The unconscious hedonism of the many in the Protagoras May 19, 2008 draft Tobita Chow A section towards the end of Plato’s Protagoras features the idea of a sort of hedonism: the thesis that ‘good’ and ‘pleasure’ are just two names for the same thing (and similarly for ‘bad’ and ‘pain’). This idea is brought up and articulated by Socrates, who manages to bring his various interlocutors to assent to this hedonist thesis (first the many, in an imagined conversation; then Protagoras and the other sophists present). But the text does not make it immediately obvious whether Socrates himself is to be interpreted as a hedonist (call this a “prohedonist” interpretation), or whether we should rather interpret him as judging his interlocutors to be hedonists and using the hedonist thesis as a premise against them, in ad hominem fashion, without ever committing himself to the thesis (call this an “antihedonist” interpretation).1 .The debate surrounding this question is pretty old. Mill in 1834 is sensitive to the question, although his answer to it is ambiguous.2 Grote in 1888 is a convinced prohedonist, and criticizes a number of other writers for thinking otherwise; most are his contemporaries, but one of his targets hails from the 15th century.3 In this paper, I aim to make what I hope to be a decisive contribution to the antihedonist side of the debate. Based on my interpretation of this section of the text, I will then go on to point towards some further consequences, concerning Socrates’ moral psychology and the nature of the Socratic method. The “prohedonist” / “antihedonist” terminology is from Zeyl, “Socrates and hedonism”. “The Protagoras”, in Collected Works XI, pp.39-61. Mill claims that hedonism “is as emphatically maintained against Protagoras by Socrates, in the dialogue, as it ever was by Epicurus or Bentham” (p. 61), but also that “Socrates merely plays with opinions throughout” (p. 45). 3 Plato and the Other Companions of Sokrates, pp. 314-316; the 15th century writer is Marsilio Ficino, mentioned at p. 314n1. 1 2 1 I. Overview of the dialogue The question lurking in the background of most of the dialogue is: can virtue be taught? Socrates thinks that it can’t be taught (319a-320b). Protagoras responds with a combination of muthos and logos to the effect that virtue can be taught, and that indeed he is a particularly good teacher of virtue (320c-328b). Socrates then raises the question of the unity of virtue: are the different virtues, or different parts of virtue (knowledge,4 courage, piety, temperance, and justice), separable from one another, or unlike one another (329c-330b)? Protagoras initially maintains that the different parts of virtue are distinct, such that a person might have any one of the virtues independently of the others. Socrates argues against this thesis in a series of arguments (330b-334c), which give way to a breakdown in the discussion, and an eight-way discussion about how the discussion should proceed (334c-338e). Protagoras gets a chance to question Socrates, which leads to a competitive bout of poetry interpretation (338e-347a). Shortly thereafter Socrates returns to the question of the unity of virtue, and then we see that Protagoras has been led to grant that knowledge, temperance, justice, and piety “resemble one another fairly closely, but courage is altogether different from all the rest” (349d). Socrates mounts an attack on the claim that courage is distinct from knowledge (349e-350c), which is then rebutted by Protagoras (350c-351a). Socrates, apparently changing topic fairly drastically, then Protagoras asks whether “some men live well, and others badly” (351b). This brings us to the part of the dialogue which is my focus here. Socrates asks a couple of apparently leading questions, first securing Protagoras’ agreement that a person does not live well “if he lives distressed and in pain”, and then that one who has lived his 4 In the Protagoras, as elsewhere, no distinction is made between epistêmê, sophia, and phronêsis. 2 whole life pleasantly to the end has lived well (351b). This leads to the following exchange: So, then, to live pleasantly is good, and unpleasantly, bad? Yes, so long as he lived having taken pleasure in honourable things. What, Protagoras? Surely you don’t, like most people, call some pleasant things bad and some painful things good? I mean, isn’t a pleasant thing good just insofar as it is pleasant, that is, if it results in nothing other than pleasure; and, on the other hand, aren’t painful things bad in the same way, just insofar as they are painful? And to this Protagoras cautiously gives his considered opinion that, “on the one hand, there are pleasurable things which are not good, and on the other hand, there are painful things which are not bad but some which are, and a third class which is neutral—neither bad nor good” (351d). Socrates repeats nearly the very same question, “I am asking whether pleasure itself is not a good”, and this time Protagoras responds by inviting Socrates to lead an investigation into the matter. Without much of a segue, Socrates then asks Protagoras whether he agrees with the many in their opinion that knowledge can be dragged around like a slave by anger, pleasure, pain, love, fear, and so on (352b-c). Protagoras agrees that this is the opinion of the many, and voices his disagreement with that opinion (352c-d). Socrates compliments Protagoras on his response, and goes on to elaborate: [The many] maintain that most people are unwilling to do what is best, even thought they know what it is and are able to do it. And when I have asked them the reason for this, they say that those who act that way do so because they are overcome by pleasure or pain or are being ruled by one of the things I referred to just now. (352d-e) Socrates then invites Protagoras to join with him in a mock discussion with an imagined audience of the many, in order to convince them that they are wrong about this experience they call “being overcome”. At first Protagoras protests that the exercise is 3 pointless, but Socrates promises that it will shed light on the question of the unity of virtue, and Protagoras acquiesces. (352e-353b) Socrates opens the mock discussion by imagining that the many ask him what he thinks this experience of “being overcome” is. Socrates does not doubt that the majority are characterizing a genuine phenomenon with that phrase; rather, he doubts that they are characterizing that phenomenon in the right way. And before he provides what he takes to be the correct characterization of the phenomenon, he first argues that the many are hedonists (with Protagoras in agreement throughout). Socrates arrives at the claim that the many are hedonists by examining the experience of “being overcome”. He proposes that this experience occurs when the many are “overcome by pleasant things like food or drink or sex” which they (claim to) know to be “ruinous” (353c). That is, “being overcome” involves things which are pleasant, but bad. The many consider these pleasures to be bad because of what happens later, after the immediate pleasures have been enjoyed: “disease and things like that”, “diseases and poverty” (353d, e). And the many find these consequences to be bad “on account of nothing other than the fact that they result in pain and derive us of other pleasures” (353e-354a). Socrates then moves on to consider those things which the many call good, but painful. The many consider good painful things to include: “athletics and military training and treatments by doctors such as cautery, surgery, medicines and starvation diet” (354a), and these things are good because “they ultimately bring about health and good condition of bodies and preservation of cities and power over others and wealth” (354b). And the many consider these consequences to be bad “because they result in pleasure and in the relief and avoidance of pain”. 4 Socrates goes on to propose to the many the conclusion that: “you pursue pleasure as being good and avoid pain as bad”, and “it’s pain that you regard as bad, and pleasure you regard as good” (354c); indeed they use “pleasant” and “good” as two names for the same thing, and similarly for “painful” and “bad” (355b-c). So the many are hedonists in this way. And the key assumption is that, for the many, all evaluations of good and bad bottom out in considerations of pleasure and pain—pleasure and pain the only teloi they use to call things good or bad (354b, 354d, 354e). Socrates repeatedly notes that this conclusion would be lost upon the specification of some other telos, but he imagines (and Protagoras agrees) that the many will be unable to provide anything of the sort. This happens three times in short succession (354d, 354e, 355a). Socrates then tells the many that their original characterization of the experience of “being overcome” is “ridiculous”: it is ridiculous to speak of someone who has knowledge of the good which is overcome by immediate pleasure. Now, it is generally thought that Socrates tries to provide an argument against the possibility of akrasia somewhere around this point of the dialogue; I find this to be a fairly difficult interpretive issue, and it’s tangential to the point of this paper, so I’m going to set it aside here.5 Instead I’d like to focus on what Socrates takes to be the correct way to describe the 5 In brief, here are the difficulties I see here. The issue of akrasia concerns psychological necessity. So if akrasia is under discussion here, then the question at issue here must be: is it psychologically necessary that knowledge cannot be overcome by pleasure or pain? But it seems to me that Socrates slips between language which could plausibly be read as indicating psychological necessity, and language which is more plausibly read as more protreptic (expressing prudential or otherwise normative necessity), or something in between. At various points I am unclear whether Socrates is saying that it is a matter of psychological necessity that one acts as one knows to be best, or making recommendations without saying anything about psychological necessity, or running the two sorts of moves together (with or without knowing it). Considerations along these lines have led Weiss (“Hedonism in the Protagoras”, XXX) to claim that the issue of psychological necessity, and hence the issue of akrasia, is never at issue at any point in the imagined debate with the many. According to her, Socrates’ discussion of knowledge with the many is thoroughly and solely protreptic. This position seems too strong to me, but I am happy to take it as an indication of the difficulty of figuring out what role the issue of akrasia is playing in this part of the dialogue. 5 experience of “being overcome”. He claims that the many, who pursue/avoid pleasure/pain as good/bad, are dragged this way and that by the “power of appearance” (that is, the power of appearances of pleasure and pain), which “often makes us wander all over the place in confusion, often changing our minds about he same thing and regretting our actions and choices” (356d). When they experience what they call “being overcome”, they are confronting conflicting appearances of the relevant object or act as (say) a source of immediate pleasure, but also as a source of greater pain further in the future; and they call the object ‘bad’ on account of that latter appearance. As the solution to the difficulties of confusion and regret which are the effects of the power of appearance, Socrates offers a kind of knowledge, the art of measuring pleasures and pains, which (he promises) “would make the appearances lose their power by showing us the truth” (356d-e). Naturally the many lack any such form of knowledge. So what they are really suffering from is ignorance, and Socrates suggests that they give their money to sophists like Protagoras, in order that they might be cured of their ignorance in return (357c-e). At this point Protagoras and the other sophists present all happily agree to the hedonist thesis, and the rest of Socrates’ analysis (358a-b). This soon turns out to be an unfortunate move for Protagoras. Socrates goes on to identify what is good with what is honourable and what is bad with what is dishonourable (358b), and (following an unexplained transition from the claim that no one goes for what one knows to be worse, to the claim that no one goes for what one believes to be worse (358b-d)) then defines the fear as the expectation of something bad. From this, he argues that, cowardly people avoid honourable and good things (like war) because of ignorance; so cowardice is 6 ignorance, and courage is knowledge. With this, courage is identified with knowledge, and so also with the rest of virtue, and Protagoras’ attempt to maintain real distinctions between the different parts of virtue suffers complete collapse. Socrates then gleefully notes that a stunning reversal has occurred: having successfully argued that all of virtue is knowledge, he has undermined his original assertion that virtue can’t be taught. He encourages Protagoras to continue their discussion, so that they might together clean up this mess, but Protagoras wants nothing more to do with Socrates (indeed, he’d already wanted out of the conversation back at 333e), and the dialogue ends. II. Two standard anti-hedonist moves The debate over what to make of Socrates’ relationship to the thesis of hedonism has gotten fairly convoluted over the years, and I won’t be able to do justice to the full depth of easy side of the dialectic here. But here are two main points made by those urging an antihedonist interpretation. First, as we’ve seen, in 354d-355a Socrates repeatedly emphasizes that the many can back out by specifying some way of making value judgments which is not based on pleasure and pain. He seems to be going to great lengths to call attention to the fact that he’s talking about their beliefs, not his own. And, so the claim goes, his statements of the hedonist thesis throughout are can similarly be understood as attributions of hedonism to others, rather than expressions of his own hedonism.6 In response to the first antihedonist point, it has been noted that focusing on 6 Two phrases in the text threaten to make trouble for this claim. The first is the egô gar legô which Socrates attaches to the statement of hedonism at 351c. According to Zeyl, though, this would necessitate reading the statement as expressing Socrates’ own view only if it were followed by an indirect statement, and what follows is a direct question (“Socrates and hedonism”, p. 266n16). The second phrase (noted by the prohedonist Hackforth in “Hedonism in Plato’s Protagoras”, p.41n4) is at 353e-354a, where Socrates presents a hedonist statement prefaced by: “Does it not seem to you, gentleman, as Protagoras and I are saying…”. But Taylor (Plato: Protagoras, p.176) notes that this phrase is ambiguous: one could read it as 7 the beliefs of his interlocutors is just Socratic business as usual. This is what Socrates does all the time. Furthermore, when he argues his interlocutor into agreeing with a conclusion, it’s generally because he has what he thinks to be an argument for the conclusion which he himself finds to be compelling and is himself inclined to believe that the conclusion is true.7 Second, antihedonists claim that Socratic hedonism doesn’t fit in with the rest of the Platonic corpus. 8 For many antihedonists, this seems the key consideration which tips the debate in favour of antihedonism.9 There are two standard prohedonist responses to this sort of move. One is to just to say that this point is quite indecisive, since there is no reason to suppose that the Protagoras must be consistent with other dialogues on this particular point; after all, in general, the corpus as a whole yields a good mix of continuities and discontinuities from dialogue to dialogue, and it seems possible to understand this as an example of such a discontinuity.10 The other response is to call into question the claim that hedonism in the Protagoras really conflicts with the positions espoused by Socrates in other dialogues.11 Socrates attributing hedonism to himself and to Protagoras, or as Socrates saying (on behalf of himself and of Protagoras) that the hedonist statement seems to be true to the many. Zeyl picks up on the ambiguity and goes further, arguing that, given the context, the latter reading makes more sense (ibid., p.255). At the moment my Greek isn’t good enough to come to my own decision on whether Zeyl is right on these issues, so at the moment I’m going to accept his claims on authority. 7 Irwin, Plato’s Ethics, §60. 8 Two obviously notable passages are Gorgias 492d-500d and Phaedo 69a-b, where Socrates directly repudiates the pleasure-oriented life. 9 E.g., Zeyl, pp. 262-4. As Zeyl notes (p.261), this is also the diagnosis of the antihedonist position given, in a critical spirit, by prohedonists like Grote (p.314); Crombie (An Examination of Plato’s Dialogues, I, p.240); and Dodds (Plato: Gorgias, p. 21 n.3). 10 Grote, p.316; Hackforth, p.42. 11 For example, Taylor (p. 170) suggests that the hedonist thesis stated by Socrates in the Protagoras can be distinguished from the thesis attacked by Socrates in the Gorgias. Nussbaum (The Fragility of Goodness, XXX) claims that the hedonism of the Protagoras, considered in conjunction with the notion of the hedonistic calculus provided by Socrates, can be understood as largely continuous with concerns found elsewhere in the Platonic corpus. Irwin claims that Socratic hedonism is not only consistent with other “early” dialogues, but supported by them—more on which later. 8 I’m pretty convinced by the prohedonist response to the first argument, but I think that there is a version of this second antihedonist strategy strong enough to settle the debate. But I think the argument needs to be made in a version which clearly defeats both prohedonist responses, and that this is still left wanting.12 That is, what we need is to identify some feature of the character[s] of Socrates in the other dialogues such that (a) it clearly conflicts with the hedonism attributed to the many and (b) we have compelling reason to read it into the Protagoras. And I think I have just the thing: what I will call ‘the Socratic ethical orientation’. III. The Socratic ethical orientation vs. the hedonism of the many In the Apology, addressing the suggestion that he might be acquitted of the charges against him, and avoid execution, on the condition that he cease practicing philosophy, Socrates responds: ...if, as I say, you were to acquit me on those terms, I would say to you: “…I shall not cease to practice philosophy, to exhort you and in my usual way to point out to any one of you whom I happen to meet: …are you not ashamed of your eagerness to possess as much wealth, reputation and honours as possible, while you do not care for nor give thought to wisdom or truth or the best possible state of your soul?” Then, if one of you disputes this and says he does care, I shall not let him go at once or leave him, but I shall question him, examine him and test him, and if I do not think he has attained the virtue that he says he has, I shall reproach him because he attaches little importance to the most important things and greater importance to inferior things. […] For I go around doing nothing but persuading both young and old among you not to care for your body or your wealth in preference to or as strongly as for the best possible state of your soul, as I say to you: “Wealth does not bring about 12 Zeyl tries to do this, but ultimately I find his efforts unconvincing—although he does make some of the points I will make below. 9 virtue, but virtue makes wealth and everything else good for men, both individually and collectively.” (29d-30b) Here Socrates claims that wisdom, truth, and virtue are crucial to the state of one’s soul, and are the most important things, worthy of our greatest care. There is perhaps some suggestion here that these all amount to the same thing, 13 but this is not worked out explicitly in the Apology. For convenience, I’ll lump all of these together under the heading of ‘the care of the soul’. Socrates contrasts the care of the soul with the concerns of health, wealth, and social status. Socrates’ core commitment here, which he claims to guide all of his philosophical activity (he does “nothing but” attempt to win others to this position) is that one ought to pursue the care of the soul in preference to those other inferior concerns of health, wealth, and social status. This is the Socratic ethical orientation. Now, this is not just any old relative ranking of goods. In the last sentence of the above quote, Socrates suggests that this ethical orientation is a necessary condition of attaining anything of value. 14 No amount of health, wealth, or social status is valuable without the care of the soul; one who cares for his soul should rather suffer any loss of health, wealth, or social status than give up the care of the soul. And, indeed, Socrates is demonstrably willing to suffer poverty (loss of wealth), exile (loss of social status), and the death penalty at the hands of his fellow citizens (total loss of health and of social status), all in the name of what he takes to be the proper care of his soul. The care of the soul is, for Socrates, unconditionally valuable; all other putative goods are, at best, only conditionally valuable. 13 Other specifications include the avoidance of doing anything unjust or impious (e.g., 32c-d), and the sort of philosophical discussion we observe in the ‘Socratic’ dialogues (38a). 14 See Vlastos, Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher, pp.200-232. 10 The Socratic ethical orientation is also found in the Republic. In the final moments of Book IX, Socrates describes the “person of understanding” (i.e., the philosopher, i.e., Socrates) as one who will “direct all his efforts to attaining [the best] state of his soul” (591bc). In contrast, he will not pursue health except insofar as doing so fosters “consonance of the soul” (591cd). And he will “keep order and consonance in his acquisition of money, with that same end in view” (591d). Likewise, with respect to honours, he will “willingly share in and taste those that he believes will make him better, but he’ll avoid any public or private honour that might overthrow the established condition of his soul” (591e-592a). That is, he pursues the best state of his soul in preference to the rival goods of health, wealth, and social status, and pursues those inferior things only insofar as they are useful for, and do not conflict with, his care for his soul. His care for his soul is unconditional, and conditions all other potential values. In these respects, the person of understanding of the Republic shares the ethical orientation which Socrates professes in the Apology. And we can find similar moments elsewhere: in the Crito (47e-48d), the Gorgias (XXX), the Phaedo (68b-c, 82b-d), etc.15 To be sure, there are significant differences between the conception of the care of the soul found in these various dialogues. Some of these differences can perhaps be understood as differences in detail or degree of elaboration; still others as substantive conflicts. 16 I think there is at least a family resemblance to be had between the various accounts (the avoidance of committing injustice, ethical dialectic, the purification of the soul, etc.). In any case, what remains 15 This is an incomplete list. The Socratic ethical orientation is presumably at least implicit in any dialogue which features the distinction between the world of becoming and the true realm of the forms. 16 An example of that latter category might be the contrast between the Phaedo’s apparent recommendation that one avoid all pleasures and pains (83d), and other dialogues where it seems that some pleasures are perfectly acceptable under the right circumstances. 11 constant is the Socratic ethical orientation: towards the care of the soul, in unconditional preference to the pursuit of health, wealth, and social status. Now, it is generally accepted that the dialogues mentioned above can be placed on a thematic continuum. Towards one end, we have the Apology, and the Crito. Further towards the middle, we have the Gorgias and the Protagoras. These are generally classed together in the category of ‘early’ or ‘Socratic’ dialogues. Meanwhile, the Phaedo, and Republic fall further towards the other end of the continuum, outside of the category of the ‘early’ or ‘Socratic’. This continuum is usually thought to be reflective of how far these dialogues should be seen as reflecting Plato’s image of the historical Socrates. And of course the continuum is often, but not so universally, thought to be roughly chronological as well as thematic.17 On any version of this continuum picture, though, the absence of the Socratic ethical orientation from the Protagoras would constitute a rather odd thematic hiatus. But, it’s not just that the Socratic ethical orientation appears in these various dialogues—say, as a claim which Socrates espouses, or a belief which he holds to be true. It is rather his very way of life. It is key to Socrates’ identity, and constitutive of what it is to be a philosopher. As Plato shows us, it is what led Socrates to be condemned to death, and then led Socrates to accept his death. If there is any feature that could be understood as essential to the character of Socrates, as he appears across the Platonic corpus, it is this one. Now, to recall, the argument that the Socrates of the Protagoras uses in attributing hedonism to the many is, briefly: sometimes the many call something both A strong position incorporating all of these claims is Vlastos’ (p. XXX). For a more cautious view, see Cooper (“Introduction” to Plato: Complete Works, pp. xii-xvii). 17 12 pleasant and bad, but when they do so they are calling the thing “bad” just because it will later cause disease or poverty, which they also evaluate in terms of pleasure and pain; when they call something both painful and good, they call the thing “good” just because it will later cause health, political safety, social-political power, or wealth, which they also evaluation in terms of pleasure and pain. However, this case for attributing hedonism to the many presupposes that their values are limited to the sorts of things mentioned above. This is an implicit assumption. If the many valued something qualitatively different from the goods countenanced in Socrates’ analysis of them, then that might count as something valued on the basis of criteria apart from pleasure and pain, and the case for the attribution of hedonism would be undermined thereby. Now, we can probably take this as unproblematic in the case of the many. But suppose we try to apply the above to Socrates. In using the argument for the hedonism of the many as an argument for Socratic hedonism, we must assume that Socrates himself does not value anything qualitatively different from those things which the many call good. In other words, we must assume that the Socrates of the Protagoras values only those things which the Socratic ethical orientation dismisses as unimportant; we must assume that the Socrates of the Protagoras rejects the philosophical care of the soul which is espoused and/or demonstrated by the Socrates of the Apology, the Republic, etc. So: we have compelling reason to think that the Socrates of the Protagoras shares the Socratic ethical orientation we see elsewhere; and, if this is so, then the case for the hedonism of the many cannot serve as a case for Socratic hedonism. IV. Answering prohedonist objections and arguments 13 [[Socrates does end up recommending knowledge to the hedonist. So the hedonist does end up valuing knowledge. But this is not knowledge valued in preference to the pursuit of unimportant things; rather it is knowledge in the service of that pursuit. It is knowledge enslaved, just as the oligarch’s reason is enslaved (R, 553cd).]] Some prohedonists argue that, far from being discontinuous with other dialogues, hedonism actually helps us to make sense of various standard pieces of (what is taken to be) Socratic doctrine—not only ones found in this dialogue (the denial of akrasia, the identification of courage and knowledge), but theses found elsewhere as well. 18 So Socratic hedonism is not only consistent with what we know of Socrates, but actually rationalizes and explains Socratic positions which are otherwise mysterious; in other words, there is a good abductive argument for attributing hedonism to Socrates. [[Response. Weiss.19]] A second major prohedonist argument is that Socrates really does appear to push hedonism upon the many (and perhaps indirectly upon Protagoras as well). As we saw above, when Socrates introduces the hedonist thesis, he notes that the many would voice disagreement with it; and Protagoras, for his part, is quite resistant; thereafter we see that Socrates works quite hard to win acceptance of the idea. 20 And this makes it difficult to 18 For example, Irwin argues that the hedonistic definition of happiness, and the analysis of virtue as a hedonistic craft, gives us a way of making sense of the Socratic claim that virtue is sufficient for happiness—nowhere else does Socrates give us anything that will do the job as well (§62). 19 Weiss has a straightforward way of dealing with the connection between hedonism and the conclusions which are inferred from it within the Protagoras: she flatly denies that those conclusions are in fact Socratic theses. According to her, Socrates does not really believe that akrasia is impossible, or that courage and the rest of virtue is identical to knowledge; rather, this is all just an imaginative construction of how things would have to stand if Protagoras and other sophists were to be capable of providing the benefits they claim to provide. She claims that Socrates is no more committed to that construction than he is to his recommendation that the many save their lives by becoming clients of the sophists. (XXX) 20 “Throughout all the Platonic compositions, there is nowhere to be found any train of argument more direct, more serious, and more elaborate, than that by which Sokrates here proves the identity of good with pleasure, of pain with evil” (Grote, p.314). Similar sentiments are found in Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p.111; Hackforth, p. 41. 14 see how hedonism could be playing a merely ad hominem role in the dialogue. The standard antihedonist response to that last point is that the many and Protagoras are hedonists, and do in fact identify the good and the pleasant, no matter what they say about the matter. Their initial denials of hedonism, and Socrates’ subsequent argument that they are hedonists, is just a case of Socrates’ interlocutor saying something false, and then being corrected by Socrates through argument.21 Now, I think some form of this response is right, but I also think there is something peculiar about this case of error— there is something peculiar about my being wrong about whether or not I identify good and pleasure. V. Socrates’ error theory and the unconscious hedonism of the many There is also a peculiarity in the structure of the imagined discussion of the many which stands need of explanation: why does the question of hedonism lead into the discussion of whether or not knowledge can be overcome? As in the Phaedo (XXX) and the Republic (XXX), Socrates has worked out that the many are hedonists, identifying the good with pleasure. But if this is true, then what are we to make of the fact that they sure seem to make distinctions between what is good and what is pleasant? There seems to be call for an error theory here. And in the Protagoras Socrates has just such an error theory: the experience of conflict between the power of the appearance of X as immediately pleasant, and the power of the appearance of X as ultimately painful, is the experience which teaches the many to distinguish between what is pleasant and what is good. (Why is it the long-term appearance which receives the name of “good” or “bad”? This appearance is mediated by intervening 21 Zeyl, p. 261; Weiss, p. XXX 15 consequences of disease, etc., which are then cashed out in terms of pleasure and pain. This requires a greater degree of learning and reason, and so receives the label appropriate to rational evaluation—even though in this case reason is deformed.) What are we to make of these distinctions made by the many? It is suggestive that Socrates consistently speaks of the many “calling” or “saying” that this or that pleasure is bad, or this or that pain is good. But it would be misleading to suppose that the distinction is merely verbal, insofar as that suggests that these statements are made insincerely. The many are genuinely unaware of their hedonism. They are mistaken about how they live. This seems different from the sort of error typically targeted by the Socratic elenchus: this is not just a failure of ethical knowledge, but a failure of selfknowledge. The many are unconscious hedonists. In invoking the term ‘unconscious’, I don’t meant to import anything peculiarly Freudian into this psychological account.22 But there are two consequences which apply here which can also be found in Freud. First: when confronting someone who is unconsciously X, one does not find that out by asking that person directly. They don’t know that they are X, so they can’t tell you that they are X. Second: when you want someone who is unconsciously X to stop being X, it will not do to tell them directly to stop being X, or to argue that they should stop being X. VI. Unconscious hedonism vs. a standard account of the Socratic method [[The picture of Vlastos’ “The Socratic Elenchus” and the “say what you believe” requirement; why the notion of unconscious hedonism would imply that that picture must 22 Freud does not have propriety rights to the notion of unconscious mental activity. As David Finkelstein notes (Expression and the Inner, p.114n.5) the notion was alive and well in the 19th century before Freud. (Of course, a different story would have to be told about how it could be alive and well in ancient Athens.) 16 be wrong; Beversluis’ critique of “say what you believe” in Cross-Examining Socrates is a good argument against Vlastos and those like him, but not against Socrates.]] 17