Philosophical Review Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty. by Stephen Engstrom; Jennifer Whiting Review by: David O. Brink The Philosophical Review, Vol. 108, No. 4 (Oct., 1999), pp. 576-582 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2998293 . Accessed: 12/03/2014 16:36 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS ThePhilosophical Review,Vol. 108, No. 4 (October 1999) ARISTOTLE, KANT, AND THE STOICS: RETHINKING HAPPINESS AAD DUTY By STEPHENENGSTROMand JENNIFER WHITING,eds. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1996. Pp ix, 310. This collection of essayscontains revisedversionsof papers delivered at a conference entitled "Duty,Interest,and PracticalReason: Aristotle,Kant, and the Stoics" that was organized by Stephen Engstrom and Jennifer Whitingat the Universityof Pittsburghin 1994. One of the main aims of the conferencewas to bring togetherscholarson Aristotle,the Stoics,and Kant to reevaluate the common view that Greek and Kantian ethics representfundamentallyopposed conceptions of ethical theoryand the roles of moralityand happiness in practicalreasoning.Accordingto a common view,the ancients are eudaimonists; they derive or justifythe virtuesby showinghow theycontributeto the agent's own eudaimoniaor happiness. By contrast,Kant sharplycriticizeseudaimonism for derivingor justifying moralityin termsof happiness. This criticismapplies to eudaimonism of all sorts,even Stoic eudaimonism,whichis perhaps closer in some respects to Kant's own views,and of which he is somewhatless criticalthan he is of other formsof eudaimonism. For Kant, moral dutyand respectforthe moral law must be grounded in reason itselfand cannot be made to depend on any independent standard.These and related assumptionsabout ancient and Kantian ethicshave helped structuremuch contemporarysystematicwork in ethical theory,as well as common conceptions of these ethical traditions.But this common view has been under reexamination lately;some of the most interestingworkin the historyof ethics in recent yearshas been in Greek and Kantian ethics,and much of it challenges one or another aspect of the received view of the ethical theoryand moral psychologyof Kant or the Greeks.However,withsome exceptions,renewed interestand recentworkin these two traditionshas proceeded in parallel. The conference aimed to correct this,by bringingtogethersome of the most distinguishedscholarsof ancient and modern ethicsto compare and assess the role of moral dutyand happiness in the two traditions.Most of the essays have such a comparativeassessmentas their main theme; but even those thatfocus more exclusivelyon one of the traditionscontribute indirectlyto thiscomparativeassessment. Aftera useful introductionby Engstrom and Whiting,the essays are divided into five pairs and topics.John McDowell discusses deliberation and moral development in Aristotle'sethics,while Barbara Herman discusses related themesin Kant's ethics.Terence Irwinexplains and critically assesses Kant's criticismsof eudaimonism,while Stephen Engstromcompares Aristotle'sconception of eudaimoniaand Kant's conception of the 576 This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS highest good. Allen Wood examines the differentattitudesAristotleand Kant have toward self-love,whereas JenniferWhitingdefends a Kantian reading of Aristotle'sview about the relation betweenvirtueand external goods. ChristineKorsgaard compares Kant's claims about the good will and Aristotle'saccount of virtuousaction, whileJulia Annas contrastsAristotelianwithStoic and Kantian viewsabout the role of moralityin practical reasoning and the unityof practical reason. John Cooper examines the metaphysicaland cosmological basis of Stoic conceptions of virtueand happiness, while Jerome Schneewind compares featuresof Kantian and Stoic ethics to defend a version of the received view that contrastsKant's deontologywiththe teleologyinherentin Greek eudaimonism. McDowell defends an intuitionisticand particularistinterpretationof Aristotle'sconception of practicalreason byattackingwhathe calls a "blueprint" model as a philistineprejudice. The blueprintmodel of practical reasoning apparentlytakes a simple syllogisticformthatappeals to exceptionless generalizations: (1) All Fs are forbidden; (2) x is F; (3) hence, avoid x. In defense of his own intuitionisticinterpretation,McDowell appeals to Aristotle'swell-knownremarksabout the inexactnessof political and ethical sciences,which admit of generalizationsthathold onlyusually or forthe mostpart (forexample, NE 1094b3-27). We can sympathizewith McDowell's rejection of conceptions of practical reasoning that aim for mechanical decision procedureswithoutembracingextremeparticularism or intuitionism.For one thing,particularistswho eschew generalization have some difficulty explaining how the practicallywise person should deliberate about novel or especiallyperplexing situations,to which her existing sensibilityis in some sense inadequate, or how moral education, which involvescreation of a moral sensibility, is to proceed. Moreover,we can be skepticalabout the possibilityof exceptionlessnormativegeneralizationswithoutembracingparticularismifwe understandnormativegeneralizationsas containingineliminable ceteris paribusclauses. As long as it is possible to say interestingthingsin advance (and not merelyposthoc) about the kinds of situationsin which other thingsare not equal, we can maintain a formof generalism.Indeed, somethinglike this is a plausible view about the nature of generalizationsin many contexts.This sort of generalismwould secure a kind of uncodifiabilitythatMcDowell seems to want and provide a natural explanation of the sortof inexactnessAristotle recognizes in ethics; it would avoid the crudeness of the blueprintmodel thatMcDowell castigateswithoutrequiringparticularism.Indeed, itwould allow for informativegeneralizationsthat could be used by an agent in deliberatingabout novel or perplexingcases and could playa role in moral education, thus avoiding some of the difficultiesthat seem to beset extremeparticularism. Herman continues her effortsat articulatinga "kinder and gentler" 577 This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS Kantian moral psychologyin which moral characterassigns an important role to nonrationalfaculties,including emotions and desires. She focuses on the relation between reason and desire. Desire can be what moves us to action, withina Kantian account of moral motivation,provided the desire is reason-responsive.Desires are reason-responsivewhen theirweight, scope, and objects are suitablyregulated by an agent's perception of the moral law. Forms of deliberationand characterthatproceed fromreasonresponsivedesires need not be inimical to virtue. Kant criticizesall formsof eudaimonism, including Stoic versions,for subordinatingmoralityto inclinationand an independent standard (KpV 20-28, 35-36, 111-12). In a careful and rewardingdiscussion of Kant's criticismof eudaimonism and its relation to Reid's assessmentof Greek ethics,Irwin argues thatGreek eudaimonistsdid not subordinatemorality to inclination,because they treated eudaimoniaas supplyingexternal or categorical reasons. And because Aristotleand the Stoics viewed virtueas a component of, rather than an instrumentalmeans to, eudaimonia,the sense in which theysubordinate moralityto an independent standard is not obviouslyproblematic. Indeed, Irwin seems to think that the eudaimonistmakes room, as Kant does not, foran explanation of whyan agent should care about moral demands.' But Kant need not appeal to eudaimonism to vindicatethe authorityof moralityif these moral demands are grounded in the capacities of rational agents as such. However,even if eudaimonism is not necessaryto vindicatemorality'sauthority, it mayhelp to vindicate its supremacyinsofaras it can help reconcile categorical demands to be concerned with one's own rational agency and categorical demands to be concerned withrational agents as such. Engstromprovides an instructivecomparison between Aristotle'sconception of eudaimoniaand Kant's conception of the highestgood. Despite Kant's criticismsof eudaimonism,Engstromidentifiesimportantsimilarities in the content of these two conceptions and the role they play in Aristotle'sand Kant's ethical theories.Aristotle'saccount of eudaimoniais an account of a final or highest good. Both view the highest good as a complex whole consistingof virtueand other goods, in which virtueis a condition of these other goods havingvalue. In his valuable emphasis on similarities,however,I think Engstrom may underestimatedifferences. Though virtueis a complete good, forAristotle,it is not an unconditionally complete good; it is chosen forthe sake of eudaimonia.Moreover,Aristotle specifiesvirtuein termsof the human function.But then even ifvirtueis the controllingingredientin Aristotle'sconception of eudaimonia,virtueis 'Also see Terence Irwin,"Moralityand Personality:Kant and Green," in Selfand Naturein Kant's Philosophy,ed. Allen W. Wood (Ithaca: Cornell UniversityPress, 1984). 578 This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS posteriorin justificationto eudaimonia,and this appears to violate Kant's strictureson the relation between virtueand the good. Moreover,I think one may wonder whetherthe value of external goods for Aristotleis, as happiness (Gliickseligkeit) is for Kant, entirelyconditional on virtue.Some external goods seem to contributeconstitutively to a complete good independentlyof their role in virtue (1099b1-7, 1100a6-8, 1100b27), and it's not clear thatAristotlerestrictstheirvalue to those who lead virtuous lives. (However,Whiting'sclaims about the kaloskagathos go some way toward defendinga Kantian reading of Aristotlehere.) Aristotlecontrastsvulgarand proper self-loveand insiststhatthevirtuous person is the true self-lover(1 168b28-34). By contrast,Kant thinksthata will that is determinedby the principle of self-loveis heteronomous and cannot provide a foundationformorality(KpV 34). Wood's essayis a nice examination of the claims about self-worth and human nature on which Kant's reservationsabout self-lovedepend. Whitingexplores Aristotle'ssuggestionin the EudemianEthics(8.3) that so-called natural goods are intrinsicallyneither good nor bad, insofaras theycan be misused by,and prove harmfulto, the nonvirtuousagent.This thesisechoes Socratic claims in Plato's Euthydemus (280a-81e) and prefigures Kant's reasons in the Groundwork for claiming that a good will is the only thinggood withoutqualification(G 393-94). In the course of exploring this thesis,Whitingargues thatAristotle'sdistinctionbetween the agathos(the good person) and the kaloskagathos (the fine-and-goodperson) vircorrespondsto his distinctionbetween naturalvirtueand authoritative tue, in which the authoritatively virtuousagent is responsible for his own fate in a wayin which the naturallyvirtuousagent is not. Korsgaardaddresses apparent differencesbetweenAristotle'sand Kant's conceptions of moral motivationand virtuousaction that are consequent upon apparent differencesin theirassessmentsof the naturallysympathetic person. Aristotlemayseem to thinkthe naturallysympatheticperson could be virtuous,whereas Kant may seem to deny thispossibility.But Korsgaard argues that these apparent differencesare illusory,because both Aristotle and Kant insistthatvirtuousactions must be chosen for theirown sakes. Kant famouslyclaims that a good will requires not just thatan agent conform to dutybut that she do so froma sense of duty (G 390). An action in conformity withinclinationcan nonethelessexpressa good willbut only if the agent's choice of actions is suitablyregulated by her beliefs about to dutyacts what's morallyrequired. In such cases, it's not thatconformity as the agent's ultimateaim; it's ratherthatit servesas a constraintor filter on eligible motivations.Kant focuses on the case of the person who acts from a sense of duty in the absence of supportinginclinationor in the presence of recalcitrantinclination,not because she alone has a good will, but because the operation of the sense of dutyis especially clear in her 579 This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS case. According to Korsgaard,Aristotle'sposition is essentiallythe same as Kant's. For, according to Aristotle,the virtuousperson must choose virtuous actions because they are fine (kalon). So there is a sense in which Aristotle,as well as Kant, must say that the person who is beneficentor generous merelyfrominclination,in a way not regulated by the requirements of virtue,fails to be virtuous.If there is a residual sense in which Aristotleis more inclined to regard the person who is reliablybeneficent as generous, it is because, Korsgaard thinks,Aristotle,unlike Kant, treats as perceptionsof normativereasons. But this emotions,such as sympathy, is more of a psychologicalthan a normativedisagreement.While there is much in Korsgaard's account to agree with,I wonder if she overstatesthe similaritiesbetween Aristotelianand Kantian conceptions of virtueby underestimatingtheirdisagreementabout the need foraffectand inclination withinan account of virtue.For whereas Kant maynot thinkthatthe presence of inclinationdisqualifiesan agent fromdisplayinga good willor that a good willrequirescontramoralinclination,nonethelesshe seems to think that the person in whom a sense of dutymust overcome indifferenceor contraryinclination (the grudgingmoralist) can and does displaya good will (G 398). But Aristotlewould certainlythinkthatthe grudgingmoralist displayscontinence,ratherthan virtue,inasmuch as he thinksthatit is the markof the virtuousperson thathe does not experience a conflictbetween the rational and nonrationalparts of his soul and that appetite and emotion harmonize with rightjudgment (1102bl4-28). Korsgaard discusses thisissue brieflybut, I think,underestimatesits significance. Annas explores the distinctivefeaturesof Aristotle'srelation to Kant in part by seeing how he (Aristotle)differsfrom the Stoics. Whereas Kant and the Stoics distinguishsharplybetween moral and nonmoral goods, puttingthem in effecton separate scales, Aristotleincludes both moral and nonmoral goods withineudaimonia.Annas suggeststhatAristotle'sunified conception of value and practical reasoning is less mysteriousand closer to common sense. But, she thinks,Aristotle'sattemptto preserve endoxacomes at a price; once we concede that happiness includes nonmoral goods, it becomes hard to explain the primacythat he assigns to moral virtuewithinhappiness. One mightwonder about Annas's contrast between Kant and Aristotlehere. If one pays attentionto Kant's claims about the role of virtueand happiness withinthe highestgood (KpV 11019) and argues, as Whitingand Engstromdo, thatforAristotlevirtueis a condition of the value of external goods, one might suppose that both Aristotleand Kant recognize nonmoral goods as well as moral goods but only such nonmoral goods as are conditioned by moral goods. Moreover, one might wonder whether Aristotle'sconstraintson eudaimonia,introduced in NE 1, don't providesome resourcesfordefendinghis claim about the controllingrole of virtuewithineudaimonia.The functionargument 580 This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS (NE 1.7) implies thathappiness consistslargelyin a lifeof activityexpressing one's rational capacities; the life of virtueis such a life,whereas a life of nonmoral goods is not (1099b25-28). Moreover,it seems clear thatAristotlethinksthathis requirementsthateudaimoniabe comparativelystable and withinour controlimplythatvirtuemustbe the controllingingredient in happiness (NE 1099bl8-20, 1100bl-7, 12-15; EE 1215a8-18). Indeed, insofaras Aristotleidentifiesand individuatesvirtuesin termsof theircontributionto the agent's eudaimonia,the most pressingquestion is not so much whyvirtueis the controllingingredientin eudaimonia,as whyfamiliar and justice, are genuine traits,such as courage, generosity, other-regarding virtues. Cooper argues thatwe cannot reach a fairunderstandingand assessment of what is distinctiveabout Stoic ethics withoutappreciating the way in which Stoic ethical viewsdepend upon theirviews about nature and cosmology.The Stoics identifyeudaimoniawitha life lived in accordance with nature,which theyidentifywith a life lived in accordance withreason or virtue. However,Cooper thinksthat this is not just an endorsement of Aristotle'sfunctionargument.Stoic beliefsabout the rational and benevolent characterof natureprovideadditional assurance thatthe lifeofvirtue is beneficial.Indeed, the Stoic belief thatthe world is ordered forthe best view thatvirtueand happihelps explain theirotherwisecounterintuitive ness are identical. For if virtueexhausts happiness, it is hard to see how the demands of virtuecould call on us to sacrificegenuine goods. This is a paradoxical view.But it becomes more intelligibleif we remember that the Stoics thinkthatnature is ordered for the best and thatvirtueis a life in accord with nature. For then what might appear to be costs of virtue can be seen to be essentialpartsof the verybest whole. However,I wonder if Stoic theodicyjustifiesStoic claims about happiness. For even compensated sacrificesappear stillto be sacrifices;yetthe Stoics cannot admitthat virtueexacts a price, even (as Plato and Aristotleclaim) one worthpaying. Also, one may wonder whether the agent is alwayscompensated for her sacrificeseven if theyare elements of the verybest whole. Others or even nature as a whole may be betterfor the agent's sacrifices,but thatdoesn't implythat theymake herbetteroffunless we define the good of the part in termsof the good of the whole. I am not sure thatStoic theodicyitself justifiesthis organic conception of individualhappiness. Schneewind attemptsto preserve the contrastivereading of Kant as deontologistand the ancient Greeks as teleologistsby criticizingtwo recent attempts(by Guyerand Herman) to read Kant as appealing to the value of a rationalwill and by contrastingKant's appeal to respectforthe moral law and Stoic appeal to the perceptionof naturalgoods. I am not sure that the distinctionbetween doing somethingout of respect for the moral law and doing it because it is perceived to be good fora rationalagent is clear 581 This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS or strongenough tojustifySchneewind'sversionof the traditionalcontrast between the Greeks and Kant. This collection of essaysrepresentsan importantand stimulatingcontributionto the historyof ethics. The qualityof the essaysis consistently high; as a rule, theydefend interestinginterpretiveand systematicclaims in resourcefulways,marshal evidence fromthe textspersuasively,and significantlyadvance the level of discussion on the topics they address. Though each of the essays repays careful reading, some of them-especially those by Irwin, Engstrom,Wood, Whiting,Korsgaard,Annas, and Cooper-strike me as especiallyrewarding.StudentsofAristotle,the Stoics, and Kant will certainlywant to studythese essaysnot onlyfortheirinsights about these figuresbut also to achieve a bettercomparativeunderstanding and assessmentof these figures.Nor should readership for this book be confined to specialistsin the historyof ethics; those whose primaryinterests are in systematicethicsshould also read these essayswithconsiderable interestand profit. DAVID University ofCalifornia,San Diego 0. BRINK ThePhilosophical Review,Vol. 108, No. 4 (October 1999) POLITICS: BOOKS VII AND VIII. Clarendon AristotleSeries. ByARISTOTLE. Trans. RICHARD KRAUT. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, Clarendon Press, 1997. Pp. x, 229. Despite itsimportanceboth historicallyand withinthe Aristoteliancorpus, scholarshipon Aristotlein the past and despite the outpouringof first-rate thirtyyears,the Politicshas received much less attentionthan it deserves. This situationis, however,beginning to be rectified.The magisterialfourvolume nineteenth-century commentarybyW. L. Newman has been joined in recent years by numerous new translationsas well as commentariesby Richard Robinson with supplementarymaterial by David Keyt on Politics III-IV, TrevorSaunders on PoliticsI and II, P. Simpson on the whole of the on PoliticsI-VI.' Richard Kraut's Politics,and in German by E. Schfitrumpf 4 vols. (Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, 'W. L. Newman, ThePoliticsofAristotle. PoliticsBooksIII and IV 2d ed., with Clarendon Press, 1887-92); R. Robinson,Aristotle a supplementaryessay by D. Keyt (Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, Clarendon PolitikBuchI (Berlin:AkademieVerlag,1991); Aristotles: Press,1995); E. Schfitrumpf, E. Schvitrumpf, Aristotles: PolitikBuchII-III (Berlin:Akademie Verlag,1991); E. SchilPolitikBuch IV-VI (Berlin: Akademie trumpfand Hans-JoachimGehrke, Aristotles: Politics:A Philosophical Commentary (Chapel Hill: Verlag,1997); P. Simpson, Aristotle's PoliticsBooksI and Universityof North Carolina Press, 1998); T. Saunders, Aristotle's II (Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress,Clarendon Press, 1995). 582 This content downloaded from 128.54.22.253 on Wed, 12 Mar 2014 16:36:54 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions