The Rise and Fall of the Factory System: Technology, firms, and

advertisement
The Rise and Fall of the Factory System:
Technology, firms, and households since the
Industrial Revolution
Joel Mokyr
Departments of Economics and History
Northwestern University
January 1, 2001
Prepared for the Carnegie-Rochester Conference on macroeconomics, Pittsburgh, Nov.
17-19, 2000.
I am indebted to Tom Geraghty for many valuable suggestions to Joerg Baten, Janice
Kinghorn, Craig Riddell, and Patricia Mokhtarian for helpful information, to Federico
Ciliberto, Dario Gaggio, Robert J. Gordon, Lynne Kiesling, Hilarie Lieb, John McDermott,
Peter Meyer, Patricia Mokhtarian, and Keith Pavitt for helpful comments and to Steve
Nafziger for research assistance.
1
The consequences which accompanied the introduction of the modern factory are
extraordinarily far-reaching... workshop industry meant the employment of the worker in a
place which was separate both from the dwelling of the consumer and from his own.
Max Weber, 1920
In half a century’s time, it may well seem extraordinary that millions of people once trooped
from one building (their home) to another (their office) each morning, only to reverse the
procedure each evening... Commuting wastes time and building capacity. One building -- the
home -- often stands empty all day; another -- the office -- usually stands empty all night. All
this may strike our grandchildren as bizarre.
Frances Cairncross, 1997
Introduction
What does technology really do to our lives and well-being? Much of the history of technological
revolutions in the past two centuries is written as if the only thing that technology affected was output,
productivity, and economic welfare as approximated by income. This is of course the best-understood
and most widely analyzed aspect of technological progress. Yet technological progress affected other
aspects of the economy that may be significant besides the quantity of output broadly defined. Among
those is the optimal scale of the basic economic production unit and the location where the act of
production takes place. These in turn determine whether “work” will be carried out in a specialized
location and thus whether households and firms will be separate physical entities.
The stylized fact is that the Industrial Revolution of 1760-1830 witnessed the “rise of the
factory.” Like all historical “facts” of this kind, it is only an approximation. In reality, there were
numerous precedents for large-scale enterprise and for people working in large plants even before the
classical Industrial Revolution. But there can be no doubt that what the Industrial Revolution meant was
the ever-growing physical separation of the unit of consumption (household) from the unit of
production (plant).1 “Factories” is a term that mixes up two economic phenomena: one is the
1
Max Weber cited above, was not the first to emphasize this aspect. Paul Mantoux opened his still classic work
on the Industrial Revolution (first published in 1905) with the words “The modern factory system originated in England in
the last third of the eighteenth century. From the beginning its effects were so quickly felt and gave rise to such important
results that it has been aptly compared to a revolution, though it may be confidently asserted that few political revolutions
2
concentration of former artisans and domestic workers under one roof, in which workers were more
or less continuing what they were doing before, only away from home. These are sometimes known
as “manufactories.” The other involves a more radical change in production technique, with substantial
investment in fixed capital combined with strict supervision and rigid discipline resulting in what became
known as “mills.” In practice, of course, this neat dual division did not hold, and most of the new plants
were blends of the “ideal” types, with the relative importance of the “manufactories” declining over time.
The purpose of this paper is to argue that this phenomenon was largely driven by technology,
which determined both the relative costs and the benefits of moving people as opposed to moving
information. These costs overlap only in small part with the “transactions costs” postulated to explain
the existence of firms by Coase and Oliver Williamson. Moreover, because I am interested here
primarily in the location where the work is carried out, the modern distinction between firm and plant
should be kept firmly in mind. In the standard theory of the firm, firms are substitutes for contracts,
they reduce uncertainty and opportunistic behavior, and set incentives to elicit efficient responses from
agents. Firms can hire workers or transact with suppliers in a long-term, repeated relationship, or on
a one-shot basis. This, however, does not fully specify the actual location of production. The key to the
understanding of the geography of the firm is the costs of moving goods, people, and information. In
a recent paper, Lamoureaux, Raff and Temin (2000) realize that information and transportation costs
determine the location and organization of economic activity but worry that these costs all decline
monotonically over time, yet the organization of business shows anything but a unidirectional trend.
Part of the answer, as they correctly point out, is the emergence of new techniques of coordination. My
argument here is that whether workers work at home or in a central location depends on the relative
costs and benefits of moving people or moving information and on the changes in the composition of
output and capital-labor ratios that may change labor demand in activities requiring workers to be
actually present on the shopfloor or in the office. While transportation costs and information costs may
have both fallen, a change in their ratio may affect the location of production in a complex manner.
Furthermore, the benefits of concentration may be moving in different direction as the result of changes
in technology and product-mix.
have ever had such far-reaching consequences” (1961, p. 25).
3
Large firms were quite widespread before the Industrial Revolution, but almost all of their
employment was domestic labor (cottage industry), much of it on a putting-out basis. In this system,
the “firm” (that is the merchant-entrepreneur) owned the raw materials, the goods in process and often
the tools and equipment as well, and outsourced physical production to workers’ homes. This may well
have been more efficient in a Grossman-Hart kind of framework, in which the raw materials and the
tools were strongly complementary, but capital markets underdeveloped. In that kind of world,
ownership confers residual rights of control and decision, but the technology may not have required
in most cases to locate the physical production in a central place.
Most workers in pre-Industrial Revolution western Europe, in any case, were independent
farmers or craftsmen and the distinction between “firm,” “plant,” and “household” is otiose. For those
who had become part of larger firms, putting-out was the answer. A condition for the putting-out
system to exist was for labor to be paid a piece wage, since working at home made the monitoring of
time impossible. In the stylized version, then, the factory, factory towns, and an industrial wage labor
force or proletariat were all created in the closing decades of the eighteenth century and the first half
of the nineteenth. The process of transition was long, drawn out, and never quite complete, but by
1914, as far as we can tell, the majority of the labor force was no longer working in their homes.
In recent years, there is some tendency for the pendulum to start swinging back. Some
telecommuting enthusiasts are predicting a return to pre-Industrial Revolution conditions, in which
suitably networked households will become once again the main location in which human work will be
carried out. The “death of distance” may mean that more and more production can take place from
any location, and that hence the need for employees to be present at some central facility may become
less and less required. To be sure, the demise of the industrial plant may be premature, and in any
event it is not the intention of this paper to engage in prediction, much less futurism. Instead, it
proposes to re-examine the causes and effects of the rise of the factory, and specifically to sort out the
role of technological change in this process, and then to apply some of the insights to issues of current
policy relevance.
The Industrial Revolution and the Rise of the Factory
Traditional industry, that is, manufacturing before the Industrial Revolution was, in François
4
Crouzet’s words (1985, p. 4) an industry without industrialists. This was surely true for the independent
craftsmen who worked on their own account with the help of their family members and a few
apprentices who were co-opted in the household. Workers who were employed by capitalists in one
form or another also worked, predominantly, in their own homes. Max Weber stated it most clearly, that
the distinguishing characteristic of the modern factory were “labor discipline within the shop ...
combined with technical specialization and co-ordination and the application of non-human power ...
The concentration of ownership of workplace, means of work, source of power and raw material in one
and the same hand. This combination was only rarely met before the eighteenth century” (1961, pp.
133, 224).
As noted above, large industrial plants were not entirely unknown before the Industrial
Revolution. For instance, Pollard (1968) in his classic work on the rise of Factory, mentions three large
plants, all employing over 500 employees before 1750.2 Perhaps the most “modern” of all industries
was silk throwing. The silk mills in Derby built by Thomas Lombe in 1718 employed 300 workers and
was located in a five-story building. After Lombe’s patent expired, large mills patterned after his were
built in other places as well. Equally famous was the Crowley ironworks, established in 1682 in
Stourbridge in the midlands (not far from Birmingham) and which employed at its peak 800
employees. Yet Crowley’s firm is the exception that proves the rule: much of the work was put out to
master workmen who worked the iron in their own homes or workshops. Crowley was unusual in
having set up a system of supervision, monitoring, and arbitration with his workers unlike anyone else.3
Blast furnaces, breweries, shipyards, mines, construction and a few other industries had long been
producing outside the domestic system since they could not economically operate at the scale of a
household.4 In textiles, Chapman (1974) has shown how supervised workshop production could be
found before 1770 in the Devon woolen industry and in calico printing. Yet in industries such as the
2
Tann (1970, p. 3) mentions a number of large works in the seventeenth century, but designates them as
“exceptional cases.”
3
The insightful biography by Flinn (1962, p. 252) calls Crowley’s firm “a giant in an age of pygmies” and notes
that his example of successful large-scale industrial organization was not followed until a century later.
4
One of the largest firms was the Neath colliery in Wales. Coalmines by their very nature required a presence away
from home, of course, but even there coalminers were often employed with their families and paid a piece wage. In a sense,
then, many coal mine employees could be regarded as subcontractors.
5
Yorkshire wool and the midland metal trades, centralized workshop production controlled only a few
stages of output and rarely displayed the control and discipline we associate with real “factories.”
Wherever possible, work was outsourced to small-scale artisans working at home who at times ran
cooperatives when scale economies were important.5 Even these early factories, then, were a
compromise between the domestic system and the need to produce away from home.
Notwithstanding these precursors, the Industrial Revolution brought about factories where none
were before. The transition was relentless but gradual. Most firms did not switch abruptly from the
domestic system to a factory system, but continued to farm out some processes to domestic workers,
until mechanization and technological complexity had sufficiently expanded to make it worthwhile to
bring the workers under one roof. The cotton industry provides the best example of this mixed factory
system. In 1760, this industry was overwhelmingly a domestic industry. The water frame spinning
machine changed all that. Richard Arkwright’s works in Cromford employed about 300 workers; he
also helped found the New Lanark mills in Scotland which employed a workforce of 1600 in 1815
(most of which were indoor). Such huge firms were unusual, perhaps, but by 1800, there were in
Britain around 900 cotton-spinning factories, of which a third were “mills” employing over 50 workers
and the rest small sheds and workshops, with a handful of workers – though even those by that time
were larger than households. The mule, especially after it was coupled to steam power, changed the
distribution of firms quickly: at first, in the early 1790s we observe something like a lognormal in which
the majority of cotton were still small firms employing at most 10 workers, with a few Arkwright-type
mills of 300-400 workers. By the early 1830s, when reasonable statistics rather than guesswork and
pronouncements of contemporaries become the basis of our estimates, the average Manchester mill
had about 400 workers. The very large and very small firms made room for medium sized ones,
between 150-400 workers. The domestic spinner had by that time long disappeared.
Some of the other branches of the cotton industry -- some of which had already been in large
workshops before -- were also quick to move into factories: carding, calico printing, and bleaching were
all absorbed quickly into factories. Weaving, however, was a different matter. Although many inventors
experimented with a variety of mechanical looms, the power loom did not make its effective entry on
5
Thus in the woolen industry of West Yorkshire, the finishing stages of the woolen output required a powered mill
and was carried out in cooperatives. Berg, 1994, p. 128.
6
the scene until the 1820s. Until then, the handloom weaver, operating from his own home, not only was
not threatened by the factory, but actually prospered. With the rapid spread of powerlooms after the
1820s, home weaving rapidly disappeared. Many of the former handloom weavers simply joined the
factories they could not beat.
Outside of cotton, the factories marched on equally inexorably. In worsteds, the combed wool
industry, spinning was mechanized early and followed the trajectory of cotton toward a rapid transition
to factories; combing itself, however, proved difficult to mechanize and and was left to domestic or
small-scale producers until the mid nineteenth century even when its output was spun in factories. Once
again, we see a “mixed” system in which some stages of the production is carried out domestically
whereas others are concentrated in factories. Wool lagged even further behind since spinning of carded
wool proved difficult to mechanize. In flax-spinning, large scale factories emerged with the wet-spinning
process invented in France and adopted in Britain in about 1825.6 Hand looms in linen persisted until
deep into the second half of the nineteenth century. On the whole, the transition from domestic
manufacture to factory was the most dramatic in textiles, but even there it took over a century to
complete.
In other industries, the transition was less spectacular because some large-scale
establishments already existed by 1760, or because for one reason or another domestic manufacturing
could continue to linger on. This was especially the case in iron. The few large ironworks around 1750
notwithstanding, this was still largely a small-scale industry, with much of the work carried out in little
forges adjacent to the homes of blacksmiths and nailers. Cort’s great invention of puddling and rolling
changed the face of the industry and in rapid time eliminated small producers from the refinement
process. Some of the new ironworks grew to unprecedented proportions, such as the Cyfarthfa
ironworks in Wales which employed 1500 men in 1810 and 5,000 in 1830, and the Dowlais works
which were of comparable size. At the same time in the hardware and engineering trades, small firms
predominated (Berg, 1994b). Large factories were rare in the metal trades of Sheffield and
Birmingham, such as cutleries, toymakers, armorers, nailers, bucklemakers and others, where much
of the production was located in small workshops and houses, interspersed with a few larger
6
John Marshall of Leeds was the leading flax-spinner in Britain and his large mill was world famous. The building
was designed by an architect who based it on the single-storey temple of Karnak in upper Egypt.
7
establishments.
It is sometimes felt that the rise of the factory in which workers were concentrated under one
roof, and subjected to discipline and supervision was not all that much of a break with the past. The
discontinuity of the Industrial Revolution has been at times overstated. It was not the beginning of
“capitalist” production – the putting-out system could be quite hierarchical and tightly controlled.
Moreover, pre-Industrial Revolution manufacturing produced quite a number of organizational forms
that could accommodate a variety of technical needs. For instance, it could and did practice a division
of labor at a fairly high level.7 Yet the Industrial Revolution marked the beginning of the process in
which the household would eventually lose its role as the prevalent locus of production. For that to be
true, it did not matter all that much whether people worked in workshops of 20 or 400 employees. The
welfare and other economic implications of the change were far reaching.
Some implications.
The rise of the modern business plant as a locational unit has given rise to enormous social
changes first fully identified and described by Marx. He developed the notion of “alienation,” and
stressed the enormous historical significance of the emergence of an industrial proletariat, the need to
form a docile and malleable labor force, and the significance of people spending much of their life
interacting with strangers, subjecting themselves to the hardships of the shopfloor and the coercion of
the factory clock.8 Many modern writers echo Marx’s views.9
The full welfare implications for the household of the rise of the factory go beyond the social
phenomena Marx was interested in. They include a social cost in terms of commuting. Little is known
about the frequency and average distance of commuting in the early factory days, although there are
7
Furthermore, Berg (1994b) has argued that decentralized organization forms lent themselves well to innovation
and that small firms that practiced “flexible specialization” were a viable alternative to the factory.
8
It might have seemed a good idea to hire factory labor in family units just as some of the pre-Industrial Revolution
industries had done, and some authors have in fact argued that this was quite common (Smelser, 1959), but others have
shown that this involved only a small portion of the labor force (Landes, 1986, p. 610, n.60).
9
Pollard (1968, p. 195) cites Ashton’s laconic comment that “there was no strong desire on the part of the workers
to congregate in large establishments” as “an understatement to the point of travesty.”
8
some striking examples.10 Before urban mass transit, the only way to commute was walking, which
limited the commuting distance, and led many factory masters to supply living quarters in so-called
factory villages. These, however, were rare in urban areas. Technologically-driven changes in the per
capita number of hours spent commuting reduced overall economic welfare in ways not wholly
captured in national income statistics since some commuting crowds out leisure. Insofar that the time
costs of commuting were compensated for in higher wages, these welfare costs were borne by others,
but society as a whole still had to pay the cost. Changes in commuting does not “distort” the
measurement of GNP as such, but any replacement of leisure by commuting time will change welfare
without changing the measured aggregates. This distortion is probably small before 1850, and relative
to the growth of incomes, probably not all that large after either.11 However, if there were a sudden
change in commuting time, it could have significant implications for economic welfare.
A related but different welfare reduction due to the rise of the factory is the collapse of the leisureincome choice to something close to a single point. Part-time employees were rare and absenteeism
was usually a cause for fines or dismissal. Under the old regime, domestic workers could choose
essentially any point on the leisure-income trade-off; this freedom of choice was much reduced once
workers had to submit to the factory regime. Even a combination of higher wage with lower leisure, it
can readily be shown, could be welfare-reducing if it became an “all or nothing” choice.12 This decline
was compounded by the relentless erosion of the undeniable opportunities towards joint production of
income and household services within the home, especially as far as childcare was concerned. The loss
of this opportunity for domestic multitasking will further increase the upward bias in the income statistics
as a measure of welfare.
Beyond that, of course, were the nonpecuniary characteristics of the factory relative to the home.
10
The distances cited in Parliamentary Papers 1831-32 are quite striking: There are repeated mentions of workers
living one full hour walking away (pp. 5, 19, 95, 98, 350, 365). The source makes it not easy to conclude how typical this
was, but in any case, the time-cost of the commute represented a social cost that was rare before the Industrial Revolution.
11
The same point is made by Nordhaus and Tobin (1973), p. 521, one of the few attempts to adjust the National
Income accounts to the many ambiguities that modernization throw in its path.
12
In practice, workers of course could exercise more freedom of choice than the grim all-or-nothing regimes
suggest. The frequent complaints about absenteeism, especially on “St. Monday,” suggest that the conditioning of workers
took generations. All the same, the evidence suggests that by the early nineteenth century, the practice of taking Mondays
off was in decline (Voth, 1998).
9
Although there was a great deal of variation in actual factory conditions, and the “dark, Satanic mills”
and large coalmines did not employ a majority of the workers, it remains true that in terms of the
physical environment, the shift to noisy, unpleasant, and dangerous locations that many new mills surely
were, reduced workers’ well-being. If factory work and life in industrial towns and villages became more
onerous, risky, or disagreeable, rising real wages would have the interpretation of a compensating
differential.13 The evidence for a significant nation-wide increase in real wages, however, has been called
into question (Feinstein, 1998).
For the economist, this represents something of a dilemma, since in the absence of coercion,
it is not logical that workers would voluntarily agree to work in factories if it reduced their utility. In fact,
of course, many workers were paid a factory or coal-mine premium as a compensating differential,
providing workers with benefits such as housing, schooling for their children, and even milch cows
(Chapman, 1967, pp. 159-60). Insofar that this was inadequate, however, factory owners, especially in
the countryside, relied on pauper children and orphans borrowed from workhouses.14 Beyond that,
however, the economic logic of the Industrial Revolution implied that workers might end up working in
factories even if it made them worse off. The reason is that the opportunity cost of many of these
potential factory employees was set by what they could earn in cottage industry. This alternative declined
rapidly and by 1850 was, in most cases, no longer available. The factories, by relentlessly driving down
the price of manufactured goods, reduced these earnings and thus forced workers (or their offspring)
to abandon their cottages and seek work in the mills or emigrate.15
The separation of worker from household means that human capital formation follows different
rules: before the emergence of the factory, the only agent who has any interest in training and human
13
This effect has been measured in an ingenious paper by Brown (1990), who concludes (pp. 612-613) that
despite rising real wages "there was virtually no improvement in living standards until at least the 1840s and perhaps the
entire first half of the nineteenth century."
14
Some of the transactions between Poor Law authorities and mill owners resembled nothing as much as slave
trade; e.g., the purchase of seventy children from the parish of Clerkenwell by Samuel Oldknow in 1796 (Mantoux, 1928,
p. 411). Recruiting agents were often sent to scour the surrounding countryside in search of workhouse labor, and some
of these children were brought in from the other end of the country, which indicates that for some industrialists pauper
apprentices were indeed a cheap and satisfactory but hardly voluntary form of labor.
15
This assumes only that labor productivity in a factory setting is higher than in a domestic setting. For a formal
demonstration of this general equilibrium model of the Industrial Revolution see Mokyr (1976).
10
capital formation beside the agent herself was her parent.16 After the formation of factories we
increasingly observe employers taking an active interest in the education and training of their labor force.
There was an obvious complementarity between the fixed capital in the plant and the human capital
necessary to operate it. This was recently pointed out in an important paper by Galor and Moav (2000).
There is a great deal of evidence that worker training initiated by the capitalist class became increasingly
important with the Industrial Revolution. The skills that were in abundant supply around 1750 were
largely the skills of the blacksmith, not those of the mathematical instrument maker. The machines
required levels of precision work that were scarce, even in Britain.17
Much of this education, however, was not technical in nature but social and moral. Workers who
had always spent their working days in a domestic setting, had to be taught to follow orders, to respect
the space and property rights of others, be punctual, docile, and sober. The early industrial capitalists
spent a great deal of effort and time in the social conditioning of their labor force, especially in Sunday
schools which were designed to inculcate middle class values and attitudes, so as to make the workers
more susceptible to the incentives that the factory needed and to “train the lower classes in the habits
of industry and piety” (Mitch, 1998, p. 245). At the same time, we observe a growing distinction between
“firm-specific” human capital (with the factories training workers in the skills needed for the core
competencies of that firm) and “general” human capital such as literacy and middle class values of
diligence and docility that the worker could take anywhere. For that reason, we see factory masters often
subsidizing schools, but almost always students’ families were expected to pay part of the cost. We also
often observe factory masters signing up their workers for long contracts or indentures ranging from 512 years (Chapman, 1967, p. 173).
The transition from household to plant involved a more subtle issue of the changing nature of
16
The skills required in the large-scale putting out industry were usually low and had few complementarities with
other workers; the more skilled craftsmen were by and large independent.
17
James Watt, often impatient with his workmen, complained that Soho people have no accuracy and that he
never could leave the firm without some gross inaccuracy or blundering (Pollard, 1968, p. 206). It is less clear to which
extent the new cotton industry required training: some elite spinners surely possessed skills that had to be acquired over
long periods, but they tend to be exceptional (Mitch, 1998, p. 261). By utilizing the existing institutions of seven year
apprenticeships -- a medieval legacy -- Britain’s craftsmen bred their own, and supplied the needs of a growing modern
sector. Factories also practiced “migration,” the rotation of workers from job to job. This system of accumulating human
capital probably did not work as fast and efficiently as the factory masters would have liked, but surely worked better than
in any other country at the time.
11
competition. In a classical world, in which firms produce and households consume, firms compete with
each other in a Schumpeterian sense. Those who choose techniques that are inefficient in some fashion
lose market share and profits and eventually shrink and disappear. This kind of Darwinian mechanism
does not work very well for households. Households that employ bad techniques may have lower utility,
but only in extreme cases will these bad techniques lead to their elimination in a Darwinian sense and
to a survival and proliferation of more efficient techniques. An inefficient owner/manager of a large
competitive firm will see his firm go under or his assets bought out and labor hired away by another. No
mechanism of such efficacy comes to mind when independent households are concerned.18 Householdfirms competed in various markets, but mechanisms that eliminated efficiency differences between them
worked only poorly. Social learning and emulation may have led to changes in technical choices if
households had a chance to observe each other very well and compare notes as happened in craft
guilds. The more efficient and industrious producers enjoyed higher incomes, but they couldneither grow
nor rapidly expand their numbers.19 Inefficient or lazy household-firms may not have “died” unless their
inefficiency reached truly disastrous dimensions. Moreover, even if households observed differences in
outcomes (in terms of higher income) between themselves and others, they could not easily distinguish
between differences in the techniques chosen and pure rents (that is, due to differences in endowments
that they cannot change). Putting all workers under one roof allowed an immediate comparison between
workers of different productivities and its remediation by instruction and the creation of better incentives.
Factory masters, knowing that they may go under if they do not choose the right techniques, will whip
workers (sometimes almost literally) into using the most efficient techniques.
In the real world of economic history, things were never that extreme. Urban artisans obviously
18
In a putting-out set-up, the entrepreneurs who owned the capital and marketed the final product would prefer
to employ more efficient workers if there was a substantial cost in terms of capital utilization and product quality due to
lower technical ability by bad workers, and if they were unable to recognize such workers and vary their piece rates
accordingly.
19
One “Darwinian” mechanism that would work to some extent here is that very successful and able craftsmen
would attract more apprentices than their competitors, and thus transmit superior skills that in the long run would drive
out inferior ones.
12
did “pool” their knowledge and compared techniques in use.20 In the early stages of the Industrial
Revolution there was a considerable variety among the practices used by early factories and the shaking
out of the inefficient was an imperfect process. All the same, the rise of the factory represented a growing
stringency of the competitive environment in which workers operated, and thus increased allocative
efficiency and speeded up the adoption of new best-practice techniques.
Explanations
Why did the factory arise when it did? There are three main explanations in the current literature
for the unprecedented phenomenon we now call the Rise of the Factory.21 One relies on purely technical
and physical economies of scale and scope, that might have caused the minimum efficient size of firms
to become larger than the household. A second is in terms of the modern micro-economics of the firm:
transactions costs were higher in decentralized households and the new technology changed monitoring
costs and incentives to self-monitor. A third argument is that by concentrating all workers under one
roof and placing them under supervision, actual labor effort is enhanced. Below, I will briefly survey each
of these arguments and then propose a fourth one.22
Fixed Costs and Scale Economies.
The most obvious candidate for the cause of such a shift is that the new technologies changed
the optimal scale of the producing unit and introduced increasing returns where once there were constant
returns. Some equipment, for purely physical reasons, could not be made equally efficiently in small
models that fit into the living rooms of workers' cottages and thus required large plants: iron puddling
furnaces and rollers, steam and water engines, silk-throwing mills, chemical and gas works -- all
required relatively large production units. Heating, lighting, power supply, security, equipment
maintenance, storage facilities, and inventory control, were all activities in which scale economies were
20
Recent research (Epstein, 1998) suggests that the enhancement and transmission of human capital was -- at
least in the early stages -- the main purpose of urban craft guilds. But with the growing migrationof manufacturing to the
countryside in the centuries before the Industrial Revolution, craft guilds lost much of their importance, and more
commonly acted as a barrier to innovation.
21
It might be noted here that this question was first asked in very explicit form by Charles Babbage (1835) in a
chapter entitled “On the causes and consequences of large factories.”
22
Some of what follows below is adapted from Mokyr, 1998.
13
obviously the result of technical considerations. In others they were economic such as marketing and
finance. But many of these advantages were at the level of the firm, not the plant. To a large extent they
had been resolved by the pre-Industrial Revolution putting-out firms. What made the difference in terms
of the locus of production in this view is mechanization.23
Machinery and other technological changes meant that fixed costs at the level of the plant went
up. As soon as fixed costs become important, the employer has an interest in supervising the workers
because shirking and volatility in labor supply reduce the utilization rate of the fixed capital.24 By the force
of this argument, the rise of the factory was a wholly technological event. Of course, “fixed costs” were
heterogeneous: if the main attraction was a heated, lighted room, in which relatively inexpensive equipment could be placed, raw materials and parts be supplied, and some instruction given, the most likely
outcome would be set-ups in which workers rented equipment and worked on their own account and
chose their own hours, as still could be seen throughout Britain in the nineteenth century. If, on the other
hand, the raw materials and the equipment were valuable and complex, factory discipline (in terms of
the hours worked, the effort put in, and their allocation over different tasks) would increasingly be the
norm.
Information Costs and Incentives. And yet, this cannot be the whole story. If it were, we would see a
tighter correlation between mechanization and the transition to “manufactories.” Berg (1980), Cohen
(1981), and Szostak (1989, 1991), among many others, have maintained that technological change and
mechanization were not necessary for the establishment of centralized workshops, which in fact
23
Long ago, Usher wrote that “machinery made the factory a successful and general form of organization. . . . Its
introduction ultimately forced the workman to accept the discipline of the factory” ( Usher, 1920, p. 350). Landes (1986,
p. 606) has restated this argument in unambiguous terms: “What made the factory successful in Britain was not the wish
but the muscle: the machine and the engines. We do not have factories until these were available.” Even Maxine Berg, who
has argued forcefully for the viability of small-scale production until the 1830s and beyond, concludes that the transition
to the factory system “proceeded at a much faster pace where it was combined with rapid power-using technological innovation” (1994, p. 207).
24
This insight is hardly indebted to modern theory: Karl Marx, in a famous passage, cites an industrialist telling
Nassau Senior that “if a labourer lays down his spade, he renders useless, for that period, a capital worth 18 pence. When
one of our people leaves the mill, he renders useless a capital that has cost £ 100,000.” Marx (1967, Vol. I, pp. 405-06).
William Smith, a Glasgow cotton spinner, noted that “when a mantua maker [a typical domestic industry, employing at most
2-3 workers] chooses to rise from her seat and take the fresh air, her seam goes a little back, that is all; there are no other
hands waiting on her... but in cotton mills all the machinery is going on which they must attend to...when there are a great
number of people congregated together, there is a necessity for the rules of discipline being a little more severe... because
the profits of the master depend upon the attention of those employed” Parliamentary Papers, 1831-32, p. 239.
14
preceded the great inventions of the last third of the eighteenth century.25 One explanation by Oliver
Williamson (1980), suggests that factories, by saving on transactions costs, were simply more efficient
than cottage industries (whether putting-out or independent producers), and thus their rise was
inexorable. Such a simplistic approach cannot possibly do justice to the historical reality (S.R.H. Jones,
1982, 1987; Szostak, 1989). After all, the domestic system survived for many centuries, and its demise
was drawn out over a very long period. Cottage industry practiced fairly fine and sophisticated division
of labor, and the proximity of cottages to each other make any reliance on physical transaction costs
a weak reed. Industry studies (e.g. Jones, 1987) confirm the importance of mechanization and
technology as a primum movens in the emergence of factories, although they rarely specify through
which mechanisms machinery brought about the factory, and do not explain the emergence of
centralized workshops without any obvious technological breakthroughs.
Some answers must come from the economics of information and especially principal-agent
problems. Paying workers a piece rate — uniformly practiced in putting-out industries — solves this
problem if the employer can assess the quality and quantity of the final product and if there are no cross
effects between workers' productivities (so that the effort of one worker does not affect the output of
another).The significance of piece wages should be realized from the following table:
Table 1: Combinations of organizational set-up and location
Domestic Location
Factory Setting
Independent Contractors
Artisans, small shopkeepers
“Manufactories,” (workers
renting space and equipment)
Piece Wage
“Putting-out” cottage
industries
Batch production
Time Wage
Unknown in nineteenth
century, cannot be monitored
Standard model, under
continuous flow or strong
interdependencies
25
Berg (1994, p. 196-97), Hudson (1992, p. 28), and Szostak (1989, p. 345) point to industry after industry that
established centralized workshops employing practically the same techniques as cottage industries: wool, pottery, metal
trades, even handloom weaving and framework knitting. Clark (1994, p. 155) shows how certain industries -- including pin
making -- practiced a fine division of labor in central workshops but did little to enforce discipline and punctuality.
Rosenberg and Birdzell (1986, p. 186) feel that “the spirit of the times was centralizing management before any mechanical
changes of a revolutionary character had been devised.” Had the steam engine and semi-automatic machinery never been
invented, “more and more control would have devolved upon the factory master”.
15
The critical point is that it was not possible for capitalists to pay their workers a time wage when they
worked at home, because it was impossible to monitor their input. This meant that for all practical
purposes employers who wanted to pay time wages had to move them to factories (where they still had
the option to pay some of the workers piece wages as well). But why would they want to?
In a classic paper, Lazear (1986) has analyzed the conditions conducive to choosing between
a time and a piece wage. In addition to the standard problem of monitoring costs, Lazear points out that
paying a piece wage has a sorting function and if workers are very heterogeneous in their ability, it
makes – for a given output-monitoring cost – more sense to pay them a piece wage. In this sorting
context, firms with large fixed costs or physical capital will pay a mixed wage, with the outputindependent (time-dependent) component higher, the higher the costs of physical capital. Lazear also
points out that while piece wages introduce direct proportionality between effort and payment, time
wages could be and were made contingent on some minimum of effort supplied. It might be added that
by paying slightly higher wages than the workers’ opportunity costs while threatening dismissal if efforts
fell below some level, time wages could be made compatible with optimal levels of effort.
Measuring net productivity in a piece-wage putting-out world ran into two further difficulties. One
was that workers had an incentive to increase their earnings by cutting corners on quality and finish and
make verification for the employer difficult. This is a classic problem of asymmetric information: the
worker knows where he can “cheat,” making it costly for most employers to monitor the quantity and
quality of output, but for the simplest processes. Lazear notes that paying a time rate not only allows
the employer to monitor quality through controlling what happens at the shopfloor, but he can persuade
the worker that for the same level of wage and effort, she can trade-off quantity for quality to attain the
combination the firm desires.
The other was that when the employer owned the capital -- as was increasingly but by no means
uniformly the case in the putting-out system -- he needed to supervise the worker’s handling his property.
Embezzlement of raw materials (which usually belonged to the capitalist) was a widespread complaint
16
(Styles, 1983).26 The problem of embezzlement, like quality control, was one of asymmetric information;
measuring the precise quantities of yarn supplied to a weaver and comparing those with the final output
was itself costly, and had to be correlated against normal losses of raw material during the process of
production and quality defects in it, which the employer did not observe directly.27 When the equipment
became more expensive and sophisticated, such as the early jennies that were still small enough to fit
in a worker’s home, employers wanted to be able to monitor how the worker handled the machines. Even
when a piece wage was possible, then, it became increasingly attractive for employers to monitor input
as well as output.28
Behind the question “will a piece wage be paid” is of course the classic Alchian and Demsetz
(1972) “team production” problem: if individual contributions to output cannot be disentangled,
supervision and monitoring is necessary just to make sure that the workers have the right incentives and
do no shirk.29 In factories there was the option of paying workers a time rate, which would be necessary
if the marginal product of labor was hard to assess or beyond the worker's control. These time rates
could then be supplemented by various incentive schemes that extracted maximum effort from workers
and made him allocate effort correctly between tasks (including maintain the equipment). Yet this does
not, by itself, explain the rise of the factory: why does “team production” become important after 1780
and not a century earlier? The answer must be, in large part, that the new technology required more
26
See Berg (1994b, p. 226). Social control gradually invaded the domestic economy during the years of the
Industrial Revolution. A series of acts passed between 1777 and 1790 permitted employers to enter the workers' premises
to inspect their operations, ostensibly to curb embezzlement. Unwin (1924, p. 35) concludes that by this time "there was
not much left of the independence of the small master, except the choice of hours."
27
Introducing factories did, of course, not eliminate embezzlement altogether but made it possible for employers
to set up safeguards against it. Robert Owen ([1857], 1920), pp. 79, 111 noted that when he started to work at the Lanark
mills in Scotland “theft was very general and carried on to an enormous and ruinous extent. To make sufficient profits I
adopted checks of various kinds to render theft impracticable ... [and] devised a plan by which losses would be at once
discovered.”
28
This problem will be recognized immediately as a standard multi-task principal agent problem analyzed by
Holmstrom and Milgrom (1991) who note that a problem for the firm is to allocate efforts and time of workers between their
various duties. If it is difficult to measure the performance of an agent in one activity, it makes less sense to produce strong
incentives for workers in another. Thus, the harder it was to monitor the way the employee treated the equipment and
unfinished products he was given, the lesser was the incentive to pay him a piece wage.
29
A formalization of the Alchian and Demsetz problem was presented in Holmstrom (1982) who pointed out that
what creates the need for a “monitor” is the fact that unobservable actions by workers lead to non-zero marginal products.
17
team production.30 In part this was due to the introduction of continuous flow production as in the case
of the large cotton spinning mills and the Portsmouth blockmaking factory, and in part because of a finer
and more closely integrated division of labor.31 Under continuous flow, the speed of the entire production
process was set by the plant manager and the interest in supervision and control of individual workers
became obvious, because in its absence the speed of production became equal to the speed of the
slowest worker.32 Above all, the new technology required larger amounts of fixed capital, and the joint
use by many workers of the same equipment makes the measurement of marginal contributions more
difficult. The movement to Factories was reinforced by consumer demand. Szostak (1991) points to
the growing desire by consumers in an integrated market to purchase a product of standardized quality.
Input monitoring became important, he argues, when consumers insisted on products of easily verifiable
quality. Workers had to conform to lower tolerance limits on the various dimensions of the final product.
This means that the employers had to worry about the variance of the final products not just because
a higher variance made the measurement of mean quality more costly, but because the variance entered
independently as a quality attribute.33
Labor Effort. Marglin (1974) revived a Marxist tradition by arguing, essentially, that factories emerged
when workers were placed under one roof in order to make them work longer hours than they would
30
Alchian and Demsetz themselves (p. 784) point out that technological development will expand the role of the
firm, and add, with some historical license, that “with the development of efficient central sources of power it became
economical to perform weaving in proximity to the power source and to engage in team production” and point out that
with the invention of steam, the sharing of power sources made team production more importance. They confuse “firm”
with “plant” (a putting-out merchant was clearly a “firm”) and get the history of weaving wrong ( factory weaving did not
come in to being with central power sources as much as with the solving of the complex mechanical problems of making
a functional power loom in the 1820s), yet their intuition about the rise of the factory is quite correct.
31
The famous Portsmouth blockmaking machines, devised by Maudslay together with Marc Brunel around 1801
to produce wooden gears and pulleys for the British Navy, were automatic and in their close coordination and fine division
of labor, resembled a modern mass-production process in which a labor force of ten workers produced a larger and far more
homogeneous output than the traditional technique that had employed more than ten times as many (Cooper, 1984).
32
Chapman, 1974, p. 470 has maintained that continuous flow was already typical of the early Arkwright-type
factories, but the cotton-spinning industry may have been atypical. Batch production was still the rule in the vast majority
of early factories and continuous flow processes became more widespread only after 1870.
33
Langlois (1995) has argued that as manufacturers produced for larger and larger markets and produced a more
and more standardized product, their fixed costs started involving specialized tools designed just for that such as jigs and
dies that make screws and other standardized parts. In other words, larger markets and standardized output made it
worthwhile to make Allyn Young’s famous hammer (which as he noted would be wasteful to make to hit a single nail).
18
have if left at home. Since the piece wage was less than the marginal revenue product, he maintained,
the more time workers put in, the higher the capitalist profit. This view is little more than a standard leftwing account according to which factories enabled employers to exercise more control over their workers
and to squeeze more profits out of them. In this interpretation, then, technological progress is not the
primum movens. Discipline and supervision in large factories in this view were not the means to adapt
to a new technological environment, but constituted the road to increased output and profits. Technological progress was a by-product of the intensification of social control. Interestingly enough, after it had
been effectively demolished (see especially Landes, 1986), this argument was rejuvenated by Clark
(1994). In a clever but ultimately inconclusive argument, Clark turns Marglin’s view on its head and
maintains that factory discipline was introduced to elicit more effort from workers lacking in self-control,
so that they would “force themselves” to work harder and earn higher wages.34 It might be added that
Clark’s argument only works when there is considerable fixed capital involved (since that allows the
capitalist to spread his capital costs over more output when workers work harder, thus enabling him to
pay them more) and insofar that the increase in fixed costs in manufacturing was due to new machinery
– thus technologically determined – Clark’s story too, boils down to a technological interpretation.35
The Division of Knowledge. Adam Smith famously believed that specialization and the division of labor
leads to economic progress through three separate processes: the growing familiarity of a worker with
the process he is assigned to; his ability to produce improvements on it once he is thoroughly familiar
with it; and the savings of time involved in moving from one task to another. The idea of the division of
labor proposed by Smith was further picked up by Charles Babbage who noted that specialization was
not only useful for the reasons laid out by Smith, but also because workers had different inherent skill
endowments and it would be wasteful for employees to carry out tasks for which they were overqualified.
34
In his paper, Clark foreshadowed some recent theoretical work by David Laibson (1997) and others following
a suggestion by Thomas Schelling (1992), which has re-introduced the issue of self-control and individual time-consistent
behavior in dynamic models to economists. These preferences do, indeed show why rational agents would voluntarily
restrict their choices. Much of that work has been directed at issues of saving, but there seems no reason why this idea
cannot be extended to labor supply.
35
A different interpretation of the need to discipline can be formulated in terms of a Grossman-Hart view of the
firm. In a normal situation, employees own no assets and yet have to be made to perform efficiently. Because it is far from
obvious that early nineteenth century workers could be made to respond to financial incentives, an element of coercion
in the form of harsh discipline (especially for child labor) seems a substitute for an efficient incentive structure.
19
An optimal matching of tasks to (exogenous) ability was a key to efficiency (Babbage, 1835, pp. 175-76;
Rosenberg, 1994, pp. 28-29).36
Whatever the case may be, the division of labor in and of itself does not explain the emergence
of factories. The domestic system lent itself well to a division of labor, including -- when necessary -- the
establishment of larger workshops away from homes where some stages (such as wool finishing) could
be carried out when the optimum scale made domestic production unpractical. The costs involved in
moving intermediate products from worker to worker were not insubstantial, but they have to be weighed
against the considerable costs of putting all workers under one roof. This ratio shifted increasingly in
favor of the factory system in the second half of the nineteenth century, when continuous flow processes
were introduced into more and more manufacturing process.
Even together, then, Smith and Babbage did not wholly explain the phenomenon of
specialization. The reason why firms needed increasingly internal specialization is because as time
advanced, there was more and more knowledge that was necessary to operate the best-practice
techniques in use. On the eve of the Industrial Revolution, it is worth recalling, modern chemistry did not
exist, physics was mostly confined to cosmology and optics, and most of engineering, metallurgy, and
farming (to say nothing of medicine) were closer to arts than to science. The vast majority of artisans
and domestic manufacturers (not to mention farmers) practiced their trades without worrying too much
about why the things they did actually worked.
It would thus be far-fetched to attribute the Industrial Revolution to “scientific progress.” But it
seems that economic historians have underestimated the intellectual roots of the Industrial Revolution.
In a recent paper (Mokyr, 2000), I have tried to explore these roots. In brief, I argue that each technique
has an epistemic base in natural knowledge, which is the minimum that has to be known about the
underlying natural phenomena for such a technique to be conceived and designed. It is important to
point out that there is a big difference between the epistemic basis necessary to generate a new
technique and that necessary to operate one. The latter is sometimes referred to in the literature as the
36
A somewhat different and original explanation of the division of labor is implied by Holmstrom and Milgrom
(1991) who point out that in a multi-task principal agent problem it may be optimal for an entrepreneur to make his workers
specialize to make sure that they allocate their time and effort between tasks optimally rather than overallocate them to easyto-monitor assignments.
20
“core competence” of the firm. In the decades that followed the initial introduction of a new technique,
it became possible in many industries to create user friendly techniques requiring little knowledge to
operate, even if they required a considerable knowledge to be invented. In the limit we could devise an
economy in which technology is designed by geniuses and operated by idiots, as Gavin Wright once
remarked. In the early stages of the Industrial Revolution, this was probably rare: machinery was
custom-made and not made of interchangeable parts, demanding in-house expertise for operation,
repairs, preventive maintenance, and so on.
Whatever the case may be, the era of the Industrial Revolution witnessed a huge expansion in
the knowledge base of the techniques in use. A great deal of engineering and technical knowledge had
been created and was available to the progressive and energetic entrepreneurs of the post-1815 period.
Access costs were crucial: much technical knowledge is self-referential: it is knowledge about knowledge.
But even if one knows that something is known, how costly is it to find out? Can such knowledge be
obtained or purchased? The expansion of the epistemic base of technology meant that in an increasing
number of industries efficient production required more knowledge than a single household could
possess. This was realized early on: in the 1806 report to Parliament on the woolen industry, the
commissioners noted that “it is obvious, that the little Master Manufacturers cannot afford, like the man
who possesses considerable capital, to try the experiments which are requisite, and incur the risks, and
even losses, which always occur, in inventing and perfecting new articles of manufacture, or in carrying
to a state of greater perfection articles already established... The Owner of a Factory, on the contrary,
being commonly possessed of a large capital and having all his workmen employed under his own
immediate superintendance may make experiments, hazard speculation ... may introduce new articles
and improve and perfect old ones.” (Parliamentary Papers, 1806, p. 12).
The fixed factor here is not just resources, but the capacity of people to learn and retain. When
the total amount of knowledge needed for production exceeds the normal ability of an individual to know,
specialization becomes inevitable. The advantages of specialization were compounded by differences
in mental endowment. In a specialized world of a division of knowledge, the smartest workers can be
assigned the most complex chunks of knowledge. As long as production was simple and could be
summarized in a finite number of rules of thumb, a single household could know all there was to know
and effectively serve as the unit of production with all the advantages thereof. But the Industrial
21
Revolution and the subsequent technological developments meant that after 1760 many of the
production process increasingly required a level of knowledge and a set of operating procedures that
went beyond the capability of the individual household.
This point was formalized and elaborated upon in a seminal paper by Becker and Murphy (1992),
which suggested a new interpretation of the role of the firm. Given the limitations on what each worker
can know, they maintain, the total knowledge that the firm has to possess is chopped up into
manageable bites, divided amongst the workers, and their actions are then coordinated by
management.37 In addition to Smith’s dictum about the division of labor being limited by the size of the
market, the division of labor is limited by the size of the knowledge set necessary to employ best-practice
techniques. The point is not just that each worker knows what she needs to know to carry out her task,
but that she becomes in charge of a subset of the total knowledge required so that others can ask her
when needed. This means that asymmetric information is not “a problem” for the firm but an essential
way for it to operate. Specialization in knowledge does not only “exacerbate the problem of asymmetric
information”but it demands it (Kim, 2000). Not everyone can and should know everything. The
organizational problem for the firm is to ensure that agents that possess knowledge, reveal if fully and
truthfully to those who need it. Inside a plant agents knew and could trust each other, and this turned
out an efficient way of sharing knowledge. Putting all workers under one roof ensures repeated interaction
and personal contact provides maximal bandwidth to maximize the chances that the information be
transmitted fully and reliably. As long as distance is a critical factor in information transmission, the
benefits and costs of proximity have to be traded against each other.
The model predicts that when the minimum core competence is small, plants can be small and
coincide with households; when it expands it will require either a sophisticated and efficient network for
the distribution of knowledge or a different set-up of the unit of production. In an age in which direct
contact was the main technique of sharing information, marginal access costs are minimized within a
single plant, especially when the exact description and formalization of the technical details of production
37
A similar point is made by Pavitt and Steinmueller (1999, pp. 15-16) in the context of the knowledge generating
activities in the firm (that is, R & D). They point out that uncertainty and much tacit knowledge require “physical and
organizational proximity” that guarantees efficient coordination of the knowledge-generating and the production and
marketing functions of the firm. The skills involved in this coordination are themselves tacit and hence some meetings and
personal contact remains important in industries that rely on a high degree of innovation, yet this does not mean that
outsourcing to individuals working normally from other locations would not be effective.
22
were more difficult than demonstration and emulation. Factories thus served as repository units for
technical knowledge and vastly reduced access costs to this knowledge for individual workers. The model
further predicts that when knowledge can be shared and trusted among people by means other than
personal contact (say, through electronic communication), firms may survive, but large plants may
become less necessary.
The replacement for the domestic system was the large-scale plant/firm which brought the
workers under one roof, made them specialize, and coordinated the exchange of knowledge between
them. In addition to unskilled laborers, such plants employed experts: engineers, mechanics, chemists,
foremen, and just dexterous, clever, employees who could fix things that were broken and knew which
tools was needed for each task. Often, of course, this expertise was supplied by the “master” or
entrepreneur himself. James Watt worked in Boulton’s plant in Soho and personally supervised the
production of engines. In an age in which there were few alternatives to the exchange of information, such
direct contact was inevitable if the firm was to practice a division of knowledge. Furthermore, as Babbage
already pointed out, because some of those in-house experts could service a large number of other
workers, it inevitably created further economies of scale.
The Becker-Murphy framework as well as the asymmetric information framework point to
centrality of the relative cost of moving knowledge relative to moving people. It was costly to move workers
from their homes to the factory, but even costlier to supervise, coordinate and instruct them at home.
These relative costs clearly are only one factor in determining the location of labor, but they demonstrate
the extent to which exogenous changes in information technology and transport technology affect the
place where work is carried out.
Moreover, knowledge has to be transmitted not only across space but also across time. The
reason is that like in all good evolutionary models, knowledge is carried by carriers who are subject to
wear and tear. Unless they have an ability to pass this knowledge on to new generations, it will go extinct.
The pre-Industrial economy had two parallel systems to accomplish this: from parent to child, and from
master to apprentice. Such a system will work well when the knowledge is relatively limited and does not
change much between generations, and when there were few gains from applying the knowledge in one
field to another. By 1750 these assumptions were beginning to be eroded in more and more industries,
and by 1850 they had become obsolete in many industries. The plant served as a unit that transmitted
23
this knowledge over time: new hires learned the trade “on the job” by direct contact with veteran workers,
observation and emulation. Hence the practice of learning through “migration” I noted above. With the
formalization and codification of much technical knowledge, this role has been eroded to some extent,
but as long as tacit knowledge remains important enough, its transmission over time will remain a main
function of the plant (Howells, 1996).38
The acceleration of technological progress placed the domestic workers at a disadvantage. As
new techniques were becoming available after their learning stage in the life cycle was completed, it would
be far more costly for them to keep up than it would be for a large plant. The diffusion and
implementation of new techniques to a group of workers in the same building was faster and cheaper
than if workers stayed in their homes, since this helped to avoid duplication and above all, workers taught
each other. Workers with a comparative advantage in learning (often negatively correlated with age) might
pick up new techniques first and help spread them. In an industry of household-sized, self-contained
cottages, such diffusion mechanisms would be more costly.39
It could be argued that much of the knowledge that firms relied upon was codifiable and could
be looked up in the ever-increasing stream of technical manuals, engineering textbooks, and
encyclopedias that became available during this period and could be accessed or purchased from
external sources (Mokyr, 2000). Moreover, inter-firm flows of knowledge obviously took this form. But
much of what the new technology required was uncodified or “tacit” knowledge that was hard to buy, sell,
or obtain from books and periodicals.40 Moreover, access to codified knowledge required uncodified
knowledge consisting just of knowing that it existed, where to find it, and the ability to read, understand
38
Pollard (1968, p. 124) notes the change in managerial and organizational requirements that accompanied
continuous technological change. He regards the improvements in management as “over and against” technical changes
and does not fully realize the direct causal connection between the two. And yet modern research establishes exactly that:
there was a strong and direct complementarity between organizational and technological change. See Geraghty (2000)
for an elaboration on how organizational change enhanced the benefits of technological change and vice versa.
39
In a putting-out context, keeping technological secrets was of course impossible and indeed some factories were
set up to keep industrial processes secret (Chapman, 1967, p. 39).
40
The original source on codified vs. tacit knowledge is Polanyi (1962). An enlightening application of the
concepts to economics is Cowan and Foray (1997) and Cowan, David and Foray (1999).
24
and apply it. These were all by and large tacit skills.41 Such tacit knowledge was costly to acquire as a
separate entity, and large plants could train or hire specialists who possessed it and thus were better
settings for easy access than individual households.
Modern economists in the traditions of evolutionary economics and organization theorists treat
the firm as a single unit that “knows things.”42 Firms have “corporate core competencies” and
“organizational practices.”43 The point I want to make turns this argument on its head: the optimal size
of the firm (or plant, to be accurate) is a function of the relative efficiency with which knowledge flows
inside a firm relative to between firms, and the total amount of knowledge necessary to run a bestpractice operation in a competitive world. For a given communications technology, the rapid growth of
knowledge necessary to use the newest techniques (let alone improve them) meant that household-sized
firms became impractical. All the same, the technological and informational trade-offs between different
forms of organization were sufficiently multi-dimensional to allow the survival and co-existence of very
different forms of organization. The large prototypical Chandlerian factory was just one of these forms.
Another is a cluster of much smaller firms working in close proximity exchanging knowledge through
informal cooperative channels (Piore and Sabel, 1984). As Sabel and Zeitlin (1985) and Scranton (1997)
have emphasized, the picture of mass production of standardized output produced by Chandler and
others ignores the many industries that needed the flexibility and agility of specialized production.44 Large
factories and domestic artisans were only extreme forms of industrial organization: in many parts of
Europe, such as Lyons, Sheffield, and the industrial districts of Northern Italy, complex networks are
41
This point is well-made by Cowan and Foray (1997) who point out that tacit knowledge is needed to access
codified knowledge and that in many ways the two are complements, not substitutes.
42
One of the most perceptive of these theorists, Paolo Saviotti, writes for example that “Firms scan the external
environment in order to detect ... possible pieces of external knowledge which are useful for their productive purposes.
When they find such useful pieces of knowledge, they have to internalize them... the capacity of firms to learn and internalize
knowledge depends on the firm’s previous knowledge.” (Saviotti, 1996, p. 175.) Firms have what he calls “knowledge bases”
which is the collective knowledge used by the organization.
43
Much of this very large literature is summarized ably in Pavitt and Steinmueller, 1999. Check Teece in JEBO
1994.
44
Some of these firms were quite large, others were medium and small. As late as 1923, Scranton shows, “specialty
production” employed only slightly fewer workers than “routinized” (mass) production. There is no evidence in Scranton’s
work that much of this specialty production operated anywhere but in plants and factories that were considerably larger
than households, but his work is an antidote to the view that in the late nineteenth century Chandlerian high “throughput”mass-production became the rule.
25
observed in which home-work and factories are mixed and combined in a variety of forms.
The large plant/firm in this set-up is thus a substitute for the incomplete markets in technical
knowledge.45 This is not to say that such markets did not exist at the time. Britain in the Industrial
Revolution had consulting engineers, instrument makers, machine-tool producers, and a variety of
independent inventors and mechanics of whom John Smeaton and Joseph Bramah were the most
famous, who could be and were hired to dispense advice. Engineering and other specialized expertise,
inevitably, were purchased by firms when in-house knowledge was inadequate. The way in which the
entrepreneurs of the time did this was either to hire specialists such as the consulting engineers working
for Boulton and Watt for a specific task, or to subcontract out work.46 One of the best examples of such
outside professional consultants were the famous British “coal-viewers” who not only advised coal mine
owners on the optimal location and structure of coal mines but also on the use of the Newcomen steam
pumps employed in mines in the eighteenth century (Pollard, 1968, p. 152-53). Civil engineers was a
term coined by John Smeaton, who spent much of his life “consulting” to a large number of customers
in need of technical advice. At first civil engineers were mixed up with mechanical engineers, but with the
proliferation of machinery and engines, independent mechanical engineers grew separate.47 All the same,
such consultants were of limited use not only because they possessed general knowledge when often
firm-specific knowledge was needed, but because of the issues of credibility and trust involved when hiring
expertise.
For many of the tasks at hand, then, this over-the-counter knowledge was not suitable. Technical
knowledge, then as now, combines the understanding of general relations and principles with local
problems, specific to an industry, to a product, and to a set of routines that a firm has adopted. The
45
The notion that the role of firms is to be above all a locus for specific and tacit knowledge has been proposed
by many writers in the so-called neo-Schumpeterian school. For examples, see Saviotti (1996); Antonelli (1999);
Nooteboom (1999).
46
The mechanics trained by Boulton and Watt at Soho were sought all over Britain for their expertise.
Apprenticeship there was “a recommendation to any firm” and only they knew how to use the special Soho slide rule
(Pollard, 1968, p. 207).
47
The list of great mechanical engineers after 1815 includes some of the inventors that sustained the technological
momentum of the Industrial Revolution: William Murdock, one of the inventors of gaslighting; Richard Roberts, the
miraculously gifted inventor of the self-actor; Arthur Woolf, the inventor of the compound steam engine; Henry Maudslay,
the first to apply mass production to the production of wooden gears and pulleys for the sailing vessels of the British navy,
and the Brunels, shipbuilders and engineers.
26
more specific and local these technical routines were, and the more tacit the knowledge was, the more
production had to rely on an in-house supply of expertise. The Becker-Murphy idea of knowledge-pooling
becomes increasingly common. Even in services, this gradually became more common: physicians were
attracted to hospitals where expertise could be pooled despite the relatively high codifiability of much of
medical knowledge. Lawyers, architects, and teachers formed larger units in part for the same purpose,
or created professional associations and cooperatives that did the same.
Beyond the Industrial Revolution.
In the decades the followed the Industrial Revolution, the process that sprouted in the years after
1760 came to its full fruition. As noted earlier, the concentration of workers under one roof depends on
the ratios of costs and benefits of moving information relative to that of moving people. Before 1850,
these costs changed little, and the emergence of the factory as described above was due primarily to
changes in the benefits due to changes in the production technology. While these changes continued at
an accelerated rate during the so-called second Industrial Revolution after 1860 or so, there were some
major developments in the technology of moving people and information. The age saw some
breakthroughs in communication and information technology: the telegraph and later the telephone, as
well as a variety of management devices that facilitated the flow of information inside the firms, such as
pneumatic tubes, mimeograph machines, public address systems, and typewriters.48 All the same the
preponderance of productivity gains were in the movement of people: trains, streetcars, bicycles and
internal-combustion cars clearly reduced the costs of moving people relative to moving information.
Production technology continued to favor large units. The Chandlerian firm, as it is often thought
of, came to the fore in the closing decades of the nineteenth century and technical factors were
paramount in its emergence. Among these factors were the development of railroads which became not
only the standard model for the next generation of large firms, but also created ever larger markets for
standardized products. In many other industries associated with the second Industrial Revolution such
48
In fact, as Lamoureaux, Raff, and Temin argue, the improvements in communications before 1914 made it
possible for firms to distribute their output in more remote areas and exploit economies of scale and speed by concentrating
production in large plants. This essentially Chandlerian interpretation abstracts from the complex relationship between
mass production and the flexible specialization of their suppliers or other firms catering to more specialized needs.
27
as steel, transportation, and chemicals, small and household-sized plants were simply impossible.
Moreover, the growing modularization of manufacturing, involving the mass production of products based
on interchangeable parts, and the use of continuous flow production on assembly lines made the largescale production plant, whether identical to the firm or not, inevitable in many industries.
Simple technological factors increasing minimum efficient scale, however, are not the entire story.
For one thing, some technological advances reduced optimal size or at least flattened the cost curves
considerably. The most important of these was electricity, which made power supply less bulky and
allowed small, household-sized firms access to power on the same terms (disregarding quantity
discounts) as their large scale competitors. But other inventions pointed in the same direction. In
transportation, the growing optimal size of ships and the obvious scale economies of railroads have to
be weighed against the democratization of transportation through bicycles and cars which allowed
household sized producers to sell transport services.
The transition was thus more gradual and complex than mass-production enthusiasts have
allowed for. Recent work on firm size during the second Industrial Revolution has noted that very smallscale business still had considerable life in it until deep into the nineteenth century.49 The statistical
difficulty that mars this debate is that most industrial and population censuses did not count people
working at home or in little workshops attached to it (what the French census, the exception in this case,
called isolés). The only country that reported the number of such workers with accuracy was France. The
1906 French census estimates that in manufacturing, about 33 percent of the manufacturing labor force
in France worked in isolation, which to a large extent must have been in workers’ homes.50 The German
49
The British census of 1851 demonstrates that the household-sized firm was far from gone: of the total number
of masters (129,002) who made a return, over half (66,497) employed five men or less, of which 41,732 employed nobody
but themselves. The 1871 shows very similar returns. Moreover, these returns were incomplete and without question
understated the number of very small and one-person firms (Musson, 1978, p. 68).
50
A summary of the proportion of manufacturing workers by industry in France in 1906 is provided below
Industry
Home-workers (1000's)
Workers away from home
Percentage home
workers
Food Processing
37.2
293
11.3
Chemicals
1.4
116.9
1.2
Rubber and paper
2.6
78.1
3.3
28
Industrial census of 1895 reported a total of 1.88 million workers who worked by themselves, out of a
total “trade and industry” (gewerbe) employment of 10.54 million (17.8 percent) and a manufacturing
employment of 7. 52 million or 25 percent.51
Undercounting and inconsistent definitions by statistical services have led to considerable
confusion on the average size of firms in the industrialized parts of Western Europe. This confusion was
sorted out by Kinghorn and Nye (1996) who note that once we correct for these omissions, Germany’s
reputation as a nation of giant, technologically progressive plants is shown to be undeserved. Although
their adjustments for these omitted firms are based on some carefully spelled-out assumptions, they are
the best estimates we have. They compute that in the decade before World War I, 95 percent of all
German industrial establishments still employed 1-5 workers and that these firms employed 67 percent
of the work force. In the United States, the proportion of such firms was smaller (91 percent) and they
Printing
5.2
91.1
5.4
Textiles
162.4
686.1
19.1
Apparel making
890
441.8
66.8
Straw and baskets
13.6
19.6
41.0
Glass and pottery
3.1
153.1
2.0
Stone-cutting
12.9
24.7
34.3
Leather
122.2
155.3
44.0
Wood and Carpentry
200.5
361.6
35.7
Iron and Steel
0
73.6
0
Metalwork
93.7
552.5
14.5
Fine metals and Jewelry
4.5
23.9
15.8
Total
1,550.0
3,071.5
33.5
Source: France (1910), pp. 188-193. The computations refer to workers “travaillant isolément” and those in firms
employing more than one worker, and leave out the category of chefs d’établissement. This tends to understate the number
of homeworkers, since many of those “bosses” were small-time artisans employing apprentices or servants.
51
These numbers reflect probably serious undercounting. More detailed data for Baden show that one worker in
six worked in plants in which there was only one worker present. I am indebted to Dr. Joerg Baten of the University of
Munich for making these data available.
29
employed 33 percent of the labor force.52 Much like what I am arguing here, Kinghorn and Nye conclude
that “the size of an enterprise is a response not only to the demands of a narrowly defined production
technology but also to organizational considerations.” Yet such “organizational considerations,” too, are
clearly a function of technology, if not the production technology of the firm itself, then the technology it
uses for management to communicate with workers, with outside suppliers and customers, and workers
to communicate with each other.
Yet as I argued before, the changes in the cost of moving people about set the numerator of the
ratio of moving people vs. moving knowledge. As a result, between 1850 and 1914, the concentration of
workers in large factories, department stores, large offices, and similar “mills” continued apace.
A Contemporary Perspective
A recent heading in USA Today (July 5, 2000, B-1) states that “Many Companies [are] Kicking
the Bricks-and-Mortar Habit” and proceeded to describe a list of firms where staffers work from their
homes and meet only a few times a year. Conference calls, email, and the internet have begun to replace
the water cooler and the meeting room, and the comfort of the living room in threatening the corporate
cubicle.53 Cairncross, in her sensible and informed book (1997, p. 234), declares that “the falling price
of communications will affect where people work and live. The old demarcation between work and home
will evaporate.” The term “tele-cottages” (coined by futurist Alvin Toffler in 1980) which has cropped up
in describing this phenomenon is particularly apt, because it clearly implies the historical connection to
a pre-1750 past.54 What has happened in recent years is that the relation between distance and the cost
of transmitting information has weakened. This change is not just due to one factor: the internet is only
52
The French census of 1906 carries out a similar exercise, and compares average firm size between different
countries.
53
Lamoureaux, Raff, and Temin (2000, p. 46) point out that the internet’s impact on specific coordination
mechanisms will be profound, but they focus on its role in goods markets, not the labor markets or communications that
involve the exchange of technological as opposed to commercial information.
54
The argument I am making here about Factories parallels the argument made about the future of cities.Gaspar
and Glaeser (1998) and Mokhtarian (2000) point out that face-to-face communications are in many case a complement
to long-distance contact, and that cities may well survive modern information technology. I should add, perhaps
unnecessarily, that even though the Industrial Revolution set into motion an unprecedented urbanization movement, large
urban concentrations of course predate the rise of the Factory.
30
one factor in this story; the sharp decline in the cost of long-distance phones and the explosion in the use
of cellular networks is another.
The notion that “distance is dead” is of course not to be taken literally. Even if people work at
home, physical goods still have to be moved and certain services still need to be provided in loco,
although technology will determine to what extent “virtual” activities will replace physical presence. It is
far from clear that the sharp decline in communications and information-processing costs reduce or
increase the economies of agglomeration. Evidence for the decline of the economies of agglomeration
due to the internet and lower phone rates so far is very mixed. In a global sense, the assumption that
travel and telecommunication are substitutes seems at least questionable (Mokhtarian and Salomon,
2000) and at some level they are obviously complements.55 Moreover, travel has a high income elasticity
and as new technology generates growth, the demand for travel is likely to increase. There is hence some
justified skepticism whether telecommuting is the panacea for traffic congestion (Mokhtarian, 1997, 1998,
2000). As Couclelis (2000) has argued, the rapid improvements in information processing have led to
a fragmentation of activity, in which work is increasingly carried out in smaller time units, interspersed
with leisure activity and at times multi-tasked with it.
All the same, much work will be capable of being performed outside the rigid confines of the
workplace. The interest in telecommuting and working at home is not new. Kraut (1989) describes some
of its advantages and possible drawbacks before the appearance of the Internet.56 The “factory” as a
system is in retreat not only as a central location where people have physically to go to, but also as a
time-organizing institution in which work begins and ends at given times and the lines between leisure and
labor are firmly drawn. Instead, work is dispersed over space as well as time, allowing workers to
calibrate their trade-offs more precisely. The welfare implications of homework are the mirror image of
the costs of the factory system: less commuting, more flexibility in the leisure-work trade-off, and the
55
As Mokhtarian and Salomon point out, the cellular phone is by construction a complement to human travel.
56
Kraut’s pessimism about the future of the option to work from home was based on his assumption that firms
and organizations need to coordinate work and thus require co-presence, and that home based employment is largely to
be found in occupations where the need for such coordination is low. He felt that such “routine” jobs are quite rare, and
did not address the possibility that information technology might make co-presence unnecessary for a large number of
other jobs. Clearly the sharp decline in communications costs and quality was not anticipated even by experts.
31
ability to combine work with household-services production.57 For many workers the freedom to design
and control the parameters of their physical work space may be equally important.58 The direction
technological progress has taken in the past twenty five years should make a partial return to householdproduction thus quite logical. For one thing, the relative costs of sending and receiving information vs.
the costs of moving people have fallen sharply. The full costs of commuting (including time) have not
declined. City and suburban highways are about as congested as they were two decades ago and public
transportation has not improved substantially. To be sure, some improvements have made the
commutes more pleasurable (e.g. better car stereos and walkmen, airconditioned cars) or more
productive (through cell phones and laptop computers). Yet on the whole this entire sector has shown
comparatively little technological progress. On the other hand, the ability to store, manipulate, and
transmit information keeps expanding at a dazzling rate, and the connections between private homes and
other homes and businesses have improved in quality and speed as dramatically as their price has
plummeted. Ever faster and cheaper access to huge stores of knowledge has shown little evidence so far
of diminishing returns. In some sense, a worker whose work consists largely of reading a computer
monitor and interacting with it, could be located practically anywhere. At the same time, the large
number of married women and single head-of-households in the formal labor force makes the
opportunity costs in terms of housework jointly produced with income particularly high.
A large and rapidly growing literature on telecommuting discusses the prospects of this
movement taking hold and it seems a reasonable speculation that the pendulum of the “unit of
production,” after two centuries, is slowly swinging in the other direction. Exact numbers are hard to
come by, and estimates differ from source to source. The 1990 census reported that 3.4 million workers
aged 16 and above worked “only or mostly at home” (Russell, 1996). In 1997, it was estimated that the
“number of telecommuters” in the US was about 11 million.59 Recent estimates put the number of U.S.
57
In this respect, however, there is a profound asymmetry with the demographic conditions in the nineteenth
century, when single-headed families with small children were rare.
58
One telecommuter reports that she has just “created the right atmosphere for herself” in her home office, with
the TV on at a low volume so that it feels as if there are people in the room with her. New York Times, Nov. 2, 2000, p. D-8.
59
The estimate was based on a survey commissioned by a New York market research company FIND/SVP, cited by
“Telecommute America” a website maintained by AT&T. This figure is also quoted by McCune, 1998. A recent estimate of
the International Telework Association and Council reported that 16.5 million (12 percent of the labor force) now work at
32
based employees who were commuting at some time in 1999 at 19.6 million, but far fewer actually
telecommuted on each given day.60 In addition, there are 21.4 self-employed homeworkers (Miller, 2000).
The distinction between telecommuters and independent contractors is getting rather murky, and with
the growth of a just-in-time labor force, statistical estimates of the two will become hard to interpret. For
my present purposes what matters, above all, is where workers spend their time at work. Recent survey
data clearly suggest that all over the industrialized world, teleworking is catching on.61
Just as the Industrial Revolution did not quite create factories de novo but turned them from a
rarity into the normal way in which production was carried out, it seems clear that the movement away
from “factory-settings” will eventually run into diminishing return and that the economy will remain a
mixture of work at home and work away from home. Certain industries and services, from food
processing to dental care, will inevitably require a physical presence. But the weights will change
significantly, and such a transformation, much like the movement in the other direction two centuries ago,
will be largely technologically-driven, depending both on the production technology itself and the
information technology used to communicate with them and monitor them.
The welfare implications of the decline of the Factory go beyond just computing the time-cost of
commuting and concerns the way we define input and output, efficiency and productivity. The
commuting costs in terms of time alone in the US nowadays is estimated at about 30 billion person
hours at an estimated cost of $320 billion. The additional costs in terms of resources and environmental
costs are at least as large. The inefficient utilization of space, pointed out by Cairncross in the quote on
top of this paper is another cost. Needless to say, there is little evidence to date that any of these costs
home at least one day a month and 9.3 million of these worked at least one full day at home. Cf.
http://www.telecommute.org/twa2000/ research _results_key.shtml
60
Khaifa and Davidson (2000). Simulations carried out by Mokhtarian (1998) suggests that 6.1 per cent of the
workforce may be currently telecommuting, with 1.5 per cent doing so on any given day. More recently, Mokhtarian has
put the number of telecommuters at about 8 percent not including independent home-based businesses (Professor Patricia
Mokhtarian, personal communication). More definitive figures will have to await the results of the 2000 census as well as
a sensible definition of what exactly is being counted.
61
The leader in teleworking appears to be Finland with 10.8 percent of its labor force telecommuting at least once
a weak, followed by the Netherlands with 8.2 percent.
See http://www.telecommute.org/twa2000/ research
_results_key.shtml. According to a recent estimate for Britain, 1.5 million workers now define themselves as “technologydependent homeworkers,” up from 1.2 million a year ago, almost 5.5 percent of the workforce. See http://www.analytica.dial. pipex.com/twstats00
33
have been reduced. All we know is that in the century and a half after 1750, these costs were gradually
imposed on industrializing economies. They dwarf, of course, compared to the enormous gains made
in income per capita, but that is not to say that if these costs were reduced rather quickly, they should
not be counted as gains.
Whether they are large or small, these costs should be included in our national income accounts,
but they rarely are. The purchases of transportation services needed for getting to work are treated as
consumption. Commuting time does not enter into GNP calculations but is treated as leisure (and thus
added nowhere).From a welfare point of view this is mildly absurd, and although economists have long
recognized this, the treatment of these items in our national accounts remains an open issue. A considerable amount of time spent on “leisure” is nothing of the sort but is spent as an intermediary cost
toward production or consumption. While NI accounting does not actually subtract these costs from
output, there can be little doubt that in principle it should do so, to preserve the notion that intermediary
inputs should be subtracted because aggregate output is a net measure.62 The new-economy pessimists
who fail to see much evidence of a gain in productivity should keep in mind that the numerator of all productivity measures fails to capture some of the most important effects of the new technology.63 In short,
commuting – much like shopping – is a “friction” that drives a wedge between total output as a measure
of effort and as a measure of welfare. Hence, a sharp increase in telecommuting and telecottaging
would have clear-cut welfare effects but would appear nowhere directly in our national accounts.
To be sure, telecommuting is still a long way off as an economy-wide phenomenon, and many
of the people who can work from home do not do so all the time. Predictions on how many people will
be telecommuting in the future have a very wide range and critically depend on assumptions about
62
Kuznets (1971, pp. 7-8) already pointed out that the changing boundary between the costs of producing
income and that income itself impart an upward bias on the long-term series of national product as measures of economic
well-being.
63
This particular aspect of Information and Communications technology is often overlooked by the new-economyskeptics such as R.J. Gordon (2000a, 2000b) who maintains that this technology is less dramatic than the great
breakthroughs in steel, electricity, the telegraph, and indoor plumbing of the late nineteenth century. Yet the computerized
access to large stores of useful knowledge and the ability to observe, coordinate, and monitor production activities taking
place far away can restore the home as a location of work, with all the concomitant social and economic ramifications.
34
changes in the costs and efficacy of data transmission.64 Changing technology will not necessarily
eliminate the workplace as an institution, but will make commuting to work increasingly optional and
part-time. The unbundling of “going to work” from “working” is unambiguously welfare-improving: it will
separate those whose net marginal utility from going to work exceed the costs from others who commute
out of necessity.65 It could be argued that the factory or office provides what one might call a “tavern
effect.” The medieval tavern and the modern pub provided the social institution in which people who
worked apart got together and interacted. Maybe the last thing an economy in which loneliness is already
a national affliction, and in which people, in Robert Putnam’s term are “bowling alone” is to get rid of the
workplace, with its watercoolers and cafetaria to compensate for the cubicles. The simple response to
that is that people in need of social interaction can still arrange to meet for lunches or conversations at
places of their choice, in which they control the timing and place. Community life has not done well in
America in the second half of the twentieth century, but perhaps the reason is in part that community life
and the workplace are substitutes, competing for the same time and serving similar needs. If the
workplace and the commute were to claim less time and effort, people might re-invent the social
institutions we associate with life before the Industrial Revolution as well as create entirely new forms of
social interaction, as witnessed by the growth of email pals and internet chatrooms.
Most scholars looking into the issue agree that there is considerable heterogeneity amongst
workers, and by allowing them to sort themselves according to their preferences, aggregate welfare must
increase. In addition, workers can, of course, mix: they go to the office on odd hours, avoid rush-hour
traffic and bad weather conditions, stay home to attend a domestic need, and so on. Finally, to repeat,
some level of multi-tasking is feasible when working at home. Baby-sitting and cooking are two activities
that can be thought off as compatible with simultaneous work but the advantages of such jointness
should not be overstated and many employers of telecommuters demand that small children be placed
64
Mokhtarian (1998) decomposes the proportion of telecommuters the intersection of those whose jobs are
amenable to telecommuting, those who prefer to work at home, and who are not prevented by inertia or fear. Over time,
however, these proportions cannot but go up. Not only that more and more workers will end up in the “information sector,”
but more and more of these jobs become sufficiently integrated with information technology to raise the proportion of jobs
that can be done from home.
65
As Cairncross (1997, p. 237) predicts, the office will become a “club” where people congregate for networking
and gossip, where firms motivate workers and embue them with loyalty to the firm, much like the early capitalists, only doing
so with the help of health clubs and “retreats” rather than religious and moralistic preaching.
35
in child care. A reasonable question to pose is whether the total full output of a worker watching a child
is less or more than a worker away from home concentrating fully, and whether employers can adjust
their payments for the reduced but still positive productivity of a mother. Switching to some kind of piece
wage might resolve this, much as it did before the Industrial Revolution. An increase in flexibility of hours
away from home is probably as important for parents and home-owners as the actual numbers (Humble
et al, 1995). An increase in the technological opportunity to telecommute will thus allow an increase in
housework at little or no costs in terms of “real” output. Again, however, our convention of not including
housework in our measures of National Income means that any such change will be welfare-improving
without registering in our national income accounts.
The degree to which a post-industrial economy will return to a home-production economy, much
like the way we arrived there, will be determined by technology. It seems natural to say that some jobs
lend themselves to telecommuting and others do not (Handy and Mokhtarian, 1996). But that is conditional on the continuous progress of technology, especially on the supply of bandwidth. If current trends
continue, it is likely that few jobs will be immune from radical changes in location and the geography of
labor supply. This is not to say that face-to-face contact will disappear. If communications techniques
can be devised which provide a “virtual meeting” of acceptable quality, location may become
indeterminate. Until then, just as the emergence of the factory system in its early days produced a “mixed
system” in which a single firm employed both factory workers and domestic workers, thus our economy
might find such a combination attractive, perhaps through workers who work at home 3 days a week and
go into the office for the other two.
How do the four causal roots of the emergence of the factory discussed above perform in
analyzing the impact of modern technology on the future of the workplace? Economies of scale at the
plant size have not been eliminated, but due to increasing automation, robotization, and the substitution
of capital for labor, fewer and fewer workers are employed in manufacturing, and the remaining are
increasingly monitoring and controlling production through automated processes. Some scale effects
are weakened by modern information technology: inventories can be kept at lower levels, and the
advantages of mainframe computers, once the sole prerogative of large firms, have melted. While it
seems unlikely that wholly robotized factories, supervised by remote monitors are in our near future, the
36
number of workers whose physical presence on the shopfloor is required has been declining.66 For
services, a similar phenomenon becomes increasingly visible on the horizon. The twentieth century
witnessed the demise of the household-sized Mom-and-Pop corner stores, to be replaced by large-scale
department and specialty stores. The current trend toward e-tailing may well encounter some teething
problems, but if it continues, there is little in the industry outside warehousing and shipping that cannot
be outsourced to independent employees working from their homes. The same holds true for banks, law
firms, insurance companies, and higher education.
The monitoring of effort put in by workers is trickier. The new technology will require one of two
things: the ability of firms to monitor output, or when that is not feasible to be able in some way to
observe what the worker does even if she is not in the same location (say, through remote closed-circuit
digital cameras). Improved information technology should make measuring output easier and thus re-institute piece wages (“tele-piece-rates”), that is, subcontracting and payment per project. The ability of
employers to monitor remote workers by electronic means may help solve other monitoring problems.
Thus the employer can observe from a distance how many hours a worker has been online, which
activities were carried out, and how the work has been performed. This will make it possible for
employers to pay a time wage to domestic workers if necessary, removing one of the most potent
reasons for factory-settings. Modern information technology is thus a large step toward reducing the
information and transaction costs that made “firms” necessary in the classic Coasian formulation. In
other words, the concept of a principal-agent problem requires asymmetrical information, assuming
information technology to be given. Insofar as modern information technology “symmetrizes” the
distribution of knowledge inside the firm, it may make the organizational structures devised to cope with
asymmetrical knowledge less necessary.
The Marglin-Clark view of factories regards them as places where workers are controlled and dis-
66
Pavitt and Steinmueller discuss the options of “informatizing the factory” which must eventually spell the decline
of the importance of distance there as well. The use of so-called intelligent agents that control robotized operations may
sharply reduce the number of workers present on the shopfloor. See “Thinking Machines,” Business Week, Aug. 7, 2000,
pp.78-86. An example is VEC (Virtual Engineering Composites) which allows the manufacturing of molded products
through internet remote control. This technology allows the production of virtually any molded product anywhere with a
minimum of labor present. See “The Revolution in a Box,”Time July 31, 2000, p. 30. Another example is a new tire-making
technology introduced by Pirelli known as MIRS (Modular Integrated Robotized System) in which 125,000 tires are
produced a year by an automated system monitored and run by three white collared employees behind their computers
(Le Monde, July 15, 2000, p. 13).
37
ciplined so as to increase their work-effort and productivity. It seems likely that in the twenty-first century
such problems of motivation will be less of a problem because the conditioning that makes workers selfmotivated is provided through the education system. This will not work for all, but the firms will have to
learn to sort workers into those who can be relied upon to work hard enough in a home setting.67 What
little anecdotal evidence there is points uniformly to an increase in productivity resulting from telecommuting.68 It is hard to know what such increases reflect precisely. Some of it must be simply selection
bias: the workers most likely to benefit from telecommuting should be expected to be the first to switch.
Other effects may be a reduction of fatigue and tension caused by commutes or fewer distractions by
fellow workers. More detailed information about relevant variables such as changes in absenteeism and
turnover rates is unavailable. All the same, even if it turns out that productivity and related measures are
not much improved by a change in location, the increase in total social welfare due to a reduction in
friction costs is enough to make it significant, to say nothing of non-pecuniary aspects of work.69
Finally, the function of the plant or office as a unit in which knowledge is divided and shared has
been widely discussed in the business literature.70 It seems plausible that if employees mostly communicate with each other electronically anyway, there may be little point in making them drive to work and
putting them in little cubicles next to each other. But things are not quite that easy. For one thing, in
addition to ease of access, proximity in a plant or office created personal familiarity and thus conditions
of trust and believability. There is always a role to body language, intonation, and general demeanor in
67
McCune (1998) argues that a home office tends to reinforce an employees tendencies: it will make a workaholic
labor harder and longer and give a procrastinator ample opportunity to delay work. Some firms have recently taken a more
skeptical view of telecommuting “believing that telecommuting causes resentment among office-bound colleagues and
weakens corporate loyalty.”
See Wall Street Journal Oct. 31, 2000.
68
The estimates tend to be all over the map. At Nortel Networks, productivity increases were estimated at 10%
(Strickland, 1999). Humble et al (1995) report a range of 10-200 percent with the mean at 30 percent which is consistent
with the survey used by DuBrin and Barnard (1993). McCune (1998) reports productivity increases ranging from 4 to 25
percent. All these figures are based on small samples and suffer from poor controls and selection biases.
69
The Nortel survey reports that 90 percent of work-from-home employees reported “increased job satisfaction”
and 73 percent “decreased stress levels” (McCune, 1998).
70
Hudson (1998) makes this point clearly: “Telecommunications networks now link manufacturers with assembly
plants, designers with factories, engineers with hardware vendors, suppliers with retailers, retailers with customers. No longer
is it necessary to have all the expertise in house.”
38
human communications.71 More important, with the continuing expansion of the epistemic base of most
techniques, the amount of knowledge to which workers need access is increasing. Even with vastly improved communications, for many purposes direct personal contact with in-house experts may still be
necessary. All the same, while much of our ICT revolution was born in industrial districts such as Silicone
valleys, the next stage may be the virtual industrial district, a network of workers all over the globe.
The amount of personal contact relative to long-distance communications depends on the ratio
of codified to uncodified (tacit) knowledge. If the new information is increasing codified, as Cowan and
Foray (1997) suggest, it may well be the case that access through impersonal connections may render
much personal physical presence unnecessary. It is true, of course, that in order to access codified
knowledge, we need the codebook, and the knowledge of the code itself may be largely tacit. Improved
access to technological knowledge may make it advantageous to produce more widely accessible
codebooks (Cowan, David, and Foray, 1999). But modern communications and search engines not
only permit quick and easy access to codified information, it also makes it easier for agents to locate and
hire people who possess the tacit knowledge that interprets the codified knowledge. Such people do not
have to be employed by the firm, and indeed are often hired as subcontractors and consultants.
Moreover, firms that need to produce something that requires access to specialized knowledge it does
not possess, tend to subcontract out the whole stage of the production to specialists. Such vertical
disintegration, if driven to extremes, may jeopardize the entire notion of a “firm” as we understand it. To
some extent, firms may be replaced by virtual “teams,” assembled on an ad hoc basis for specific
projects. This will require some kind of reputation-maintaining technology, which is precisely what the
internet provides.
Does the introduction of modern ICT enhance the competitiveness of the economy and the
diffusion of new techniques? The return to household-plants and even household-firms will not mean
a return to a world of peasants and artisans with loose selection standards. Modern ICT will make it quite
easy to establish and lose a reputation for expertise and reliability. Establishing standards for veracity will
be one of the challenges of the world of cheap access to knowledge. In such a world, however, the image
of a pre-1750 household-producer muddling on without continuously keeping up with best-practice
71
In the late nineteenth and early twentieth century it was believed, similarly, that the telephone could replace
face-to-face meetings and that telecommunications would reduce transit congestion (Mokhtarian, 1997).
39
techniques seems remote. More worrisome is how society will handle those individuals who cannot or
will not stay up-to-date.
To sum up, in recent years, modern communications and information technology are weakening
many of the advantages that the “factory” has had over the household. With increased female
participation in the labor force and little improvement in commuting technology, the relative costs of
factories vs. home production have gone up. It is hard to make predictions about the trend, especially
given how little hard information we have about the current state of telecommuting.72 The changeover will
be slow, much like the full establishment of the factory was and for much the same reason: a major
social constraint is that the baby-boom generation grew up using typewriters, telephones, and cars to
commute to work and will have a difficult time to fully change its lifestyle.73 It will have to await workers
who grew up in hard-wired homes, and for whom the internet comes naturally to accept fully the new
lifestyle implied. Technology, now as in the past, opens doors; it does not force society to walk through
them. It seems, however, that on the whole the changes may mean a social improvement quite
comparable in its impact on society as the rise of the factory did in the eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries. The difference is that in modern age, a sorting principle will be operational: more and more
of those workers that want to work at home will be able to, whereas those who prefer to work in
centralized settings, or who would not be as productive at home for one reason or another, will be able
to maintain the status quo. This is an option the handloom weavers, the frame knitters and the
nailmakers of the nineteenth century never had.
References
Alchian, A. and Demsetz, H. 1972. “Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization.
American Economic Review, Vol. 77, pp. 388-401.
Antonelli, Cristiano. 1999. “The Evolution of the Industrial Organization of the Production of Knowledge.”
Cambridge Journal of Economics, Vol. 23: 243-260.
72
It might be worthwhile to cite the 1806 British Committee which predicted confidently that it was their “decided
opinion that the apprehensions entertained of [the Domestic System] being rooted out by the Factory system are, at present
at least, wholly without foundation” (Parliamentary Papers, 1806, p. 10).
73
Andrew Ure’s words in 1835 (p. 15) resonate with the modern experience: It was found "nearly impossible to
convert persons past the age of puberty, whether drawn from rural or from handicraft occupations, into useful factory
hands."
40
Ashton, T.S. 1968. Iron and Steel in the Industrial Revolution. 4th ed., Manchester: Manchester
University Press (orig. published in 1924).
Babbage, Charles. 1835. On the Economy of Machinery and Manufactures. Repr. ed., Fairfield, NJ.,
Aug. Kelley.
Becker; Gary S. and Kevin M. Murphy. 1992. The division of labor, coordination costs, and knowledge.
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107: 1137-1161.
Berg, Maxine. 1994a. "Factories, Workshops, and Industrial Organization" In Roderick Floud and D.N.
McCloskey, eds., The Economic History of Britain since 1700, 2nd ed., Vol. I, pp. 123-50.
Berg, Maxine. 1994b. The Age of Manufactures. London: Fontana Press. second rev. edition, London:
Routledge.
Brown, John C. 1990. “The Condition of England and the Standard of Living: Cotton Textiles in the
Northwest, 1806-1850.” Journal of Economic History 50:591-615.
Cairncross, Frances. 1997. The Death of Distance: How the Communications Revolution will change
our Lives. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Chapman, Stanley D. 1967. The Early Factory Masters. Newton Abbot: David and Charles.
Chapman, Stanley D. 1974. “The Textile Factory Before Arkwright: A Typology of Factory Development,”
Business History Review, Vol. 48, No. 4, pp. 451-478.
Clark, Gregory. 1994. “Factory Discipline.” Journal of Economic History 54: 128-163.
Cohen, Jon S. 1981. “Managers and Machinery: An Analysis of the Rise of Factory Production.”
Australian Economic Papers 20:24-41.
Cooper, Carolyn. 1984. "The Portsmouth System of Manufacture." Technology and Culture Vol. 25
(April), pp. 182-225.
Couclelis, Helen. 2000. "From Sustainable Transportation to Sustainable Accessibility: Can we avoid
a new ‘tragedy of the commons’?" In Information, Place, and Cyberspace: Issues in Accessibility, eds.
Donald Janelle and David Hodge. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Cowan, Robin and Foray, Dominique. 1997. “The Economics of Codification and the Diffusion of
Knowledge,” Industrial and Corporate Change Vol. 6, No. 3 (Sept), pp. 595-622.
Cowan, Robin, David, Paul A., and Foray, Dominique. 1999. “The Explicit Economics of Knowledge
Codification and Tacitness.” Unpublished, presented at the 3 rd TIPIK Workshop, Strasbourg, April 1999.
Crouzet, François.1985. The First Industrialists: The Problems of Origins. Cambridge: Cambridge
41
University Press.
DuBrin, Andrew J. and Barnard, Janet C. 1993. “What Telecommuters like and dislike about their Jobs,”
Business Forum (Summer), pp. 13-17.
Epstein, S.R. 1998. “Craft Guilds, Apprenticeships, and Technological Change in Pre-industrial Europe.”
Journal of Economic History (Sept.) pp. 684-713.
Feinstein, Charles. 1998. “Pessimism Perpetuated: Real Wages and the Standard of living in Britain
during and after the Industrial Revolution,” Journal of Economic History (Sept.) pp. 625-58.
Flinn, Michael W. 1962. Men of Iron: The Crowleys in the Early Iron Industry. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
France, 1910. Ministère du Travail et de la Prévoyance Sociale, Statistique générale de la France,
Resultats Statistiques du Recensement général de la Population effectué le 4 Mars, 1906. Paris:
Imprimerie Nationale.
Galor, Oded and Moav, Omer. 2000.”Das Human Kapital.” Unpublished working paper, Hebrew
University of Jerusalem.
Gaspar, Jess and Glaeser, Edward L. 1998. “Information Technology and the Future of Cities.” Journal
of Urban Economics Vol. 43, pp. 136-156.
Geraghty, Thomas M. “A Model of Organizational and Technological Choice in the British Industrial
Revolution.” In process, Northwestern University, Sept. 2000.
Gordon, R.J. 2000a. “Does the ‘New Economy’ measure up to the Great Inventions of the Past?” NBER
working paper 7833.
Gordon, R.J. 2000b. “Not Much of a New Economy.” Financial Times, Wednesday, July 26.
Handy, Susan and Mokhtarian, Patricia L. 1996. “Forecasting Telecommuting: an Exploration of
Methodologies and Research Needs.” Transportation Vol. 23, No. 2 (May), pp. 163-190.
Holmström, Bengt R. and Milgrom, Paul. 1991. “Multitask Principal-agent Analysis: Incentive Contracts,
asset Ownership, and Job Design.” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization Vol. 7 (Spring), pp.
24-52.
Holmström, Bengt R. and Roberts, John. 1998. “The Boundaries of the Firm Revisited.” Journal of
Economic Perspectives Vol. 12, No. 4 (Fall), pp. 73-94.
Howells, Jeremy. 1996. “Tacit Knowledge, Innovation and Technology.” Technology Analysis &
Strategic Management Vol. 8, No. 2, pp. 91-106.
Hudson, Heather E. 1998. “Global Information infrastructure: Eliminating the Distance Barrier.”
42
Business Economics Vol. 33, pp. 25-32.
Hudson, Pat. 1992. The Industrial Revolution. London: Edward Arnold.
Humble, Jane E., Jacobs, Sheila M. and Van Sell, Mary. 1995. “Benefits of Telecommuting for Engineers
and other High-tech Professionals.” Industrial Management Vol. 37 (March-April), pp. 15-20.
Jones, S.R.H. 1982. “The Organization of Work: A Historical Dimension.” Journal of Economic
Behavior and Organization 3:117-137.
Jones, S.R.H. 1987. “Technology, Transaction Costs, and the Transition to Factory Production in the
British Silk Industry, 1700-1870.” Journal of Economic History Vol. XLVII, No. 1 (March), pp. 71-95.
Khaifa, Mohammed and Davidson, Robert. 2000. “Exploring the Telecommuting Paradox”
Communications of the ACM, March pp. 29-32.
Kim, Sukkoo. 2001. “Markets and Multiunit Firms from an American Historical Perspective.” In Joel A.C.
Baum and Heinrich R. Greve, eds., Multiunit Organization and Multimarket Strategy: Advances in
Strategic Management. Vol. 18, (JAI Press), forthcoming.
Kinghorn, Janice Rye and Nye, John V.C. 1996. “The Scale of production in Western Economic
Development.” Journal of Economic History Vol. 56 (January): 90- 112.
Krau, Robert E. 1989. “Telecommuting: the Trade-offs of Home Work.” Journal of Communications
Vol. 39 (3), (Summer), pp. 19-46.
Kuznets, Simon. 1971. Economic Growth of Nations. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Laibson, David, 1997. “Golden Eggs and Hyperbolic Discounting.” Quarterly Journal of Economics,
Vol. 112, pp. 443-477.
Lamoureaux, Naomi, Raff, Daniel and Temin, Peter. 2000. “Beyond Markets and Hierarchies: Towards
a New Synthesis of American Business History.” Presented to the Annual Meeting of the Economic
History Association, Los Angeles, Sept.
Landes, David. 1986. “What Do Bosses Really Do?” Journal of Economic History Vol. 46, No. 3 (Sept.),
pp. 585-623.
Langlois, Richard N. 1995. “The Coevolution of Technology and Organization in the Transition to the
Factory System.” In Paul L. Robertson, ed. Authority and Control in Modern Industry. London:
Routledge.
Lazear, Edward. P. 1986. “Salaries and Piece Rates.” Journal of Business Vol. 59, pp. 405-31.
Mantoux, Paul. 1961. The Industrial Revolution in the Eighteenth Century. New York: Harper
Torchbooks. Rev. ed., orig. pub. 1928.
43
McCune, Jenny C. 1998. “Telecommuting Revisited.” Management Review Vol. 87 (Feb) pp. 10-17.
Miller, Thomas E. 2000. “Sizing the Small Business/Home Office Internet Universe.” Cyber Dialogue,
Inc., Industry Brief Yr. 2000 (No. 1): The Internet Consumer.
Mitch, David. 1998. “The Role of Education and Skill in the British Industrial Revolution.” In Joel Mokyr,
ed., The British Industrial Revolution: An Economic Perspective. Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 241-279.
Mokhtarian, Patricia L. 1997. “Now that travel can be virtual, will congestion virtually disappear?”
Scientific American (October).
Mokhtarian, Patricia L. 1998. “A Synthetic Approach to Estimating the Impacts of Telecommuting on
Travel.” Urban Studies Vol. 35 ( February) 1998, pp. 215-41.
Mokhtarian, Patricia L. 2000. “Telecommunications and Travel: the Case for Complementarity.”
Unpublished ms., University of California, Davis.
Mokhtarian, Patricia L. and Salomon, Ilan. 2000. “Emerging Travel Patterns: Do telecommunications
make a difference?” Unpub. ms., revised, Sept.
Mokyr, Joel. 1976. “Growing-Up and the Industrial Revolution in Europe.” Explorations in Economic
History Vol. 13, pp. 371-396.
Mokyr, Joel. 1998. “Editor’s Introduction: The New Economic history and the Industrial Revolution.” In
Joel Mokyr, ed., The British Industrial Revolution: An Economic Perspective. Boulder: Westview Press,
pp. 1-127.
Mokyr, Joel. 2000. “Knowledge, Technology, and Economic growth During the Industrial Revolution.”in
Bart Van Ark, Simon K. Kuipers, and Gerard Kuper, eds., Productivity, Technology and Economic
Growth. The Hague: Kluwert Academic Press.
Nordhaus, William D. and Tobin, James. 1973. “Is Growth Obsolete?” In Milton Moss, ed., The
Measurement of Economic and Social Performance. New York: Columbia University Press for the
NBER.
Nooteboom, Bart. 1999. “Innovation, learning and Industrial Organization.” Cambridge Journal of
Economics, Vol. 23: 127-150.
Owen, Robert. [1857] 1920. The Life of Robert Owen by Himself. London: G. Bell and Sons.
Parliamentary Papers, 1806. “Report from the Committee on the Woolen Manufacture of England.”
1806, Vol. III.
Parliamentary Papers, 1831-32. “Report from the Select Committee on the Labor of Children in Mills and
Factories.” 1831-32, Vol. XV.
44
Pavitt, Keith and Steinmueller, W. Edward. 1999. “Technology in Corporate Strategy: Change, Continuity
and the Information Revolution.” Forthcoming in The Handbook of Strategy and Management, edited
by A. Pettigrew, H. Thomas and R. Whittington.
Piore, Michael J, and Sabel, Charles F. 1984. The Second Industrial Divide. New York” Basic Books.
Polanyi, Michael. 1962. Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago: Chicago
University Press
Pollard, Sidney. [1965] 1968. The Genesis of Modern Management. London: Penguin.
Rosenberg, Nathan. 1994. Exploring the Black Box. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Russell, Cheryl. 1996. “How Many Home Workers?” American Demographics, Vol. 18, pp. 6-7.
Sabel, Charles, and Jonathan Zeitlin. 1985. “Historical Alternatives to Mass Production: Politics, Markets,
and Technology in Nineteenth-Century Industrialization.” Past and Present 108:133-176.
Saviotti, Pier Paolo. 1996. Technological Evolution, Variety, and the Economy. Cheltenham: Edward
Elgar.
Schelling, Thomas C. 1992. “Self-Command: A New Discipline.” In George Loewenstein and Jon Elster,
eds., Choice over Time. New York: Russell Sage Foundation, pp. 167-176.
Scranton, Philip. 1997. Endless Novelty: Specialty Production and American Industrialization, 18651925. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Strickland, Amanda. 1999. “Telecommuters Raise Productivity.” Triangle Business Journal (Raleigh,
N.C.) Vol. 15 (October), p. 24.
Smelser, Neil J. 1959. Social Change in the Industrial Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Szostak, Rick. 1989. “The Organization of Work: The Emergence of the Factory Revisited.” Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization 11:343-358.
Styles, John. 1983. “Embezzlement, Industry, and the Law in England, 1500-1800.” In Maxine Berg, Pat
Hudson and Michael Sonenscher, eds., Manufacture in Town and Country Before the Factory.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 173-208.
Szostak, Rick. 1991. The Role of Transportation in the Industrial Revolution. Montreal: McGill's-Queen's
University Press.
Tann, Jennifer. 1970. The Development of the Factory. London: Cornmarket Press.
Unwin, George. 1924. Samuel Oldknow and the Arkwrights. Reprint ed. New York: Augustus Kelley,
1968.
Usher, Abbott Payson. 1920. An Introduction to the Industrial History of England. Boston: Houghton
45
Mifflin.
Ure, Andrew, 1835. The Philosophy of Manufactures; or, An exposition of the scientific, moral, and
Commercial Economy of the Factory system of Great Britain. London, C. Knight.
Voth, Hans-Joachim. 1998. “Time and Work in Eighteenth Century London.” Journal of Economic
History 58: 29-58.
Weber, Max. 1961. General Economic History. New York: Collier Books (translated from German ed.,
published in 1923).
Download