness; Sidgwick calls this “empirical hedonism” (Book I, Chapters 2 and 3). There are also indirect forms of the methods. One of the other forms of egoism, “objective hedonism” (Book II, Chapter 4), is indirect, because according to it the trick to achieving happiness for oneself is to “seek and consciously estimate the objective conditions and sources of happiness, rather than happiness itself” (151). To sum up: Sidgwick’s theory of a moral theory countenances the following three complications: the end of the method might be indirectly aimed at; the agent might be unconscious of the end at the time of acting; and whatever her aim is, the ultimate end the agent is helping to bring about by following the rules generated by the method might not be the end she has in mind, either at the time or acting or at some other time. IV 14 Sidgwick called these variations “forms” in the first edition (xiv). The egoist method, for instance, has, in addition to empirical and objective forms, deontic and deductive forms. Unfortunately for clarity, Sidgwick drops the designation “forms” in later editions, though the variations of the method remain. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 14 In a simple direct theory of egoism, the agent’s acting on rules generated from having the conscious aim of individual happiness leads to the individual’s happiness. In a simple direct theory of utilitarianism, agents’ acting on rules generated from having universal happiness as a conscious aim leads to universal happiness. With respect to either egoism or utilitarianism, if the end achieved is other than the one aimed at, the resulting indirect moral theory might be called “paradoxical,” following Sidgwick, who spoke of the paradox of (egoistic) Hedonism, wherein “the impulse towards pleasure, if too predominant, defeats its own aim” (48); the agent’s acting on those rules still leads to the ultimate end of individual happiness. In another kind of egoist theory, a complex one (such a theory may be plausible but we don’t know yet whether it is valid), rules are generated from individual happiness as a conscious or unconscious aim, and agents’ acting on those rules contributes to a different kind of ultimate end, universal happiness.15 15 The only kind of egoism or universalism (utilitarianism) Sidgwick considers is the hedonistic kind. In the explanation he gives for making pleasure wholly coincidental with the ultimate good in Methods (see esp. Book I, Chapter 9, and Book II, Chapter 2) and elsewhere (see especially “Hedonism and Ultimate Good,” Mind 2 [1877], 27–38), he makes the simple mistake, Darwall has noted, of assuming that if the good must be experienced, then (some aspect of) experience must be the good. See Stephen L. Darwall, “Pleasure as Ultimate Good in Sidgwick’s Ethics,” Monist 58 (July 1974), 475–489. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 15 It is not just hedonism that has this paradoxical nature. In another context Jorge L. A. Garcia gives an example which is helpful here.16 Imagine, he says, a school that admits only students who seek knowledge only for its own sake, a school whose graduates are well-rewarded with prestige, high-paying jobs, etc. We might further imagine that these graduates and no others are essential to a thriving community. It would happen then that the ultimate end or state of affairs brought into being by students whose conscious aim was knowledge for its own sake was desirable on (non-hedonistic) egoistic as well as utilitarian grounds.17 This resulting state of affairs would not be able to be brought about unless students had a goal other than the one(s) achieved.18 16 Jorge L. A. Garcia, “On ‘Justifying’ Morality,” Metaphilosophy 17 (October 1986), 218. 17 If such an arrangement is possible, then, mutatis mutandis, consequentialists can be friends. See Peter Railton, “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (Spring 1984), 134–171. 18 The question of ends is more complex than I indicate here. Students who go to a school because and only because they seek knowledge for its own sake are of course in some some sense also choosing to go to that school. That kind of end, the end or aim of going to that school, is a constitutive end. Going to the school is not a mere means to the end of knowledge for its own sake; rather going to the school constitutes getting knowledge for its own sake. For a discussion of constitutive ends, see J. L. Ackrill, “Aristotle on Eudaimonia,” in Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 16 Although the task of examining moral theories would be too extensive if all putative ultimate ends were examined, Sidgwick confines himself to those ultimate ends of common sense morality that are rational: If we confine ourselves to such ends as the common sense of mankind appears to accept as rational ultimate ends, the task is reduced, I think, within manageable limits; since this criterion will exclude at least many of the objects which men practically seem to regard as paramount. (9) In short, Sidgwick’s study is limited by common sense morality and by rationality.19 In the end, he thinks only one of the rational ultimate ends of common sense morality is the right one, namely, universal happiness (398, 406). To further complicate the picture, the ultimate end might be best served when different agents have different aims. Universal happiness is brought about (or best brought about, or maximally achieved) by having only some—rather than all—agents be There may be another kind of end: David Schmidtz thinks that there are four kinds of ends: final, instrumental, constitutive, and what he calls “maieutic”; see “Choosing Ends,” Ethics 104 (January 1994), 226–251. 19 There are some who think that whereas Sidgwick thinks of egoism as a rational theory, he thinks of utilitarianism as a moral one. See David Phillips, “Sidgwick, Dualism, and Indeterminacy in Practical Reasoning,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 15 (January 1998), and David Brink, “Sidgwick’s Dualism of Practical Reason,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy (1988). But it is clear that Sidgwick considers both egoism and utilitarianism to be both rational and moral. I do not have space to defend this claim here. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 17 do-gooders, that is, agents whose aim is the utilitarian one. Marcus Singer points out that Sidgwick is the first moral philosopher to consider the desirability, on utilitarian grounds, of a society not made up of utilitarians—that is, not made up only of agents whose conscious aim is maximizing the good.20 The best ultimate end might not be and perhaps should not be motivating to ordinary citizens. It may even become necessary to deceive the public about the ultimate end in order to bring it about.21 20 A society desirable on utilitarian grounds but not made up entirely of utilitarians would be one in which the ultimate end of universal happiness was achieved by having agents act on rules generated by one or more different conscious aims. Singer writes, “Sidgwick raises questions about the differences that obtain in applying the utilitarian method in a society of utilitarians and in a society not made up of utilitarians, a distinction not heretofore thought of” (“Henry Sidgwick,” in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, [New York: Garland, 1992]). Derek Parfit thinks that a consequentialist theory with a conscious aim different from its ultimate end is indirectly self-defeating; see Reasons and Persons (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), 27. 21 “Thus, on Utilitarian principles, it may be right to … teach openly to one set of persons what it would be wrong to teach to others; it may be conceivably right to do, if it can be done with comparative secrecy, what it would be wrong to do in the face of the world.… These conclusions are all of a paradoxical character: there is no doubt that the moral consciousness of a plain man broadly repudiates the general notion of an esoteric morality, differing from that popularly taught …” (489–490). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 18 By a moral theory, then, Sidgwick means the connection of a certain aim or of certain aims—consciously held or not at the time of acting, resulting in a set or sets of rules for right conduct—with the good ultimately achieved by agents acting on those rules. It is central to his notion of a moral theory that an aim or method may be paired with a different end or principle. V What is the moral theory implicit in common sense morality? At first that morality seems to imply several methods and several ultimate ends. But Sidgwick argues that, upon examination, the methods that generate the rules of common sense morality “in the main” (xxv) reduce to three: egoism, utilitarianism, and intuitionism. The egoist method assesses rules of action as to whether they conduce to the agent’s happiness. The utilitarian method assesses rules of action as to whether they conduce to the general happiness. Intuitionism is complicated by the fact that it passes through “phases” or “stages” (102). Sidgwick gives short shrift to the first stage, perceptional or ultra-intuitionism; it can hardly be called a method.22 In the second stage, jural intuitionism, there is no mention of an ultimate end; there are, in short, just the rules. As such jural intuitionism is not adequate as a theory: Having no principle, it has no ultimate end according to which, 22 “… [I]t recognises simple immediate intuitions alone and discards as superfluous all modes of reasoning to moral conclusions: and we may find in it one phase or variety of the Intuitional method,—if we may extend the term ‘method’ to include a procedure that is completed in a single judgment” (100). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 19 in union with a method, rules of conduct can be judged for rightness; an end-less system of rules is nor precise enough.23 But in its mature phase the intuitionist method is linked to a principle, according to which excellence is the ultimate end. The discovery of three methods in common sense morality means that the moral theory implicit in common sense morality is indirect and complex. If the three methods of egoism, intuitionism and utilitarianism are successfully joined to just one principle, whatever that principle is, then common sense morality is justified: It would presuppose a complex moral theory. As for the ends implied in common sense morality, these, too, seem at first to be many: Ordinary people give lip service to so many different goods, without obvious consistency. In the course of his examination Sidgwick finds that the the number of putative rational ends reduces to two; the two finalists for ultimate end are happiness and excellence (or perfection—virtue, in other words).24 23 The precision requirement runs throughout Methods. On this point of an end-less method and scientific precision, see especially the third and fourth conditions for selfevident proposition in the book on Intuitionism, Book III: 341–345. 24 “I use the terms ‘Excellence’ and ‘Perfection’ to denote the same ultimate end regarded in somewhat different aspects: meaning by either an ideal complex of mental qualities, of which we admire and approve the manifestation in human life: but using ‘Perfection’ to denote the idea as such, while ‘Excellence’ denotes such partial realisation of or approximation to the ideal as we actually find in human experience” (10n). “It is more convenient, for the purpose of expounding the morality of common sense, to understand by Virtue a quality exhibited in right conduct; for then we can use Sidgwick’s Methods, page 20 The provisional moral theory implicit in common sense morality —and therefore the single moral theory of Methods—is this complex moral theory, linking the three methods of egoism, intuitionism, and utilitarianism to some end. If it can be shown that there is just one ultimate end and if it can be shown that this one ultimate end is the one achieved by agents acting on rules generated by all three methods, then the theory stands and common sense morality is justified. Sidgwick cannot justify common sense morality. He suggests no other way for justifying common sense morality. Given the great emphasis he puts on systematization and precision, it is safe to conclude that he thought that the common sense morality of his own day, and any other version that includes the egoist end, could not be justified.25 VI There are only two finalists for ultimate end: excellence and happiness; but eventually even excellence reduces to some aspect of universal happiness, because the latter is ultimate: As regards the general conception of the duty [of Benevolence], there is, I think, no divergence that we need consider between the Intuitional and Utilitarian systems. … [And] as the chief element in the common notion of the good (besides the common notions of the particular virtues as heads for the classification of the most important kinds or aspects of right conduct as generally recognised” (219n). 25 I am grateful to Sean McKeever for a good discussion as to whether Sidgwick leaves open the possibility that common sense moralities of other times and places might be rendered into coherent moral theories. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 21 happiness) is moral good or Virtue, if we can show that the other virtues are— broadly speaking—all qualities conducive to the happiness of the agent himself and of others, it is evident that Benevolence, whether it prompts us to promote the virtue of others or their happiness, will aim directly or indirectly at the Utilitarian end. (430–431) In the last analysis, therefore, universal happiness, the end named in the utilitarian principle, is the ultimate end, and therefore the utilitarian is the right principle, the principle to which the three methods of common sense morality must be linked if that morality is to be justified: While yet if we ask for a final criterion of the comparative value of the different objects of men’s enthusiastic pursuit, and of the limits within which each may legitimately engross the attention of mankind, we shall … conceive it to depend upon the degree in which they respectively conduce to Happiness (406). If the three methods of common sense morality are to be systematized at all, it is according to this principle.26 If systematization succeeds, the moral theory implicit in common sense morality links three methods with their various aims to just one principle, the utilitarian one. If common sense morality is justified, that moral theory is valid: By aiming at individual happiness or at excellence or at universal happiness—or by simply following the rules of rightness (jural intuitionism), without having an aim, conscious or unconscious—agents achieve the ultimate end of universal happiness. So is common sense morality justified? 26 See also pages 391–407. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 22 VII The systematization of the three methods implicit in common sense morality begins with intuitionism—the form of it which prescribes rules without adverting to an end.27 Upon examination Sidgwick finds that the link between the method of intuitionism and the utilitarian principle is successful. What follows is how. Reliance on rules is just what distinguishes ordinary agents from moral philosophers; ordinary people do not rely on moral theories—adequate or not—in order to act rightly. Ordinary people are justified if they act according to certain rules of rightness which are really right, and with the accompanying belief that these rules are right (207). Jural intuitionism accurately describes the mental state of the justified moral agent; intuitionism gets credit from Sidgwick for this insight about agents.28 Sidgwick himself is, as he says, a utilitarian on an intuitional basis (xxii). But for philosophers rules are not enough. Jural intuitionism is not a complete moral theory, but philosophical intuitionism is. Philosophical intuitionism is a moral theory linking a method which gives agents the conscious aim of rightness with the intuitionist principle, giving excellence as an end. Although the addition of the principle makes intuitionism a complete moral theory, Sidgwick is not satisfied with philosophical 27 Sidgwick wrote Book III first; it is the longest, and it is the book with the greatest number of direct references to common sense morality. 28 For these reasons I suggest that Sidgwick be called an internalist about justification. He may also be an internalist about motivation, a claim I do not consider here. For a discussion of motive internalism and externalism in Sidgwick, see the contributions of David O. Brink and John Deigh in Schultz, ed., Essays, 199–258. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 23 intuitionism, either. Whereas jural intuitionism is unsatisfactory as a moral theory because it lacks a principle, philosophical intuitionism is unsatisfactory because it misidentifies the ultimate good (391–394). Excellence is really good but it is not really ultimate: It can still be asked of individual excellence what purpose or end it serves. In Sidgwick’s view, the true ultimate end that individual excellence serves is the utilitarian one, universal happiness. If we are not to systematise human activities by taking Universal Happiness as their common end, on what other principles are we to systematise them?… I have failed to find—and am unable to construct—any systematic answer to this question that appears to me worthy of serious consideration: and hence I am finally led to the conclusion that … the Intuitional method rigorously applied yields as its final result the doctrine of pure Universalistic Hedonism,—which it is convenient to denote by the single word, Utilitarianism. (406–407) The principle of utilitarianism thus receives pride of place in Sidgwick’s moral theory because it correctly identifies the right state of affairs brought about by agents who follow rules generated by both the method of intuitionism and the method of utilitarianism. “Utilitarianism appears in friendly alliance with Intuitionism” (86).29 29 Given the nature of virtue, the method of philosophical intuitionism works adequately well (Methods, 424–425). In a general way, but a way apparently specific enough to satisfy Sidgwick’s requirement for scientific precision, a set of rules generated by this method of intuitionism whose end is individual perfection does bring about a state of affairs satisfactory on utilitarian grounds. The fit between the method and principle of utilitarianism is not perfect, either. “But, that our practical Utilitarian reasonings must Sidgwick’s Methods, page 24 Thus far there is a valid moral theory underlying common sense morality. Sidgwick says that he has successfully represented “the intuitions of Common Sense” as “inchoately and imperfectly Utilitarian” (427). Indeed, “the moral codes of different ages and countries are for the most part strikingly correlated to differences in the effects of actions on happiness” (426). But common sense morality clearly implies more than the two methods of intuitionism and utilitarianism; it also implies egoism. Unfortunately for the project of systematizing common sense morality, what has been said of the rules generated by the methods of intuitionism and utilitarianism cannot be said of the set of rules generated by the method of egoism.30 A set of rules generated by the egoistic method, whose end is individual happiness, cannot be harmoniously allied with the principle of utilitarianism. Some of egoism’s rules pass the test (502), but a number do not (503)—a number sufficient to make the connection between the egoist method and the utilitarian principle fall short of Sidgwick’s requirement of precision and scientific exactness in a moral theory.31 The conjunction of the undeniable fact of common sense morality’s reliance on necessarily be rough, is no reason for not making them as accurate as the case admits …” (416). 30 Without egoism, common sense morality avoids a “dualism of practical reason” (Methods, 404n). The real enemy of ordinary morality is “the new doctrine” of egoism, “endorsed by the dreaded name of Hume” (104n). 31 The precision requirement runs throughout Methods. On this point of an end-less method and scientific precision, see especially the third and fourth conditions for selfevident proposition in the book on Intuitionism, Book III, 341–345. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 25 the egoist method and (to Sidgwick’s mind) the undeniable rationality and morality of the egoist end dashes hopes for a valid moral theory for common sense morality. Its presence and irresolvable conflict with the utilitarian end is responsible for the so-called (by Sidgwick) Dualism of Practical Reason.32 The sad conclusion: We are stuck with the egoist method, which cannot be logically or plausibly connected to the utilitarian principle in the complex moral theory of common sense morality. And we are stuck with the egoist end, because its rationality as an end cannot be dismissed. Because the egoist end is both really rational and really ultimate, and because many rules generated by the egoist method are not “in friendly alliance” with the utilitarian end, common sense morality cannot be saved. Since the controversy over egoism’s claims and those of the two other methods (intuitionism and utilitarianism) cannot be similarly “harmoniously settled,” the honest and thorough philosopher must reach the same pessimistic conclusion Sidgwick did:33 Not only is common sense morality left unjustified, the institution of morality itself lacks rationality: 32 On page 404, Sidgwick says that the Dualism of Practical Reason is the subject of the concluding chapter of Methods. In the context of the interpretation of Methods presented here, the Dualism of Practical Reason results from Sidgwick’s failure to do for egoism what he had done for intuitionism: to reduce the egoist end to the utilitarian one. The Dualism of Practical Reason is mentioned by name only on pp. xxi and 404; but see p. 503. 33 Sidgwick’s pessimism is deftly analyzed by J. L. Mackie, in “Sidgwick’s Pessimism,” in Philosophical Quarterly 26 (October 1976), 317 -327; reprinted in Schultz, ed. Essays, 163–174. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 26 The Cosmos of Duty is thus really reduced to a Chaos; and the prolonged effort of the human intellect to frame a perfect ideal of rational conduct is seen to have been foredoomed to failure. (first edition, 473) Note the depth of Sidgwick’s commitment to common sense morality: When he found an end—the egoist end—hostile to systematization but undeniably part of common sense morality, he did not simply eliminate this end: A scientist does not consider some data and ignore others in order to arrive at a valid theory. Nor did Sidgwick form a moral theory from a blank slate, which would have been easier and which other moral philosophers have chosen to do; he took his role as moral philosopher to be to see whether common sense morality is justified—that is, founded on a valid moral theory. These remarks should suffice to illustrate the difficulty of reading Methods as a unified argument, but they should also offer assurance that the unity is there. VIII Some philosophers fail to recognize that Sidgwick’s utilitarianism is indirect, but others do: Marcus Singer, Robert Adams, and Derek Parfit.34 Some philosophers use Sidgwick to lend authority to their own moral theories: Dean Cocking and Justin Oakley 34 For Marcus Singer, see “Sidgwick and Nineteenth-Century Ethical Thought,” in Schultz, ed., Essays, esp. 76–86. For Robert Adams, “Motive Utilitarianism,” Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976), 467. For Derek Parfit, see Reasons and Persons, especially Chapter 7 (Oxford: Clarendon, 1984). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 27 do, for their version of indirect consequentialism.35 Overall, however, the importance of this complex and indirect type of moral theory has not been appreciated as the key to the unity of Methods. Philosophers tend to footnote Sidgwick, or use some sentence from his work as a starting point for their own. This temptation is understandable, given the many ways Sidgwick anticipated contemporary moral philosophy.36 Misreadings of Methods derive either from a failure to see that Sidgwick esteems common sense morality, or from a failure to see that Methods is his attempt to uncover in common sense morality one unified moral theory, joining three methods to one principle. C. D. Broad, perhaps the earliest important commentator on Methods, failed to see that Sidgwick matched a method to a differently-named principle. Consequently, he mistakenly assumed that Sidgwick was presenting three direct and distinct moral theories. The direct theory of egoism identifies the ultimate good as one’s own happiness, and the direct theory of utilitarianism identifies the ultimate good as the general happiness; at least these two have in common the same content as ultimate end (happiness), if not the same allocation of it (self and all). So, Broad thinks, it makes sense to treat the two hedonisms in the same place—rather than, as Sidgwick did, to separate their treatment by the long book on intuitionism. Broad says this: 35 Dean Cocking and Justin Oakley, “Indirect Consequentialism, Friendship, and the Problem of Alienation.” Ethics 106 (October 1995), 87n. 36 An interesting pursuit for another paper, for example, would be a comparison of Sidgwick’s utilitarianism in Methods and R. M. Hare’s two levels of moral thinking. See R. M. Hare, Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point (Oxford: Clarendon, 1981). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 28 The order which Sidgwick takes is Egoism, Intuitionism, and Utilitarianism. This does not seem to me to be the best order, since a great deal of the argument that is used in connexion with Egoistic Hedonism has to be assumed in dealing with Universalistic Hedonism, and the reader is rather liable to forget what has been established in connexion with the former when he emerges into the latter after the very long and complicated discussion on Intuitionism which is sandwiched between the two.37 But Sidgwick realizes that he could have made this choice and his decision not to treat them together is deliberate. He takes up the intuitionist method directly before the utilitarian method because he thinks that both methods are linked to the one utilitarian principle. Indeed, Sidgwick thinks that philosophers who overlook the antagonisms between the two hedonisms are importantly mistaken (103). It is true, of course, that Sidgwick thinks that egoists and utilitarians correctly identify the good, but this fact alone does not warrant their simultaneous treatment: I am aware that these two latter methods [Egoistic Hedonism and Universalistic Hedonism] are commonly treated as closely connected.… Nevertheless it seems to me undeniable that the practical affinity between Utilitarianism and Intuitionism is really much greater than that between the two forms of Hedonism. (84, 85) The “practical affinity” in question is the common connection of their distinct methods to the utilitarian principle, an affinity lacking in the method of egoism to that same 37 Broad, Five Types, 150. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 29 principle. The method of intuitionism generates rules generally consistent with or even identical to those generated by the method of utilitarianism. It is in order to emphasize this affinity between the intuitionist and utilitarian methods that Sidgwick deliberately treats them together. It is necessary to his strategy that the exposition of the two hedonist methods be separated by “the very long and complicated discussion on Intuitionism.” He would not have heeded Broad’s suggestion that he treat the two hedonist methods together, even if (anachronistically) he had known of it. As he writes: … I have made as marked a separation as possible between Epicureanism or Egoistic Hedonism, and the Universalistic or Benthamite Hedonism to which I propose to restrict the term Utilitarianism. (84) A more recent misreading of Methods appears in Schneewind’s volume on the work. Here is Schneewind’s view of what Sidgwick means by a principle and a method: Roughly speaking, a principle asserts that some property which acts may or may not possess is an ultimate reason for the rightness of acts. A method is a regular practice of using some property of acts as the property from whose presence or absence one infers that specific acts are or are not right.38 Schneewind thinks that this property has to be the same property in the method and principle. I have argued that central to Sidgwick’s conception of a moral theory is that a method may be matched with a differently-named principle. As we have seen, this is the aspect of Sidgwick’s notion of a moral theory that Broad simply ignores. Schneewind does see this aspect but fails to understand its significance: 38 Schneewind, Sidgwick’s Ethics, 194–195. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 30 Some of the remarks in I, vi, where principles and methods are discussed are misleading. After comment on a variety of principles and methods apparently used by the plain man, Sidgwick says, ‘we find that almost any method may be connected with almost any ultimate reason by means of some—often plausible— assumption.’ (ME 7, p. 83). In the first edition this was preceded by the comment that ‘we seem to find … that there is no necessary connexion between the Method and the Ultimate Reason in any ethical system’ (ME 1, p. 64). But here, as so often in Sidgwick’s writings, what we ‘seem to find’ does not give the substance of his own view.39 Thus Schneewind cannot make sense of the assertion he quotes, and is reduced to claiming that Sidgwick does not mean what he said. But his reason for thinking this—the hedge “we seem to find” in the first edition of Methods—seems odd. After all, Sidgwick in fact withdrew the cautious phrase in subsequent editions, he did not add it. It seems obvious, then, that the unqualified statement does “give the substance of his own view.” Others fail to see that Sidgwick’s task in Methods is to uncover the one moral theory implicit in common sense morality. They have mistakenly thought that Sidgwick considered common sense morality to be another method or another moral theory, perhaps identical with intuitionism. Marcus Singer, for instance, writes: 39 Ibid. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 31 Another point of interest in Sidgwick’s account … is his identification of common sense morality with Intuitive Morality, that is, with the philosophic theory of Intuitionism.40 But common sense morality is not a moral theory of any sort. As we have seen, the correct way of describing the relationship between common sense morality and intuitionism is to say that intuitionism, along with egoism and utilitarianism, is implicit in common sense morality. (It is true, however, that because one form of intuitionism consists only of following rules for their rightness, intuitionism is closer to common sense morality than either egoism or utilitarianism.) Another misreading of Methods resulting from a failure to distinguish methods and principles from the moral theories of which they are components is that it is a defense of just one moral theory, utilitarianism. So, for example, Peter Singer, drawing from an early article by Schneewind, sees Methods “as an elaborate attempt to ‘prove,’ in a special sense, the truth of utilitarianism.”41 In a more recent article on Sidgwick’s methodology, Steven Sverdlik summarizes the standard view of Methods. 40 Marcus G. Singer, “Ethics and Common Sense,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie (1986), 238. 41 Peter Singer, “Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium,” Monist 58 (July 1974), 490– 517. The Schneewind article Singer refers to is “First Principles and Common Sense Morality in Sidgwick’s Ethics,” (Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 45 (1963), 137– 156. Sidgwick’s Methods, page 32 The first question to ask is, what did Sidgwick say in The Methods of Ethics about his methodology? Now it is true that he disclaims on occasion the purpose of arguing for any moral conclusions, seeking instead to expound and criticize the major “methods of ethics” “from a neutral position, as impartially as possible.” But readers have always taken this contention with a grain of salt and have seen Sidgwick’s book as an extended defense of utilitarianism. This is not to say that he is partial or unfair in his treatment of other positions. Sidgwick rightly enjoys a reputation as one of the most fair-minded and judicious philosophers in the tradition. Still, his own views are not completely hidden from view. And he does make some remarks that suggest what sorts of arguments exist that support his illconcealed utilitarianism.42 Passing over this cavalier dismissal of the clearly-expressed intention of an author—a bad policy, no matter who is being criticized, but especially someone as “judicious” as Sidgwick—note that the author does not say whether Sidgwick is defending the principle or the method of utilitarianism. And anyway it is not accurate to describe Methods as a defense of utilitarianism or anything else; it is an analysis of common sense morality. 43 42 Steven Sverdlik, “Sidgwick’s Methodology,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 23 (October 4, 1985), 538–539, emphasis added. 43 Sidgwick certainly resists the characterization of Methods as a defense of utilitarianism. In the preface to the second edition he has this to say: I find that more than one critic has overlooked or disregarded the account of the plan of my treatise, given in the original preface and in §5 of the introductory chapter: and has consequently supposed me to be writing as an Sidgwick’s Methods, page 33 Of course one might say that Sidgwick was mistaken in thinking that the moral theory behind common sense morality was such as he described; if Sidgwick is to be criticized, the criticism must be in those terms. Bernard Williams is another who fails to notice the differences between methods, principles, and theories in Methods. Because of this oversight, he gives a criticism of Methods that does not apply to it: One difficulty of the book is that it is formed by a distinction between the intuitionist method and the Utilitarian method, which at an ultimate level Sidgwick eventually rejects. I think that it is this structural feature of the book, the fact that its design is not actually very well adjusted to its conclusions, that helps to make some of it so boring ….44 But Sidgwick does not reject the distinction between the intuitionist method and the utilitarian method; he is quite adamant about the importance of the distinction, even “at an ultimate level.” Sidgwick thinks that moral philosophers must prefer the utilitarian method to the intuitionist one, even if they give rise to the same actions. His preference for the utilitarian method over the intuitionist one is sufficient indication that the distinction between them is maintained, not rejected: assailant of two of the methods which I chiefly examine, and a defender of the third. (xii) 44 Bernard Williams, “The Point of View of the Universe: Sidgwick and the Ambitions of Ethics,” Cambridge Review (May 7, 1982), 186. The article is reprinted in Making Sense of Humanity And Other Philosophical Papers 1982–1993 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995). Sidgwick’s Methods, page 34 … [I]t may still be objected that this coincidence [of the intuitionist and utilitarian methods] is merely general and qualitative, and that it breaks down when we attempt to draw it out in detail, with the quantitative precision which Bentham introduced into the discussion…. But it must be borne in mind that Utilitarianism is not concerned to prove the absolute coincidence in results of the Intuitional and Utilitarian methods. (424–425) Both methods are connected to the utilitarian principle in the moral theory of Methods, and it is to this fact about the structure of the moral theory to which Williams may be referring. But of course this structural feature is not at all the same as rejecting a distinction between the two methods. Indeed, given his commitment to common sense morality, Sidgwick cannot reject any feature of the moral theory implicit in common sense morality, including the intuitionist method. IX At the beginning of this essay I noted that reading Methods only as “isolated insights,” as Schneewind puts it, is common. The practice continues; perhaps it could be called “pericopism,” the tendency to read a work as individual, loosely related essays. In her book on Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature, Annette Baier urges consideration of that work as a whole, in order to counteract this tendency: Philosophical reading habits still seem to be resistant to Hume’s attempt to link the theses of Book One with those of Books Two and Three, indeed resistant to Sidgwick’s Methods, page 35 treating the Treatise as a treatise, as distinct from a series of self-contained section-long philosophical essays.45 It is a tribute to the richness and complexity of Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics that it runs the same risk. I hope that in the present work I have gone some way in showing how to read Methods as a unified argument, and in so doing have helped to move Sidgwick scholarship to the full maturity it deserves.46 Janice Daurio Moorpark College 45 Annette C. Baier, A Progress of Sentiments (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), 158. 46 This essay is a revision of part of my doctoral dissertation, presented at Claremont Graduate University in 1994. Charles Young, chair of the dissertation committee, saved me from less clear earlier versions. I have learned from him both respect for the integrity of a text and how to extract arguments from it. For these reasons, I owe him a debt of gratitude. Similar debts are owed to the other members of my committee: Paul Hurley, Linda Zagzebski, and earlier, A. R. Louch. Encouragement is perhaps the greatest gift; from Marcus Singer I received initial and continuing encouragement; from me he can expect continuing thanks.