CHAPTER 2: UTILITARIANISM AND EQUALITY CONTENTS [pp 38 B 46] Page 2.1. Introduction 38 2.2. 2.3. Utilitarianism Critique of Utilitarianism 39 40 2.4. 2.5. The Egalitarian Elements in Utilitarianism Conclusion 43 45 2.1. INTRODUCTION Before embarking, in Chapters 3 to 10, on an investigation of equality in modern liberal theories, a brief diversion to utilitarianism, and its egalitarian content, is necessary, because utilitarianism was the dominant political theory for almost 150 years (prior to Rawls) and Rawls explicitly developed his theory of justice as fairness in reaction to the deficiencies he perceived in utilitarian theory (in its main manifestations) as a theory of justice. Rawls in turn, provided the platform for Dworkin, Sen and Walzer to further develop modern liberal theories broadly along the lines first shown by Rawls. Likewise, Nozick=s Anarchy, State and Utopia may be seen as a libertarian response to the challenge posed by Rawls=s A Theory of Justice. The main body of this thesis goes beyond utilitarianism1 and focuses on the work of the previously mentioned modern theorists. Logically one therefore needs to enquire, even if in a cursory fashion, Awhat one wants to go beyond@, before embarking on one=s journey. It is this starting point that is provided in this chapter. The aim of this chapter is not to subject utilitarianism to an in-depth egalitarian analysis, but to point to some of its characteristics [Section 2.2.], the critique these have attracted [Section 2.3.], and the extent to which a tendency towards equality may be found in utilitarianism [Section 2.4.]. The conclusion is reached that, while utilitarianism may provide the normative justification for very strong forms of affirmative measures [even amounting to unfair Areverse discrimination@], utilitarianism is an insufficient theory for the compound equality of opportunity model [the ACEOP model@], for a number of reasons [Section 2.5.]. 1 This phrase is borrowed from the title of a book by Sen A. K. & B. Williams (Eds) (1982): Utilitarianism and Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 38 2.2. UTILITARIANISM Utilitarianism2 is characterized by three features:3 (i) Consequentialism: The rightness of actions must be judged entirely by the goodness of the consequent state of affairs. This means that if two or more actions are compared, that one which yields the most Agoodness@ (however this may be measured) is to be preferred irrespective of the nature or rightness of the action itself. For example, if blatantly unfair Areverse discrimination@ will yield more aggregate utility or Agoodness@ than other less extreme forms of affirmative action, the former should be preferred over the latter. (ii) Welfarism: The goodness of states of affairs must be judged entirely by the goodness of the set of individual utilities in the respective state of affairs. This means that whatever is deemed to constitute Awelfare@ (be it happiness, income or wealth), this is the only measure that is to be used in determining which is the Abest@ state of affairs. (iii) Sum-ranking: The goodness of any set of individual utilities must be judged entirely by their sum total. This implies that if two or more sets of individual utilities are compared, no special weight may be given to any individual=s holding of utilities or disutilities. Each and every person is to be treated as of equal worth and hence the only matter that counts is the individual=s aggregate holding of utilities. The aim of utilitarianism is to maximize the aggregate utility taken over all the members of society, irrespective of the shape of the actual distribution, but this will be attained when the marginal utility of everyone is equal, because the utility that a person derives from his share of a resource increases at a diminishing rate as his share in the resource increases. For this reason one could argue that there is a built-in tendency toward equality of well-being in the utilitarian conception of equality and that the total utility approach collapses into the utilitarian equality approach. Much of the critique directed at utilitarianism is directed at the total utility approach to welfarist equality. For example, Rawls criticizes the violations to our notions of liberty and equality that can be justified in the name of utilitarianism, and Sen, from a different perspective, 2 For the purposes of this brief chapter on utilitarianism (which is of an introductory nature only), I do not distinguish between rule and act utilitarianism. Rule utilitarianism focusses on the likely aggregate consequences if a particular rule were to be applied whereas act utilitarianism has as its object the likely consequences of particular acts. Similarly, the distinction between aggregate and average utility is not given any attention. The main purpose of this chapter is to point to the historical passage from utilitarianism to modern liberal theories, using Rawls as our link between the Apast@ and the Amodern@. 3 Sen A. (1984): Resources, Values and Development, Oxford: Blackwell, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: p 278. 39 criticizes utilitarianism for allowing, because of human diversity, very unequal distributions as long as aggregate utility is maximized. In what follows, this distinction between utilitarian equality and total utility equality is set aside. 2.3. CRITIQUE OF UTILITARIANISM 2.3.1. General The critique of utilitarianism is structured by reference to the three features of utilitarianism listed at the beginning of Section 2.2.. 1. Consequentialism B The rightness of actions must be judged entirely by the goodness of the consequent state of affairs: However, there is nothing self-evidently valuable as a moral goal in the mere increase in aggregate pleasure or happiness abstracted from all concerns with the shape of the distribution of wealth or happiness. Separate individuals are of no intrinsic importance other than as mere receptacles or collection points of what is regarded as important, namely some mental state, such as happiness or need satisfaction.4 This allows for trade-offs between the need satisfactions of individuals as long as the aggregate need satisfaction is increased thereby.5 The major problem with this way of judging the morality of actions is that it ignores the possibility that some actions are intrinsically wrong, irrespective of the utilities these may yield for the doer. I here subscribe to Mill=s Aharm principle@ in holding that the harm done to another cannot be off-set against the good consequences that the perpetrator may derive from his or her harmful act. To steal is wrong, and the fact that the thief may be able to put the stolen object to better use (either for himself or for the greater general good) or derive greater goodness from it, than I can, does not make the theft morally right. 4 5 Hart H.L.A.: ABetween utility and rights@, in Columbia Law Review, Vol. 79, 1979: pp 828-846 Idem: pp 829 B 830. 40 2. Welfarism B The goodness of states of affairs must be judged entirely by the goodness of the set of individual utilities in the respective state of affairs: A welfarist approach has two fundamental shortcomings. Firstly it conceives of human beings as no more than receptacles of certain mental states, such as happiness, but humans are not only experiencers or preference satisfiers, they are also evaluators and doers.6 As such they form and revise conceptions of the good and pursue desire satisfaction associated with these conceptions. Utilitarianism ignores the Kantian aspects of agency and autonomy of human beings. For Sen, agency and well-being are two fundamental but distinct and irreducible dimensions of being human. Secondly, Sen argues that Autility does not adequately represent well-being@.7 While happiness and desire-fulfilment are important aspects of well-being it is not sufficient for well-being and are totally inadequate as measures of well-being. Sen illustrates this point by using the example of the poor person who, although objectively deprived, has accepted his disadvantaged position and has scaled down his aspirations and desires to such an extent that he is happy and his needs are satisfied by the smallest windfall that comes his way despite still being objectively in a state of non-well-being.8 Conversely, rich people may have well-being and yet be unhappy and frustrated. Together these considerations show the moral deficiencies of welfarist and utilitarian methods of moral accounting. What is needed is a theory that is concerned with what people are able to do and be, where being happy or having one=s desires fulfilled is only one valuable capability among others.9 3. Sum-ranking B The goodness of any set of individual utilities must be judged entirely by their sum total: Utilitarianism treats people as of equal worth in the sense that it treats persons equally as of no worth. It is true that utilitarianism may tend towards equal welfare due to factors such as diminishing marginal utility and the disutility of envy if 6 Nozick (1974) provides an excellent example of the fact that humans have an innate propensity to Ado@ rather than to only Aexperience@. Nozick invites us to imagine an Aexperience machine@ that has the ability to let one experience everything you wish for as if it occurs in real life. One could spend one=s whole life in this machine and maximize your experience of happiness, or whatever takes your fancy. Nozick then asks the rhetorical question: would most people opt to be connected to the experience machine (which in all respects will be Areal@) to optimize their pleasure or happiness, or will most people decline the opportunity to maximize their happiness in favour of actually living their lives, taking the good with the bad [Nozick R. (1974): Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York: Basic Books]. This example of Nozick is echoed in the 1999 film, AThe Matrix@, which also illustrates the point that most people will rather experience the hardships of the Areal@ world as opposed to a simulated good life. 7 Sen A. (1987): On Ethics and Economics, Oxford: Blackwell: pp 47 B 60. 8 AThe hopeless beggar, the precarious landless labourer, the dominated housewife, the hardened unemployed or the overexhausted coolie may all take pleasures in small mercies, and manage to suppress intense suffering for the necessity of continued survival, but it would be ethically deeply mistaken to attach a correspondingly small value to the loss of their well-being because of their survival strategy@ [Sen, cited by Crocker (1992): p 602 -- see Crocker D.A.: AFunctioning and Capability: The Foundations of Sen=s and Nussbaum=s Development Ethic@, in Political Theory, Vol. 20, No. 4, November 1992: pp 584-612]. 9 Idem: p 602. 41 great inequalities of wealth occurs, but this is by no means inevitable because there are also factors pointing the other way, such as loss of incentives and the failure of assumptions such as that individuals derive the same utility from the same amount of wealth and that all individuals are equally good pleasure or satisfaction machines.10 Utilitarianism proceeds on the false analogy between the individual (who can postpone pleasure or willingly subject himself to pain in the expectation that such sacrifices will yield, in the long term, greater need satisfaction or deferred pleasure), and the population at large. While it may be rational for the individual to incur these sacrifices it is not rational for an individual to incur these disutilities if the benefits will ultimately fall elsewhere.11 2.3.2. Rawls=s Critique of Utilitarianism 10 11 Idem: p 830. Idem: p 831. 42 In his preface to A Theory of Justice Rawls explains that the main aim of his theory of justice is to offer an alternative to utilitarianism.12 It is therefore not surprising that the largest share of Rawls=s critical comments are reserved for utilitarianism, both in its Aclassical@ form [which stresses the maximization of total utility] and its more modern form [which argues for the maximization of average utility]. The issues raised by his critique of utilitarianism, at various stages of the exposition of his theory of justice, are too numerous to do justice to here, but two points are worth mentioning: First, Rawls alleges that Autilitarianism does not take seriously the distinction between persons@13 in that in its pursuit of the maximal total utility to all, it ignores the fairness of the distribution of goods to specific individuals. People are distinct in a way that makes it impermissible to discount a harm to one against a benefit to another.14 The charge on this count is that utilitarianism fails to account for our considered conviction that persons have rights that should not be subject to the calculus of social interests.15 The central proposition of classical utilitarianism is the greatest happiness principle, which prescribes that the best political and social arrangement is the one that yields the maximum aggregate happiness of the members of society as a whole. In principle the utilitarian maxim would be satisfied by a social arrangement whereby some are enslaved for the greater happiness of others, provided that the aggregate disutility or unhappiness of those enslaved is offset by the aggregate utility of the beneficiaries of the arrangement to the extent that this arrangement yields the greatest nett aggregate utility. To put it differently, Rawls charges utilitarianism of asking too much of individuals, in that people are required to sacrifice 12 Rawls (1999): A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press (Revised Edition): pp xvii -- xviii. 13 Rawls (1999): p 24; p 26; pp 163 B 164; p 167; and p 189. 14 Also see Glover J. (1988): The Philosophy and Psychology of Personal Identity, London: Penguin Books: pp 104 B 105. The author cites an argument by Parfit, that ostensibly weakens the separateness of persons argument relied upon by Rawls. 15 Rawls (1999): p 4. 43 their own particular good for others, if this would lead to greater aggregate utility.16 According to Rawls, this conception of justice will lead to social instability and a loss of self-esteem by those who are required to make sacrifices for the greater social good. 16 Ibid: p 154; p 155; p 180; and p 157. 44 Rawls=s second criticism directed at utilitarianism is that it erroneously proposes that there is only one good that counts, namely mental pleasure. Utilitarians assume, according to Rawls, that while many goods may contribute to psychological well-being, only one conception of the good exists and that is mental pleasure. Rawls rejects this monistic conception of the good, claiming that a plurality of conceptions of the good, some of which may even be irreconcilable with other conceptions, exists among members of society and that any adequate political theory should reflect this. These two criticisms against utilitarianism form the starting points of Rawls=s theory which aims to account for the fact that, first of all, individuals have rights that should be immune to the calculus of social interests, and, secondly, recognizes that not all rational and informed individuals would accept a single conception of the good, that conceptions of the good in a modern constitutional democracy are irreducibly plural. Rawls conceives of society as a fair system of social cooperation among free and equal individuals under conditions of moderate scarcity.17 Because of the plurality of conceptions of the good existing alongside the need to cooperate with other members of society to achieve our respective individual ends, the relations among members of society are marked by conflict as well as mutual benefit.18 The Kantian basis of Rawls=s rejection of utilitarianism is clear: Kant argued that empirical principles such as utility, are unfit to serve as basis for the moral law, because an instrumental defence of freedom and rights not only leaves rights vulnerable, but fails to respect the inherent dignity of persons. The utilitarian calculus treats people as means to the happiness of others, not as ends in themselves, worthy of respect.19 2.4. THE EGALITARIAN ELEMENTS IN UTILITARIANISM In utilitarianism, the concept of equality fulfils the following functions: Firstly, everyone should be counted as one and no one as more than one. This means that no person, by virtue of his status or power or privileged position in society, or for whatever other reason, has a claim that his level of welfare or happiness or need satisfaction, or whatever is used as the metric for assessing utility levels, should be regarded as more important than that of another. Secondly, alternative systems of political and social arrangements will be regarded as equal if their aggregate utility levels (or average utility levels) are the same, irrespective of vast differences in the actual shape of their distributive outcomes. For example, in a society consisting of persons A, B, C and D, the distributions depicted in Table 2.1. will be regarded as 17 18 19 Ibid: pp 3 B 19; and Rawls J. (1993): Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press: pp 3 B 46. Ackerman (1980): Social Justice in the Liberal State, Binghampton, N.Y.: Yale University Press. See Sandel=s Introduction in Liberalism and Its Critics [Sandel (ed)(1984): p 3]. 45 equally just, despite the fact that the shares allocated to each individual differ significantly depending on which distributive scheme is adopted. Note that under a system of truncated utilitarianism,20 only distribution III will be regarded as just, if we assume that 10 utiles is the subsistence level or social minimum. Person Distribution I Distribution II Distribution III A 70 5 40 B 20 60 30 C 10 35 20 D 0 0 10 100/25 100/25 100/25 Aggregate/Average Utility Table 2.1.: Equally Just Distributions Under Utilitarianism 20 The term Atruncated utilitarianism@ is used here to describe a distributive scheme which provides a social minimum to everyone, irrespective of aggregative utility considerations; above this social minimum the utilitarian principle applies unchecked. 46 Thirdly, (and as previously stated) on some interpretations of utilitarianism, a political and social system based on its precepts will tend towards an equal distribution of social goods, because the marginal utility of the same amount of goods will be more for the person with a smaller holding than for a person with a larger holding. The consequence of this is that transfers from the rich to the poor will always lead to an increase in the aggregate or the average utility. However, this interpretation is not without its detractors. For example, Miller argues, from a Marxist perspective, that it is plausible to assume that the rich, or the ruling class, have an Aespecially acute need for wealth and power.@21 If this assumption holds, then it may not necessarily be true that transfers from the wealthy to the destitute will always increase the aggregate or the average utility of society. To accommodate this concern, the transfer from the rich to the poor may be made subject to the qualification that everyone should have the same welfare function. Thus the rule for selecting a distribution will now be: if everyone has the same welfare function, then any transfer from a wealthier person to a poorer person, 22 which does not reverse the inequality, is always preferable. Sen proposes the following equity axiom: If person A is worse off than person B, whenever A and B have the same income level, then person A should receive more or at least the same income than person B, in the optimal solution to the pure distribution problem. According to Sen, this rule is not extremist in the sense that Rawls=s difference principle is, that is, concentrating only on the worst-off group, and yet it uses exactly the same type of information as the Rawlsian rule.23 The point that Sen makes can be illustrated by the example of distributions provided in Table 2.1.. Under Rawls=s difference principle only the position of Person D, being the worst-off person, will receive attention (or at least until his position equals or exceeds that of the second worst-off person, Person C). The difference principle will therefore not concern itself with the great disparity between Persons B and A in Distribution I, nor can Person B complain that the position of Person D is improved while his position remains unaltered. Under the equity axiom, any transfer from A to B or C or from B to C (Distribution I) or from A to B or C or from B to C (Distribution III) may be justified, while the Rawlsian difference principle is completely insensitive to these transfers. 21 22 Miller, in Daniels (1989), pp 206 B 230: p 211. Sen, in Daniels (1989), pp 283 B 292: p 285. 23 See Sections 5.4. and 6.4.4. infra for a discussion of how Rawls proposes to determine Arelevant social positions@ and the problems associated with his solution. 47 From the previous point, another interesting comparison between utilitarianism and Rawlsian equality flows: As was seen, the utilitarian procedure is based on comparing the aggregate gains and losses in welfare between different persons, under different distributive arrangements (for example, Person A gained more in the move from one distributive system to another, than did Person B, and it is the aggregate gains or losses which determine which distributive scheme is to be preferred), while ignoring levels of welfare comparisons between people (for example, Person A is in a relatively better position than Person B). Rawls=s theory, on the other hand, is sensitive to comparing welfare levels only, without computing for comparative gains and losses. In this sense, one may conclude that both utilitarianism and the Rawlsian system of justice as fairness are incomplete normative theories, because distributive judgements should be based on both comparisons of total welfare gains and losses (as utilitarianism does) and on comparisons of relative levels of welfare (as Rawlsian justice does).24 One can agree with Sen=s conclusion regarding Rawls on the implementation level, as long as it is kept in mind that under the Rawlsian model of justice as fairness, the comparison of distributive schemes (that is of comparing absolute gains and losses) would have been done when the selection of the principles of justice took place in the original position.25 Thereafter, Sen is correct: only welfare levels are compared. 2.5. CONCLUSION What is the relevance of utilitarianism for equality and distributive justice? The equality asserted in utilitarianism is only the equality of the like amount of utility of any two individuals and places no constraints on unequal distributions, as long as aggregate nett utility is maximized. For example if Person A gets 100 utiles and Person B minus 50 utiles, this distribution would be preferred to one under which Person A and Person B only got 20 utiles each, for the aggregate nett utility is higher under the former than the latter distribution.26 But, because the marginal utility of economic goods diminishes as one’s share increases, it may be that utilitarianism has egalitarian implications for economic justice, as Hume puts it: 24 25 26 Sen, in Daniels (1989), pp 283 B 292: p 284 & p 292. In this regard, see Section 5.3.6., in which the social nature of talents and handicaps is discussed. Narveson J.: AEquality vs. Liberty: Advantage, Liberty@, in Social Philosophy & Policv, Vol. 2, No. 1, Autumn 1984, pp 33-60: pp43 -- 46. 48 AIt must be confessed, that, wherever we depart from this equality, we rob the poor of more satisfaction than we add to the rich, and that the slight gratification of a frivolous vanity, in one individual, frequently costs more than bread to many families, and even provinces@.27 But Hume also argues, along with Adam Smith and Rawls, that inequalities should be permitted as incentives to move people to produce more for the greater good. On this reading economic inequality can be justified on utilitarian grounds because allowing self-interested accumulation of wealth by those best-suited to produce wealth will result in greater aggregate utility. Therefore, if one can argue polar opposite implications from the same basic premises, utilitarianism does not provide us with the conceptual tools necessary to argue in favour of economic equality. Utilitarianism therefore fails the feasibility test, as specified by the second question in Section 1.7. The conception of equality found in utilitarianism is insensitive to the different spheres of life and social activities from which the individual may derive his happiness and this is contrary to the postulate contained in the third question posed in Section 1.7. Furthermore, as the critique discussed in Section 2.3. clearly demonstrates, utilitarianism cannot supply the basis for the compound equality of opportunity model proposed in Chapter 11, because, amongst others: utilitarianism ignores the agency aspects of personhood [Sen, Hart and Nozick]; it gives insufficient recognition to the individual [Rawls], and, as explained in Section 1.6., I set out to develop a model which recognizes the importance of the individual, albeit in a particular social context; it places too large a burden on altruistic social benevolence [Rawls]; and it has perfectionist tendencies, based on an inadequate conception of the person [Rawls and Sen]. Per definition, utilitarianism therefore cannot begin to provide the moral basis for the model as encapsulated in the general problem statement in Section 1.5. 27 Hume D. (1751): Inquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Chap. III. sec. ii. [cited by Narveson (1984): p 44]. 49 Utilitarianism, by paying exclusive attention to only one aspect of human well-being, namely, utility, is an inaccurate and incomplete conception of individual well-being and fails to yield an appropriate concept of social equality.28 For example, because it ignores the shapes of competing distributive schemes, in favour of aggregate nett welfare as the sole normative standard, types of unfair discrimination [such as affirmative measures amounting to Areverse discrimination@], may easily be justified under utilitarianism, especially if the principle of decreasing marginal utility is used to determine total welfare levels [i.e. redistribution from the rich to the poor, other things remaining constant, will always lead to a greater increase in the welfare levels of the poor compared with the accompanying reduction in the welfare levels of the rich]. The focus of this thesis being liberal conceptions of equality, no more attention is given to utilitarianism. Utilitarianism is important mainly for being grounded in an intuitively appealing, but grossly simplified, psychology (humans seek to maximize pleasure and minimize pain) and for the fact that it was the dominant political philosophy in the pre-Rawlsian period. In the next three chapters I discuss Rawls=s theory of justice and his claims how his theory avoids the alleged deficiencies of utilitarianism as a theory of justice. 28 Crocker (1992): p 600. 50