Baxter’s Prefatory Remarks on Berkeley’s Philosophy 1. “… it seems impossible that a man should be seriously persuaded that he has neither country nor parents, nor any material body, nor eats, or drinks, nor lies in a house, but that all these things are mere illusions, and have no existence but in fancy.” 2. Baxter’s own arguments for the existence of God are based on premises concerning the inertia, motion & cohesion of matter. “… if the conclusions [of those arguments] be solid, this itself will be a weighty argument against [Berkeley’s] scheme.” Problems with Baxter’s First Remark Berkeley did not deny the existence of any of the things Baxter listed — he just considered them to be either spirits or collections of ideas rather than material things. Berkeley did not consider any of the things Baxter listed to be mere illusions or to exist only in his imagination — he just considered them to either be spirits or to exist only “in” the mind of some spirit, i.e., only insofar as they are perceived Problems with Baxter’s Second Remark Baxter commits the fallacy of affirming the consequent. If we grant the conclusions of his arguments, it does not follow that we have to accept their premises. Berkeley was able to provide for the truth of claims concerning the inertia, motion, and cohesion of matter by reducing those claims to claims about laws governing the manner in which ideas follow one another over time. Nothing in Berkeley’s philosophy is inconsistent with any of the principles of physics. Baxter’s Parity Argument The same considerations that Berkeley invoked to deny the existence of matter can be invoked to deny the existence of spirit. Berkeley’s Argument: We perceive only our own ideas. None of these ideas is a material substance. No property of a material substance could be like any of our ideas. Any talk of material substances must be either contradictory or meaningless. Baxter’s Paired Argument: We perceive only our own ideas. None of these ideas is a spiritual substance. No property of a spiritual substance could be like any of our ideas. Any talk of spiritual substances must be either contradictory or meaningless. Problems with Baxter’s Parity Argument Baxter allowed for an exception: intuitive self-consciousness Baxter considered this exception to drive Berkeley into solipsism. He didn’t appreciate that once you grant that we can have a direct or immediate consciousness of the existence of our own minds, you have given Berkeley all he needed to claim that we can form some extra-ideational concept of minds and spiritual causes, and so infer the existence of other minds as causes of our ideas of sense. Baxter’s Attempt to Deepen the Problem Berkeley not only denied that we can have any ideas of spirits, but also that we can have any ideas of the active properties of spirits (perceiving or willing). So nothing having to do with spirit should ever have come into our minds. (The same neglect of Berkeley’s appeal to intuitive self-consciousness occurs here.) A further attempt to deepen the problem Berkeley’s claim that we have no ideas of perceiving or willing is based on the assumption that we can only have ideas of things that can be pictured or imaged (“painted in the imagination”) But then it should follow (wrongly) that we can have no ideas of virtue, justice, or truth, as well as no idea of spirits or activities. Baxter’s Principal Objection A review of the argument of Principles 1-4: Principles 1: The objects of human knowledge are ideas. [Principles 2: In addition to ideas, we recognize the existence of spirits.] Principles 3: An idea cannot exist apart from being perceived by some spirit. So, all the objects of human knowledge are things that cannot exist apart from being perceived. Principles 4: Three rhetorical questions asked in response to those who would hold the strangely prevalent opinion that things continue to exist unperceived. Baxter took the rhetorical questions of Principles 4, rather than the argument of Principles 1-3, to be Berkeley’s initial “two line demonstration” of his thesis. This allowed Baxter to charge Berkeley with “sleight-of-hand reasoning” (because Principles 4 insinuates, rather than proves, that we only perceive our own sensations) The sleight of hand is not present in Principles 1-3 (Principles 1 is explicit in asserting all we perceive are our own sensations.) Nonetheless, Baxter’s criticism is forceful: It is question-begging to simply assert that we perceive nothing but our own sensations. Baxter’s Alternative Account Sensations are effects brought about in us by objects acting on our sense organs. We do not automatically perceive these effects (though we can bring ourselves to do so through a subsequent “reflex act” of self-consciousness) Instead we perceive objects through our sensations. e.g., perceiving a wall in the dark by means of the interrupted motion of a stick In this case, I do not perceive the motion of the stick; I perceive the wall. In any act of perception there are two objects the sensation, which passes unnoticed and can only be recalled by a reflex act the proper object, which causes the sensation and is perceived by means of the sensation So the assertion of Principles 1 is false. The objects of human knowledge are not just ideas impressed on the senses, ideas formed by reflection on the operations of the mind, and ideas formed by memory and imagination. They are also external objects. A Berkeleyan Reply All that we immediately perceive is our sensations. Objects are at best inferred as external causes of our sensations. But there is no way of conceiving these supposed causes that is not either contradictory or empty. (Proving this requires appeal to arguments Baxter neglects, esp. the likeness principle.) Baxter’s Argument against Berkeley’s Minima theory According to Berkeley, nothing smaller than the minimum visibile can exist. So a million-millionth part of a minimum visibile cannot exist (it must be 0) But 1012 x 0 = 0. So a minimum visible cannot exist. Baxter’s error A minimum visible is a smallest possible part. You cannot assume it is composed of yet smaller parts without begging the question by presuming infinite divisibility. [A variation on Baxter’s Argument] Suppose a minimum visible is a smallest possible part. Then either it has unit magnitude or it has no magnitude. If it has unit magnitude, then it is divisible (because any positive quantity of magnitude, e.g., the unit, 1, is divisible into ½’s) If it has no magnitude, then it does not exist. [An answer] Minima do not compose an extension through addition of their magnitudes (they have none), but through being disposed at immediately adjacent locations. Though a minimum visible has no magnitude, it is not nothing because it has colour (or tangible quality) and location. A Further Argument Where do solidity and figure exist? There seem to be only three answers: in themselves (not “in” anything else) in material substances (as their properties) in ideas (as their properties) The first answer turns solidity & figure into matter, the second into properties of matter. The latter answer entails that there are solid, figured ideas. But this is “monstrous.” (Baxter does not say why.) An Objection to Baxter’s Position God could have given us the same ideas we are having now without having created a material world. So we can have no assurance that he actually did so. Baxter’s Reply The laws of nature are laws concerning the behaviour of matter, not laws concerning the behaviour of ideas in God’s mind. (Baxter again shows his ignorance of Berkeley’s philosophy of science, according to which laws of nature describe regularities in the succession of ideas.) But it is inconsistent with the “reason and truth” of God that he should … … make us concerned to discover laws concerning the behaviour of something that does not exist … … by giving us ideas in such a way as to trick us into believing it does exist, … and so perpetrate a massive hoax. Further Replies If God can deceive us in this way about the existence of material things, he can similarly deceive us about the existence of other minds. In that case: When we are tempted by others to do wrong, it is God alone who tempts us. (and why shouldn’t he if he deceives us in other things?) We have less reason to refrain from wrongdoing, because we have no assurance that there is anyone else who actually suffers from our deeds. The fact that an all-good being would not tempt us to evil is the best argument for the existence of other minds. It is, moreover, an argument that is not available to us to prove the existence of unthinking stuff. We have less reason to accept the design argument for the existence of God if the world around us is just a collection of ideas.