Lecture 32: Utilitarian Theory, Pt. III Lecture objectives: To develop greater familiarity with utilitarian analysis by assessing a case To identify the strengths and weaknesses of the utilitarian approach to morality To explore Singer’s weak utilitarian response to Rachels’ challenge re. a duty of famine relief To distinguish between duty and charity Strengths of the utilitarian approach: 1. It captures our common sense intuition that consequences matter. 2. It identifies improving the human condition as a worthy moral goal. 3. It offers a rational basis for evaluating what is morally right. 3. It has a broad scope. 4. It is impartial and egalitarian 5. It gives an account of our obligations to others. Weaknesses of the utilitarian approach: 1. It makes illegitimate interpersonal comparisons: a) the relative importance of needs of different people and b) the magnitude of each individual’s satisfaction cannot be reliably measured. But is this a fair critique of utilitarianism? “We have a well-founded belief that starvation hurts most people more than a shortage of grape-fruit, and no knowledge how much more it will hurt even ourselves tomorrow; and it is on such beliefs that we have to act; we can never know either our objective duty or our objective long-run interest” (Carritt) 2. It does not seem to allow any room for justice. 3. It is not impartial about the value of particular pleasures and pains. 4. It cannot accommodate promise-keeping. 5. It is too simplistic. 6. It conceives of moral agents in a distorted way. 7. It conflates obligation and inclination. (Kant) Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality” Recall where we left off with Rachels: the ethical egoist position fails: there is no basis upon which my needs are any more relevant to me than those of any other person are to him or her “We should care about the interests of other people for the very same reason we care about our own interests; for their needs and desires are comparable to our own.” Singer’s argument: 1. Suffering and death from lack of food, shelter and medical care are bad. 2. If it is within our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought morally to do it. 3. Therefore, we should contribute to famine relief as a matter of duty. Duty vs. Charity Common ‘Yes, but’ replies to the argument: 1. proximity or distance makes a moral difference 2. number of relevantly situated moral agents makes a moral difference If these are morally relevant, then either: a) there is an even weaker duty to give for famine relief than Singer supposes, or b) to give for famine relief is an act of charity. But Singer argues: if the primary moral fact is the fact of suffering, it should make little difference how many people are in a position to contribute or how far away the sufferers are. an evaluation of “comparable moral importance” must be done with reference to this primary moral fact. Would we be sacrificing anything of comparable moral value (relative to the suffering of the starving) if we gave up on our luxuries for famine relief? Singer argues: we should give at levels of our own marginal utility our resistance to this duty reflects a distortion of our moral conceptual scheme How we tend to see famine relief: Charity = doing what is good or beneficent From carus (L.), dear “generosity”, mercy, kindness, compassion remedying misfortune not required admirable but not morally praise/blameworthy motivated by emotional or psychological identification with the other How we should see famine relief: Duty = doing what is right From debere (L.), to owe (as in a debt), e.g., Fr. DÛ “morality”, the moral point of view, justice remedying unfairness, maintaining fairness required morally praise/blameworthy justified in relation to morally relevant criteria it’s not just unfortunate that these people are suffering, it’s unfair given that we have resources available to alleviate their suffering and to not jeopardize our own well-being.