The Ploy of Instinct Victorian Sciences of Nature and Sexuality in Liberal Governance Kathleen Frederickson Fordham University Press New York 2014 153-57397_ch00_1P.indd 5 1/24/14 7:35 PM Copyright © 2014 Fordham University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be repro­ duced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means—­electronic, mechanical, photocopy, recording, or any other—­except for brief quotations in printed reviews, without the prior permission of the publisher. Fordham University Press has no responsibility for the per­sis­ tence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-­party Internet websites referred to in this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. Fordham University Press also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books. Library of Congress Cataloging-­in-­Publication Data is available from the publisher. Printed in the United States of America 16 15 14 5 4 3 2 1 First edition 153-57397_ch00_1P.indd 6 1/24/14 7:35 PM Contents Ac­know­ledg­ments Introduction ix 1 1. Reading Like an Animal 27 2. The Case of Sexology at Work 61 3. Freud’s Australia 94 4. Angel in the Big ­House Coda 120 155 Notes159 Bibliography197 Index000 153-57397_ch00_1P.indd 7 1/24/14 7:35 PM Introduction The definition of instinct as an impetus that substitutes for reason entails a strange but familiar catachresis. The first entry for “Instinct” to appear in the OED, for instance, switches between the language of ­impulsivity and epistemology without seeming to find this vacillation unusual: Instinct (iֺnstiᶇkt), sb. . . . 1. Instigation; impulse; prompting. Obs. 2. I nnate impulse; natural or spontaneous tendency or inclination. Formerly applicable to the natural tendencies of inanimate things. In modern use associated with sense. 3. spec. An innate propensity in or­ga­nized beings (esp. in the lower animals), varying with the species, and manifesting itself in acts which appear to be rational, but are performed without conscious design or intentional adaptation of means to ends and the faculty 1 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 1 1/24/14 7:36 PM 2 Introduction supposed to be involved in this operation (formerly often regarded as a kind of intuitive knowledge). b. A ny faculty acting like animal instinct; intuition; unconscious dexterity or skill. 4. Comb.1 In spite of its gestures toward doing away with “former” beliefs, the entry, published in 1900, foregrounds assumptions about instinct that substantially predate the nineteenth century. The theorization of instinct as a bestial substitute for human reason and will, for example, dates back to Avicenna’s reading of Aristotle.2 What is new, the entry tells us, is the repudiation of the idea that instinct can be understood as “intuitive knowledge.” As it accretes multiple definitions of the term, the entry nonetheless drops even this claim in the second half of the same definition—­a wise move, given that intuition continues to persist even today as a highly common synonym for instinct. The entry’s varied account of whether instinct means intuition might seem odd enough on its own. Still more confounding, however, is that it denies that instinct is intuition while, in the same breath, depicting instinct as an alternative to reason. How can instinct be an alternative to reason and not be aligned with intuition? By the entry’s own terms, after all, instinct’s ability to act as an “innate propensity” depends on its capacity to mimic a mode of knowledge: instinct is an innate impulse that can only be distinguished from rational activity by subtracting the deliberative volition presumed to accompany rational acts. This catachresis introduces a set of paradoxes that structure theories of sexuality and sexual difference in Britain at the turn of the twentieth century. Instinct’s importance to the rise of modern sexuality is ironic for the same reasons that the OED’s decision to renounce instinct as “intuition” is ironic. The classic instinctive agents—­animals and “savages”—­were instinctive precisely because they ­were supposedly incapable of producing a self-­conscious narrative about themselves or their actions. It is thus peculiar that instinct was so necessary to the elaboration of models of Eu­ro­pe­an sexual subjectivity based, by Michel Foucault’s famous account, on confession and introspection. As an agency or epistemology in which self-­k nowledge does not operate, instinct proves to be a useful tool for naturalist projects that seek to observe, describe, and categorize patterns of behavior. But sex- 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 2 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 3 ology, psychiatry, and psychoanalysis gained disciplinary legitimacy by entrenching a methodology that blends the epistemological criteria of the natural sciences with casework data drawn from patients’ introspective self-­ narration. Freud famously resolves the tensions between these two modes by understanding instinct as an unconscious force whose effects can be found in the traces left in the empirically observable peregrinations of an analysand’s speech, affect, and embodiment.3 For many of his contemporaries, though, the relationship between instinct and self-­conscious speech was much less consistently theorized. As a result, the would-­be bifurcation between instinct and self-­consciousness fails to hold fast in any sustained way. By the end of the nineteenth century, it becomes increasingly untenable to see instinct as dialectically opposed to reasoned self-­conscious action, even though a sizable quotient of sexological writing (not to mention the OED) persists in attempting to do so. The changes that made the opposition between reason and instinct seem implausible had already begun to be elaborated in the Enlightenment, but they come to the fore in the nineteenth century because the popularization of evolutionary theory (both Lamarckian and Darwinian) stressed instinct’s centrality as a mechanism for civilizational progress. Many seventeenthand eighteenth-­century natural phi­los­o­phers had believed that living organisms could be classed into Aristotelian essential types endowed with God-­given instincts appropriate to their form.4 The nineteenth century not only saw challenges to the fixity of these types but also recognized instinct as one of the tools through which this fixity was undermined. As a result of these shifts, instinct takes on new appeal to elite Eu­ro­pe­an men who identify instinct as both an agent of civilizational “progress” and a force that offers (in contradistinction to the lack associated with desire) a plenitude that can hold the alienation of self-­consciousness at bay. Without wholly or consistently unseating the idea that instinct marks the proper province of women, working-­class men, and/or savages, this shift in instinct’s appeal to civilized Eu­ro­pe­an men nonetheless modified the governmentality of empire, labor, and gender. What, therefore, the OED entry does not allow its readers to acknowledge is that, by the end of the nineteenth century, depending on whom you asked and in what context, instinct could appear as an alternative to, a precondition for, or a defining feature of civilized, self-­conscious rationality. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 3 1/24/14 7:36 PM 4 Introduction In one line of argument, instinct distinguishes the actions, intentions, and capacities of animals, “savages,” and the metropolitan poor from the supposedly more rational and deliberative behavior of privileged Eu­ro­pe­ans. In another, instinct lurks at the root of all or most action, savage and civilized alike. Within this latter formulation, moreover, instinct sometimes designates a savage kernel at the core of otherwise civilized behavior and sometimes an entity that can be civilized in and of itself. As the OED entry implies, the different connotations of the word instinct are bound together by the fact that they all represent a retroactive projection from the vantage point of self-­conscious and deliberative subjectivity, a projection that accounts for instinct’s ability to conjoin intuition and impulse because deliberative volition and rationality are presupposed to be normatively connected. That said, these multiple opinions about whether instinct is civilized could coexist with stunning facility because little consensus prevailed about what constitutes properly instinctive activity. The flexibility of this assemblage enables instinct to adapt and respond to a variety of immediate contingencies. For the most part, instinct eases contradictions and gaps in liberal po­liti­cal and economic theory that had been made palpable as nineteenth-­century writers grappled with the legacy of Enlightenment humanism. All of the versions of instinct’s position with respect to civilized life that I just described regularly stepped in to mediate when classic categories of liberal philosophy such as reason, choice, and self-­ ownership faltered as adequate justifications for the praxis of capital and empire. Instinct also, however, initiated a series of questions that w ­ ere more unsettling. How rational are choices? What does “wanting” something signify if you are biologically compelled toward your desire? Is it possible to imagine an emotion or an attachment outside of a rational hedonic calculator? When and how does it matter that you know why you act? Can will and instinct be distinguished from each other? This book charts some of the answers to such questions and their effects on the development of the concept of sexuality at the turn of the twentieth century. Because many instinct theories distinguished instinct from reflex by suggesting that instinct implicates a creature’s entire bodily and psychological being,5 instinct was especially well poised to license sexuality as a legitimate basis upon which, as Michel Foucault so famously argues, to found something as supposedly totalizing as a subject position. While Fou- 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 4 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 5 cault does not mention instinct in his famous argument that the homosexual became a species in the History of Sexuality Volume 1,6 he was nonetheless interested in instinct’s relevance to the scene of psychiatric power/knowledge that provides the context for that argument. Foucault’s most elaborate engagement with instinct occurs in the lectures that he gave at the Collège de France in 1974–­1975, the year before The History of Sexuality appeared in print. There Foucault identifies instinct as a new dominant problematic that materializes in the psychiatry of the 1840s. Arguing that instinct emerges as the entity that accounts for psychiatry’s expanded sphere of influence in the nineteenth century, Foucault notes, correctly, that eugenics and psychoanalysis represent the “the two great technologies” that allowed psychiatry to gain “a hold on the world of instincts.”7 But Foucault does not veer too far from this domain of psychiatric power/knowledge in the one lecture in which he gives instinct sustained attention. Nor does he venture answers to the questions about instinct he deems central to the nineteenth century’s engagement with psychiatry: “Are human instincts the same as animal instincts? Is the morbid human instinct a repetition of an animal instinct? Is the abnormal human instinct the resurrection of archaic human instincts?”8 While he accepts that instinct is po­liti­cally significant, he assesses that significance chiefly in relation to how psychiatry claims power by yoking the juridical to the familial.9 The genealogy he traces in these lectures does not set out to investigate the changes to what instinct meant in different scenes of disciplinary or regulatory power. Any attention to how instinct is coproduced in relation to Eu­ro­pe­an imperialism, nascent or­ga­nized feminism, or metropolitan class politics thus remains outside of the purview of his analysis. I have structured this book around texts that allow me to attend to such domains, such as the memoirs of hunger-­striking suffragettes, ethnologies about Aboriginal Australians, pornographic fiction and the legal decisions that regulated it, evolutionary po­liti­cal philosophy, and writing on perversion by sexologists and homophiles. Reading across disciplinary categories in this way provides one of the main or­ga­niz­ing logics of this book because instinct’s presence, absence, and characterization within different disciplines is in itself instructive about the changes to sexuality taking place around the turn of the century. This disciplinary breadth, moreover, is proliferated in a discursive milieu that is not easily bounded by the logic of the nation-­state. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 5 1/24/14 7:36 PM 6 Introduction Aggressive and violent imperial expansion and increasingly transnational intellectual dialogue make it clear that Britain did not create itself on its own. Because I understand “Britain” to be an imaginary produced in a transnational context, my analysis of its formulation of instinct draws on texts written in Australia, the United States, and continental Europe—­all disseminated, read, and discussed as Britons sought to articulate even their most “national” modes of po­liti­cal subjectivity. This book begins in the late 1850s and ends around the eve of the First World War. Between these two moments, the sexual sciences became legitimated as professional domains of knowledge, liberal po­liti­cal economy donned neoclassical garb, and the new discipline of anthropology adopted the “savage”—­a creature famously associated with instinct—­as its consti­ tutive object of knowledge. During this same period, the popularization of evolutionary discourse meant that speciation was a topic of debate and speculation, the unconscious came into being at Freud’s hands as a repository of repressed psychic material, and the liberal state become consolidated as that which governs through “freedom.”10 In all of these changes, moreover, instinct was a key agent. A Queer Biopolitics Accounting for nineteenth-­century instinct in the terms of The History of Sexuality Volume 1 should seem fitting because instinct discourse proliferated within the same scientia sexualis that Foucault describes. Inasmuch as instinct is a component of sexuality, it makes sense that it should be coproduced with it. Further, in the account of sexuality that Foucault offers in History 1, instinct inhabits the point of intersection between the individual and the population, the disciplinary and the regulatory: a creature’s instinctive actions might be performed solo, but the shift to population biology that occurs over the course of the nineteenth century means that instinct was increasingly oriented to species rather than individual survival. Penelope Deutscher identifies the Foucauldian toggle between the disciplinary and the regulatory as operating in the sphere of sexual reproduction; Nancy Armstrong in that of gender.11 Instinct is of course implicated in both of these arenas (and vice versa). It also, however, names a biological mecha- 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 6 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 7 nism for this interchange that explains how any number of behaviors that are not necessarily “about sex” might be more broadly oriented toward the social reproduction of the population. Instinct becomes integral to the production of sexuality because it draws together, on the one hand, immediate, local, and embodied action and, on the other, investment in far-­off abstractions such as “race” and “species.” Summarizing commonly held views among evolutionists, the psychologist William James observes that instincts are the “functional correlatives of structure,” such that “with the presence of an organ goes, one may say, almost always a native aptitude for its use.”12 In this sense, a specifically sexual instinct could designate something like an ingrained users’ manual for genital organs. This yoking together involves mixing two timescales: the immediacy of the ability to use an organ and the infinitely longer evolutionary horizon that orients instinctive action far more distantly than even the temporalities of aspiration and delayed gratification that inhered in liberalism’s work ethic. Instinct’s efficacy as a concept hinges on making the immediate and the multigenerational timeframes work in tandem. The fact, however, that instinct and sexuality are subsets of each other suggests that instinct’s participation in the production of sexuality revises the Foucauldian thesis in a number of important ways. At the turn of the twentieth century, sexuality encompasses not only instinct but also desire, fantasy, and intimate speech. For its part, instinct participates in, for example, debates about cognition, war, hunger, labor, and migration in modes that are only tenuously related to sexuality as such. Instinct also has a longer history than the comparatively modern category “sexuality,” having, as I have already noted, been first elaborated in antiquity as the binary twin to reason. Looking at instinct’s relationship to sexuality thus allows this book to modify the domain of analysis for sexual biopolitics and to elaborate an analysis of how the genealogies and methods of an older natural philosophy constitute sexuality at the turn of the twentieth century. Last, this book’s account of the disciplinary and regulatory apparatuses producing instinct offers up a stronger emphasis on conflict and loose ends than Foucault’s work permits. In History 1’s account of sexuality, different sites of power/knowledge tend to function in mostly happy tandem: Foucault emphasizes, for instance, how the medical and familial interact in order to produce a regulatory regime. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 7 1/24/14 7:36 PM 8 Introduction Focusing on instinct allows this book to reexamine what Lynne Huffer, with some frustration, describes as the “strangely American twinning of Freud and Foucault” that has “produced the odd, distorted, infamously ungraspable conception of sexuality that has become the common fare of queer theory.”13 I am much more sanguine than Huffer in my thinking about the intertwining of ideas drawn from Freud/Lacan and Foucault. Nonetheless, I am compelled by Huffer’s argument that queer theory has turned to psychoanalysis because History 1 has been “sapped of what we might call the messy thickness of erotic life” in favor of “the thin abstractions of a dispositif.”14 I hope that this book might offer some answers about the architecture of the subjective thickness that Huffer finds missing in History 1. Much of the Lacanian queer theory that Huffer believes promises “messy thickness,” after all, deploys psychoanalytic drive (which, this book maintains, is more historically indebted to nineteenth-­century instinct theory than Lacanians tend to allow) to point toward a space outside of Foucauldian dispositifs. Leo Bersani’s “Is the Rectum a Grave?” and Lee Edelman’s No Future, for instance, put forward the belief that psychoanalytic drive denotes that which is unassimilable to a social/symbolic order. This book does not read drive or instinct as an actual exit route from a Symbolic order in the way that Bersani or Edelman would have us do. But I am interested in assessing the reasons why instinct, in psychoanalysis and elsewhere, comes to provide the name for the location where such alternatives and exit routes might be imagined. Instinct’s promise of an out to excessively disciplined subjectivity is a large part of what generates its somewhat incongruous appeal to liberal cognition. Training instinctive action, after all, requires the disciplining of something other than instinct itself in order to produce acceptable behavior. As a result, once instinct is attached to idiosyncrasy and plea­sure, it can seem well suited to act as a paradoxical locus of individual autonomy, outside of disciplinary control. Even Foucault elsewhere acknowledges this point. In his lectures on psychiatric power in 1973–­1974, Foucault reads Édouard Séguin’s analysis of the “idiot” children warded at the Bîcetre hospital by noting that Séguin emphasizes that “the idiot seems not to have any will, but in actual fact he has the will not to will, and this is precisely what characterizes instinct.”15 This instinctive will not to will, Foucault continues, is not an adult will because it cannot obey and because it refuses 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 8 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 9 “any kind of integration within a system.”16 Such a snub might seem to offer a paradigm for negative liberty, but it’s worth noting that it is no accident that the figure for this freedom—­the “idiot” child incarcerated in an asylum—­is anything but. All this child has available to him is recalcitrance. Similarly, the “antisocial” thesis emphasizes negativity: Edelman exhorts us to “cast our vote” for “the primacy of a constant no in response to the law of the Symbolic.”17 It is not clear where, if anywhere, instinct is supposed to lead if it offers a path out of discipline. Why, then, did Victorian liberals adopt it as an at least occasionally desirable quality for the arts of governance? Like the Monkeys Instinct’s potential for generating negative freedom generated a number of incoherencies as Victorian writers attempted to think through how sexuality was or was not invested in liberal personhood. “There is a great story,” the banker and Liberal economic adviser Walter Bagehot tells his readers in Physics and Politics, “of some African chief who expressed his disgust at adhering to one wife, by saying it was ‘like the monkeys.’ The semi-­brutal ancestors of man, if they existed, had very likely an instinct of constancy which the African chief, and others like him, had lost.”18 Bagehot tells us very little—­and perhaps knows very little—­about this story. A caricature that is localized in neither time nor space, the “African chief” represents the continent ­wholesale: Bagehot’s choice of the word “some” emphasizes the polygamous man’s substitutability for any other chief and Bagehot’s own lack of interest in the origin or particularity of his tale. While Bagehot uses the anecdote to highlight the remoteness of the “African chief” from the civilized developments of putative Eu­ro­pe­an monogamy, the story is nonetheless comic precisely because it implies that the most civilized way to have sex is to have it simian style. Given that, as I will show in the next chapter, Bagehot regards instincts as waning over evolutionary time, this anecdote evinces a tinge of nostalgia as it suggests that, in this case, “animal” instinct is preferable to a distinctively human sexuality. With respect to sex, the vaunted strongholds of liberal personhood—­imagination, individuality, and the self-­made subject—­do not retain the value that Bagehot claims they do in other realms of activity. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 9 1/24/14 7:36 PM 10 Introduction A first glance at this anecdote might suggest that sexuality should be understood as an exceptional case as far as liberal values are concerned. In this reading, instinct helps distinguish sexuality from other scenes of desire, action, or fantasy. As I noted earlier, though, by the end of the century, some of liberalism’s most prized sites of subject formation—­t hose centered on work and contract most notably—­also found themselves lured by the kind of instinctiveness appearing in writing about sexuality. We should, that is, be wary of regarding sexuality as inhabiting a special zone in which instinct’s relationship to liberalism is wholly and necessarily different from other sites of subjective and agential formation. Arguments in favor of instinct’s value and usefulness ­were more broadly part and parcel of a critique of rationality and deliberative volition that was appearing frequently in debates over effective governmentality. When the Duke of St. Bungay, the esteemed Whig politician in Anthony Trollope’s Palliser novels, voices his plea­sure over a cabinet minister’s resignation, he does so by noting that the minister lacks po­liti­cal instincts.19 This kind of casual usage may seem to be of a different order than the meditations on instinct that ­were appearing in evolutionary tracts such as Bagehot’s. But the Duke nonetheless iterates many of the same tropes about instinct and reason that, as I will elaborate further in Chapter 2, also animate Bagehot’s Physics and Politics. The resigning minister, Trollope’s Duke opines, “has high principles” but ones that are “too exalted to be of any use for everyday purposes”; this problem transpires, the Duke laments, because “he has no instinct in politics but reaches his conclusions by philosophical deduction. Now, in politics I would a deal sooner trust to instinct than to calculation.”20 In the Duke’s mind, “principles” cause actions that are out of step with the practical tasks of governing; instinct, in contrast, induces appropriate responses to problems that actually and commonly arise in the work of government. Instinct offers something like a po­liti­cal knowhow that functions on the ground and designates a way of engaging appropriately with an environment—­taking cues from an immediate context and acting rapidly and with assurance. Note, too, that instinct and reason do not actually generate the same results in this instance: principle gives you bad politicking whereas instinct does not. In the Duke’s chastisement of the minister’s ineptitude, it becomes clear that one of the reasons that instinct can be so useful as a paradigm for skillful and efficient action is precisely because it 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 10 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 11 can unite intuition and impetus. To be sure, the predominant contrast between instinct and principled calculation suggests that the passage, for the most part, portrays instinct as a synonym for intuition. At the same time, the Duke nevertheless faults the minister for his inability to act in a manner properly fitted to the situations at hand: a large part of the problem seems to be that the minister thinks too much and acts either too little, too slowly, or too in­effec­t ive­ly. The kind of praise that the Duke lavishes on instinct strikes a chord with what Trollope’s contemporaries believed ­were startling changes to the pace and structure of nineteenth-­century experience made manifest in increasingly rapid industrial production, newly mass-­based politics, and growing urbanization.21 Instinct’s swiftness and certainty made it particularly well suited to this version of nineteenth-­century life: by virtue of their speed and surety, instinctive agents w ­ ere not stymied in the face of too many options, nor w ­ ere they liable to lag behind the pace of the industrial city. This state of affairs is, however, paradoxical, given that these conditions ­were the markers of civilized modernity while instinct had long been supposed to be the entity that belonged to the savagely primeval. By the end of the nineteenth century, the belief that instinct substitutes for reason in animals and those humans or human qualities that are animalistic had to be balanced with one in which instinct materializes as, first, more capable than reason and, second, more ubiquitous and useful in so-­called civilized society. Given its history as a binary twin to reason, it should seem as though instinct has little place within the proper orbit of liberalism. Histories of liberalism tend to highlight the significance of reason as a mechanism for ensuring progress. The historian Jonathan Parry’s claim that the Liberal Party “attached great importance to the pursuit of truth and progress through reason and freedom of conscience” is emblematic of a wider consensus within accounts of nineteenth-­century liberal philosophy.22 These beliefs have, moreover, been central to the important work on the limited reach of liberalism’s claims to universality in the subaltern and postcolonial studies of the 1980s and 1990s. In a book that examines the connections between liberalism and empire in the nineteenth century, Uday Singh Mehta claims that liberalism contains an internal urge toward imperialism that exists because liberalism’s investment in rationality makes it possible to compare and classify—­and thus dominate—­t he world without experiencing it. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 11 1/24/14 7:36 PM 12 Introduction Liberalism’s “singularly impoverished understanding of experience,” he maintains, occurs because “it has sought in an abstract reason a short cut to a perilous journey with its unavoidable surprises.”23 Arguments analyzing reason’s centrality to British liberalism have been hugely important. But the ubiquitous scholarly focus on liberal reason has sustained two side-­effects that this book seeks to redress. First, scholarship on liberalism has tended to produce overly rigid, binaristic accounts of reason and its others that do not do justice to how modes of unreason also enliven liberal governmentality. Second (and relatedly), critics have frequently ignored the forms of embodied life necessary to liberal subjectivity. As a corrective to this latter tendency, Elaine Hadley pairs the formalized practices of what she dubs liberal cognition with an “abstract embodiment” that coordinates the relationship between a mind that formulates ideas privately and a body that acts as its public agent.24 This book shares Hadley’s interest in revising accounts of liberal cognition with respect to its formalization of embodied practices but tackles the account of reason and deliberation in studies of liberalism differently by examining moments when reason and deliberation need to be supplemented by recourse to an instinct discourse that, in some sense, seems as though it should only occur outside the purview of living liberalism properly. By liberalism, I mean a set of interwoven beliefs that valorize a respect for character and self-­reliance as the basis for progress, a doctrine that the state should intervene in daily life and in the economy only to help elaborate this character, a critique of aristocratic land tenure as the basis for just rule, and a stance that po­liti­cal reform should be gradualist in its temporality.25 I am not focused primarily on the Liberal Party—­t hat strange agglomeration of Whigs, Radicals, and free-­trade (former) Conservatives that, after its founding in 1859, only took on the properties of a “modern” po­liti­cal party with an official platform in the 1870s.26 While my last chapter, on the suffragette hunger strikes, features the Liberal Party under Prime Minister Herbert Henry Asquith quite prominently, most of the chapters in this book focus instead on instinct’s participation in a number of the pivotal narratives that inform British liberalism’s po­liti­cal and economic philosophy: those of work ethic and bootstrapping, of free contract and in­de­pen­dent opinion, and of the belief in British superiority in these arenas that was used to justify the subjection of indigenous people in the colonies 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 12 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 13 who supposedly lacked these economic, po­liti­cal, and (more broadly) characterological aptitudes. Given the primacy accorded to Locke in the histories of liberalization in Britain, the tendency in these histories to focus on distributions of rationality and concomitant “progress” should seem to make sense.27 For Locke, the “materials” for reason come exclusively from sensation and reflection28 —­a philosophy of experience that, as Jonathan Kramnick argues, allows Locke to identify consciousness with a consistent sense of self that can make people “responsible for their actions.”29 Instinct has little place in this picture. Given that it is defined in contradistinction to the very qualities of sensation and reflection that Locke esteems, it is not surprising that Locke should find instinct to be a meaningless term.30 Lockean sensationalists, in turn, either follow Locke in refuting the existence of instinct entirely or opted to separate out impetus and intuition in order to claim that instinct operates solely as an impetus and that “instinctive” intuition is instead actually intelligence at work.31 The OED’s ambivalence about whether instinct is intuition stems largely from these different approaches to tackling instinct’s role in Lockean sensationalism. But even for sensationalist writers who did not discredit instinct entirely, instinct does not permit the consciousness that produces the responsible, consistent self that could ground liberal po­liti­cal philosophy. If I am right that instinct becomes necessary not only to liberalism’s constitutive exclusions but also to its own sense of its own virtues, something has evidently shifted over the course of the nineteenth century in the formulation of liberal cognition. How did this come to be, given the Lockean re­sis­tance to instinct’s existence, let alone to its relevance to the kind of cognition that could support a liberal po­liti­cal philosophy? Hadley notes that, while Locke’s influence remained palpable, the context for the gene­ ration of reason had shifted by the mid-­nineteenth century: the Lockean subject’s rational deliberations had become a “form of social interaction rather than a precursor to it” to the extent that disinterested thought becomes “a prosthetic for social policy.”32 Such formalization of idealized sites of privatized reflection, though, left gaping holes in the theories of motivation and action available to Victorian liberals. The Duke’s claim about the difficulties entailed by principled calculation’s usefulness to the work of government demonstrates the problems that arise when disinterested 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 13 1/24/14 7:36 PM 14 Introduction thought governs in the place of those policies it is supposed to generate: the resigning minister’s overinvestment in the formalized reason of “philosophical deduction” fails as a “social policy” precisely because he does not recognize that it keeps him from solving the immediate problems of governance he faces. Instinct was not conscious or reflective, but it offered a con­ ve­nient means of explaining how action happened efficiently and accurately that, as I will elaborate in the next chapters, Victorian liberals identified as useful to their technē. Instinct helps make sexuality out of these tactical engagements because it possesses the capacity to stitch together disparate acts, desires, affects, and social relations into a single assemblage. Each of the chapters of this book explains a stitch between instinct’s intervention in one of liberalism formative scenes and instinct’s activity in making sexuality or sexual difference in law, anthropology, sexology, psychoanalysis, and medicine. This book thus proceeds by looking at exemplary cases that illuminate how instinct resolves or produces a problem in the relationship between science and liberal governance. By staging a conversation between materials that are not frequently read together, each chapter charts how instinct moves and changes from one discursive domain to another. In doing so, the book seeks to avoid, first, a contextualist reading in which a fictive social totality could explain how instinct develops in a given text and, second, a purely reductive claim that sexuality offers a simple reenactment of instinct’s operations in other apparatuses concerned with character and agency. Nonce Science Sexuality is, of course, in no way more singular or coherent than instinct. Elizabeth Povinelli argues that “sexuality” names a pro­cess through which the carnal is attached to what she dubs “genealogical and intimacy grids” that are, in turn, separated into different geopo­liti­cal imaginaries.33 Her main cases for this argument, published in 2002, involve land rights claims by Aboriginal Australians and the desire for the recognition of gay and lesbian families on the part of the mainstream U.S. gay/lesbian movement. In the latter, she observes, gay rights activists pitch their demands in terms of the fact that “in mainstream America, it is said that love makes families 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 14 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 15 elemental(ly).”34 In the former, in contrast, only genealogy matters: “love does not make an indigenous family qua traditional family according to the Australian Parliament and the courts, nor do local notions of corporeality, proximity, affect, place, context, or spirituality.”35 For her, intimacy and genealogy both offer strategies through which sex acts become constituted and legitimated as social acts, but, as strategies, they circulate differently, and in so doing “coloniz[e] social imaginaries and territorializ[e] regional social worlds.”36 Still, in spite of this differential distribution, we speak of “sexuality” as though it w ­ ere a single assemblage that could be identified as a consistent domain of social existence within these widely varying imaginaries. Why? The History of Sexuality Volume 1 of course offers itself as an answer to exactly this question. Foucault, that is, provides a genealogy of an assemblage that Povinelli seeks to unravel. While Povinelli inherits a Foucauldian legacy in her understanding of the piecemeal nature of sexuality, her work nonetheless invites a methodological revision of the Foucault of History 1. When Foucault argues that the “disciplines of the body and the regulations of the population constituted the two poles around which the or­ga­ni­za­tion of power over life was deployed,”37 he focuses on how this “great bipolar technology” operates as a single overall strategy. Although they remain fundamentally separate, Foucault sees the poles as “linked together by a ­whole intermediary cluster of relations,”38 a view he adopts so that he can assess how they work in conjunction with each other. For Foucault, local tactics and apparatuses may be “heteromorphous with respect to the other power mechanisms,” but their very insularity allows them to “support” the “great maneuvers” that History 1 chronicles.39 He is not at all concerned with how the shape of their dispersal might in and of itself produce asymmetrical forms of power. Povinelli, in contrast, emphasizes discontinuities in the allocation of intimacy and genealogy: subordination, for her, is a product of unevenness in how the two grids she identifies circulate. Not only are the apparatuses different, but they do not necessarily cooperate. In spite, however, of seeing the “disciplines of the body” and the “regulations of the population” as interlaced, History 1 nonetheless does surprisingly little to document how the supposedly “later” advent of biopolitics reshapes anatamopolitics. Nor is this omission simply an oversight: Foucault is firm when he claims that there is “no real exchange” between the 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 15 1/24/14 7:36 PM 16 Introduction “biology of reproduction” and the “medicine of sex.”40 Any examination of instinct, though, makes this claim ultimately untenable: while it may serve different functions in each, instinct discourse nonetheless shuttles regularly and densely between these two domains. The instincts that appear in the Foucauldian “medicine of sex” can indeed only function as they do because debates within natural philosophy around the turn of the nineteenth century forced the question of how instinct could simultaneously be an entity oriented to the problem of population and a divinely ordained capacitation of individual (usually animal) bodies. Specifically, the consequences of population thinking in natural philosophy exemplify instinct’s capacity to remake the individual body as machine. In these debates, a biopo­liti­cal philosophy reconstitutes an anatamopo­liti­cal one. To argue this point, I am going to return to the scene that Foucault identifies as the crux of the invention of nineteenth-­century sexuality: the restaging of confession from penitential sacrament to (especially) medicine and psychiatry.41 Instinct can enter the scene of confession only as a result of this shift to medicalization because it is, at least before the nineteenth century, entirely incompatible with sin and thus with the need for the interventions of Christian pastoralism. When the poet Alexander Pope argues in his 1734 Essay on Man that instinct is more infallible than reason because God “directs” instinct, he points out the uselessness of religious guidance for any creature entirely motivated by instinct: “Say, where full instinct is th’ unerring guide, / What pope or council can they need beside?”42 Pope cites the idea of instinct as a divine agency bequeathed by God to animals in lieu of reason, a theological proposition (derived, again, from Aristotle) that had the authority of medieval theologians, Aquinas included.43 In spite of the changes to the theorization of instinct that took place during the nineteenth century, this view retained substantial currency in the period that this book examines. Darwin, as David DePew and others suggest, spent a substantial amount of time writing about instinct precisely because he regarded it as one of the main concepts his opponents, committed to this theological view, would invoke in order to challenge the legitimacy of natural selection.44 Even in the Liberal periodical press of the 1880s, it was still possible for St. George Mivart—­a biologist who sought (to everyone’s chagrin) to make natural selection compatible with Catholicism—­to invoke instinct as proof of God’s hand in creation because, he claims, instinct 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 16 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 17 is too precise, quick, and reliable to be evidence of anything other than the miraculousness of the divine.45 These divine qualities should render instinct incompatible with the Foucauldian story. How could an “unerring guide” become the location of a disease? Instinct’s ability to enter the scene of confession demanded two transitions: first, as Foucault insists, the staging of confession had to move from the sacramental to the medical; second, the definition of instinct had to change so that it could become a problem requiring intervention. The first of these—­the turn toward medicalization—­entailed reconstituting instinct as something other than the sanctified entity it had been supposed to be. This reshaping was already underway in the eigh­teenth century: natural phi­lo­ s­o­phers in the sensationalist tradition had made the case that instinct could not be, in the dismissive words of Erasmus Darwin (Charles’s grandfather), simply a “divine something.”46 While they may have wrestled instinct away from what they regarded as an overly vague affiliation with the divine, eighteenth-­century sensationalists ­were nevertheless not identifying instinct as the site of a problem. They continued, that is, to believe that instincts generate felicitous behavior. For instinct to become potentially diseased, it had to be reframed from individual to population thinking. In Britain, it is Thomas Malthus’s 1798 Essay on the Principle of Population that provides the most important manifestation of this reconfiguration. It is not that Malthus’s thinking about instinct is incompatible with the proposition that God gives animals instinct to guide their behavior; it is simply that, instead of being (to return to Pope) “Sure by quick Nature happiness to gain,”47 instinct leads to misery. In the Malthusian account, instinct becomes biopo­liti­cal by linking individual action to far-­off, species-­level outcomes. But it does so on the condition that instinct’s lack of suppleness or awareness of environment does not garner the sense of overjoyed wonder that is evident in descriptions such as Pope’s. Malthus was the progenitor of the idea that an instinct to reproduce lurks at the root of the behavior of all organisms, voicing the now-­famous proposition that unlike other living creatures (all of which also possess an instinct to reproduce), humans have the ability to check this instinct with rational decisions. “Among plants and animals,” Malthus writes, “the view of the subject is simple. They are all impelled by a powerful instinct to the increase of their species, and this instinct is interrupted by no reasoning or doubts about providing for their 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 17 1/24/14 7:36 PM 18 Introduction offspring.”48 When Foucault, writing about the “idiot” children under Édouard Séguin’s watch, maintains that instinct refuses “any kind of integration within a system,”49 he could be describing the kind of recalcitrant instinct that Malthus imagines. God may endow all creatures with instinct to help ensure their survival and reproduction, but this instinct, if left to itself, begets extreme suffering. Malthus’s prognosis for unchecked reproduction is, after all, notoriously dire: wars, plagues, famines, mortal epidemics all ensue to wreak “dreadful devastation” upon humanity if instincts to breed remain untempered.50 Malthus’s work, however, is not enough on its own to offer the conditions through which instinct could enter the psychiatric consulting room. While Malthus may have set the terms for the radical popularization of the concept of instinct over the course of the nineteenth century, his readiness to attribute this reproductive power and impulsion to plants should highlight the fact that this “instinct” is not the same entity that would come to define sexological or psychoanalytic medico-­confessional subjects around the turn of the twentieth century. When the literary critic Catherine Gallagher discusses Malthus’s consternation over the relationship between reproduction and resources, she observes that his analysis of reproduction had been far more shocking than his examination of resources because “no one before Malthus contended that the sexual instinct was at the very core of our human nature or that it was as permanent and intractable as the instinct for self-­preservation.”51 We should not, however, misread her by assuming that such a claim is psychological. It is about as difficult to imagine applying a Freudian theory of instinct to plants as it is to imagine Malthus’s account of instinct as a kind of hydraulic pressure placed upon a psychological entity. If instinct was to take on the salience it did in the nineteenth-­century sciences of sex, the Malthusian concern over instinct as a problem at the population level thus had to be twinned with something Malthus himself does not expound: the idea of instinct as having relevance to a psychology of feeling. Erasmus Darwin, in his case against instinct as a “divine something,” was already suggesting in 1794 that instinct is “attended with consciousness, by the repeated efforts of our muscles under the conduct of our sensations or desires.”52 But it was the work of the early-­nineteenth-­century French evolutionist Jean-­Baptiste Lamarck who did most to pop­u­lar­ize the 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 18 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 19 idea of instinct as a feeling in the terms that made it available to the medicine of sex. Unlike Malthus, Lamarck could not adhere to the idea that instinct animates all living creatures.53 For him, instinct stirs only those creatures with enough biological complexity to possess ner­vous systems because nerves permit animals to experience the internal feeling that he designates as instinct;54 in contrast, caloric and electric “subtle fluids” alone are responsible for vivifying simpler organisms.55 While Lamarck insists that this “internal” instinct differs from a capacity to sense external conditions, the two cannot be wholly unrelated: Lamarck’s most famous contribution to models of instinct is the idea that acquired habits (that is, responses to external conditions) can be inherited as instinct in subsequent generations. The result of this argument is that Lamarck is in a position to argue that instinct can determine affection and taste; instinct is thus not behavior that is uniform—­or, rather, uniform except for activities identified as sex specific—­t hat identifies a species imagined to be a static form.56 By rescripting instinct into a multigenerational pro­cess of change—­one in which instincts might develop, wane, or worsen over time—­new evolutionary theories altered instinct’s ability to govern. As evolution made the case that instincts, like organic structures, w ­ ere adaptable, the status of instinct’s relationship to the influence of both experience and environment became much thornier.57 This shift to believing in the transformation of species thus meant not only jettisoning the idea of instinct as a divine agency but also abandoning the notion that instinct does not learn from experience or environment. Whereas an instinct that is fixed and repetitive can carve up the living world into the rational and the nonrational as a means of ensuring that the latter are governed by the former, the idea that an instinct might, over generations, adapt makes it subject to debates over progress and degeneration, a pro­cess more consistent with the precepts of liberal bootstrapping and the promise of class mobility. What makes Lamarckian instincts fitting for the Foucauldian consulting room is that they are both narratable as “internal” sensations and (as a result of Lamarck’s interest in individual adaptation and habit) much less fixed in character than either Malthusian or Aristotelian instincts. It thus is not surprising that, as historians of both sexuality and science contend, most of the sociobiology of the late nineteenth century tends to focus on Lamarckian rather than Darwinian evolution.58 Ignoring Darwin, however, means 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 19 1/24/14 7:36 PM 20 Introduction missing out on the science of instinct that accounts for instinct’s efficacy within the British liberal imaginary. Darwin does not share Malthus’s pessimism about instinct’s impact on populations, even though it was Malthus’s work that had led him to thinking in population terms in the first place.59 Unlike Malthusian instincts, Darwinian instincts are themselves optimized to the survival of the population and not the organism: “it will be universally admitted,” Darwin writes in the Origin, “that instincts are as important as corporeal structure for the welfare of each species.”60 Natural selection takes on the job of “checking” instinct such that reason does not have to;61 those instincts that exist are by definition beneficial for population survival. This instinct, though, cannot be the recalcitrant figure for something that refuses to integrate into a system: instinct ­here defines behavior in relation to a system. It is this quality that appeals to the Duke of St. Bungay as the best means for doing politics. The resigning minister fails because he lacks not a recalcitrant “no” but a quality that is finely attuned to an environment, in both its immediate and future needs. In laying out these arguments, I hope to emphasize the multiple—­and often incommensurate—­political imaginaries that instinct calls into being as it gathers together assemblages of liberalized, sexualized governance. In this respect, this book owes a debt to the phi­los­o­pher Isabelle Stengers, who, in a book dedicated to Bruno Latour and Felix Guattari (“in memory of an encounter that never took place”), invites participants in scientific controversies to be “on the lookout for the transversal consequences in their own field of what is proposed in another, heterogeneous field,” a pro­cess that gives the heterogenesis of scientific concepts a “po­liti­cal inscription.”62 Following Latour, she emphasizes that scientists (and indeed human beings) are neither the only actants that produce science nor the only ones that determine its transverse circulation. Thinking about instinct as heteroge­ne­tic and circulating transversely allows this book to draw together select conversations tactically and locally that in turn can spin out into other scenes of engagement. This emphasis on the territorializing of local, tactical interventions is especially necessary for an analysis of instinct, in that instinct fits poorly with grander metanarratives about the history of science such as, for instance, the one that Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer provide in their field-­defining Leviathan and the Air-­Pump. Shapin and Schaffer famously 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 20 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 21 distinguish the philosophies of scientific truth associated with, on the one hand, Robert Boyle, inventor of the air pump, and, on the other, Thomas Hobbes, author of the po­liti­cal philosophy in Leviathan and opponent of both Boyle’s methods and his findings inasmuch as they claim to prove the existence of a vacuum. For Boyle, Shapin and Schaffer argue, scientific truth demands an experimental method in which creditable witnesses could produce testable experimental “facts” within a segregated “philosophical space within which dissent was safe or permissible.”63 For Hobbes, in contrast, scientific “truth” should proceed like a geometric proof, seeking the universal assent through which order can be secured under absolutist rule. Nineteenth-­century instinct theories work poorly with both sides of this debate. Malthus, Lamarck, and Darwin all understood themselves to be writing an ontology of life that could not be compartmentalized into a safe scientific corner in the way that Boyle’s method would have demanded; they did not think that instinct had ever been modern in the sense that the anthropologist of science Bruno Latour means modern.64 Unlike Hobbesian science as it appears in Shapin and Schaffer’s account, however, nineteenth-­ century instinct discourse does not demand universal assent, a fact that makes sense given that instinct itself is by definition lived as local and tactical. The muddle in the dictionary definition (still the definition in print in the OED as of late 2013) suggests the extent to which instinct fails to become standardized. Moreover, the model of “universal assent” was increasingly difficult for a topic of inquiry such as instinct in light of the waning of natural philosophy in favor of separate and professional scientific (and social scientific) disciplines in the first half of the nineteenth century. The rise of the disciplines recast instinct into separate sets of practices.65 It is not, though, that the rise of the disciplines makes instinct more isolated within separate categories but rather that it draws together new networks of affiliation that themselves produce governmental effects. Instinct may provide the conditions for individualized choice, possess an eerily savvy investment in futurity, and enact an equally mysterious coordination of the body (and especially the carnal body), but, like the circuits in Povinelli’s account of genealogical and intimacy grids, these transverse movements are unevenly distributed. The significance of the Darwinian account, for instance, in which instinct is efficacious, environmentally responsive, and oriented toward species survival means that instinct might become a desirable 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 21 1/24/14 7:36 PM 22 Introduction quality for citizenship if you believe in “life” as a po­liti­cal goal (a contentious topic in the debates over the suffragette hunger strikes that I discuss in this book’s last chapter); it also, as I will elaborate in Chapter 2, allows instinct to script a division of labor into species discourse. At the same time, however, the debates over this version of instinct invoke a population thinking that is at odds with the interests of the governing classes that wanted to claim it as their own, inasmuch as instinctive creatures cannot “represent” a population but can only act as a member of it.66 Setting out to trace how instinct’s shifting relationship to reason and civilization was implicated in the production of sexuality would seem to place this book’s project in line with Giorgio Agamben’s effort to identify the mode of a qualified, po­liti­cal life (bíos) that is proper to unqualified, bare life (zoē). Instinct appears to be a ready affiliate of zoē: after all, the argument that instinct remains fundamentally opposed to social or environmental influence—­and is thus by definition life “unqualified” by the political—­informs many of the definitions of instinct, even in the contemporary moment. In Agamben’s recasting of Foucault’s historiography, biopolitics are not new to the modern era in the way that Foucault claims. Rather, what is par­t ic­u­lar to modern state power is the fact that zoē and bíos come to inhabit, in the guise of the state of exception, a “zone of irreducible indistinction” through which life becomes not only an object for po­liti­cal power but also its subject.67 It is all too easy to imagine instinct as a protagonist of Agamben’s claim that modern democracy “wants to put the freedom and happiness of men into play in the very place—‘bare life’—­t hat marked their subjection.”68 Precisely because it designates a quality that resists social experience, instinct offers the fiction of an individualized autonomy that is not at risk from, for example, the alienation of obligation or contract; it seems, moreover, to make sense to regard instinct as the effect of a split between right and fact, law and nature, that, for Agamben, itself constitutes both the foundation and exercise of power. Instinct, however, is as often what grounds proper po­liti­cal being as it is the condition of exclusion from it. Reading instinct in line with Agamben’s argument would thus entail a problematic belief that instinct participates in biopo­liti­cal governance only by virtue of being, to deploy Agamben’s description of the state of exception, “included by means of an exclusion.”69 This kind of analysis would miss out on a much more complex matrix of 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 22 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 23 governmentality at work in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. While Agamben’s corrective to Foucault’s historiography is well taken, his contention in Homo Sacer is, as many critics have noted, both too simple and too sweeping.70 Agamben’s argument does not function well for an analysis of instinct in two ways. First, instinct fails to inhabit a state of exception as Agamben’s assertion about zoē would necessitate. One of the finicky things about instinct in the period this book examines is that it fails to remain consistently designated as other to the proper operation of law. Second, I share the skepticism that Aihwa Ong, Paul Rabinow, Nikolas ­Rose, and others evince about Agamben’s overly exclusive focus on the state.71 Inasmuch as this book offers a discourse analysis of instinct in Britain during the period between the 1850s and the First World War, it retains a Foucauldian belief in the dispersal of power across a field of immanent dispositifs. I begin the book with a chapter in which I examine how instinct’s resolution of a contradiction in the liberal theorization of desire-­based choice provides the animus for its ghostly relevance to pornography. In the Lockean models adapted by the late Victorians, “free” choice was a condition of liberal contract through which a person might suspend part of his or her self-­ownership. Instinct worked as a palliating corrective to this alienation because it offered a model of self-­continuity that could not be alienated, being safeguarded against the alienation of contract precisely because it exists outside of reason and rational choice. Instinctive individuals supposedly could not create or manage instinct; as a result, they could not contract their instincts away. In consequence, somewhat ironically, instinct helped ensure a germ of inalienable self-­possession. As a result of standing outside of the economies of “choice” and “contract,” instinct could intervene in a late Victorian world in which an abundance of information and objects made the understanding of how and why people make choices an important object of curiosity. To make this claim, I examine the work of Charles Darwin and his protégé George Romanes, noting that naturalists such as these demonstrate a fascination with instinct’s “lack of selection of means” as they investigate moments when instinct seems to respond to “mistaken” objects. Because of this kind of characterization, instinct winds up being helpful for imagining how and when people act in the face of a profusion of potentially stimulating objects. I tackle this problem by looking at the 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 23 1/24/14 7:36 PM 24 Introduction late-­nineteenth-­century production and regulation of obscenity. Alexander Cockburn’s 1868 R. v. Hicklin decision entrenched the notion that a text’s professed aspirations or broader genre was immaterial to determining whether it is obscene. Examining how instinct was mobilized in the legal language of this kind of obscenity regulation, as well as within pornographic fiction such as My Secret Life, allows me to demonstrate that the acontextual reading model depends upon the scientific elaboration of conventions around instinct. The Hicklin decision, I suggest, imagines that readers will react ineluctably and forcefully to specific passages in a way that is utterly in­de­pen­dent of the context of the rest of the text in question. In this respect, obscenity legislation borrowed from the scientific conventions surrounding instinct in which instinct also acts immediately, forcefully, and unavoidably, without paying attention to setting or context. In Chapter 2, I trace two parallel trajectories. On the one hand, I examine the movement from understanding instinct as an alternative to reason to regarding instinct as a complement to reason. On the other, it considers the shift from reading instinct as a force that produces bad laborers who are incompatible with the demands of liberalism to seeing instinct as lurking at the root of all laboring and indeed economic activity. Assessing Walter Bagehot’s optimism about liberal po­liti­cal institutions in Physics and Politics (1872), I first argue that liberal po­liti­cal and economic theory turns to instinct to explain how savages can act without desire. Because instinct was thought to be insensible to any knowledge of the relationship between means and ends, it presented liberal theorists with the means of explaining a sharply limited aspirational horizon that nonetheless could account for agency by working as a substitute for motivation. I argue that this formu­ lation was crucial in allowing late Victorian liberalism to imagine savages who ­were conceived as, on the one hand, fiery and passionate in bursts of activity and, on the other, indolent and responsible for their own poverty. Liberals and radicals all agreed, however, that instinct had no place in the scene of wage work under industrial capital—­a fact that presented complications for the nascent movement for the rights of inverts (or the “inter­ mediate sex”) as it sought to argue that certain forms of labor might be biologically intrinsic. Looking at labor allowed sexologists such as Havelock Ellis and Edward Carpenter to appropriate the connection between instinct and work to legitimate the kind of nonreproductive functions that 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 24 1/24/14 7:36 PM Introduction 25 can be performed by instinctive agents and then to reread these connections within the language of gender. By turning to Victorian ethnology, Chapter 3 investigates how psychoanalysis developed its theorization of instinct in relation to nineteenth-­ century Eu­ro­pe­an presumptions about “savagery.” Freud’s Totem and Taboo famously establishes an analogy between the psyche of an individual Eu­ro­ pe­an neurotic and the social or­ga­ni­za­t ion of savage life. This chapter reads two of Freud’s key sources for this argument: a set of nineteenth-­century ethnological monographs about indigenous Australians that exerted tremendous influence on the development of British anthropology. The first, Lorimer Fison and A. W. Howitt’s Kamilaroi and Kurnai (1880), was researched in the heavily colonized regions of Gippsland in the 1870s; the second, Baldwin Spencer and Frank Gillen’s Native Tribes of Central Australia, was a study of Arrernte people in the central desert, where the incursion of whites was much sparser. By the mid–­nineteenth century, ethnology had developed a professional niche in focusing on institutions, ceremonies, and material culture as the basis for their knowledge about savages. Chapter 3, however, argues that this kind of ethnological work reproduced eighteenth-­century depictions of instinctive savages by recasting the tropes associated with instinct—­unreflecting, binding, and immediate attachment—­ onto the relationship between savages and savage governmentality. Neither of these texts, however, mentions instinct—­an omission that is in fact common in nineteenth-­century ethnological writing. Freud’s engagement of the partial erasure of instinct in nineteenth-­century ethnology, I suggest, occasions his striking ambivalence about the relationship between instinct and social institutions that pervades his first instinct theory, especially as it is expounded in Totem and Taboo and the earlier Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality. My final chapter asks why the suffragette hunger strikes emerged as such powerful po­liti­cal tactics in Britain in the years leading up to World War I. It does so by tracking moments in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries in which the perceived failure of an instinct of self-­ preservation generates po­liti­cal crisis or social panic. By reading suffrage literature by Christabel Pankhurst, Constance Lytton, and Constance Maud alongside the emerging literature on suicide, anorexia, and the birth-­ rate panic, the chapter investigates the mediations between the instinctive 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 25 1/24/14 7:36 PM 26 Introduction citizen and the instinctive woman at a moment when instinct had been regarded as one of the key determinants of sexuation. In a move that reflects instinct’s position in civilization more generally, the rational citizen was sometimes the binary counterpart to the instinctive woman and sometimes a figure endowed with his own set of instincts that ­were different and ideally complementary to those of women. The suffragette hunger strikes tackled both of these positions simultaneously. On the one hand, strikers sought to parody rational citizenship by staging a protest designed to suggest that they could embody the model voter’s ability to abdicate interest in the name of principle. On the other, they made the case that women’s instincts ­were in fact entirely in line with characteristics desired in the electorate. Their decision to mobilize hunger as a po­liti­cal tactic directly impacts the theorization of gendered instinctiveness. Nineteenth-­century evolutionary theory, in both Darwinian and Lamarckian guises, positioned hunger as the most primal of instincts such that hunger provided the template through which other instincts came to be theorized. In this sense, hunger helped define the models through which sexuating instincts—­believed to occur phyloge­ne­ tically later—­could be shaped. As suffragettes mobilized the concept of the strike in order to describe their refusal of food, they linked their protest to the strikes of Chartists seeking electoral reform in the first half of the nineteenth century. In so doing, the hunger strikers suggested that their instincts should be understood as forms of labor, a fact that implied a critique of the way that the sexual division of labor had become newly scripted as an instinct-­based discourse of sexual difference. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 26 1/24/14 7:36 PM t h r e e Freud’s Australia A text that undertakes a thorough perusal of late Victorian ethnological sources, Freud’s Totem and Taboo (1913) is unabashed in identifying “savages” as the instinctive analogues of Eu­ro­pe­a n neurotics. By adapting the detailed descriptions of “savage” rules and customs that prevailed in nineteenth-­century texts—­and especially those about indigenous Australia— Totem and Taboo makes its famous argument that savage social or­ga­ni­za­t ion and customary practice produce the simultaneous satisfaction and regulation of ambivalent unconscious wishes. But Freud’s reliance on Victorian ethnology as the source of evidence for savage instincts should strike any reader familiar with his archive as curious. Seldom, after all, does instinct appear as a term in late Victorian ethnological writings; unlike Freud’s more speculative psychology, these ethnological writings demonstrate a preference for the concrete description of material objects and cultural practices. If, as Totem and Taboo argues, savage custom can provide the map to the Eu­ro­pe­a n psyche, the Eu­ro­pe­a n fantasy of the “savage mind” itself 94 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 94 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 95 undergoes a shift in the pro­cess because the social systems that Freud takes as psychic guides to the instinctive ­were new features of savagery that revised an earlier fantasy of the instinctive savage as largely outside of social influence. Freud’s argument in Totem and Taboo navigates what was already a cultural paradox in the late nineteenth century: if instinct was to be appropriated as a crucial term for the smooth functioning of “civilized” life, this appropriation had to be accomplished without entirely uprooting the value of the “civilized” things that had been commonly defined in dialectical opposition to the instinctive itself. This chapter argues that while the nineteenth-­century consolidation of the anthropological culture concept shifted ethnological interest away from the figure of the solitary savage to the wider structures of communal governance, it nonetheless accommodated the eighteenth-­century caricatures of instinctive and passionate savages by redeploying the terrain of the instinctive onto collective forms of social or­ga­ni­za­t ion. At the same time, Eu­ro­pe­an instincts would be thought to achieve greater in­de­pen­dence from the material stuff of daily life, being increasingly figured as outside of either social or material influence. In this sense, in aligning instinct with both the fiery transparency of the savage whose unconscious knows no repression and the buried sexual psychology of the medicalized (Eu­ro­pe­an) bourgeois subject, Totem and Taboo navigates a complex referential bifurcation in late Victorian semiotics of the instinctive. This is to say that instincts, in becoming newly respectable, had come to mean different things when predicated of savages and of civilized men. The terms of Freud’s analysis in Totem and Taboo ­were already prevalent in the idealization of instinct that was becoming more widespread in the later part of the nineteenth century. In his famous 1869 essay “The Subjection of Women,” John Stuart Mill characterizes the nineteenth-­century reaction to the Enlightenment as tending “to accord to the unreasoning elements in human nature the infallibility which the eigh­teenth century is supposed to have ascribed to the reasoning elements.”1 Mill likely had in mind Jeremy Bentham’s admiration for rational systems when describing the eigh­teenth century in these broad strokes and not the idealization of sentiment demonstrated by, for example, Lawrence Sterne in Britain or Jean-­Jacques Rousseau on the continent—­nor, of course, had reason ceased to be a significant term in late-­nineteenth-­century po­liti­cal philosophy. But 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 95 1/24/14 7:36 PM 96 Freud’s Australia when Mill writes that “for the apotheosis of Reason we have substituted that of Instinct,”2 he nonetheless gestures to the importance of the natural and instinctive to nineteenth-­century po­liti­cal ethics. This importance, however, meant that late-­ nineteenth-­ century American and Eu­ ro­ pe­ an thinkers became invested in rethinking the relationship between instinct and evolutionary “progress.” In consequence, when, as I observed in Chapter 1, William James argues in 1890 that instinct increases rather than decreases with civilization,3 he provides an evolutionary psychology that reflects the “apotheosis” of instinct that Mill describes. While savages still bear the cultural burden of being natural in their instinctive unreason, their consequent status as guides to the purported infallibility of the natural presented a problem for Eu­ro­pe­an po­liti­cal philosophy that eventually came to condition the redefinition of instinct itself. By examining the imperial logics that helped enable the writing of Totem and Taboo, I also seek to understand the cultural politics that produced the theorization of instinct in the Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality—­a text that predates Totem and Taboo but that Freud continued to revise until well after Totem and Taboo had appeared in print in 1912–­1913.4 Arnold Davidson and Jean Laplanche have both argued that Freud’s chief contribution to the theorization of instinct lay in revising the Victorian idea that, as Davidson summarizes, “a specific object and a specific aim formed part and parcel of the instinct.”5 I am arguing ­here that this account of instinct as it appears in the Three Essays inherits the legacy of the anthropological writings Freud cites as he wavers on the question of whether instinct’s objects are naturally pregiven or not. The in­de­pen­dence that instinct was acquiring in civilized venues—­a n in­de­pen­dence that increasingly unraveled the primacy of the link between instinct and “natural” aims and objects—­helped occasion the kind of “apotheosis of instinct” that Mill descries.6 But although these new civilized instincts may show flexible and creative cathexes to a multiplicity of objects, they are nonetheless modeled on what Freud insists is an instinctive attachment between savages and savage social structures. Freud’s analogy should remind us that even ontoge­ne­t ic accounts of instinctive cathexis carry a cultural history beyond the register of an individual’s lived history. In the original German of Totem und Tabu, Freud uses the term Trieb (drive) substantially more frequently than Instinkt—­ both of which are 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 96 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 97 translated as “instinct” in the En­glish of the Standard Edition. Commonly deplored as a failure on the part of the Standard Edition’s translator James Strachey, this dual usage of the word instinct obscures the idea that, as Jacques Lacan once put it, Trieb “has nothing to do with instinct.”7 Strachey’s decision to translate Trieb as instinct may sacrifice some of the clarity that Lacan and others might wish; it is, however, not wholly unwarranted. Adrian Johnston observes that Freud never fully shakes the biologism associated with instinct and that Lacan’s dictum may thus be “too extreme, too sweeping.”8 But it is not only Freud’s tendency toward biological meta­phors that makes a stark and clear division between instinct and drive untenable. Freud’s Trieb emerges in explicit reference to the ideas around instinct that ­were circulating broadly in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. In the original German Totem und Tabu, Freud himself translates James Frazer’s use of the En­glish “instinct” as Instinkt only to discuss it as Trieb in the following sentence.9 While Freudian Trieb may depart from late Victorian instinct theories in a number of important ways, it nonetheless bears the marks of the changes in thinking instinct that ­were occurring around the turn of the twentieth century. My archive for this paper follows Freud’s in Totem and Taboo, at least to the extent that Freud opts to “select as the basis of this comparison the tribes which have been described by anthropologists as the most backward and miserable of savages, the aborigines of Australia.”10 Late Victorian anthropological speculation commonly regarded Aboriginal Australians in the way that Freud does ­here: in spite of Charles Darwin’s selection of the Fuegans for the title, Australian Aborigines occupied a heightened burden of repre­sen­ta­tion as the most primitive of humans and consequently the people thought to be closest to apes and to some imagined fantasy of primeval, nascent humanity. The narratives about local indigenous people that white ethnologists in Australia ­were producing and sending to En­gland in the form of journal articles, monographs, and personal correspondence thus acquired a prominent place in the evolutionary theory central to the emerging discipline of anthropology. In par­t ic­u­lar, two texts would strongly influence Freud’s account of Australian Aborigines: Lorimer Fison and A. W. Howitt’s 1880 monograph Kamilaroi and Kûrnai, and the 1899 ethnography that is dedicated to Fison and Howitt, Baldwin Spencer and Frank Gillen’s Native Tribes of Central Australia. Not only does Freud cite both pairs of 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 97 1/24/14 7:36 PM 98 Freud’s Australia authors throughout his analysis, but his reliance on authorities such as James Frazer and Edward Burnett Tylor also refracts these earlier texts in that they provided the most sizable quotient of data in the work of the Oxbridge anthropologists. The Institution of Instinct In the fourth and most famous of the essays in Totem and Taboo, Freud both cites and praises a key sentence from James Frazer’s Totemism and Exogamy (1910): “It is not easy to see,” Frazer had written, “why any deep human instinct should need to be reinforced by law.”11 Freud approves of Frazer’s argument about instinct and law because it allows him to argue against the idea that there is such a thing as a widespread “horror of incest”;12 Frazer’s almost quizzical musing on law and instinct reappears in Freud’s text as a more forcefully stated assertion that laws are not instituted to reinforce instincts but rather to counteract them. In Frazer, that is, Freud finds an ally for his famously contentious arguments that Oedipal wishes are universal and that there is no “no” in the unconscious. For Freud and Frazer alike, the fact that there are institutions such as exogamy in place to prevent sex between close kin is evidence enough that no such thing as a “horror of incest” should be thought to inhere in the human psyche. Institutions, by this account, must necessarily be at odds with instinct, stepping in to counteract the potentially destructive effects of truculent instinctive energy. Instinct would consequently seem to need no institutional buttressing or activation, appearing to the two men as fully self-­sufficient in its activities, by definition broaching no need for or interest in the social institutions that spring up to or­ga­nize human collective life. But although Freud voices support for Frazer’s advocacy of this ­wholesale dichotomy between instinct and law, his own sense of the division between the two is by no means consistently so stark. Freud may regard himself as partisan to the idea that instinct obviates institutional enforcement when he needs to make the case that social structures are not the transparent reflections of human wishes, but the regulatory institutions that appear throughout Totem and Taboo—­taboo, totemism, and exogamy themselves, for instance—­are at the same time cast as products of the same instincts 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 98 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 99 they are said to counteract. The fact that ambivalence appears so frequently in Freud’s analysis highlights the fact that institutions cannot be thought solely to regulate the undesirable components of instinct. Because cathexis is multivalent in its emotional expression (hate still means love), institutions cannot help but reinforce some articulations of instinctive attachment in the very same acts through which they prohibit others. In Freud’s gloss on Darwin’s theory of the primal horde, the band of brothers murders the primal father out of fear and envy—­only to atone for their act out of guilt, love, and identification with the figure whom they have supplanted. The injunction not to murder that the brothers install in the wake of their crime clamps down on an instinctive aggressivity, but the totemic institutions they form at the same time revere what Freud regards as a cathexis to the father figure that is itself instinctive in character. The difficulty ­here is substantially the same as the one that Freud encounters when he confronts the task of analyzing narcissism in light of his early instinct theory. At this moment in 1912–­1913, Freud was still working with the first theory of instincts that dominates his work before the appearance of the death drive in Beyond the Plea­sure Principle in 1920. In this earlier formulation, the sphere of the social (and the reality principle entailed by it) is aligned with the self-­preservative instincts and distinguished from the sexual instincts, which are, in turn, conceived in more aggressive and antisocial terms. Freud’s work on narcissism was, however, already beginning to put pressure on his separation between the social and sexual.13 Freud’s 1911 case history of the paranoiac Daniel Paul Schreber had identified Schreber’s belief that he was the wife of god as the outgrowth of a homosexuality founded on narcissistic fixation. The account of homosexual narcissism elaborated in the Schreber case would come to haunt Totem and Taboo because, as Peter Gay writes, it allowed Freud to investigate “the relations of men to their gods as derivatives of their relations to their fathers.”14 The yoking of ego instincts and sexual instincts that Freud identifies in the Schreber case underwrites his understanding of savage social life in Totem and Taboo because it makes possible, for instance, his reading of the sacralized totem animal as an incarnation of the murdered primal father. As Freud sees it, these relations to what he understands as the psychologically equivalent figures of god, father, and totem are determined by specifically sexual instincts that allow for narcissistic identification to occur; they 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 99 1/24/14 7:36 PM 100 Freud’s Australia thus position sexual instincts at the basis of social life. In the course of tracing the connections between the homosexual investments in both Totem and Taboo and the Schreber analysis, Mikkel Borch-­Jacobsen asks, in a rhetorical vein, whether “since the ego, according to the first Freudian theory, is supposed to represent society’s interests and values, ­doesn’t the discovery of narcissism permit the libidinal ground of sociality and morality to be unveiled?”15 Sociality and morality include the “law” that Frazer and Freud had concurred was categorically at odds with instinct; what we see, in contrast, through the theory of narcissism is rather the idea that social institutions are products of an instinctive energy that collapses the distinction between the erotic and the egoistic. The ­whole idea of a psychoanalytic subject with a set of instincts acting in reference to the events of a personal history is radically undercut by such accounts of institutions. Even before penning the famous Oedipal legend in the book’s concluding chapter, Freud had found troubling the status of the institutional. The dominant analogy of the second of the essays compiled in Totem and Taboo—­t hat between savages and neurotics—­also relies on the idea of “social instincts” as the basis for social institutions.16 “The neuroses,” Freud tells us, “are social structures; they endeavour to achieve by private means what is effected in society by collective effort,” adding that “the determining influence in them is exercised by instinctual forces of sexual origin; the corresponding cultural formations, on the other hand, are based upon social instincts.”17 Because, as Freud so repeatedly insists, the neuroses are made of the same stuff as savage social institutions, the discussion of the instinctive investments in neuroses holds firm for these externalized savage equivalents as well; Freud, in fact, insists that savage institutions owe their existence to the fact that savages are privy to “the projection outwards of internal perceptions . . . which therefore normally plays a very large part in determining the form taken by [the] external world.”18 Freud had always asserted that mental events do not need to be materially “real” in order to have real effects on the experiencing subject. But Freud’s account of savage psyches is starker still in that he positions the institutions that make up a savage social world as a constitutive part of the savage psyche to the point that it becomes impossible to discern the edges of where the experiencing psyche stops and the experienced world begins. This tangle is obviously a far cry from the observation that we started with, 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 100 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 101 namely that institutions are superfluous where instinct is at play. This claim becomes almost impossible to sustain because the categories it presumes—­ categories such as “individual psyche” and “social world”—­overlap so fundamentally that it becomes hard to make a definitive claim about how they are distinguished. The very untidiness of Freud’s sense of these relationships, however, bears the traces of reforms in late-­ nineteenth-­ century anthropological methodology. Freud, we have seen, regards the ­whole operation of any savage society as analogous to the mind of an individual Eu­ro­pe­a n neurotic.19 The ethnology that he cites also effects this kind of transposition between individual and group but in a different way. I noted earlier that instinct ceases to be a significant term in Eu­ro­pe­a n ethnological texts about savage life. Late-­nineteenth-­century ethnology instead borrows from the features that had hitherto been commonly deployed to characterize individual savages and uses them to designate a way of being in a group that, in turn, forecloses the possibility of the production of individuality in the first place. By the end of the nineteenth century, institutions have replaced the individual savage as the chief objects of interest for anthropologists and ethnologists.20 Instinct fades from explicit focus, but the nascent discipline’s inability to shed the terms of its own constitution nonetheless makes instinctiveness a necessary, if tacit, presumption in the way that savages ­were thought to comprise and relate to these institutions. The position in which academic anthropology found itself by the end of the nineteenth century virtually necessitated this kind of transposition between individual and group. At its core, nascent academic anthropology owed a tremendous debt to earlier figurations of savages because the tropes affiliated with this figure designated the terrain that made anthropology’s project intelligible. Michel-­Rolph Trouillot observes that anthropology inherited its monopoly on the production of knowledge about Savages “almost by default” from a Re­nais­sance Eu­rope that constituted itself as such by projecting the as-­yet-­generically undifferentiated specters of the Savage and Utopia as its “Elsewhere.”21 Only in the nineteenth century, Trouillot argues, did the Savage and Utopia become distinguished from each other in the course of a professionalization that sought to distinguish ethnographic writing from travelogue-­romances and other fictional accounts of Elsewheres whose specificity and factuality had hitherto been deemed 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 101 1/24/14 7:36 PM 102 Freud’s Australia substantially uninteresting and irrelevant. Because, Trouillot concludes, anthropology inherited the “Savage slot” from this early modern world, it “never bothered to theorize” the category that constituted its raison d’être.22 Stated otherwise, the Savage constituted the imagined baseline in reference to which the new field of academic anthropology articulated itself. This is not, of course, to say that anthropological texts did not undermine their generic constitution or that this constitution was not itself perpetually shifting. But even admitting this shifting and différance, Trouillot’s point nonetheless largely holds: while anthropology may debate the accidents of the savage figure and strive to work against the imperialist logics that founded the field, it does not manage to overthrow the definition of the savage as the primitive counterpart to the modern Eu­ro­pe­an because that figure designates the basis of its intellectual enterprise. Instinct numbered among the key tropes that produced the savage figure that allowed academic anthropology to come into being. In both the “Discourse on the Origin and Foundation of In­e­qual­ity Among Men” and On the Social Contract, for instance, Rousseau famously argues that instinct renders man utterly capable of living happily in the state of nature: “In instinct alone,” Rousseau writes in the second “Discourse,” man “had all he needed to live in the state of Nature, in cultivated reason he has no more than what he needs to live in society.”23 This lone, male figure appears to the famously misanthropic Rousseau as content because his instinctive self-­sufficiency allows him to avoid the complications of society. The fact that this savage is also happily fulfilled with hetero sex presents no problem for this theory of blissful relative solitude, because women are not, in Rousseau’s po­liti­cal theory at any rate, persons enough to proffer threatening ontological re­sis­tance.24 On the Social Contract is, in contrast, premised on the passage, as Rousseau puts it, “from the state of nature to the civil state,” which produces “a remarkable change in man, for it substitutes justice for instinct in his behaviour and gives his actions a moral quality they previously lacked.”25 The sense of substitution between rule-­ governed conduct and instinct helps highlight why it is that Frazer (and Freud, in the moments where he voices his approval for this tendency) can regard instinct as obviating the need for institutional governance: it is in fact their similarity that allows them to be positioned as mutually exclusive binary opposites. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 102 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 103 In earlier formulations such as Rousseau’s, instinct marked a defining feature of the savage in the state of nature. Instinct’s role in demarcating this figure will, moreover, reappear as a key assumption in anthropological literature of the twentieth century at least through the structuralist epoch.26 At the moment I am examining, however, the dictates of the intellectual cultures through which anthropology was becoming professionalized placed the theorization of instinct outside of the purview of what might be legitimated as anthropological research. While being compelled to preserve the terms of the “Savage slot,” late-­nineteenth-­century British anthropology also found itself bound to the protocols and evidentiary standards of scientific empiricism. In Britain, academic anthropology came into its own through the auspices of the British Association for the Advancement of Science and a reformed university curriculum in which empirical science was acquiring new legitimacy.27 As distinct from disciplines such as biology, psychology, and neurology that might legitimately undertake a “scientific” study of instinct, anthropology investigated questions that ­were located at a transindividual level consistent with its developing niche in the scientific study of savage culture.28 While “armchair anthropology” remained a professionally viable mode of intellectual engagement into the early years of the twentieth century, the kinds of information demanded by study-­bound anthropological men seeking to authorize the science of their claims could increasingly only be produced through sustained, long-­term contact with the groups of people being studied by ethnologist-­correspondents in the field.29 Anthropological theorists needed substantial ethnological data that could be empirically observed in order to produce the generalizations about “culture” upon which they based their articulation of the laws of socioevolutionary progress. As a consequence of this new structuring of anthropological science, by the end of the nineteenth century, the term “institution” was acquiring greater social prominence as the term for the units of social life that became aggregated under the rubric of the newly consolidated anthropological culture concept. Late in his career, Edward Burnett Tylor, chief among the early architects of the idea of culture, published a field-­defining essay titled “On a Method of Investigating the Development of Institutions; Applied to Laws of Marriage and Descent” (1889), in which he deployed the term “institution” chiefly in relation to practices of customary avoidance, 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 103 1/24/14 7:36 PM 104 Freud’s Australia residence, “marriage,” descent, and naming practices—­many of those same interlocking aspects of social life that interest Freud in Totem and Taboo. Anthropologists such as Tylor regarded “institution” as the appropriate way of naming units within the category of culture because the term had, by the 1880s, come to invoke the kind of relative permanence thought to be necessary to defining culture as a hypostatized entity that is knowable as a ­whole—­and opposed to the immanence predicated of instinct by virtue of the same qualities. Tylor’s essay introduced the practice of statistical analysis into anthropological writing, deploying institutions as the informational building blocks from which such analysis might be undertaken. Such institutions could be observed and described by ethnologists in the field, becoming the specimens with reference to which anthropologists could speculate about the evolution of culture just as their naturalist confreres could examine fossils in order to describe the evolution of species. The utility of institutions to projects such as Tylor’s was further overdetermined by what Christopher Herbert describes as a growing and socially widespread critique of disciplinary institutions within En­gland itself—­a critique that, Herbert suggests, led to a censure of excessive social control projected outward onto imperial terrain. This projection marks a new moment in this disavowal from the more commonplace distinctions between savage instinct and civilized reason. H ­ ere, the savage occupies a place in which Eu­ro­pe­a n anxieties about the relation between subject and law emerge full force. “What we see, then,” Herbert writes, “is a broad reversal of assumptions in which savage society is transformed from a void of institutional control where desire is rampant to a spectacle of controls exerted systemically upon the smallest details of daily life.”30 This excessive social control, however, possesses a characteristic feature that is only slightly marked in Herbert’s assessment. The symptomatic “spectacle of controls” implies a society too rife with rules—­t hat is, a society in which formal regulatory classifications have assumed too much authority and too much in­de­pen­dence with respect to the material that they categorize, classify, and discipline. The difference between savagery and civilization is thus not that the former actuates a socially freeform expression of instinctive licentiousness but rather that savagery represents an overproliferation of institutions with regard to which savages have no metacategorical self-­reflexivity.31 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 104 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 105 We should, however, by now hear the resonance of the rhetoric habitually associated with instinct in reference to what Herbert describes as savage overdiscipline. If, as I suggested in the last chapter, instinct appears as the epistemology that is defined as a back-­formation from Reason in which the relation to the function of a rule is subtracted, it thus describes exactly the relation to law that Herbert sees as newly emergent in the late nineteenth century. In the many nineteenth-­century definitions that view instinct as a substitute for reason, instinct’s effectiveness and structure are defined relative to the standards and categories established by reason; instinct steps in to explain how a creature might act in a way that mimics the actions of a rational human being while denying the idea that this instinctive creature possesses the ability to access any rational metacategorical awareness about the action that instinct has produced. Such a model, though, flies in the face of the opposition between instinct and institution that Frazer had elaborated and, indeed, of some of the principles grounding the definition of the institutional in the first place. The verb form “to institute” that, historically speaking, preceded the nominalization had after all emphasized its originary function: the act of instituting was regarded as attached to some form of decisive volition—­t hings that are instituted contrast, for example, with those that simply emerge. Even critiques of such models of institutionality—­a nd especially, those models that would soon blossom into an explicit structural-­f unctionalist insistence on institutions as ideologically neutral expressions of rational social functioning—­accept the idea that institutions at least present the effect of functional cultural “self-­expression.”32 As I have said, however, this kind of shift toward anthropological concern with institutions does not preclude the supposition of a savage object conceived as fundamentally instinctive in nature. Savages still figure prominently in the naturalist and psychological literatures about instinct at this time; it is simply that instinct ceases to figure prominently in the literature about savages even though instinctiveness is still presumed to be a defining characteristic of the savages in question.33 The institutions that replace instinctive individual figures as objects of focus come to take on many of the qualities of the figure for whom they substitute. Francis Galton’s response to Australian kinship systems is illustrative of the way in which instinct came to characterize the relations between savages and institutions. Galton 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 105 1/24/14 7:36 PM 106 Freud’s Australia admits, openly and unabashedly, to being perplexed by the “peculiarly complicated system of Australian marriages,” noting with considerable frustration that he “had often tried, in vain, to find an easy clue to this strange custom, feeling assured that no aboriginal Australian brain could acquire the accurate and almost instinctive knowledge they have of it without one.”34 Galton’s frustration is telling, as is the language in which he narrates it. He invokes a sense of dizzying categories, which (it turns out later in his text) subscribe to a simple logic that he, after much effort, has managed to unearth; rather than a complex social system, Galton thus finds the elaborated repetitions of a simple categorizing idea. This rhetorical move thus effectively sidesteps the epistemological quandary presented by the possibility that an aboriginal society might be more subtly sophisticated than a civilized Eu­ro­pe­an one. ­Here, the underlying principles are discovered to be rudimentary but manifested into an overabundant profusion of social forms that are consequently illogical and unnecessary. Similarly, the “aboriginal Australian brain” can only have “instinctive” knowledge of the system, a means of accounting for knowledge while preserving the idea of ignorance necessary to regarding tribal societies, to return to Herbert’s assessment of this schema, as “ ‘fettered,’ ‘bound,’ ‘chained down’ by mindless conventionality.”35 Being fettered to social institutions without any ability to have a self-­ reflective relationship to those institutions foreshadows Freud’s argument about the excessive intimacy between savages and savage social structures that I discussed earlier. I will come back to Freud more fully later in this essay, but it is worth noting h ­ ere that Freud not only accepts the premise of Galton’s claim that savages have no meta-­awareness of their social institutions but also goes a step further in maintaining that those savage “social structures” actually result from the instincts of those savages who are governed by the institutions in question.36 For Freud, that is, savage social institutions express the instincts of a collectivity of individual savages. These savages are, moreover, not distinguishable from one another. As a result, the “projection outward”37 of instinctive psychic matter can produce social structures without substantial difficulty: there are no contradictions and tensions between individuals with different psychic investments that might make the transposition between individual and group fraught with trouble. These movements between individual and group are, moreover, crucial to 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 106 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 107 the definitions of savagery and civilization themselves—­a fact that proves integral to Fison and Howitt’s critique of the Rousseauian savage in Kamilaroi and Kûrnai. Individualizing the Individual Fison and Howitt’s Kamilaroi and Kûrnai includes a set of essays from each author, drawing on Howitt’s firsthand experience with Kûrnai people while he worked in Gippsland as a police magistrate and the survey data on Kamilaroi people that Fison had gathered in response to his correspondence with the American ethnologist Lewis Henry Morgan. By the 1870s, white colonization had overwhelmed Gippsland: the gold rush of the 1850s had led to the tripling of the white population and the rapid eradication of the Kûrnai, whose tribe of 1,500 people in 1839 had been reduced to only 140 members by 1877.38 So thorough had been the mixture of settler violence, imported disease, and destruction of traditional land use (not to mention other forms of colonial violence that Achille Mbembe reads as infrastructural warfare)39 that by and large the colony of Victoria was conceived as predominantly British in character, supposedly bearing scant cultural trace of its earlier Aboriginal history.40 With nearby Melbourne taking the title of the “London of the south” and the comparatively temperate climate more proximate to what was familiar to Eu­ro­pe­an standards of comfort and health, the imaginary of the frontier had shifted both west and north by the 1870s, as the new Overland Telegraph line (completed in 1872) was staffing outposts through central regions in which few white people had previously traveled, let alone settled, and the discovery of gold in northern Queensland led to a boom of fortune-­seeking whites migrating to the northeastern tropics.41 Naturalizing the genocide of indigenous people in the wake of white contact was commonplace at the end of the nineteenth century. The observation that Aboriginal people would soon be extinct after civilization had made its purportedly inevitable inroads regularly graced the prefaces of ethnological texts that sought to justify the importance and urgency of their intellectual work. Neither Fison and Howitt nor Spencer and Gillen are exempt from such a charge, despite that both duos saw themselves as in 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 107 1/24/14 7:36 PM 108 Freud’s Australia a patronizing and protective relationship to the communities they studied—­and indeed, they did work to temper some of the most extreme forms of endemic settler violence. Spencer and Gillen open Native Tribes with the authorizing claim that “unless some special effort be made, many tribes will practically die out without our gaining any knowledge of the details of their organisation, or of their sacred customs and beliefs.”42 The exhortation that more ethnological research (and not a staunching of the pro­cesses of extinction) marks what is urgently needed with respect to Aboriginal people makes the practice of regarding ethnology as obituary writing a particularly egregious insouciance on the part of ethnological men who mostly considered themselves “sympathetic” to Aboriginal suffering. Morgan reasons similarly in his introduction to Kamilaroi and Kûrnai: “The Australian tribes,” he frets, “are melting away before the touch of civilization, even more rapidly than the American aborigines. In a lower ethnical condition than the latter, they have displayed less power of re­sis­ tance.”43 Thrusting the responsibility for the ravages of imperialism back onto colonized subjects themselves is a familiarly violent ideological maneuver through which the success of colonialism becomes its own justification. Under Morgan’s evolutionary system, the slightly more evolved Native American barbarians are better possessed than the Australian savages of the self-­awareness necessary to understanding and resisting the violent social impositions of civilization, and the evidence that they are slightly more evolved is that they are able to do so. Morgan’s rhetorical tautology reinscribes the notion that what distinguishes evolved humanity is the capacity to have a “mindful” response to imposed social conditions, be they one’s own or those of an imperial presence.44 The context of this nearly decimated Kûrnai population is crucial to understanding Fison and Howitt’s adaptation of Morgan’s evolutionary speculations about the history of the family. Kamilaroi and Kûrnai readily shares in the pervasive idea that savages remain in primitive stasis until forced to progress by some external force. In breaking down the community structures that grounded customary life, the recent genocide had “freed” the Kûrnai from the dictates of tribal law—­a crutch that, Fison and Howitt maintain, because savages reason deductively rather than inductively, had hindered their entry into Eu­ro­pe­an epistemology and its concomitant forms of sociality. In contrast, the idea that Eu­ro­pe­ans reason 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 108 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 109 inductively had allowed Kamilaroi and Kûrnai to imagine a Eu­ro­pe­an institutional life that emerges out of the reason of its polity rather than as a force that both imposes upon and controls the possibility of knowledge (the idea that induction can operate in­de­pen­dent of social setting remains a tacit assumption for Fison, just as the idea that Eu­ro­pe­ans might possess formal institutional cathexes is conspicuously absent). The Kûrnai provide what Fison and Howitt regard as a “missing link” in the paleontology of social institutions. Morgan’s Ancient Society (1877)—­t he text that Friedrich Engels would adapt to materialist history in The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State—­had elaborated a theory of the social evolution of marriage systems from matrilineal communalism to the monogamous patrilineal system that Morgan identified with civilized life. The debates around “primitive” marriage had been hugely influential on both sides of the Atlantic from the 1860s onward—­before which time, as Engels writes, “one cannot speak of a history of the family.”45 By the 1880s, the terms of the debate had focused rather on classification systems themselves than on the evolutionary speculation on origins that had been characteristic of Morgan’s generation. More advanced in their kinship systems than the Kamilaroi who retain a “primitive” system of group marriage, the Kûrnai “are a tribe of savages off the rails”46 because their marriage laws have been rendered untenable given the fact that they have lost about 90 percent of their population in less than forty years. With quite simply not enough people to permit the system of classes that, Fison and Howitt claim, had governed the greater sexual communalism of their earlier social or­ ga­ni­za­t ion, the Kûrnai ­were obliged to adapt to a partial “pairing system” that marked their course toward the civilized ideal of companionate and monogamous coupledom. In effect, the text implies, the Kûrnai had been forced into progress but died from its influence, thus providing would-­be evidence for the claim that savages could not adapt to the forms of civilized life. The new pairing kinship, however, is significant not only for the shifts it produces in social or­ga­ni­za­t ion but also for the changes in subject formation that result from it. Being thrust “off the rails,” it seems, may destroy tribes, but it creates individuals. In Kamilaroi and Kûrnai, the tendency of Australian tribes to subdivide into progressively larger numbers of marriage classes marks a gradual pro­cess of differentiation whereby the very fact of 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 109 1/24/14 7:36 PM 110 Freud’s Australia what is imagined as a too-­u niform collective unit becomes the model of primitivism that the pairing marriages help the Kûrnai to escape. “In the tribal divisions and subdivisions,” Fison writes, “we see what appears to be a steady progress towards the individualizing of the individual (if the phrase may be allowed), with a continued struggle against the old tribal law along all the line.”47 Fison’s presumption that “to the savage the group is the individual”48 is, as George Stocking notes, a clear adumbration of Emile Durkheim’s emphasis on primitive collective life in Elementary Forms of Religious Life—­a fact that is hardly surprising given Durkheim’s heavy reliance on Fison and Howitt’s work to provide the ethnological basis for his argument. “Progressing” toward Eu­ro­pe­an standards of civility means severing the ties that had hitherto, by this account, turned you into only a nodal extension of “the old tribal law” itself. Nonetheless, it is unclear what the unit struggling against tribal law is, ­here—­whether struggle happens in the same way and degree at all stages of “individualization,” whether old tribal law has always maintained a conflicted relationship with the collective unit of the tribe it governs, or whether the old tribal law is the residual legacy of an earlier tribal unit that it defined. In spite of this lack of clarity, they use their conceptualization of an aggregated, anti-­individualist savage state as a corrective to what they see as a malign communism spreading from the tenets of Rousseau: It was Rousseau’s deep sympathy with the woe and anguish of down-­t rodden humanity that gave life and apparent reason to the visionary fallacies of his writings. The twofold conception of man in a state of nature and man degraded from a primeval condition of innocence, became in its new form and its fantastic dress a potent agent in bringing about the first French Revolution. In the conception of the primitive in­de­pen­dent freedom and equality of mankind, Communism has its roots, and from these roots the future may see spring forth a growth that will perhaps cast a baleful shadow over the ­whole earth. The progression theory, on the contrary, is of modern origin, and has arisen through the scientific investigation and comparison of the social condition and customs of savage and barbarous races.49 For Fison, the collective identity of savages stands in contradistinction to the alliances and citizens produced by more civilized politics, and a return 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 110 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 111 to that collective life, so feared in his worried assessment of communism, is hardly desirable in its would-­be atavism. The shift that Fison locates ­here between what he describes as the “degradation” and “progressive” models of human history focuses not only on the kinds of people imagined to exist as the primitive models of humankind but also on the way that is imagined by specific disciplinary practices. The focus on the system of rules that governed societies as a ­whole seeks to undermine the myth of merger that had pervaded the Rousseauian idealization of savage life. Indeed, the basic gist of Fison’s critique recurs among more recent critics of Rousseau; aligning himself with both Jacques Derrida and Jean Starobinski, James Martel, for example, maintains that “neither of the options Rousseau initially presents us with—­rapturous merger with the other (as ‘citizens’), or radical isolation (as ‘men’)—­are particularly demo­cratic principles.”50 What looked like a happily collective, sufficiently transparent selfhood to Rousseau appears in Fison’s more “scientific” account as a collective unit so tightly bound to custom and law that its members have no possibility for knowing what “freedom” might be. Fison’s objections to Rousseau and his followers highlight the importance of the role of family forms in terms of producing individual persons with an appropriate relation to law. The shift to the civilized patrilineal family that Morgan and Engels alike identified as a necessary, foundational principle of the nineteenth-­century Eu­ro­pe­a n state was seemingly contingent upon violence, just as the transition to this state entailed a fair quotient of “residual” (to use Raymond Williams’s historiographical terminology) kinship formation. Both Fison and Howitt see vestiges of communal marriage present as a cultural “default” that reemerges in the moments when the conjugal couple falters. Howitt, likely recalling the spearing of an “eloping” married woman he had witnessed in 1876,51 mused: “The expected fidelity towards the husband was enforced under severe penalties. In the event of a woman eloping with some other man, all the neighbouring men might turn out and seek for her, and, in the event of her being discovered, she became common property to them until released by her husband or her male relatives. The husband, on his part, probably speared her. Her life was in his hand.”52 With little language invoking anger or lust (either by the men or the woman), the “penalties” ­here are characterized as a matter of course, evoking a rather different tone from the reportage of violence 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 111 1/24/14 7:36 PM 112 Freud’s Australia focused on savage events, such as the Ripper murders, in the metropole. The banality of the language of law and entitlement belies the fact that this type of scene is supposedly the evidence of the newfound individualism that Fison lauds with such fervor. The penalties function as a toggle between two systems rather than as violations of either. Glossing Howitt’s narrative, Fison summarizes the practice with the statement, “By her own act she has severed the tie which, binding her to her husband, guarded her against the old communal right, and forthwith that right asserts itself.”53 The language of protection that Fison employs in the description of the couple form elides all questions about unwanted subjection to the sole husband’s “right,” just as elsewhere he emphasizes that group marriage is not a thing of contract. The fact that the woman in question sends herself into the expectation of communal right “by her own act” emphasizes the fact that the paired couple is contractual and chosen, both in entering into and departing from the couple; nowhere does Fison so much as intimate that a woman could ever opt to return to communal right. The structure of group sex forecloses the conditions of contract. Desert Hearts In 1903, Emile Durkheim and Marcel Mauss published a jointly authored text titled Primitive Classification, published as an essay in the pages of the Année sociologique. The essay’s conclusion relied on two interlocking arguments that extend the idea that communal right precludes individual choice into a ­wholesale theory of savage epistemology. First, Durkheim and Mauss suggest that savages classify things in the world in the terms of categories produced by affectively generated social relations; second, they argue that the attachment savages evince toward their social or­ga­ni­za­tion forecloses their capacity for self-­consciousness: “Scientific classification,” they write, “is, in the last analysis, the history of the stages by which this element of social affectivity has progressively weakened, leaving more and more room for the reflective thought of individuals.”54 The pa­ram­e­ters of this argument recollect Freud’s thematization of instinctive institutions in that they suggest a nonreflexive pro­cess of classification that produces a too-­t ightly focused attachment to savage law, as a result of which savages effectively 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 112 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 113 become a bundle of diverse but specific and focused instinctive cathexes to customary practices. In claiming that “social affectivity” designates savage overattachment to law and custom, Durkheim and Mauss ­were summarizing a tendency in Australian ethnological writing that had been developed, more explicitly than in Fison and Howitt’s work, in Spencer and Gillen’s famous ethnography Native Tribes of Central Australia. Spencer and Gillen ­were believed to be in a more credible position from which to imagine such an overattached social affectivity in that they regarded the Arrernte people they studied as standing in different relation to civilization than did the Kûrnai in Fison and Howitt’s assessment. Fison and Howitt interest themselves in the Kûrnai because they believe they demonstrate the effects of civilization on the “progress” of savage culture; Spencer and Gillen ­were, in contrast, fascinated with the Arrernte because of what they regarded as their relative lack of contact with white norms. Setting made a big difference in this respect in that, unlike the sizeable and well-­established white population in Victoria, the Central Desert saw only a scattering of Eu­ro­pe­a n settlement. While the Telegraph Station at Charlotte Waters, where Gillen was based; the police camp and nascent settlement at Stuart (later Alice Springs); and the Lutheran mission at Hermannsburg all marked an increased white presence in the Central Desert, it was nonetheless small enough to preserve the myth of a surrounding natural Aboriginal culture in need of investigation before whites would eventually eradicate it. This context also helped facilitate the idealization of untouched autochthony as the sought-­after ethnological commodity (the idea that their own presence as observers might in any way affect their ideal of a true native object available for white speculation remains unmentioned—­never mind the fact that not even Gillen was fully fluent in the Arrernte language).55 Gillen, indeed, occasionally hesitated about whether to interview Arrernte people in the Hermannsburg mission because their at least nominal conversion to Christianity rendered them suspect as pure examples of customary indigeneity.56 The emphasis on marriage classes in Native Tribes of Central Australia thus assumes a greater sense of unfamiliarity between its subjects of enquiry and its implied readers. The language of instinct appears no more ­here than it does in Kamilaroi and Kûrnai, but the way Native Tribes deploys the emotional category of jealousy mirrors Freud’s use of instinct in relation to the 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 113 1/24/14 7:36 PM 114 Freud’s Australia savage institutions. In Freud’s work, emotions regularly appear as the ideational formations of the affect that is a component of instinctive energy. Because of this connection between instinct and emotion, Freud is able to derive a theory of the interrelations between instinct and institutions from ethnological studies that use institutions to substitute for instinct as well as for emotion. With that in mind, it is worth observing that jealousy is the only term that appears in Spencer and Gillen’s index to Native Tribes of Central Australia that would have been recognizable as an emotion word to a turn-­of-­t he-­century audience. At that, it gets scant mention, with Spencer and Gillen only briefly noting its absence among Arrernte people. Spencer and Gillen highlight the difference between Eu­ro­pe­a n and Arrernte sexual affective economies by noting that Arrernte attachment to custom acts as a substitute for jealousy. “For a man,” Spencer and Gillen write, “to have unlawful intercourse with any woman arouses a feeling which is due not so much to jealousy as to the fact that the delinquent has infringed a tribal custom.”57 Arrernte men, by Spencer and Gillen’s account, experience a binding to law that is as psychically entrenched as the naturalized accounts of jealousy that appear in the plots of Eu­ro­pe­an domestic fiction—­a fact that both serves to distance them from the complex emotional psyches of Eu­ro­ pe­an men and naturalize their experience of legality. While jealousy may be understood as natural and tolerable because ubiquitous in bourgeois Eu­ro­pe­an life, it is not typically an object of aspiration or idealization that surrounds the discourse around the law. Immanent, moreover, rather than transcendent, sudden and reactionary rather than stable and noumenal, the idea that savages relate to law as a jealous husband does to his wife brings us back to the fact of the undue attachment to customary institutions that had so troubled Fison and Howitt. Jealousy, after all, typically figures in the plots of domestic novels as something slightly unseemly and beyond propriety. In the context of instinctive institutions, then, the intimacy that both Fison and Howitt and Spencer and Gillen predicate of savages and tribal law entails a focused attachment to specific customary precepts in and of themselves—­t hat is, minus any relation to legality as an abstraction. The temporalization of savage law and affect as insistently immediate and immanent allowed for savages to be characterized as disinterested in futurity. Spencer and Gillen observe that Arrernte people are not invested 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 114 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 115 enough in the future in the abstract, although they may experience specific moments of fear—­a fact that suggests more of the immediate, focused, and unreflecting responsiveness that often, though not always, characterized the instinctive in Darwinian accounts of animal behavior (and, indeed, in the writings of many of his pre­de­ces­sors in natural philosophy, although I do not have the space to rehearse this history ­here). Spencer and Gillen write: There is, however, in these, as in other savage tribes, an undercurrent of anxious feeling which, though it may be stilled and, indeed, forgotten for a time, is yet always present. . . . It is, however, easy to lay too much stress upon this, for h ­ ere again we have to put ourselves into the mental attitude of the savage, and must not imagine simply what would be our own feelings under such circumstances. It is not right, by any means, to say that the Australian native lives in constant dread of the evil magic of an enemy. The feeling is always, as it ­were, lying dormant and ready to be at once called up by any strange or suspicious sound if he be alone, especially at night time, in the bush; but on the other hand, just like a child, he can with ease forget anything unpleasant and enter perfectly into the enjoyment of the present moment.58 As I discussed in the first chapter, John Locke and his followers famously maintained that anxiety is a necessary basis for liberalism and for the development of desire as an economic motivator. The version of anxiety that emerges in Native Tribes is derided not for the false or irrational fears that Eu­ro­pe­ans sometimes identified with savages but rather for not being sufficiently continuously present. In Spencer and Gillen’s analysis, the idea that anxiety might be dormant is deemed childlike in such a way that implies, by way of negative contrast, the figure of a civilized adult man who productively spends his time vigilant and worried as, indeed, a condition of his capacity to desire. This position of course replicates the opinion, as I observed in the last chapter, of nineteenth-­century po­liti­cal economists as different as John Stuart Mill and William Stanley Jevons, who could nonetheless agree that the absence of this desire was the source of savages’ lack of access to the goods promised by liberal economic theory. Freud’s argument in Totem and Taboo that savage social institutions form part and parcel of savage instincts suggests that part of what is savage about savages is their focused intimacy with their specific customary precepts. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 115 1/24/14 7:36 PM 116 Freud’s Australia The focused, object-­specific quality of instinctive attachment applies, however, to fear as much as to law (remembering that, for Freud, the potent psychic reality of a thing is not dependent on its material reality). When, for example, Adam Phillips attends to the distinction between fear and anxiety (“Fear has an object, anxiety has a vague location”),59 he notes that Freud wavers in his position on whether analysts should seek to identify par­tic­u­lar objects of ill-­defined anxiety or to demonstrate the psychic irrelevance of par­tic­u­lar objects to the structure of fear.60 Phillips’s obser­ vations parallel the discussion of object specificity that concerns Laplanche and Davidson in Freud’s theory of the instincts. When Spencer and Gillen suggest that savages can experience acute dread while simultaneously manifesting insufficient anxiety, they effectively maintain that savage instincts can be distinguished from civilized desire because their focused immediacy places them outside of the extended temporal horizons necessary for appropriate economic motivation. Anxiety is figured in Spencer and Gillen’s account as commendable emotional preparedness for the possibility of calamity in general; fear, in contrast, emerges as an overfocused, irrational state that ascribes too much power to specific objects. Freud, Redux It might, then, be less surprising that Freud’s most influential move in theorizing Eu­ro­pe­an sexual instincts consisted of severing the model of focused attachment between instinct and object that we have seen to inform these accounts of savage instinctive institutional life. If Eu­ro­pe­an po­liti­cal forms are valued, in contradistinction to savage ones, for their supposedly greater proximity to the conditions of abstract generality, instinct becomes similarly modeled in Freud’s estimation. Such a move, flying in the face of instinct’s object-­bound definition in the nineteenth century, nonetheless proves difficult for Freud to maintain. Laplanche notes that the status of particularity with respect to both the aims and objects of both drives and instincts remains a quandary that Freud never fully resolves: The question then arises of determining the relation between an aim which is entirely general and (as with “impetus”) abstract—­t he appeasing of tension—­ 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 116 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 117 and, on the other hand, the very specific and determined acts which are the aims of various instincts: eating, seeing (since one finds in Freud a “drive to see”), making love, ­etc. The problem is that of the specification of the aim: why is it that something quite specific and not simply appeasement represents the final aim?61 In what way is either an instinct or a drive in­de­pen­dent of its actions and objects? How general can satisfaction be? What, if anything, allows an instinct to be delineated from another with any particularity? What limits can be placed on the possibilities of what can appease an instinct? In attempting to lay out a distinction between drives and instincts, Laplanche observes that the two share analogical definitions in that they can both be described in relation to impetus, object, aim, and source.62 While noting, as many others have done, that Freud is lamentably inconsistent in this aspect of his terminology, Laplanche nonetheless ventures the idea that drives can be distinguished from yet related to instincts through “propping” (étayage). Laplanche’s desire to retain the aspect of reproduction and self-­preservation as the definitions of instinct most appropriate to the Freud of the Three Essays leads him to separate drives and instincts with reference to Freud’s famous analysis of the autoerotic plea­sure in sucking that, Freud claims, emerges in reference to breastfeeding. For Laplanche, the anaclitic moment is a key model of the instinct/drive relationship because it highlights both the bond and the departure of sexuality from a vital, self-­preservative function. “Without the terminological coherence of Freud’s writings being absolutely systematic,” Laplanche writes, “we shall nevertheless find, in a manner sufficiently motivated to allow us in turn to ‘lean’ upon it, that the terms function, need, and instinct characterize generally the vital register of self-­preservation in opposition to the sexual register.”63 While the theory of ego instincts and the death drive was yet to be elaborated as such, the splitting off of the sexual from the self-­preservative that Freud describes in the breastfeeding anecdote in the Three Essays opens up the space that will allow that distinction to emerge more concretely fifteen years later. Freud’s theorization h ­ ere allows the arena of the sexual to be separated from that of reproduction and self-­preservation by means of an imaginative production of the civilized individual—­indeed, it is this imaginative 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 117 1/24/14 7:36 PM 118 Freud’s Australia production that designates, for Laplanche, the orbit of the properly sexual. If, as I pointed out in the Introduction, Michel Foucault is right in maintaining that, as early as 1840, sexologists began to unyoke instinct from reproduction in order to align it with plea­sure and imagination,64 Freud’s innovation in this regard was not unpre­ce­dented. But in terms of the sociology of instinct that interests us h ­ ere, this severing matters because it allows us to see the difference in the application of instinct to Eu­ro­pe­ans and savages. Civilized neurotics may have individualizing particularity in their objects and aims, but they are individual precisely because they reflect a personal adaptation of a species-­wide, itinerant instinctive substance. Something akin to the way in which, for Lacan, being the phallus precludes wielding it, savages, because they are identified with the objects of their instincts, are denied that particularity of having individually produced objects and aims for an instinct imagined as universal in its unattached aimlessness. The varying answers to the question of how instinct attaches to its objects and aims have been crucial in the debates over the value of psychoanalysis for feminist and queer studies projects, as the question of whether appropriately gendered heterosexuality remains a “natural” telos in Freud’s thought or a contingent, socially conditioned accident.65 What remains underemphasized in accounts of instincts such as Laplanche’s, however, is that Freud’s modification to the theory of instinct and drive had the effect of recasting instinct as something that was increasingly valuable to privileged, white Eu­ro­pe­ans (however diseased these latter might be). In a moment when sexuality became something that could provide at least bourgeois Eu­ro­pe­ans with a means of self-­identification, the dynamics around savages and sexual “identification” ­were quite different. In Samuel Butler’s satiric Erewhon (1872), the savage Chowbok who leads the narrator to the beautiful but diseased titular settlement can nonetheless not enter it himself because he is paralyzed by his fear of gruesome totems barring the way.66 This state of affairs, nevertheless, is apparently for the best: Chowbok and his kin, the narrator informs us, would have been too ugly to be allowed to exist freely in Erewhon anyhow.67 In spite of the anagrammatic “nowhere” of the title, the novel’s setting bears striking affinity in geography, climate, and industry to the pastoral regions of the Antipodes. (Not so coincidentally, Butler lived in New Zealand between 1858 and 1864.) The savage guide who cannot enter Butler’s diseased parody of Eu­rope tells us 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 118 1/24/14 7:36 PM Freud’s Australia 119 something about the relationship between savages and neurotics that Freud lays out in Totem and Taboo. In Erewhon, being sent to the “straightener” to help cure the ailment of embezzlement remains a pitiable but socially acceptable state of affairs; being physically ill, in contrast, is punishable by imprisonment or death. The critique of medicalizing what had formerly been identified as a punishable moral issue appears as a fairly clear critical transposition of the discourse around the medicalization of sexuality that Foucault has so famously predicated of Butler’s era. The fact, however, that Chowbok leads the narrator to this inverted world but cannot enter it allegorizes the relationship between savage instincts and Eu­ro­pe­an neurotics that I have been describing ­here. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 119 1/24/14 7:36 PM notes Introduction 1. At this point, the OED was still entitled New En­glish Dictionary on Historical Principles Founded Mainly on the Materials Collected by the Philological Society. The entry for “Instinct” was originally published in 1900, in the “Input-­I nvalid” fascicle. In 1901, the Input-­I nvalid entries w ­ ere subsumed into the Dictionary’s Volume V, which contained all the entries for words beginning with H, I, J, and K. I am citing this entry, omitting the passages cited to exemplify usage. This definition of instinct has, moreover, yet to be revised and is still the one in use in the OED as of 2013. James Murray, ed., “Instinct,” A New En­glish Dictionary on Historical Principles Founded Mainly on the Materials Collected by the Philological Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1901), 352. 2. Robert J. Richards notes that “From the resources of Aristotle’s De anima, Avicenna developed a theory of ‘instinct’ in Kitāb al-­shifā, the Sufficientiae of the Medieval translation. The distinctive and skillful behaviors of different species evinced to him that the estimative faculty, that internal sense which detected intentiones, was infused with a divine ‘inspiration’ (ilhām, rendered by the Latin translator variously as cautela naturalis and instinctus insitus).” Robert Richards, “The Evolution of Behavior: Theories of Instinct in the Nineteenth Century with an Essay on Animal Instinct and Intelligence Before Darwin” (Chicago: University of Chicago, Department of History, 1978), 14n1. 3. Freud’s tendency to prefer the German word Trieb over the German word Instinkt has led recent translators to distinguish between drive (Trieb) and instinct (Instinkt). I will have more to say on the Trieb/Instinkt distinction later in this book, but for the moment I would like to note that while there are valid theoretical reasons for enforcing this distinction between drive and instinct, it risks obscuring the fact that even Trieb was formulated in dialogue with the instinct theories that w ­ ere being published in En­glish during Freud’s lifetime. 4. Providing an elaborate history of the natural philosophy of instinct is beyond the scope of this project. For an account of the different strands of 159 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 159 1/24/14 7:36 PM 160 Notes to pages 000–000 belief about instinct within natural philosophy, see especially Richards, “The Evolution of Behavior,” 20–­70. 5. Herbert Spencer, for instance, argues that instinct is “a compound reflex action,” a form of agency distinguished from simple reflex because it demands coordination between different organs and functions in the body. Herbert Spencer, The Principles of Psychology (New York: D., 1883), 1:432. Tony Bennett points out that Spencer’s theorization means that, for him, “there is no break ­here between habit and the will, just a seamless transition.” Tony Bennett, “Habit, Instinct, Survivals: Repetition, History, Biopower,” in The Peculiarities of Liberal Modernity in Imperial Britain, ed. Simon Gunn and James Vernon (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011), 110. 6. Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, vol. 1: An Introduction (New York: Vintage, 1990), 43. 7. Michel Foucault, Abnormal: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1974–­1975, ed. Valerio Marchetti and Antonella Salomoni, trans. Graham Burchell (New York: Picador USA, 2003), 132. 8. Ibid. 9. Ibid., 139, 276. 10. Patrick Joyce develops the argument that the liberal state uses “po­liti­cal freedom as a means of governance.” Patrick Joyce, Demo­c ratic Subjects: The Self and the Social in Nineteenth-­Century En­gland (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 3. 11. Penelope Deutscher, “Foucault’s The History of Sexuality Volume 1: Rereading Its Reproduction,” Theory, Culture & Society 29, no. 1 (January 2012): 120. Nancy Armstrong, “Gender Must Be Defended,” South Atlantic Quarterly 111, no. 3 (2012): 535. 12. William James, The Principles of Psychology (New York: Dover, 1950), 2:383. 13. Lynne Huffer, Mad for Foucault: Rethinking the Foundations of Queer Theory (New York: Columbia University Press, 2010), 36. 14. Ibid. 15. Michel Foucault, Psychiatric Power: Lectures at the Collège de France 1973–­ 1974, ed. Jacques Lagrange, trans. Graham Burchell (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006), 215. 16. Ibid. 17. Lee Edelman, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2004), 5. 18. Walter Bagehot, Physics and Politics (London: Kegan Paul, 1887), 124–­125. 19. Anthony Trollope, Can You Forgive Her? (London: Chapman and Hall, 1865), 2:147. 20. Ibid. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 160 1/24/14 7:36 PM Notes to pages 000–000 161 21. The classic text on the psychology of urban life at the turn of the twentieth century in Eu­rope remains George Simmel’s “The Metropolis and Mental Life,” in which Simmel argues that “the psychological foundation upon which the modern individuality is erected, is the intensification of emotional life due to the swift and continuous shift of external and internal stimuli.” Georg Simmel, “The Metropolis and Mental Life,” in The Blackwell City Reader, ed. Gary Bridge and Sophie Watson, 2nd ed. (London: Wiley-­Blackwell, 2010), 103. In terms of the effects of the emergence of mass population’s effects on governmentality, Nancy Armstrong argues, following Foucault, that “the mass body that emerges in nineteenth-­century literature—­w ith the increase in urban populations, the extension of empire into the colonies, and the migration of w ­ hole demographic groups across regional and national boundaries—­ was (in contrast to those that both Hobbes and John Locke imagined) not one that could be broken down into individual bodies. Nor could this body be understood as a single unified people.” Armstrong, “Gender Must Be Defended,” 535. 22. Jonathan Parry, The Politics of Patriotism: En­glish Liberalism, National Identity, and Eu­ rope, 1830–­ 1886 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 89. 23. Uday Singh Mehta, Liberalism and Empire: A Study in Nineteenth-­Century British Liberal Thought (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 20, 23. 24. For Hadley, liberal cognition designates the “quite specific techniques of thought production and judgment, such as ‘free thought,’ reflection, abstraction, logical reasoning, and internal deliberation” that formalize the production of liberal ideas. Elaine Hadley, Living Liberalism: Practical Citizenship in Mid-­V ictorian Britain (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2010), 9, 14. 25. Widespread debates internal to liberalism over franchise extension, Irish Home Rule, tax and tariff reforms, state intervention in education and the economy, military expenditure and imperialism, and acceptable methods for pacifying class conflict all provide ample evidence of the different presumptions about governance and personhood that could be legitimated in accordance with “liberal principles.” For a history of some of these debates, see especially Parry, The Politics of Patriotism, 43–­85. Most historians note that liberalism becomes more collectivist and prointerventionist later in the century, with the advent of New Liberalism. The classic history of this change remains Michael Freeden, The New Liberalism: An Ideology of Social Reform (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978). More recently, Zarena Aslami has emphasized that while New Liberals believed in a collectivist stance on state welfare, they nonetheless “by no means abandoned an individualist model of the self.” Zarena Aslami, The Dream Life of Citizens: Late Victorian Novels and the Fantasy of the State (New York: Fordham University Press, 2012), 148. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 161 1/24/14 7:36 PM 162 Notes to pages 000–000 26. Most historians of the Liberal Party attribute the rise of formal party politics to the reor­ga­ni­za­t ion and cohesion produced by William Ewart Gladstone from the late 1860s onward. On Liberal Party or­ga­n i­za­t ion during this period, see especially Martin Pugh, The Making of Modern British Politics, 1867–­ 1939, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), 23. 27. Locke’s importance to histories of British liberalism is most famously attributed to C. B. McPherson’s now-­classic 1962 account of possessive individualism. See C. B. MacPherson, The Po­liti­cal Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011). 28. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 105–­106. 29. Jonathan Kramnick, Actions and Objects from Hobbes to Richardson (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2010), 15. 30. Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, 512. 31. For an example of this kind of thinking, see the work of Charles-­ Georges LeRoy, the author of a series influential essays on animal behavior first printed in the Encyclopédie Méthodique in 1764 and republished in Nature in 1871. On LeRoy’s contributions to the natural philosophy of the 1760s, see Robert J. Richards, Darwin and the Emergence of Evolutionary Theories of Mind and Behavior (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 26. LeRoy’s writings ­were republished in Nature in 1871. Alfred Russel Wallace observes that “M. Leroy appears to reject altogether what is commonly termed Instinct, maintaining that the word should be applied only to those acts which are the direct consequences of organisation, such as the grazing of the stag, or the flesh-­eating of the fox; but not to the expedients to which those animals resort in the gratification of their natural wants, which are due to sensation, observation, memory, and experience. To the objection that many animals perform complex operations perfectly well without experience, and always in the same manner, he replies that in many cases the fact is not so.” 32. Hadley, Living Liberalism, 50, 50n18. 33. Elizabeth Povinelli, “Notes on Gridlock: Genealogy, Intimacy, Sexuality,” Public Culture 14, no. 1 (2002): 216. 34. Ibid., 228. 35. Ibid., 227. 36. Ibid., 216. 37. Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 1:139. 38. Ibid. 39. Foucault’s example h ­ ere is the family. See ibid., 1:100. 40. Ibid., 1:54–­55. 41. Ibid., 1:68. 42. A lexander Pope, “Essay on Man,” in The Works of Alexander Pope, ed. Whitwell Elwin, vol. 2 (London: John Murray, 1871), III.ii:98, III.ii:83–­84. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 162 1/24/14 7:36 PM Notes to pages 000–000 163 43. Richards, Darwin and the Emergence of Evolutionary Theories of Mind and Behavior, 23n5. 44. David J. DePew, “The Rhetoric of the Origin of Species,” ed. Michael Ruse and Robert J. Richards (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 244. 45. St. George Mivart, “Organic Nature’s Riddle,” The Fortnightly Review 43, no. 219, New Series (March 1, 1885): 591. 46. Erasmus Darwin, Zoonomia; Or, the Laws of Organic Life, 2nd ed. (London: J. Johnson, 1796), 1:137. 47. Pope, “Essay on Man,” III.ii:92. 48. Thomas Malthus, An Essay on the Principle of Population, ed. Antony Flew (London: Penguin, 1983), 76. 49. Foucault, Psychiatric Power, 215. 50. Malthus, An Essay on the Principle of Population, 253. 51. Catherine Gallagher, The Body Economic: Life, Death, and Sensation in Po­ liti­cal Economy and the Victorian Novel (Prince­ton, N.J.: Prince­ton University Press, 2006), 159. 52. Darwin, Zoonomia, 1:137–­138. On Erasmus Darwin’s rejection of “preestablished” instinct, see especially Richards, Darwin and the Emergence of Evolutionary Theories of Mind and Behavior, 34–­36. 53. Jean-­Baptiste Lamarck, “Habitude,” in Nouveau dictionnaire d’histoire naturelle (Paris: J. Deterville, 1817), 14:130. 54. Jean-­Baptiste Lamarck, Système analytique des connaissances positives de l’homme (Paris: A. Belin, 1920), 193–­194. 55. See Richard W. Burkhardt, “Lamarck, Cuvier, and Darwin on Animal Behavior and Acquired Characters,” in Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology, ed. Snait B. Gissis and Eva Jablonka (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2011), 33–­4 4. Also see Richard Burkhardt, The Spirit of System: Lamarck and Evolutionary Biology (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995), 155. 56. Lamarck, Système analytique des connaissances positives de l’homme, 216–­217. 57. Michael Davis points out that “any instinct, in Darwin’s view, arises in the context of the lived experience of many generations: it is an adaptation, rather than an essential, immutable feature of species and, as such, is open to further change in the future.” Michael Davis, George Eliot and Nineteenth-­ Century Psychology: Exploring the Unmapped Country (Burlington, Vt.: Ashgate, 2006), 55. Charlotte Sleigh suggests that although Darwin at times rejects “habit-­ based instinct acquisition” (153), he also acknowledges that “habits might be inherited and thus to all intents and purposes become indistinguishable from instinct” (153). Charlotte Sleigh, “ ‘The Ninth Mortal Sin’: The Lamarckism of M. W. Wheeler,” in Darwinian Heresies, ed. Abigail Lustig, Robert 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 163 1/24/14 7:36 PM 164 Notes to pages 000–000 J. Richards, and Michael Ruse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 153. 58. The most sustained argument of this sort in the history of biology remains Peter J. Bowler, The Non-­Darwinian Revolution: Reinterpreting a Historical Myth (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992). I will discuss the primacy of Lamarckian evolution in the history of sexology further in Chapter 2. 59. A lthough he had already heard Malthusian theory discussed, Darwin first read Malthus’s Essay in the fall of 1838 and was compelled by the hostility of nature that he identified in Malthus’s work. See Adrian Desmond and James Moore, Darwin: The Life of a Tormented Evolutionist (New York: Norton, 1994), 264–­265. 60. Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species. Facsimile of the First Edition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1859), 209. 61. Darwin writes in the Origin that natural selection “is the doctrine of Malthus applied with manifold force to the ­whole animal vegetable kingdom.” Ibid., 63. 62. Isabelle Stengers, The Invention of Modern Science, trans. Daniel W. Smith (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000), 162. 63. Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-­Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Prince­ton, N.J.: Prince­ton University Press, 1985), 107. 64. On the modern constitution, see Bruno Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, trans. Catherine Porter (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993), 34. 65. Richard Yeo observes that “between 1781 and 1840 the monopoly of the Royal Society was overthrown by the foundation of some two dozen specialist scientific societies. By the early nineteenth century, the entries on these general terms in major encyclopaedias ­were displaced by detailed articles on separate disciplines; if included at all, they invariably pointed the reader to the entries on specific subjects. Similarly, the people who studied the natural world ­were coming to be identified as astronomers, chemists, botanists, or geologists.” See Richard Yeo, Defining Science: William Whewell, Natural Knowledge, and Public Debate in Early Victorian Britain (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 33. 66. There is a large literature on the concept of po­liti­cal “repre­sen­ta­t ion” in the Victorian period. Catherine Gallagher offers an important early study on the connections between the concept of repre­sen­ta­t ion in politics and in literature. David Lloyd and Paul Thomas examine how “culture” operated as a pedagogy through which Victorians came to learn what it meant to be represented po­liti­cally. David Lloyd and Paul Thomas, Culture and the State (New York: Routledge, 1997), 5–­7; Catherine Gallagher, The Industrial Reformation of En­ 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 164 1/24/14 7:36 PM Notes to pages 000–000 165 glish Fiction: Social Discourse and Narrative from 1832–­1867 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), 187–­268. 67. Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, trans. Daniel Heller-­Roazen (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1998), 9. 68. Ibid., 9–­10. 69. Ibid., 7. 70. Aihwa Ong, for instance, suggests that Agamben focuses too exclusively on the arena of law, thus missing out on “other systems for valuing and devaluing bodies,” and that his “bifurcation of the population” into po­liti­cal beings and bare life does not do justice, either po­liti­cally or ethnographically, to the complexity of the “shifting legal and moral terrain of humanity.” See Aihwa Ong, Neoliberalism as Exception: Mutations in Citizenship and Sovereignty (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2006), 22–­23, 197. In Paul Rabinow and Nikolas R ­ ose’s reading, Agamben’s apparent belief that all sovereign power is backed up by the threat of death forgets that Foucault’s understanding of the immanence of productive power means that the threat of death is not, in fact, “the guarantee or underpinning principle of all forms of biopower.” Paul Rabinow and Nikolas ­Rose, “Biopower Today,” BioSocieties 1 (2006): 201. 71. Ong, Neoliberalism as Exception, 22. Rabinow and ­Rose, “Biopower Today,” 202. 1. Reading Like an Animal 1. George John Romanes, The Natural History of Instinct: A Lecture Delivered to the Tyneside Sunday Lecture Society, November 22, 1885 (London: Walter Scott, 1886), 24. 2. Writing in 1879, only a few years before Romanes, the French entomologist Jean Henri Fabre orients his discussion of the theory of instinct with reference to this type of wasp and its provision of living food for its buried grubs. See Jean-­Henri Fabre, Souvenirs entomologiques. Études sur l’instinct et les moeurs des insectes (Paris: Delagrave, 1891), 1:186. Solitary wasps that exhibit this kind of behavior have a long history in French entomology in that they also occupy a prominent place in Rene Antoine de Reaumur’s early account of insect behavior. See René Antoine Ferchault de Réaumur, Mémoires pour servir a‘ l’histoire des insectes (Paris: de l’Imprimerie royale, 1734), 251–­265. J. F. M. Clark claims that the En­glish entomologist Henry Brougham used the case of the sphex to mediate a “middle ground between Darwin and Paley.” See J. F. M. Clark, Bugs and the Victorians (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 2009), 37. Darwin, having read Fabre, directed Romanes’s attention to the creature in a letter during 1881. See George John Romanes, The Life and Letters of George John Romanes, ed. Ethel Duncan Romanes (New York: Longmans, Green and Co., 1896), 109–­112. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 165 1/24/14 7:36 PM 182 Notes to pages 000–000 91. Ibid., 57. 92. Ibid., 51. 93. Edward Carpenter, Sex-­Love, and Its Place in a Free Society (Manchester: Labour Press Society, 1894), 6–­7. 94. Ibid., 10. 95. Elisabeth Bronfen, Over Her Dead Body: Death, Femininity, and the Aesthetic (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1996), 157. 96. Elizabeth Freeman, Time Binds: Queer Temporalities, Queer Histories (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2010), 9. While Freeman finds the argument of No Future “compelling,” she worries that it “risks . . . evacuating the messiest thing about being queer: the actual meeting of bodies with other bodies and with objects.” Ibid., xxi. For Edelman, the drive represents a surplus in the fabric of the social that “dissolves those congealments of identity that permit us to know and survive as ourselves.” Lee Edelman, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2004), 17. 97. Judith Halberstam, Skin Shows: Gothic Horror and the Technology of Monsters (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 1995), 36–­37. 98. The literature on queer sexuality and the Gothic is large. On male homoerotics in Frankenstein see, for instance, Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, The Coherence of Gothic Conventions (New York: Methuen, 1980), vii–­x; Anne Mellor, Mary Shelley: Her Life, Her Fiction, Her Monsters (New York: Routledge, 1989), 121; George Haggerty, Queer Gothic (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2006), 52–­57; Freeman, Time Binds, 96–­105. On sexuality, science, and the late Victorian Gothic see especially Kelly Hurley, The Gothic Body: Sexuality, Materialism, and Degeneration at the Fin-­de-­Siècle (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 117–­150. 99. Halberstam, Skin Shows, 37–­38. 100. Nancy Armstrong, “Gender Must Be Defended,” South Atlantic Quarterly 111, no. 3 (2012): 536. 3. Freud’s Australia 1. John Stuart Mill and Harriet Taylor Mill, “The Subjection of Women,” in Essays on Sex Equality, ed. Alice Rossi (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), 128. 2. Ibid. 3. William James, The Principles of Psychology (New York: Dover, 1950), 2:389. 4. Freud published the first two essays of what would become Totem und Tabu in Otto Rank and Hanns Sach’s newly founded journal Imago in 1912; the third and fourth essays w ­ ere published in the same periodical in 1913, during which year all four ­were collected and published in book form. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 182 1/24/14 7:36 PM Notes to pages 000–000 183 5. Arnold Davidson, The Emergence of Sexuality: Historical Epistemology and the Formation of Concepts (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001), 79; Jean Laplanche, Life and Death in Psychoanalysis, trans. Jeffrey Mehlman (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976). 6. Mill and Mill, “The Subjection of Women,” 128. 7. Jacques Lacan, “On Freud’s Trieb and the Psychoanalyst’s Desire,” in Reading Seminars I and II: Lacan’s Return to Freud, ed. Richard Feldstein, Bruce Fink, and Maire Jaanus, trans. Bruce Fink (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1996), 417. 8. Adrian Johnston, Time Driven: Metapsychology and the Splitting of the Drive (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 2005), 156. 9. Sigmund Freud, Totem und Tabu: Einege Übereinstmmungen im Seelenleben der Wilden und der Neûrotiker (Leipzig: Internationaler Psychoanalytischer Verlag, 1920), 165. 10. Sigmund Freud, Totem and Taboo, trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton, 1990), 4. 11. James Frazer, Totemism and Exogamy: A Treatise on Certain Early Forms of Superstition and Society (London: Macmillan, 1910), 4:97. 12. Freud, Totem and Taboo, 154. 13. Freud first began to theorize narcissism in 1910, beginning a pro­cess that would eventually lead to aggregation of the self-­preservative and sexual instincts as “life instincts” in Beyond the Plea­sure Principle. 14. Peter Gay, Freud: A Life for Our Time (New York: Norton, 1988), 328. 15. Mikkel Borch-­Jacobsen, Lacan: The Absolute Master, trans. Douglas Brick (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1991), 29. 16. The subtitle on many editions of Totem and Taboo is Several Congruencies in the Mental Life of Savages and Neurotics. Peter Gay observes that Freud surpasses the promise of his subtitle, investigating in addition the congruencies between savages and all forms of thought. Gay, Freud, 328. 17. Freud, Totem and Taboo, 92. 18. Ibid., 81. 19. Freud was able to sustain this analogy because, as Ranjana Khanna observes, his reliance on Lamarck’s idea that acquired characteristics could be inherited “offered him a way to conceptualize the relationship between individual and group without having to share Jung’s theories of a collective unconscious.” Ranjana Khanna, Dark Continents: Psychoanalysis and Colonialism (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2003), 81. 20. The word is either not mentioned at all or mentioned only with respect to animals in all of the ethnological works discussed in this essay (namely, Spencer and Gillen’s Native Tribes of Central Australia, Fison and Howitt’s Kamilaroi and Kûrnai, and Morgan’s Ancient Society). None of the major ethnological works written about Australia rely on the term. It is absent in, for example, 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 183 1/24/14 7:36 PM 184 Notes to pages 000–000 Spencer and Gillen’s Northern Tribes of Central Australia, Edward Curr’s The Australian Race, William Pridden’s Australia: Its History and Present Condition, George French Angas’s Savage Life and Scenes in Australia and New Zealand, and Richard Sadleir’s The Aborigines of Australia. Among all the essays in The Native Tribes of South Australia, only J. D. Woods’s introduction mentions instinct at all; it does so to claim that the savage finds civilized life to be “foreign to his instincts and to his habits”—­a mention, to be sure, but hardly one that indicates that savages are instinctive at core. J. D. Woods, “Introduction,” in The Native Tribes of South Australia, ed. George Taplin (Adelaide: E. S. Wigg & Son, 1879), xxvii. The absence of instinct is notable but slightly less stark among the anthropologists who ­were reading the ethnological literature, often within an evolutionary frame that had itself theorized instinct extensively. James Frazer does not use the word at all in Totemism. In The Golden Bough, Frazer invokes instinct to apply to savages only when he makes the case that savages will not abandon sexual instincts for an ideal of moral purity but will do so for the instinct of self-­preservation. James Frazer, The Golden Bough: A Study in Magic in Religion, 2nd ed. (London: Macmillan, 1900), 2:215. Edward Burnett Tylor does not deploy the term in Primitive Culture. In Tylor’s Researches Into the Early History of Mankind, the term only appears in a statement of Darwin’s that the Fuegans’ workmanship is instinctive like that of animals—­a claim that Tylor cites in order to refute. Edward Burnett Tylor, Researches Into the Early History of Mankind and the Development of Civilization (London: John Murray, 1865), 162. In Tylor’s Anthropology, the only time the term appears in reference to savages occurs with respect to law, as Tylor suggests that primitive law uses “for the public benefit the instinct of revenge which man has in common with the lower animals” (415). 21. Michel-­Rolph Trouillot, Global Transformations: Anthropology and the Modern World (New York: Palgrave, 2003), 19. 22. Ibid. 23. Jean-­Jacques Rousseau, “Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of In­e­qual­ity Among Men,” in The Discourses and Other Early Po­liti­cal Writings, trans. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 150. 24. T he phrase “ontological re­sis­tance” is Fanon’s in his critique of the applicability of Hegelian dialectics of recognition between whites and blacks in a world structured by colonial violence. Frantz Fanon, Black Skin, White Masks, trans. Richard Philcox (New York: Grove Press, 2008), 90. Hegel’s dialectic of recognition, Fanon claims, does not apply to white/black interactions because whites do not regard blacks as beings who can confer recognition—­t here is no “being for other” for blacks encountering whites in colonial situations. 25. Jean-­Jacques Rousseau, On the Social Contract, trans. Donald Cress (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1987), 26. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 184 1/24/14 7:36 PM Notes to pages 000–000 185 26. In Totemism, for example, Claude Lévi-­Strauss praises Rousseau for largely skirting the language of instinct in his discussions of sociality because instinct, Lévi-­Strauss claims, “belonging as it does to the order of nature, could not enable [man] to go beyond nature.” Claude Levi-­ Strauss, Totemism, trans. Rodney Needham (Boston: Beacon, 1963), 99. In the same section, Lévi-­Strauss also proffers a critique of Henri Bergson that exactly reproduces Frazer’s argument that institutions only exist to fill in what has not already been stipulated by instinct. In Lévi-­Strauss’s earlier Elementary Structures of Kinship, the incest taboo operates as the self-­t ranscending lever between nature and culture because it possessed both “the universality of bent and instinct, and the coercive character of law and institution.” Claude Levi-­Strauss, Elementary Structures of Kinship, ed. Rodney Needham, trans. James Harle Belle and John Richard von Sturmer (Boston: Beacon, 1969), 10. Totemism does not investigate the dialectical movement that allows for the supercession of this instinct/institution binary, but it is worth noting that both texts retain the sense of institutions as coercive social forces acting on instincts that are thought to precede and exist in­ de­ pen­ dently of social influence. 27. On anthropology and reforms to the British university system, see especially Henrika Kuklick, The Savage Within: The Social History of British Anthropology, 1885–­1914 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 54. 28. George Stocking famously makes the case that the idea of separate, distinct, and plural cultures did not prevail in the nineteenth century, which rather preferred the hierarchization of a single human Culture that had been fragmented in such a way as to “presuppose a hierarchical, evaluative approach.” George Stocking, Race, Culture, and Evolution: Essays in the History of Anthropology (New York: Free Press, 1968), 80. See also James Buzard, Disorienting Fiction: The Autoethnographic Work of Nineteenth-­Century British Novels (Prince­ton, N.J.: Prince­ton University Press, 2005), 6. 29. The term “ethnologist” was typically reserved for the people in the field who ­were understood as gathering information about a par­t ic­u ­lar group of people. “Anthropologist” at this historical moment most commonly designated those men, most of them study-­bound in Britain, who ­were producing theories about the progression of human cultures. See George Stocking, Victorian Anthropology (New York: Free Press, 1987), 249–­257. Jim Buzard argues that “the explicit formulation of culture as an anthropological category used mainly on remote, so-­called underdeveloped societies actually follows and reverses a great deal of implicit reliance upon something operating discernibly like culture in novelistic repre­sen­t a­t ions of British society.” Buzard, Disorienting Fiction, 13. 30. Christopher Herbert, Culture and Anomie: Ethnographic Imagination in the Nineteenth Century (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 65. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 185 1/24/14 7:36 PM 186 Notes to pages 000–000 31. Povinelli argues that for the modern subject, “the real difference between the West and the rest no longer [lies] in Morgan’s famous descriptive and classificatory distinctions, but in the stance people took in relation to their capture by culture.” Herbert’s argument provides a historical account of the genealogy of that capture during the moment that Morgan was writing. Elizabeth Povinelli, The Empire of Love: Toward a Theory of Intimacy, Genealogy, and Carnality (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2006), 236. 32. Cornelius Castoriadis’s emphasis on the imaginary component of institutions, for example, does not contradict the fact that institutions are insti­t utions “because they have been posited as universal, symbolized and sanctioned ways of doing things,” even though Castoriadis’s training in Marxism and psychoanalysis allows him to offer a critique of the ideological structuring of that positing. Cornelius Castoriadis and Kathleen Blamey, The Imaginary Institution of Society (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), 124, 132. Castoriadis’s distinction between autonomous and heteronomous societies depends on the assumption that it is possible but not assured that a society knows how it is instituting itself. 33. In the one instance in which he mentions instinct in his pop­u­lar ethnological narrative entitled Among Cannibals (1889), Carl Lumholtz explains that “it is not true, as many maintain, that the Australian native is guided wholly by his instincts. I am willing to admit that his reasoning powers are but slightly developed, as he is unable to concentrate his thoughts for any length of time on one subject, but he can come to a logical conclusion, a fact which has been denied.” Lumholtz’s protestations that indigenous Australians possess “slightly developed” reason was typical of ethnological writers in that, while claiming to position itself more moderately with respect to pop­u­lar opinion, it hardly upends what he describes as the widespread identification of Aborigines with instinctive epistemologies. Carl Lumholtz, Among Cannibals: An Account of Four Years’ Travels in Australia and of Camp Life with the Aborigines of Queensland (London: J. Murray, 1889), 168. 34. Francis Galton, “Notes on the Australian Marriage Systems,” Journal of the Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland 13 (1889): 71. 35. Herbert, Culture and Anomie, 66. 36. Freud, Totem and Taboo, 92. 37. Ibid., 81. 38. George Stocking, After Tylor: British Social Anthropology, 1888–­ 1951 (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1995), 22. 39. Achille Mbembe, “Necropolitics,” Public Culture 15, no. 1 (2003): 29. 40. This evisceration of Aboriginal populations occurred in spite of, as Richard Broome describes, the fact that the 1836 Port Phillip Protectorate was purported to safeguard Aboriginal people in Victoria against the worst forms of colonial violence. Richard Broome, Aboriginal Victorians: A History Since 1800 (Sydney: Allen and Unwin, 2005), 39. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 186 1/24/14 7:36 PM Notes to pages 000–000 187 41. Warwick Anderson, The Cultivation of Whiteness: Science, Health, and Racial Destiny in Australia (Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 2002), 78–­ 79, 121–­122. 42. Baldwin Spencer and F. J. Gillen, Native Tribes of Central Australia (Oosterhout: Anthropological Publications, 1969), ix. 43. Lewis Henry Morgan, “Introduction,” in Kamilaroi and Kûrnai: Group Marriage and Relationship, and Marriage by Elopement (Melbourne: George Robertson, 1880), 2. 44. Elizabeth Povinelli argues that liberalism justifies its violence by maintaining that it can encounter radical alterity from the “perspective of perspective,” noting further that the mixture of expert culture and “sympathetic understanding” provided by anthropologists was germane to such belief. Elizabeth Povinelli, The Cunning of Recognition: Indigenous Alterities and the Making of Australian Multiculturalism (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2002), 129. 45. Friedrich Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, ed. Eleanor Burke Leacock (New York: International Publishers, 1972), 74. For an excellent account of the debates on “primitive marriage” in the 1860s, see Catherine Gallagher, The Body Economic: Life, Death, and Sensation in Po­liti­cal Economy and the Victorian Novel (Prince­ton, N.J.: Prince­ton University Press, 2006), 161–­172. 46. Lorimer Fison and A. W. Howitt, Kamilaroi and Kûrnai: Group Marriage and Relationship, and Marriage by Elopement (Melbourne: George Robertson, 1880), 132. 47. Ibid., 128. 48. Ibid., 90. 49. Ibid., 338–­339. 50. James Martel, Love Is a Sweet Chain: Desire, Autonomy, and Friendship in Liberal Po­liti­cal Theory (New York: Routledge, 2001), 77. 51. George Stocking notes that Howitt wrote to Morgan about the incident. See Stocking, Victorian Anthropology, 22. 52. Fison and Howitt, Kamilaroi and Kûrnai: Group Marriage and Relationship, and Marriage by Elopement, 205. 53. Ibid., 310. 54. Émile Durkheim and Marcel Mauss, Primitive Classification, trans. Rodney Needham (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963), 88. 55. On Gillen’s fluency, see Povinelli, The Cunning of Recognition, 89. 56. A lthough he did, in practice, frequently interview people at the Mission, Gillen wrote to Spencer on June 5, 1896, that the “Mission Station is not a good field for the anthropologist, everything possible has been, and is being done, to blot out old customs.” F. J. Gillen, “My Dear Spencer”: The Letters of F. J. Gillen to Baldwin Spencer, ed. John Mulvaney, Howard Murphy, and Alison Petch (Melbourne: Hyland ­House, 1997), 119. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 187 1/24/14 7:36 PM 188 Notes to pages 000–000 57. Spencer and Gillen, Native Tribes of Central Australia, 99. 58. Ibid., 53–­54. 59. Adam Phillips, Terrors and Experts (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1997), 62. 60. Ibid. 61. Laplanche, Life and Death in Psychoanalysis, 11. 62. Ibid., 13. 63. Ibid., 16. 64. Michel Foucault, Abnormal: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1974–­1975, ed. Valerio Marchetti and Antonella Salomoni, trans. Graham Burchell (New York: Picador USA, 2003), 131, 286. 65. Teresa de Lauretis, for example, summarizes the debates around instinct and heterosexuality by noting that “Freud’s equivocation with regard to this issue—­whether a normal sexual instinct, phyloge­ne­t ically inherited, preexists its possible deviations (in psychoneurotic individuals) or whether instinctual life is but a set of transformations, some of which are then defined as normal, i.e., non-­pathogenic and socially desirable or admissible—­is a source of continued but ultimately insoluble debate.” Teresa de Lauretis, The Practice of Love: Lesbian Sexuality and Perverse Desire (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994), 10. 66. Samuel Butler, Erewhon; or, Over the Range (New York: New American Library, 1960), 25. 67. Ibid., 71. 4. Angel in the Big ­House 1. Sigmund Freud, Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality, trans. James Strachey (New York: Basic Books, 1975), 1. 2. Havelock Ellis, Studies in the Psychology of Sex: The Evolution of Modesty; The Phenomena of Sexual Periodicity; Auto-­Erotism (Philadelphia: F. A. Davis, 1901), iv–­v. This preface dates from 1897, when Ellis published Sexual Inversion, which was then the first volume of the Studies. Only a very few copies of the 1897 edition ­were circulated. In 1901, with the U.S. publication of the second edition, he reordered the series such that The Evolution of Modesty (1899) became the new first volume. The Preface became affixed to this volume. On the publication history of the Studies, see Phyllis Grosskurth, Havelock Ellis: A Biography (New York: Alfred Knopf, 1980), 184–­185. 3. H. J., “Short Cuts,” Once a Week (October 18, 1862): 461–­462. 4. Mona Caird, The Daughters of Danaus (New York: Feminist Press at CUNY, 1993), 210. 5. Thomas Laqueur regards the figure of the pure and dispassionate woman as a post-­Enlightenment invention accompanying a new two-­sex model in 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 188 1/24/14 7:36 PM Stefanos Geroulanos and Todd Meyers, series editors Georges Canguilhem, Knowledge of Life. Translated by Stefanos Geroulanos and Daniela Ginsburg, Introduction by Paola Marrati and Todd Meyers. Henri Atlan, Selected Writings: On Self-­Organization, Philosophy, Bioethics, and Judaism. Edited and with an Introduction by Stefanos Geroulanos and Todd Meyers. Catherine Malabou, The New Wounded: From Neurosis to Brain Damage. Translated by Steven Miller. François Delaporte, Chagas Disease: History of a Continent’s Scourge. Translated by Arthur Goldhammer, Foreword by Todd Meyers. Jonathan Strauss, Human Remains: Medicine, Death, and Desire in Nineteenth-­ Century Paris. Georges Canguilhem, Writings on Medicine. Translated and with an Introduction by Stefanos Geroulanos and Todd Meyers. François Delaporte, Figures of Medicine: Blood, Face Transplants, Parasites. Translated by Nils F. Schott, Foreword by Christopher Lawrence. Juan Manuel Garrido, On Time, Being, and Hunger: Challenging the Traditional Way of Thinking Life. Pamela Reynolds, War in Worcester: Youth and the Apartheid State. Vanessa Lemm and Miguel Vatter (eds.), The Government of Life: Foucault, Biopolitics, and Neoliberalism. Roma Chatterji (ed.), Wording the World: Veena Das and the Scenes of Inheritance. Kathleen Frederickson, The Ploy of Instinct: Victorian Sciences of Nature and Sexuality in Liberal Governance. 153-57397_ch01_1P.indd 213 1/24/14 7:36 PM