Beauty Beauty is powerful. It compels our attention and appreciation, unites us in shared visions and divides us with different ones. Our goal is to describe beauty in a way that illuminates its power. The description consists of arguments for three claims. First, one enjoys the items one judges to be beautiful. Second, the enjoyment is a special kind; one does not enjoy in that way items one does not find beautiful. Third, to believe that something is beautiful is to believe, on the basis of the special kind of enjoyment, that others will, other things being equal, enjoy the item in that special way. The arguments for the second characterize beauty’s power to compel attention and appreciation; the arguments for the third claim address its power to unite and divide. The first claim is an essential preliminary. The inspiration for this approach is Kant’s Critique of Judgment, in which Kant (arguably) advances all three claims. Our concern, however, is with the truth of the claims, not with Kantian exegesis, and our arguments will not, for the most part, be the same as Kant’s. I. The First Claim The First Claim is that one must enjoy what one believes is beautiful. This appears false. Imagine that you and Jones are looking that the Taj Mahal. Your enjoyment leads you to exclaim, “Beautiful, isn’t it?” Jones agrees, thereby expressing his own judgment that the Taj is beautiful. Jones, however, does not enjoy the Taj, never has enjoyed it, and does ever expect to. He agrees with you because he knows that the received opinion is that the Taj is beautiful, and his agreement acknowledges that the Taj 1 belongs with that diverse collection of items that people generally take to be beautiful. Doesn’t this show that one can judge something beautiful even if has never enjoyed the item and never expects to? A. Reasons, Enjoyment, and Judgment Our response rests on two points. The first is that we support our judgments of beauty with reasons. One does not, for example, treat the “Taj is beautiful” like “Chocolate tastes good.” If, after a good faith tasting of chocolate under appropriate conditions, you and Jones disagree over whether chocolate tastes good, you will not try to change Jones’ mind. Chocolate tastes good to you but not to Jones, and that is the end of the matter. In contrast, if after a good faith viewing of the Taj Mahal under appropriate conditions, if you think the Taj is beautiful, and Jones does not, it would neither be out of place nor unusual for you to try to change Jones’s mind by offering him reasons to think the Taj is beautiful. We are not claiming that, when one gives reasons for a judgment of beauty, one expects others to infer on the basis of these reasons that the item is beautiful. As we discuss more fully in Sections III and IV, the purpose of giving reasons is not to compel agreement by providing evidentiary grounds. The second point is a distinction between derivative and non-derivative judgments of beauty. Our claim is only that one must enjoy what one nonderivatively judges to be beautiful. When Jones judges the Taj beautiful, his judgment is derivative. A judgment of beauty is derivative if and only if it is based solely on the reports of others. We intend the “solely” to exclude 2 cases in which the reports of others provide one with reason to think one will enjoy something, and in which one judges it beautiful on the basis of one’s own possible future enjoyment. By way of illustration, suppose that, Arthur sends the following text message to Gwen, “At Taj. Beautiful! Must see to appreciate.” Gwen, who shares Arthur’s tastes and whom she regard as a competent judge, assumes that if she were to see the Taj, she would not only enjoy it but would also, on that basis, judge it beautiful. Her post-textmessage assertion that the Taj is beautiful is not—in the sense we intend— based solely on Arthur’s report, but on her expectation of her own enjoyment and consequent judgment. Not all judgments of beauty are derivative. Your “Beautiful, isn’t it?” in response to the Taj is an example. If you were required to defend your judgment, you would you would describe the aspects of it that you enjoy. It is your belief that you enjoy the Taj in the way you, not the reports of others, that constitutes your reason for your judgment that the Taj is beautiful. This is typical; one gives reasons for one’s judgment that, for example, a face, painting, statue, or poem is beautiful by indicating the features one enjoys. Typically, when one non-derivatively judges that something is beautiful, one’s reason for the judgment is, at least in part, that one enjoys (has enjoyed, or expects to enjoy) the item in a certain way. It is sufficient for our purposes simply to note that this is typically true; however, one might well wonder whether what is typically true is also necessarily so, and the question merits some brief attention. It appears at first sight that the answer is no. One might not be prepared to offer one’s enjoyment as a 3 reason if one arrived at the conviction that something is beautiful was instilled by hypnotic suggestion, or a mad psychophysiologist, or some other form of manipulation. One can, however, defend the necessity claim by regarding such cases as qualify as judgments of beauty only because they are degenerate instances of the paradigm case in which one’s past, present, or expected enjoyment is one’s reason for the judgment. To summarize, the First Claim is that one enjoys the items one judges to be beautiful; we can now reformulate the claim as: Typically, when one non-derivatively judges that something is beautiful, one’s reason for the judgment is, at least in part, that one enjoys (has enjoyed, or expects to enjoy) the item in a certain way. The reformulation of the First Claim leads to the following reformulation of the Second Claim: the enjoyment which serves as the reason for a non-derivative judgment of beauty is a special kind of enjoyment. To characterize the relevant kind of enjoyment, we first focus on the fact that to enjoy is to enjoy an experience or activity. The question is what the relevant experience or activity is in the case of the enjoyment which serves as a reason for a non-derivative judgment. We argue that that one enjoys the experience of something’s appearing in a certain way. That argument comprises the conclusion of this section. Section II then distinguishes the enjoyment of this experience from other types of enjoyment. A final terminological point: since we will be exclusively concerned with non-derivative judgments, we will from here on drop the qualification “non-derivative”. 4 B. The Enjoyed Experience Reflection on examples strongly suggests that when one judges something beautiful, one enjoys the item’s appearing a certain way. We use “appear” as it is used in “Objects in the mirror will appear more distant than they are”; that is, under normal conditions, objects will appear more distant. Our reference to normal conditions assumes that, in a variety of contexts, one can identify factors which alter the way things appear, and that there is widespread agreement that these factors qualify as abnormal. By way of examples, consider what one says when one explains what it is that one enjoys about an item one regards as beautiful. The colored squares in the abstract painting appear to dance; the (real or painted) ship’s gently full sails appear to mirror the tranquility of the sea; the washerwoman appears to have the face and bearing of a Madonna; the statue of Aphrodite presents the goddess’s flesh as at once marble-hard and humanly soft; the strong diagonal elements in a painting, building, face, or body are broken up to just the right degree to appear just short of being mechanical. Note that these are all examples of sensuous appearances. We will not provide any definition or account of the notion of a sensuous appearance; we rely on the above examples to indicate what we mean. The appearance involved in the enjoyment of beauty need not be sensuous. Thus: when Stephan first encounters Cantor’s diagonal proof of the existence of uncountable sets, understanding dawns simultaneously with the apprehension of beauty as the elements of the proof appear to organize themselves with an astonishing simplicity and clarity, a clarity and simplicity 5 that appears to Stephan to invest him with the power to tame the infinite. The appearance, although non-sensuous, has a force and immediacy analogous to a sensuous appearance. We will call such appearances nonsensuous appearances, and again we rely on examples to indicate what we mean. We offer one more. Sarah reads the following lines from Wallace Stevens’ “Peter Quince at the Clavier”: Beauty is momentary in the mind— The fitful tracing of a portal; But in the flesh it is immortal. The body dies, the body’s beauty lives. Sarah finds the lines beautiful as she sees in the image of immortality in the flesh a simultaneous rejection and endorsement of a Platonic conception of beauty as a Form that shines through physical appearances. This is not to say that she formulates to herself the thought, “The image of immortality in the flesh is a simultaneous rejection and endorsement of a Platonic conception of beauty as a Form that shines through physical appearances”; rather, the image encapsulates this idea with a force and immediacy analogous to Stephan’s experience of Cantor’s argument. Three further points are in order. First, one can be mistaken about the way things appear. Imagine that, as you turn a corner, you suddenly see a modern interpretation of a traditional church constructed entirely out of concrete; you think that the strong diagonal elements appear just short of mechanical. However, when you return the next day, it is plain to you that the elements appear quite mechanical. You attribute your earlier belief to your surprise and consequent unexpected enjoyment at discovering the structure; your sudden enjoyment made you see the building in a more 6 favorable light than you do on your return. When you see the building under more normal conditions, it appears differently. Similar remarks are possible in the case of all the examples. It is indeed typical for us to change our minds about the way things appear on ground that conditions were not normal. Second, the way things appear may vary from person to person even under normal conditions. When you look at the statue, Aphrodite’s body may appear to you to be covered with flesh at once marble-hard and humanly soft, but when Jones looks, the statute may not appear as having flesh at all, but simply as a marble rendition of a human form. Neither you nor Jones need be mistaken about how the statue appears. Under normal conditions, it just appears differently to you than it does to Jones. Third, as we will argue more fully in Section IV, when one enjoys something one judges beautiful, some selection of the item’s parts, qualities, internal and external relations appear as an interconnected whole. Even with the relatively less complex beauties of flowers and geometrical designs, the eye ranges over the form, appreciates the variations in color, calls to mind perhaps other beautiful flowers. Even apparently simple beauties, like the beauty of a particular shade of red, only stand out as beautiful because of the relation of that red to its surroundings (visual or conceptual) and our ability to compare it to many other closely similar shades. The point is commonplace in discussions of beauty; Kant, for example, emphasizes that one regards the items one judges beautiful as exhibiting the unity of the objects to which the concepts of the Understanding apply (even though, in 7 the case of beauty, the Understanding does not actually supply any relevant unity-creating concept). Our version of the commonplace point is that the enjoyed features of a beautiful object appear as an organized array.1 To summarize: typically, one judges something x beautiful, one’s reason for the judgment consists, at least in part, in the fact that, for some organized array A of features, one enjoys x’s appearing to have A. That is, one’s reason consists at least in part in the fact that, some organized array A of features (1) x appears to one to have A; (2) x's so appearing causes one (a) to occurrently believe, of x’s appearing to have A, that it is an appearance of x as having A; and (b) to have the felt desire, of x’s appearing to have A, under A, that it occur for its own sake. Our description in (2a) of the belief may strike one as unnecessarily cumbersome. Once we describe the belief as “of x’s appearing to have A,” surely it is just repetitive to say one believes that the appearance is an appearance of x as having A. In fact, it is not. As noted earlier, one may mistakenly think something appears in a way which it in fact does not. The specification of the belief rules out this type of mistake; one must believe, of Kant describes the appearance of a organized array as a product of the “free play of the Imagination.” The Imagination to which Kant appeals is a transcendental faculty, and we wish to avoid any such appeal. We can nonetheless find a role for non-transcendental imagination in the enjoyment of beauty. Beauty creates opportunities for imaginative interaction, opportunities we value highly. The interaction is typically temporally structured in a way which involves attention to the various features in question as a sustained appreciation of the whole. One typically repeatedly contemplates and investigates things one finds beautiful in ways that extend and enrich that array of features one apprehends it as having. 1 8 x’s in fact appearing to one to have A, that it is an appearance of x’s having A as opposed to an appearance of x’s having some other array A’. A similar point holds for the specification of the desire. One might desire, of x’s appearing to have A, under some other array A’, that it occur. (2b) requires that one desire that x appear in the way it in fact does. II. The Second Claim: A Special Kind of Enjoyment The Second Claim is that the enjoyment which serves as the reason for judgment of beauty is a special kind of enjoyment. This section characterizes the relevant kind. It is important to be clear about what the task is. In the last section, we claimed that typically, one judges that something is beautiful only if one’s reason for the judgment is, at least in part, that one enjoys (has enjoyed, or expects to enjoy) the item’s appearing to have some organized array of features; in this section, we characterize the type of enjoyment that typically provides the reason. Let us call the enjoyment which plays this role a b-enjoyment. Not just any sort of enjoyment can serve as a b-enjoyment. Suppose Alex enjoys the following verse from “In-A-Gadda-Da-Vida” by Iron Butterfly: In-A-Gadda-Da-Vida, baby (in the Garden of Eden) In-A-Gadda-Da-Vida, honey Don’t you know I am loving you? Alex regards the lines as childish trash, and, as he is well aware, he would actually find listening to them distasteful were it not for his memories of the ‘60’s, a time and culture to which he remains deeply emotionally attached. 9 Alex does not, however, think the lines are beautiful, nor does he think that his enjoyment is any reason whatsoever to think so. If he were asked why he listens to the verse as opposed, say, to songs with more worthy content, he would reply that he has discovered, to his surprise, that he still enjoys listening to the “In-A-Gadda-Da-Vida” verse, and taking the time to enjoy the song is a way of remaining connected to his past. The example suggests that a plausible candidate for the role of benjoyments—normative reason enjoyments. Normative reason enjoyments are characterized by the presence of an underived normative reason to have the relevant experience or engage in the relevant activity. Alex’s enjoyment is not paired with any such reason. Consider any proposition to the effect that the verse has a certain array of features A. Alex does not regard any such proposition as an underived normative reason to experience the verse as having A. He regards the verse as childish trash. Alex’s normative reasons to experience the verse are derived from his conviction that enjoying the verse is a means to staying in touch with his past, and from his desire to remain so connected. When one enjoys what one regards as beautiful, on the other hand, one typically regards some array A of features of the time as an underived normative reason to enjoy the item as appearing to have A. Suppose, for example, Alex were asked why he took time out of his business trip to New York to look at Van Gogh’s “Starry Night.” He answers by identifying the features he enjoyed—the luminescence and intense activity of the stars, moon, clouds, and sky above the quiet town, all of which contrast with the potentially ominous massive dark shape in the foreground. These 10 features make the painting worthy of enjoyment in Alex’s eyes; that is, he regards the proposition that the painting appears to him to have those features as an underived normative reason to enjoy the painting’s appearing to have those features. His conviction that this reason exists plays a central role in his justification and explanation of why he takes time out of the New York trip to enjoy the painting. We suggest therefore that: One b-enjoys x’s appearing to one to have A only if (1) x appears to one to have A; (2) x's so appearing causes x (a) to occurrently believe, of x’s appearing to have A, that it is an appearance of x as having A; and (b) to have the felt desire, of x’s appearing to have A, under A, that it occur for its own sake. (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) functions as an active reason to experience x’s appearing to have A. (4) one regards the proposition that x appears to have A as an underived normative reason for one to experience x’s appearing to have A. The fourth condition is our version of Kant’s claim that the enjoyment of beauty is a “disinterested” enjoyment. As Kant explains in a famous passage, If any one asks me whether I consider that the palace I see before me is beautiful, I may, perhaps, reply that I do not care for things of that sort that are merely made to be gaped at. Or I may reply in the same strain as that Iroquois sachem who said that nothing in Paris pleased him better than the eating-houses. I may even go a step further and inveigh with the vigor of a Rousseau against the vanity of the great who waste the sweat of the people on such superfluous things. Or, in fine, I may quite easily persuade myself that if I found myself on an 11 uninhabited island, without hope of ever again coming among men, and could conjure such a palace into existence by a mere wish, I should still not trouble to do so, so long as I had a hut there that was comfortable enough for me. All this may be admitted and approved; only it is not the point now at issue. All one wants to know is whether the mere representation of the object is to my liking, no matter how indifferent I may be to the real existence of the object of this representation. It is quite plain that in order to say that the object is beautiful, and to show that I have taste, everything turns on the meaning which I can give to this representation, and not on any factor which makes me dependent on the real existence of the object. Every one must allow that a judgment on the beautiful which is tinged with the slightest interest, is very partial and not a pure judgment of taste. One must not be in the least prepossessed in favor of the real existence of the thing, but must preserve complete indifference in this respect, in order to play the part of judge in matters of taste. Our version of “All one wants to know is whether the mere representation of the object is to my liking” is that “all one wants to know” is whether I regard the proposition that the item appears to me to have a certain array of features (this appearance being the “representation”) as an underived normative reason to experience the item as so appearing. Our appeal to the underived nature of the reason is our version of Kantian “disinterestedness.” Note that we have replaced Kant’s appeal to “liking” with an appeal to the recognition of underived normative reasons; Kant links “liking” to reasons through his (in our eyes mythical) transcendental psychology. For us, and indeed for Kant as well, Alex’s attitude toward the “In-A-Gadda-Da-Vida” verse is not “disinterested,” but his attitude toward Van Gogh’s “Starry Night” is. Despite this incorporation of a version of Kantian “disinterestedness,” the proposed conditions are not sufficient, as the following example shows. Byron enjoys looking at his wife’s face. The relevant belief/desire pair functions as an active reason, and Byron regards the proposition that his 12 wife’s face appears to have certain features as an underived normative reason for him to experience her face as appearing to have to those features. His regarding the way her face appears as an underived normative reason is the result the years of marriage that have given this particular appearance a unique place in his heart. Her face is quite plain, however, and, as Byron acknowledges, no one would regard it as beautiful. Bryon certainly does not, and he does not regard his enjoyment as any reason whatsoever to think otherwise. To see how to work toward sufficient conditions, ask why Byron declines to judge his wife’s face beautiful. The most plausible answer is that he knows his recognition of the normative reason is idiosyncratic. He does not expect others to recognize any such normative reason. It is one of the oldest and most compelling insights about beauty that its appeal transcends differences in interests, attitudes, time, and place. It is commonplace to characterize beauty as involving the presentation of the universal in the particular. For Plato, for example, the Form of Beauty shines through the particulars in which participate in it with a unique power to awaken in us a memory of our prior perception of, and love for, the eternal Form itself. Shorn of appeal to the Forms, the claim in Kant becomes that the claim that beauty speaks with a “universal voice”: Whether a dress, a house, or a flower is beautiful is a matter upon which one declines to allow one's judgment to be swayed by any reasons or principles. We want to get a look at the object with our own eyes, just as if our delight depended on sensation. And yet, if upon so doing, we call the object beautiful, we believe ourselves to be speaking with a universal voice, and lay claim to the concurrence of everyone, whereas no private sensation would be decisive except for the observer alone and his liking. 13 To formulate our version of the claim that beauty speaks with a universal voice, suppose you are looking at the Taj Mahal. The Taj appears to you to have an organized array A of features, and its so appearing causes the relevant belief/desire pair; that pair functions as an active reason to so experience the Taj, and you regard the proposition that the Taj appears to have A as an underived normative reason to so experience the Taj. In addition, you have the following, not uncomplicated, thought: there is a sufficiently large group G of relevantly similar others, and collection C of relevant similar arrays of features such that, for any member y in G, there is some array A’ in C such that y would regard the proposition that the Taj appears to have A’ as an underived normative reason to experience the Taj as appearing to have A’. For us, beauty speaks with a more or less universal voice, depending on the size of the group G. We conclude this section with a discussion of issues surrounding the size of G. In Sections III and IV, we discuss at length the issues surrounding the appeal to a “sufficiently large” group, the two appeals to relevant similarity. To avoid misunderstanding, we should emphasize that we are not claiming that one who judges something beautiful must have a relevant group explicitly in mind, or even that—implicitly or explicitly—any relatively definite criteria for membership in such a group. Implicit appeal to a vaguely defined, over-inclusive group may well be the norm, where one comes to appreciate the need to limit the group as one bumps into disagreements with one’s judgment of beauty. Sections III and IV examine the process of disagreement and revision. 14 To generalize from the Taj example, let us first say that one believes that the proposition that x appears to have A is a G-universal normative reason to experience x’s appearing to have A if and only if one believes that there is a group G of relevantly similar others, and collection C of relevant similar arrays of features such that, for any member y of G, there is some array A’ in C such that y would regard the proposition that x appears to have A’ as an underived normative reason to experience x as appearing to have A’. Then: One b-enjoys x’s appearing to have A only if (1) x appears to one to have A, (2) x’s so appearing (a) to occurrently believe, of x’s appearing to have A, that it is an appearing of x as having A; (b) to have the felt desire, of x’s appearing to have A, under A, that it occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) functions as an active reason for one to experience x’s appearing to have A; (4) one regards the proposition that x appears to have A as an underived normative reason for one to experience x’s appearing to have A; (5) one regards the proposition that x appears to have A as a Guniversal normative reason to experience x as having A. To regard a normative reason as G-universal it to see its recognition as dependent on only on the attitudes and interests that define membership in 15 G. The more widely those attitudes and interest are shared, the more closely G approximates all of humanity. The Taj, with its considerable cross-cultural, appeal is an example; from its completion in 1631, an increasingly large and culturally diverse group has enjoyed the Taj and has on that basis judged it beautiful. The larger, more diverse, and more temporally extended the similarity group, the less the recognition of the normative reason depends on any person’s idiosyncratic attitudes or interests. It depends only on the shared interests and attitudes defining membership in the group, and on the formation of a relevant belief; moreover, in the case of the Taj, the arrays of features attributed to the Taj tend to be quite similar (focusing on the completely unified presentation of perfect symmetry, simplicity, lightness, complexity, immense detail, and massiveness). Even the formation of the relevant belief seems largely independent of idiosyncrasies. The G-universal normative reason to enjoy the Taj is thus a contingency-transcending reason. Contingency-transcending reasons matter greatly to one. One is immersed we in contingencies. One finds oneself thrown into a particular time, in a particular place; the circumstances in which one is born, raised, and educated, largely shape one’s interests and attitudes; some of these interests and attitudes reflect the peculiarities of one’s unique circumstances and personality, others are shared by smaller or larger groups but are still the product of the contingent conditions and may not be shared by groups formed by other circumstances (New Yorkers take things for granted that Los Angelinos find bizarre, and vice versa). We take it for granted that one has a 16 compelling reason to seek such reasons, to see oneself as having at least partly transcended the web of ruthless contingencies in which one must otherwise live (we do not of course mean to suggest that it is a trivial task to explain why one has compelling reason to seek such reasons). G-universal normative reasons offer an escape from the contingences that shape us. They allow one to answer the question, “What reason was there for you to experience that?”, by offering a reason the existence of which does not (in one’s eyes) depend on one’s idiosyncratic interests and attitudes. Contingency-transcending reasons are more or less transcendent depending on the size of G. The Taj example illustrates the “more”; the following example illustrates the “less.” William is listening to Son House’s 1965 a cappella rendition of the following verse from the Gospel/blues song, John The Revelator: You know God walked down in the cool of the day Called Adam by his name But he refused to answer Because he's naked and ashamed. William ascribes an array of features to the rendition (concerning Son House’s tone, cadence, the relations of his version to Blind Willie Johnson’s, and so on); he enjoys the verse as having that array, and he judges it beautiful on that basis. He regards the possession of the array as a Guniversal normative reason, where G includes only those who appreciate the blues more or less as he does, who understand the references to Genesis 3: 8 – 10, and who can compare Son House’s rendition to other treatments of the same song, such as Blind Willie Johnson’s. Given such a similarity group, whether someone will acknowledge the existence of the normative reason 17 depends on interests and attitudes that are far less widely shared than the interests and attitudes in the Taj example. We have—we assume— compelling reason to discover G-universal reasons we share with a likeminded community, even when that community is relatively small. The current conditions for b-enjoyment incorporate notions of “disinterestedness” and “universality,” but they omit one crucial consideration: causality. The key to sufficient conditions consists in recognizing causal relations between the item’s appearing in a certain way and the reasons one has to so experience it. C. Causation An analogy reveals the need to incorporate causal relations. Suppose Jim enjoys his dining with his wife, Ellen. He fulfills these conditions. For some array A and group G, (1) he dines with his wife, (2) his dining with is wife causes him (a) to occurrently believe, of his dining with his wife, that it has an array A of features; (b) to have the felt desire, of his dining with his wife, under A, that it occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) functions as an active reason for him to enjoy dining with his wife; (4) he regards the proposition that dining with his wife has A as a Guniversal normative reason to engage in that activity as exemplifying A. 18 Focus initially on (3). (3) is true only because Jim thinks that, since Ellen is his wife, he ought to enjoy dining with her. When he actually dines with her, however, the enjoyment is a tepid one, and its half-heartedness not only constantly reminds him of other, more lively, enjoyments he could pursue, it is also a poignant, sadly insistent, contrast with the dinners when they first met. Back then, the experience of her company causally sustained his active reason to share her company; the experience continually enlivened the reason, constantly renewing its power to keep his full attention directed on her. When the relationship was new, dinning with the woman who was to become his wife exercised a power over him that has long since faded way. In b-enjoyment, the power to causally sustain the relevant active reason is fully present. “A thing of beauty is,” as Keats would have it, a joy for ever: Its loveliness increases; it will never Pass into nothingness; but still will keep A bower quiet for us, and a sleep Full of sweet dreams, and health, and quiet breathing. A companion case to the Jim’s wife example provides a (partial) illustration. An elderly museum curator is enjoying looking at his favorite Gauguin. The relevant belief/desire pair functions as an active reason to look at the painting, but the experience of looking does not causally sustain that reason. It used to; in his youth, one look at the painting would rivet his attention on it. But now to look at the painting is to be reminded of his youth and of the comparative shortness of the rest of his life. The painting is powerless to hold these thoughts at bay; indeed, power the painting now has is the power to spark unpleasant reflections, and the curator turns away from the painting 19 in the hope that the reflections will more quickly run their course. Far from causally sustaining his active reason to look at the painting, the experience of looking at the painting causes him to turn away. The painting no longer “keep[s] a bower quiet . . . full of sweet dreams.” We do not deny that the curator can still judge the painting beautiful on the basis of his present enjoyment; however, we also take it to be clear that, if the painting had never causally sustained an active reason, the curator would have no reason to judge it beautiful. The painting would lack beauty’s attention riveting power. We propose then that one b-enjoys x’s appearing to have A only if x’s so appearing causes (causally sustains) the relevant belief/desire pair’s functioning as an active reason to experience x as appearing to have A. We make essentially the same claim in regard to the normative reason involved in b-enjoyment: one b-enjoys x’s appearing to have A only if x’s so appearing causes (causally sustains) one’s conviction that the proposition that x so appears is an underived normative reason for one to so experience x. To see that causation is also required here, suppose you and Jones are looking at the Taj; you enjoy it and find it beautiful; Jones enjoys it but does not find it beautiful. Disturbed by his failure to find the Taj beautiful, Jones returns the next day, having spent the prior evening studying expert discussions of the Taj. He looks at the Taj again—armed this time with a thorough knowledge of the features the experts regard as contributing to the Taj’s beauty. When he looks at the Taj, it does indeed appear to him to have 20 the organized array of features the experts identify, and fulfills the proposed conditions for b-enjoying the Taj’s so appearing. That is, he enjoys the Taj’s appearing to have that array; the relevant belief/desire pair serves as an active reason to enjoy the Taj’s so appearing; he regards the proposition that the Taj appears to him to have A both as an underived normative reason for him to enjoy the Taj’s appearing to have A, and as a G-universal normative reason for him to enjoy the Taj’s appearing to have A. He so regards the proposition, however, only because his reading of the experts has convinced him it is true. He finds no ground for the belief in his own experience. As he says, “The Taj does not speak to me in the way it evidently speaks to others,” and he still does not find the Taj beautiful. He thinks it is a nicely designed building, and he enjoys the harmony of the design, but, as far as he is concerned, the Taj belongs with the wide variety of other things— including tastefully appointed bathrooms, HBO’s Sex and the City, and an immense variety of faces and bodies—that he enjoys as harmoniously designed but does not (non-derivatively) judge it beautiful. He continues to regard the belief that the Taj has the array as an underived normative reason and as a G-universal normative reason, but this belief persists in spite of, not because of, his experiences. Now imagine that, in the midst of his disappointment at not finding the Taj beautiful, Jones notices the unexpected presence of a friend who is also contemplating the Taj. They fall into conversation for some time, and, then, in a lull in the conversation, Jones happens, without thinking about it, to look back at the Taj. He looks without any expectations, without any explicit 21 thought about the expert-identified features which he was scrutinizing earlier. Suddenly, the building speaks to him in a way it did not before: he enjoys its appearing to have the expert-identified array of features, and, this time, the enjoyment causes him to regard the proposition that it appears to have the array both as an underived normative reason for him to enjoy the Taj as appearing that way, and as a G-universal normative reason. This time the belief persists because of, not in spite of his experiences. Jones thinks, “Now I see! It is beautiful!” The experience testifies to its own justification by causing one to believe in the existence of a normative reason to have the experience. Should we add a final causal condition—that the experience cause one to regard the proposition that x appears to have A as a G-universal normative reason? The following example argues in favor of doing so. At age 22, Mason reads Vladimir Nabokov’s novel, Pale Fire. The novel contains a long poem by the—fictional—famous poet, John Shade; the poem is preceded by an introduction by Shade’s friend, Charles Kinbote; Kinbote’s commentary, correlated with the poem’s numbered lines, follows the poem. The poem and Kinbote’s observations comprise a highly allusive and selfreferential narrative in which Shade and Kinbote are the characters. Mason enjoys the novel’s appearing to have an array A of features, where the features consist of those involved in his appreciation and understanding of the novels themes of loneliness, alienation, love, self-consciousness, multiple simultaneous viewpoints, the elusiveness of the self, the power and danger of fantasy. The novel’s appearing to him in this way causally sustains his 22 active reason to so experience the novel, and his conviction that the proposition that Pale Fire appears to have A is an underived normative reason for him to experience Pale Fire’s appearing to have A. In addition, there is a group G such that he regards the proposition that Pale Fire appears to have A as G-universal underived normative reason to enjoy Pale Fire as appearing to have A. But he believes this only because he has discovered, from conversations, and from reading reviews and discussions, that it is true. Pale Fire speaks to him so directly about his particular loneliness and alienation that, whenever he reads the novel, he is astonished that it would appear to anyone else in more or less the way it appears to him; indeed, he finds the thought that of its appearing so to others as inconceivable, or he would so regard it if he did not know it was true. In his eyes, the novel is a message from Nabokov to him, to what is unique and idiosyncratic about his experience, experience that is, in his eyes, essentially unknown and unknowable by others. He reluctantly admits that others seem to be receiving a similar message, but the way the novel appears to him when he reads it does not causally sustain that admission; it works against it. Mason reads the novel when he is 44. He enjoys it as before, and again the way the novel appears to him causally sustains his active reason to so experience the novel, and his conviction that its so appearing is an underived normative reason for him to experience it as appearing that way. Further, as before, there is a group G such that he regards the proposition that Pale Fire appears to have A as G-universal underived normative reason 23 to enjoy Pale Fire as appearing to have A. This time, however, his experience of the novel causally sustains that belief. He sees his youthful obsession with a unique message as just one more illustration of feelings of isolation and alienation that plagued him when he was young. It is obvious to him now that many readers would respond to the novel by believing that there is an appropriate G-universal reason. If the forty-four year old Mason were asked if Pale Fire was beautiful, he would answer that it was. The twenty-two year old Mason would reject the question as irrelevant. To make the claim that it is beautiful would be to claim, on the basis of his enjoyment, that not just that there a normative reason for him to experience the novel in a certain way, but that others recognize a similar normative reason as well. He knows they do, but that fact remains a mystery to him. In the case of benjoyment, it is not mystery because the enjoyed experience causally sustains that belief that others recognize a similar normative reason. Thus, we suggest: One b-enjoys x’s appearing to have A if and only if (1) x appears to one to have A, and x’s so appearing causes (2) – (5): (2) one (a) occurrently believes, of x’s appearing to have A, that it is an appearing of x as having A; and, (b) one has the felt desire, of x’s appearing to have A, under A, that it occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) functions as an active reason for one to enjoy x’s appearing to have A; (4) one regards the proposition that x appears to have A as an underived normative reason for one to enjoy x’s appearing to have A; 24 (5) one regards the proposition that x appears to have A as a Guniversal normative reason. A final point is in order. The enjoyment of beauty captures us in a feedback loop: the item’s appearing in a certain way causally sustains an active reason to experience it as so appearing, which may lead one to act in ways which continue the experience, which may continue to cause the relevant belief/desire pair and to sustain that pair as an active reason to have the experience, which . . . One is all the more likely to act on the active reason to have the experience when one believes that there is an underived normative reason to do so. That belief eliminates doubt about whether the active reason should indeed function as an active reason. A similar point holds for one’s belief that the proposition that the items appear a certain way is a G-universal normative reason. That belief removes any concern about whether one is investing one’s time and energy in the pursuit of an idiosyncratic passion that others will neither share nor understand. The feedback loop makes it hard to tear one’s eyes away. As we enjoy the work we attend to it, and as we attend to it we may (or may not) discover additional features of the work which give it even greater power for us, which then feeds back into our enjoyment, and so on. The Taj example illustrates the point. The array of features you believe the Taj to have is the initial focal point of your enjoyment; however, as you continue to enjoy the Taj, the array of features you subjectively ascribe to the Taj may increase in number and complexity, and your original enjoyment of the item as having the array A may transform into the enjoyment of the Taj as having the more 25 complex array A’; A’ then becomes the focal point of your continued contemplation and investigation of the Taj, with the result that the array of features you subjectively ascribe to the Taj, which may increase in complexity . . . and so on—until some natural limit is reached (or perhaps, for optimists, once the critical task of understanding the artwork is fully complete). It is worth noting that the changes in the array A that occur as the feedback loop operates may alter one’s conception of the relevant similarity group. As one apprehends the item differently, one may change one’s view about whose responses will parallel one’s own. III. The Third Claim The Third Claim is that to judge that something is beautiful is to judge that certain others will enjoy the item in that way. Kant comments, It would . . . be ridiculous if any one who plumed himself on his taste were to think of justifying himself by saying: "This object (the building we see, the dress that person has on, the concert we hear, the poem submitted to our criticism) is beautiful for me." For if it merely pleases him, be must not call it beautiful. Many things may for him possess charm and agreeableness—no one cares about that; but when he puts a thing on a pedestal and calls it beautiful, he demands the same delight from others. He judges not merely for himself, but for all men, and then speaks of beauty as if it were a property of things. Thus he says the thing is beautiful; and it is not as if he counted on others agreeing in his judgment of liking owing to his having found them in such agreement on a number of occasions, but he demands this agreement of them. To formulate our version of this Kantian claim, recall first that one’s reason for the judgment is (typically) one’s b-enjoyment. One b-enjoys an item’s appearing to have an organized array A of features only if the experience has the causal properties specified in the last section, including, for some group 26 G, causing one to regard the proposition that the item has A as a G-universal underived normative reason to experience the item as having A. One believes that the proposition that x appears to have A is a G-universal normative reason to experience x’s appearing to have A if and only if one believes that there is a group G of relevantly similar others, and collection C of relevant similar arrays of features such that, for any member y of G, there is some array A’ in C such that y would regard the proposition that x appears to have A’ as an underived normative reason to experience x as appearing to have A’. To judge that x is beautiful is to judge that for some—sufficiently large—group G and for some collection C, for any member y in G, there is an array A in C such that: other things being equal, if x appears to y as having A, y will, b-enjoy x as having A. Thus, when, one basis of one’s benjoyment, one calls a thing beautiful, one “demands the same delight from others.” One’s own b-enjoyment provides a reason for this judgment to the extent that it provides a reason for thinking that the causal effects on oneself of one’s experience of x as appearing to have A will be appropriately replicated in relevantly similar others. A key difficulty this account faces is that there is an apparently compelling argument that one’s b-enjoyment cannot be a reason to think that appropriately believing members of the relevant similarity group will benjoy the item in question. Consider Carol’s judgment that Michelangelo’s David is beautiful. She b-enjoys the David as having an array A of features, and, on that basis, judges that those in the relevant similarity group will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the item as having a sufficiently similar 27 array A’, provided x appears to them as having A’. The difficulty that one knows that one routinely encounters disagreement with one’s judgments of beauty. Imagine, for example, that, in a discussion with his friend, Roger, William expresses his belief that the “naked and ashamed” verse in Son House’s rendition of John The Revelator is beautiful. William is confident Roger will agree; he knows from the discussion that they both have formed very similar beliefs about the verse, and he knows Roger belongs to the appropriate similarity group: they share a very similar understanding and appreciation of the blues; Roger understands and appreciates the references to Genesis, and he is very familiar with other renditions of John the Revelator. Roger does not, however, think the verse is beautiful. “I think it is very fine,” he says, “and I enjoy listening to it, but—beautiful? No, I draw the line there. Beautiful it is not.” Such disagreements are commonplace. Appropriately-believing others whom one, on excellent grounds, regards as relevantly similar nonetheless often reject one’s judgments of beauty. This happens even in cases like the David, cases in which there is widespread agreement that the thing is beautiful. Suppose Carol expresses her view that the David is beautiful to her companion, Mason. Mason, who does not b-enjoy the statue, replies, “Sadly, not for me.” Carol first assumes that he simply fails to perceive the sensuous harmony expressive of composure, confidence, and readiness for action, but she is quickly corrected. Mason, an art historian, offers a description of the David that elaborates on the sensuous harmony theme in ways that Carol finds illuminating and that deepens her b-enjoyment; in offering the description, 28 Mason is not merely reporting the views of other experts; he sees what he is describing with his own eyes and is articulating his own belief. Carol is now even more puzzled. She cannot understand how Mason can see the statue as he does and not find it beautiful. She suggests to him that a homophobiainduced inability to enjoy looking at a naked male body prevents him from benjoying the statue and on that basis finding it beautiful. Mason, who is gay, responds that he is certain that homophobia is not the problem. He nonetheless does not b-enjoy the David, and never has; he does not know why. Mason acknowledges that many others agree with Carol, and he is more than willing on that basis to agree that the David is beautiful, but this agreement does not express his own non-derivative judgment that the statue is beautiful. He makes no such judgment; his agreement merely acknowledges the view of the majority of others. The solitary b-enjoyer who declares, “My b-enjoyment is a reason to attribute a like enjoyment to all relevant others,” would appear to be clinging to slender reed of support, one quickly crushed the obvious fact of widespread disagreement. So how can it be at all plausible to represent someone who judges an item beautiful as predicting, on the basis of his or her b-enjoyment, that all members of a group who form an appropriate belief will b-enjoy the item? We know that our b-enjoyments are not generally a reliable guide in this regard. The key to a solution to this problem lies—paradoxically—in first seeing why it does not arise for Kant. Kant appeals to transcendental psychology: the transcendental faculty of Judgment, which is the same in all 29 subjects, links representations and pleasure in a way that justifies one in thinking a priori that certain representations will arouse pleasure in all subjects. This is why Kant remarks that, when one “says the thing is beautiful; and it is not as if he counted on others agreeing in his judgment of liking owing to his having found them in such agreement on a number of occasions.” Against this background, our position looks hopeless. We have eschewed any appeal to transcendental psychology, but we have also abandoned basing the judgment of beauty on an appeal to the fact that others generally agree with one’s judgments of beauty. We seem to have left ourselves without any reason for judgments of beauty. Further reflection on Kant provides the solution. For Kant, the beautiful object presents itself a unity, an organized whole; the source of this perceived unity does not lie in any determinate concept of the Understanding, and one cannot consequently expect the agreement of others based on a shared application of such a concept. This is why he notes that nothing is postulated in the judgment of taste but such a universal voice in respect of delight that it is not mediated by concepts; consequently, only the possibility of an aesthetic judgment capable of being at the same time deemed valid for everyone. The judgment of taste . . . only imputes this agreement to everyone, as an instance of the rule in respect of which it looks for confirmation, not from concepts, but from the concurrence of others. The universal voice is, therefore, only an idea—resting upon grounds the investigation of which is here postponed. It may be a matter of uncertainty whether a person who thinks he is laying down a judgment of taste is, in fact, judging in conformity with that idea; but that this idea is what is contemplated in his judgment, and that, consequently, it is meant to be a judgment of taste, is proclaimed by his use of the expression "beauty." For himself he can be certain on the point from his mere consciousness of the separation of everything belonging to the agreeable and the good from the delight remaining to him; and this is all for which be promises himself the agreement of everyone-a claim which, under these conditions, he would also be warranted in making, 30 were it not that he frequently sinned against them, and thus passed an erroneous judgment of taste. Kant treats the judgment of beauty as a working hypothesis. It is possible to adopt this idea without also thereby embracing Kant’s transcendental psychology, and this is what we propose. The person who judges something beautiful entertains as a working hypothesis that those in the relevant similarity group will, other things being equal, b-enjoy provided the item appears to them in a relevant way. One adopts this working hypothesis, not because of the operations of transcendental psychology, but because one wants to investigate whether the causal effects the item has on oneself are replicated in others. Thus, when Carol judges the David beautiful, she knows it is highly likely that she will encounter those who, like Mason, fail to b-enjoy the David even though they belong to the appropriate similarity group and have a relevant experience of the statue. She nonetheless predicts their b-enjoyment as a working hypothesis. Like a full-fledged belief, the hypothesis guides her thought and action. She uses it to identify similarities and dissimilarities between the David and other items she and others judge beautiful; and, to elicit their reaction, she asserts to others that the David is beautiful. She proceeds in this way because she wants to know who does and does not share her conviction that the David’s possession of the relevant array of features (or a closely similar array) is a G-universal normative reason. She wants to know this because, as we noted earlier, one has compelling reason to discover a like-minded community with which one shares a vision of Guniversal normative reasons. Responding to others disagreements can lead 31 to revisions of the working hypothesis that yield a more accurate definition of the relevant community. There are three ways in which Carol can respond to Mason’s failure to b-enjoy the David. 1. Refusing to revise She can leave her judgment unrevised. A judgment of beauty is an “other things being equal” judgment, and, Carol could take the position that other things are not equal. Something unknown in Mason’s character or history might inhibit his b-enjoyment; the statue might, for example, remind him of his first love, a memory that enlivens pain still fresh despite the passage of time. In such a case, Mason is excluded from a community to which Carol belongs. The community consists of all those attribute the same (or a very closely similar) array of features as Carol does, and who b-enjoy the statue as having that array. Members of this community see their benjoyment has having revealed the same contingency-transcending Guniversal normative reason to enjoy. Mason does not share this vision of transcendence. Where one has sufficient reason to suspect that other things are not equal, the failure of someone to b-enjoy does not provide any reason to abandon one’s other things being equal judgment that they would so enjoy. Many disagreements over beauty are plausibly disagreements over whether “other things” are “equal.” Suppose Sally b-enjoys Carl Orff’s Carmina Burana and for that reason judges it beautiful; Sam disagrees, calling Orff’s compositions childish compared to Brahms. Sam does not b-enjoy Carmina Burana since his perception of the music as childish prevents him from 32 thinking that there is a G-universal normative reason to experience the music in any relevant way. Sally regards Sam’s accusation of childishness as simply one more manifestation of his obsessive need to appear superior to anyone with whom he engages in conversation, and she is convinced that, if Sam were freed from his obsession, he would b-enjoy Orff. Sam, who is well aware of Sally’s view of him, thinks Sally lacks a sophisticated musical ear. The claim that other things are not equal is not a plausible defense if a sufficient number of those who form the appropriate belief fail to b-enjoy the item. It is, of course, possible for “other things” not to be “equal” in such a case; evil space aliens may have distorted the responses of almost everyone. Such eventualities are extremely unlikely, however. So what are Carol’s options if a significant number of people disagree with her judgment that the David is beautiful? 2. Revising the belief One option is to decide that she has not identified the relevant organized array of features with sufficient precision and detail. Perhaps she could count on agreement from those who form the belief that the David has a different, perhaps richer and more complex, array of features. It is helpful to switch examples. Suppose Carol finds the opening lines of the poem in Nabokov’s Pale Fire beautiful: I was the shadow of the waxwing slain By the false azure in the window pane; I was the smudge of ashen fluff—and I Lived on, flew on, in that reflected sky. 33 Carol believes that the lines capture the situation of a self-consciousness that identifies itself only with its own self-consciousness, not with any contingent circumstance in which that self-consciousness happens to be embodied. Mason forms the same belief, but he thinks any sufficiently mature adult should regard the lines as the adolescent and indefensible refusal to accept that the self is embodied in a particular contingent setting, and, far from regarding the lines as beautiful, he finds their adolescent indulgence unpleasant. Grant, for the sake of argument, that the vast majority of readers agree with Mason. Carol could respond by attempting to reformulate her first-personauthoritative assessment of the lines in a way that side-stepped the charge of adolescent indulgence. To respond this way is to concede the nonexistence of the community of b-enjoyers to which one thought one belonged and to seek to a differently defined community. Carol might, for example, set the lines in the context of the rest of the poem and see the lines, not as the endorsement of a self-consciousness refusing to identify with anything beyond its own self-consciousness, but as introducing the plight of such a self-consciousness and laying the foundation for considering ways to escape its isolation (the first line, after all, reads “I was” not “I am”). Debates over beauty often exhibit just this sort of criticism and redefinition. In taking this line we do not wish to decide whether there is some specific set of concepts (as invoked by our critical vocabulary) which are the exact beauty-making features of the thing, or whether, as argued in an influential paper of Isenberg’s, there is some kind of non-conceptual 34 perceptual content which our critical vocabulary gestures at rather than explicitly identifying. Whether the features in question relate most primordially to a way of experiencing or to a way of conceptualizing, or whether there is even a coherently expressible difference between the two, is not at issue. The point is just that whatever the specific array of features in question is, and however we indicate it, it is an open possibility for the lonely lover of beauty to try to work harder to make others see or understand, and for the lonely holdout to believe that there something he or she is simply missing, in either case no matter how much intelligent scrutiny has come before. 3. Relativization Another way to defend one’s judgment of beauty against disagreement is to revise one’s description of the similarity group. By way of illustration, suppose Vicki reads Wallace Steven’s Sunday Morning, a poem offering Stevens’ reflections, from a distinctly non-Christian perspective, on the Christian story of the crucifixion of Christ, the sacrament of communion, and the Christian promise of immortality. She forms the belief that the poem has a certain array of features (concerning the elegance of the language, the power of the metaphors to capture aspects of the Christian themes of communion, suffering, salvation, and immortality); she b-enjoys the poem as having that array, and, on that basis, judges it beautiful. That is, she thinks that appropriately-believing others in the relevant similarity group will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the item. In her enthusiasm for the poem, she takes the relevant similarity group to include anyone with sufficient 35 knowledge of Christianity. A few days later, she encounters Guanglei, a Buddhist, who is a counter-intelligence analyst for the Chinese government. He has thoroughly studied Christianity and Christian culture, and, when he reads Sunday Morning, he easily forms a belief which is not at all dissimilar to the one Vicki forms, but he does not b-enjoy the poem as having the array of features he attributes to it. He does not in fact enjoy the poem in any way at all, but, even if he did, his enjoyment would not amount to b-enjoyment as he does not, and would not, regard the poem’s possession of the array of features he attributes to it as normative reason for him to enjoy the poem. The poem offers him a vision of an alien world, a world he understands, but with which he does not identify or sympathize. In response to Guanglei’s reaction, Vicki revises her judgment of beauty; she now restricts her prediction of b-enjoyment to those who are not only sufficiently familiar with Christianity but who also have an affective attachment to it similar to her own. Vicki could have tried to avoid this revision by claiming that other things are not equal in Guanglei’s case. The boundaries of “other things are not equal” claims are hardly clear, but we interpret such claims as asserting interferences with processes and attitudes that would otherwise yield a particular result, and we do not think it is plausible to posit such interference in cases like Guanglei’s. Some debates about beauty are plausibly regarded as debates about the proper relativization of a judgment of beauty. Consider Vladimir Nabokov’s novel, Pale Fire, for example. The novel contains a long poem by the—fictional—famous poet, John Shade; the poem is preceded by an 36 introduction by Shade’s friend, Charles Kinbote; Kinbote’s commentary, correlated with the poem’s numbered lines, follows the poem. The poem and Kinbote’s observations comprise a highly allusive and self-referential narrative in which Shade and Kinbote are the characters. The novel makes considerable demands on the readers intellectual abilities, sophistication, and literary knowledge (the title, “Pale Fire,” for example, is from Act IV, scene 3 of Shakespeare's Timon of Athens: "The moon's an arrant thief, / And her pale fire she snatches from the sun", a line traditionally interpreted as a metaphor for creativity and inspiration). Carol and Mason both attribute more or less similar arrays of features to the novel; each b-enjoys it as having the relevant array, and each judges it beautiful on that basis. They restrict their respective judgments to different similarity groups, however. Carol excludes from her group traditionalists about the novel who regard Pale Fire as “self-referential trash”; Mason includes them on the theory that they would abandon their “self-referential trash” assessment if they were ever to form a belief about the novel similar to Mason’s own. Mason is convinced that if they could see the novel through his eyes, they would indeed b-enjoy it and judge it beautiful. Carol is convinced they would not. Mason attributes greater power to the novel to generate b-enjoyment than Carol does. The extent of an item’s power to generate b-enjoyment matters. Compare the community that b-enjoys Pale Fire as having arrays of features similar to those Carol and Mason attribute to it to the community that benjoys the Taj. Members of each group are convinced their b-enjoyments 37 reveal a contingency-transcending G-universal normative reason; however, the contingency transcending vision of the Pale Fire group is available to the relatively few capable of understanding the novel; the vision of the Taj group, however, is accessible to many. One cares about both. The benjoyments accessible only to “specialist” groups may offer profound insights, but few would forego membership is wide reaching communities such as those who b-enjoy the Taj. B. Knowledge? If one successfully defends/revises one’s judgment of beauty in one or more of the above ways, does one thereby qualify as knowing, or at least having good reason to believe, that appropriately-believing others in the relevant similarity group will b-enjoy the item? One may plausibly offer the David as an example. Carol b-enjoys the statue for the way the sensuous harmony of the naked form expresses composure, confidence, and readiness for action, and judges that those who form the same or similar belief will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the David as having the same or similar array of features. The group that has made the same or more or less similar judgment is quite large, and has endured as a sizable group from the creation of the statute in 1504 to the present. One might plausibly regard Mason-like failures to b-enjoy (failures of appropriately believing members of the relevant similarity group) as cases in which other things are not equal, and hence regard Carol as knowing that relevant others will b-enjoy the statue. The background of agreement, moreover, need not be agreement 38 about the particular item one judges beautiful. Imagine Carol sees a man on the street during a trip to Beijing; she b-enjoys his face and judges it beautiful. She will never see the man again, nor ever meet anyone who has, but the face is similar to those that people have for centuries judged beautiful. Compare a case of “unique beauty.” Suppose Carol is the first to see a new painting by an aspiring artist. The painting is as innovative as impressionist painting was when it first appeared. She thinks the painting is beautiful, but there is no David-like history she can rely on to support her claim that others will b-enjoy the painting; indeed, apart from her and the artist, there is no history of others judging, or refusing to judge, the painting beautiful. Of course, Carol—and others—can develop a relevant history by determining whether others agree with her judgment of beauty, and, if there is sufficient agreement, she will at some point know that others will b-enjoy. We want, however, to deemphasize the importance of knowledge in this context. Responses to other’s disagreement may lead to knowledge, but, on the way, they may also define communities of like b-enjoyers. Consider that the process involves determining whether other things are equal, whether the first-person-authoritative-belief should be revised, or whether the similarity group should be redefined. The process may lead one to join with others in forming the same or similar beliefs that an item has a certain array of features, and to b-enjoy the painting as having that array. One may care as much or more about the formation of such communities as one does about whether one ultimately achieves knowledge. Of course, none of this may happen. The innovative artist may abandon painting to go to law 39 school, and burn his paintings, leaving Carol the only one who has seen them. In this case, Carol may never know whether others would have benjoyed them. IV. False Positives, False Negatives False positives and false negatives would show that our account of the judgment of beauty was incorrect. False positives are cases in which the definition is fulfilled but in which one withholds any judgment of beauty; false negatives, cases in which one makes a judgment of beauty when the definition is not fulfilled. We consider a number of false negatives and false positives. Our goal is not merely to dispose of objections, but to illustrate the explanatory power of the account. A. False negatives 1. Simples On our account, a completely uniform shade of blue cannot be judged beautiful; only items which one regards as having an organized array of features can be so judged. This may seem questionable. After all, people do say, “That is a beautiful shade of blue,” and, in any case, to avoid the charge of arbitrariness, the requirement of an organized array needs a justification. To begin with, one should set aside examples which do not really involve a uniform shade and which are not disallowed by our account. A shade of blue can be the dominant feature in a b-enjoyed organized array of features (in an abstract painting, for example) where that b-enjoyment serves as the reason for a judgment of beauty; further, a “color connoisseur” 40 (an artist, for example) might attribute to a shade of blue an organized array of relations to other shades of that color, b-enjoy the shade as having that array, and, on that basis, judge it beautiful. What follows from our account is that one cannot b-enjoy a shade of blue as merely having the feature being that shade of blue. Since we require that b-enjoyment be the reason for one’s judgment of beauty, it follows that one cannot judge the shade beautiful. To justify this result, suppose one did claim to b-enjoy the shade of blue merely as being that shade. That is, one claims that, for some group G, (1) x appears to be blue and x’s so appearing causes (2) – (5): (2) one (a) occurrently believes, of x’s appearing to be blue, that it is an appearing of x as blue; and, (b) one has the felt desire, of x’s appearing to be blue, under being blue, that it occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) functions as an active reason for one to enjoy x’s appearing to be blue; (4) one regards the proposition that x appears to be blue as an underived normative reason for one to enjoy x’s appearing to be blue; (5) one regards the proposition that x appears to be blue as a Guniversal normative reason to experience x as appearing to be blue. (4) and (5) are the problem. Can one coherently regard the proposition that the color is that shade of blue as an underived normative reason for one to experience the color as being that shade? The proposition the shade is blue is an underived normative reason for one to experience the shade as blue if 41 and only if it one believes the shade is blue, or should believe the shade is blue, and (2) that belief should function as active reason to experience the shade as blue. To function as an active reason is to play a motivationaljustificatory role. What answer can one give to the question of why the belief should play motivate and justify experiencing the shade as blue? The task is demanding. The reason must be underived, so one cannot appeal to reasons for other ends for which enjoying the shade would be a means. Merely identifying the shade of blue as that shade of blue must be sufficient to reveal its being that shade as an underived normative reason to experienced the shade as that shade of blue. One simply does not grant shades of blue this status. The cases in which one does do so are organized arrays of features—the chess playing experience of maintaining forces in dynamic tension in way that calls for creativity, courage, and practical judgment in an exercise of intuition and calculation akin to both mathematics and art; or the experience of the David as having a sensuous harmony expressive of composure, confidence, and readiness for action. Typically, one engages in, or could engage in, a sustained interaction with the item one judges beautiful, an interaction which reveals the beauty of the item in a variegated, temporally extended experience. That experience may increase the number and richness of the enjoyed features and increase the detail and complexity of the array of features one believes the item to possess. The result is a richer, more complex and detailed reason. 2. Beauty without enjoyment 42 There are some examples that suggest b-enjoyment is not required for a judgment of beauty. Goya’s “Third of May” is an example. It is arguably a case of what one might call “horrific beauty.” The center of the painting is occupied by a white-shirted guerilla with arms outstretched about to be shot by faceless firing line of blue-uniformed French soldiers, executing the lined up guerillas with mechanical precision. Suppose you are looking at the painting. It appears to you to portray the horror of war as faceless, machine-like soldiers execute the guerillas whose terror-filled faces nonetheless depict the passion behind their rebellion. You do not b-enjoy the painting as having this array A; the scene is too horrific for you to enjoy looking at it. The painting’s appearing to have A nonetheless causes you: (a) to regard the proposition that the painting appears to have A as an underived normative reason for one to experience its appearing to have A; and, (b) to regard the proposition that x appears to have A as a G-universal normative reason to experience x as having A. You might, for example, express these convictions by saying, “This is an experience to which one must submit oneself,” or something along those lines. Why should you not be able to judge the painting beautiful simply on the basis of it having the power to cause (a) and (b)? Your judgment would attribute a similar response to all G-similar others. Our answer is that merely causing (a) and (b) is not an adequate reason for a judgment of beauty. Suppose, for example, that Katya is a Russian engineer in the 1930s; she favors the development of the untouched Russian Steppe. She thinks that "[o]ur steppe will truly become ours only 43 when we come with columns of tractors and break that thousand-year-old virgin soil. On a far flung front, we must wage war. We must burrow into the earth, break rocks, dig mines, construct houses. We must take from the earth." Her vision is of humans as masters of the earth, transforming it in their image, and she emphasizes the enormous benefits to the Russian people of an industrialized steppe. But she has never seen the steppe, and when she finally travels through it, she is overcome with awe at the untamed and untouched vastness of it. The steppe’s appearance of untamed vastness causes her (a) to regard the proposition that the steppe that way as an underived normative reason for one to experience its appearing that way; and, (b) to regard the proposition that it appears that way as a G-universal normative reason to experience it as appearing that way. But she does not regard the steppe as beautiful; on the contrary, she finds it rather ugly, just awe-inspiringly so in its untamed vastness. Let us say that one regards x’s appearing to have A as having aesthetic value when and only when one regards the proposition that x appears to have A as (a) an underived normative reason for one to experience its appearing to have A; and (b) a G-universal normative reason to experience x as having A. In the “Third of May” example, you regard the painting’s appearing in a certain way as having aesthetic value, and Katya regards the steppe’s appearance of untamed vastness as having aesthetic value. But, just as Katya does not regard the steppe as beautiful, you need not regard the painting as beautiful. You may regard it as a masterpiece, but a masterpiece that depicts such horror that you cannot call it beautiful. 44 Consider one more example: Matthias Grünewald’s triptych of the crucified Christ, which depicts the horror of the crucifixion. Perry is contemplating the painting. The painting causes him to open himself to the full horror of the crucifixion. The painting appears to him as having an array of features that depict the horror of Christ’s suffering, and the deeply religious Perry regards the paintings so appearing as having aesthetic value, but he would never call it beautiful. None of this is intended to deny that one can b-enjoy the “Third of May,” or, for that matter, the steppe, or Grünewald’s triptych. In the case of the “Third of May,” suppose, as we did, that It appears to you to portray the horror of war as faceless, machine-like soldiers execute the guerillas whose terror-filled faces nonetheless depict the passion behind their rebellion, and that you do not b-enjoy the painting as having this array A. You may still benjoy the painting as having some other array A’; you may see the painting as appearing to have distinctive harmony of line, color, composition, and, on the basis of b-enjoying this array, you may judge the painting beautiful. Similar remarks hold for the steppe and the triptych. 3. Beauty without a G-universal reason It appears that one can judge that something is beautiful without regarding the proposition that the item has a certain array of features as a G-universal normative reason. If history had been different, impressionist painting would have been a putative example. Impressionism was not well received when it first appeared (Henry James, for example, lamented the 45 retreat from the “good old rules that decree that beauty is beauty and ugliness, ugliness”2). Imagine a world in which impressionism never catches on; painters eventually stop painting in that style until only a single impressionist painter remains. Imagine him looking at one of his paintings. As he does so, he fulfills the following conditions: for some group G, (1’) the painting appears to have a certain array A, and x’s so appearing causes (2) – (5): (2’) he (a) occurrently believes, of its appearing to have A, that it is an appearing of the painting as having A; and, (b) he has the felt desire, of the painting’s appearing to have A, under A, that it occur for its own sake; (3’) the belief/desire pair in (2) functions as an active reason for him to experience the painting as having A; (4’) he regards the proposition that the painting appears to have A as an underived normative reason for one to experience the painting as having A. The above conditions are almost the conditions for b-enjoyment. The objection is that the painter may judge the painting beautiful on the basis of the enjoyment characterized by (1’) – (4’) and hence that benjoyment is not required as the reason for a judgment of beauty. To make his plausible, suppose that, over the years since the disappearance of impressionism, the painter has encountered many who have looked at the painting and formed beliefs very similar to the painters; however, not a 2 Henry James, “Parisian Festivity,” New York Tribune, 13 May 1876. 46 single one of them has thought the relevant normative reason existed. They understood the painting, they just didn’t like it. The negative responses have worn the painter down to the point at which, when he looks at the painting, he no longer expects anyone else to agree with him that the normative reason exists. Our answer is that when the painter fulfills (1’) – (4’), there is a G such that he regards the proposition that the painting has the array as a Guniversal normative reason to experience the the painting as having A. The group consists of anyone who shares his attitudes and reactions to impressionism. That group currently consists, as far as the painter knows, only of himself; however, even when, at a certain time, a group consists just of oneself, one may still judge a painting beautiful on the basis of the related b-enjoyment. We offer the following considerations in defense of this claim. We begin with the observation that groups of people making the same judgment of beauty can be categorized along two dimensions. The first is the size of the group that b-enjoys the item as having more or less the same array of features. The “more or less” allows variation in enjoyed arrays; they must just be more alike than they are different. The second dimension is temporal duration, the length of time the group exists. Michelangelo’s David illustrates both ideas. Recall Carol’s judgment that the David is beautiful. She b-enjoys the statue for the way the sensuous harmony of the naked form expresses composure, confidence, and readiness for action, and judges that those who form the same or similar belief will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the David as having the same or similar array of features. The group 47 that has made the same or more or less similar judgment is quite large, and has endured as a sizable group from the creation of the statute in 1504 to the present. Similar remarks hold for the Taj, the Parthenon, and selections from Shakespeare, Goethe, and Keats, to take just a few examples. Contrast the judgment that 1960 pop song Teen Angel is beautiful. In the song, the teen-aged narrator’s car stalls on a railroad track; he helps his girlfriend to safety, but she runs back to the car and is killed when the train strikes; they find the narrator’s high school ring in her hand. The group that judges the song beautiful is small (if it exists), and it most likely reached its maximum size around February 1960 when Teen Angel ranked number one on the U. S. Billboard Hot 100. Innumerable examples fall between extremes represented by the Taj and Teen Angel, including Sunday Morning and Pale Fire. The former, like the David, has a large group that judges it beautiful on the basis of b-enjoying it as exhibiting arrays of features that are more or less similar, and the group has remained sizable since the first publication of the poem in 1915; however, unlike the David, which has cross-cultural appeal, the group that judges Sunday Morning beautiful is almost certainly restricted to those with sufficient emotional and intellectual attachment to Christianity and Christian culture. The group that judges Pale Fire beautiful is even more restricted, given the demands the work makes on its readers; nonetheless, a sizeable group has endured since the book’s 1952 publication. We concede that, when one expresses a judgment of beauty, others most naturally understand the judgment as follows: one judges that others who form the appropriate belief will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the 48 item as having a specific organized array of features, where, at the time of the judgment, the relevant similarity group is, or under appropriate circumstances would be, a reasonably sizable group that is a successor to similar groups extending significantly back into time (more or less like the groups that, for example, judge the Taj, Sunday Morning, and Pale Fire beautiful). The “or under appropriate circumstances would be” qualification allows one to judge something beautiful in this way even if few, if any, others have encountered it. The rationale for this attitude lies in a point we emphasized earlier: to regard a reason as G-universal is to regard it as transcending the contingencies of one’s particular situation—in the sense that others in other situations with other attitudes and interests also acknowledge the reason. The larger and more diverse the similarity group, the less one’s recognition depends on idiosyncratic attitudes and interest, and the more it depends only on widely shared attitudes and interests. Given one’s compelling reason to discover such contingency-transcending reasons, our interest in judgments of beauty involving sizeable similarity groups is understandable. This does not, however, mean that, when the similarity group consists just of oneself, one cannot judge something beautiful on the basis of the related b-enjoyment. It just means that others may not be much interested in the judgment. B. False positives 1. Beauty without a contingency-transcending reason 49 It appears possible to judge something beautiful in the absence of any relevant contingency-transcending reason. The example: outside Oprah’s studio in Chicago, there is a sign with a slanted “O” on top that reads “HARPO STUDIOS,” and below that, in smaller letters, “The Oprah Winfrey Show.” A group from a small town in Iowa gathers before the sign on Mother’s Day; having laid flowers before it, they contemplate it. The sign appears to each of them to have a certain organized array of features—the slanted, script-like “O” appears complement the straight block letter “HARPO STUDIOS,” which appears as harmoniously offset by modest, “The Oprah Winfrey Show.” They fulfill—at least apparently fulfills—the remaining conditions b-enjoyment: the sign’s appearing to them to have A causes: (3) the relevant/belief desire pair to function as an active reason to experience the sign as having the array A of features; (4) each to regard—or apparently to regard—the sign’s having the array as an underived normative reason for each to experience the sign as appearing to have the array (5) each to regard—or apparently to regard—the sign’s having the array as a underived G-universal normative reason to experienced the sign as appearing to have the array, for some group G. On the basis of this apparent b-enjoyment, each judges that the sign is beautiful—at least they appear to do so. There is a continuum of cases to distinguish here; at one extreme, the fans do not judge the sign beautiful, or at least do so only in a degenerate way; at the other extreme, they do plausibly judge the sign beautiful. To distinguish the extremes, recall that to judge that sign is beautiful is to judge that for some—sufficiently large—group G and for some collection 50 C, for any member y in G, there is an array A’ in C such that: other things being equal, if the sign appears to y as having A’, y will, b-enjoy x as having A’. The fans b-enjoyment of the sign as having the array A is their reason for this judgment. At the “no or degenerate judgment” extreme, the fans would have judged the sign beautiful no matter what array was involved in their b-enjoyment. They are sufficiently besotted with Oprah that, for a very wide range of arrays A*, they would have b-enjoyed the sign as having A* and would have judged it beautiful on that basis. This makes is problematic to see them as regarding that the proposition that the sign appears to have the array A is an underived normative reason to experience the sign as having A. The proposition that they recognizing as an underived normative reason to experience the sign as having A is the proposition that the sign is the sign for Oprah’s studio. They do not, therefore, fulfill the condition of benjoyment, and hence cannot have b-enjoyment as their reason for their judgment of beauty. One should not regard them as judging the sign beautiful, or as only doing so in a degenerate way. To judge something is beautiful is to assert the existence of a contingency-transcending reason, and to claim that others will recognize it. The fans do not find in the features of the sign a contingency-transcending reason to experience the sign as having those features; rather, their reason is depends entirely on the contingency of having sufficient adoration for a particular person. At the other extreme, the fans do regard the proposition that the sign appears to have the array A is an underived normative reason to experience the sign as having A. Their adoration of Oprah drew them to the sign, and it 51 may have endowed the sign with a particular luminosity, but once drawn to the sign, they form the conviction the proposition that the sign appears to have A is not only a normative reason for them to experience the sign as having A, but a G-universal normative reason to do so as well. In such a case, the only question is whether the relevant group G is sufficiently large for their judgment that the sign is beautiful to qualify as a full-fledged judgment of beauty, or whether, as in the hypothetical rejection of impressionist painting, the judgment concerns a group that is only potentially sufficiently large. 3. Beauty without a “sufficiently large” group Popular art may seem to offer examples in which one can judge something beautiful even though the group G of relevantly similar others is, sub specie aeternitatis (so to speak), quite small. Consider Michael Jackson’s Thriller. On our account, one can b-enjoy Thriller as appearing have certain array A of features (concerning the combination of elements of music, lyrics, dance, and video), and one can judge it beautiful on that basis. “Oprah sign” issues do not arise because the experience of the album plausibly causes fans to regard the proposition that album appears to have a certain array A as both a normative reason for them to experience the album as having A, and a G-universal normative reason to do so. Many, perhaps most, will nonetheless think something has gone wrong if, when the visitors from outer space ask for examples of beauty, earth’s representatives offer, without further comment or qualification, the David 52 and Thriller. We suggest the reason lies in a point we made earlier: when one expresses a judgment of beauty, others most naturally understand the judgment as predicting that others in a certain similarity group will b-enjoy the item, where the group is reasonably large and a successor to similar groups extending significantly back into time. Thus, imagine the space visitors return fifty years later; they again ask for examples of beauty and are again offered the David, but no one even mentions Thriller. When the aliens enquire about Thriller, earth’s representatives explain that Thriller is passé; it has been years since any significant number of people b-enjoyed it and judged it beautiful. It is currently viewed as in the same league as Teen Angel—a somewhat embarrassing moment in cultural history. This is not to deny that Thriller was once (on our story) b-enjoyed and judged beautiful. We are just pointing out that we recognize an important distinction between judgments of beauty which are associated with sizeable and enduring similarity groups, and judgments which are not. A distinction sufficiently important that we would not be likely to offer the aliens Thriller as an example of beauty even at the height of its fame—the court still being out on whether it should take its place alongside the David or Teen Angel. 3. Wine, chocolate, and chess Compare “Michelangelo’s David is beautiful” with “This Côtes du Rhône is beautiful.” Although wine connoisseurs sometimes describe wines as beautiful, wine is hardly the example one would produce if asked for a paradigm case of beauty, and—as we will argue shortly—for good reason. 53 Our account of beauty, however, there is no relevant difference between judging the David beautiful and making the same judgment about the Côtes du Rhône. Imagine Robert, the gout-ridden wine critic, tastes a wine. He benjoys the wine. That is: (1) he forms a first-person authoritative belief ascribing array A of features to the wine; he finds in it an aroma of cherry and a touch of smoke combined with light taste of tannin and a soft taste of red fruit, spice, and earth). (2) This belief motivates and justifies his enjoyment of the wine for its own sake; that is, that belief is an underived active reason to enjoy of the wine has having that array. Further, as a deeply committed wine connoisseur, he thinks he should believe that the wine has that array, and that the belief should serve as an underived active reason. That is, he regards the proposition that the wine has A as an underived normative reason for him to enjoy the wine as having A. In addition, for a similarity group G of wine connoisseurs of similarity sophistication and discriminatory abilities, he thinks that if one of them forms the same or sufficiently similar belief, he or she will also believe that he regards the proposition that the wine has A as an underived normative reason for him to enjoy the wine as having A. That is, (3) he regards the proposition that the wine has the array as a G-universal normative reason for any member of G to enjoy the wine as having A. Finally, his enjoyment causes or causally sustains (3). On the basis of his b-enjoyment, Robert judges the wine is beautiful. Similar remarks hold for b-enjoying the complexities of chocolate, or any item one can experience with sensations of sufficient structure and complexity. 54 We think the wine, chocolate, and the like can be beautiful; however, we also think there is an important difference between, for example, judging a wine beautiful and judging the David beautiful. Take the latter example first. Now, by way of contrast, suppose Barbara and Carol are looking at the David; unlike Carol, Barbara fails to b-enjoy it. When Barbara expresses her disappointment, her remarks reveal that, unlike Carol, she does not believe that statue to evince a sensuous harmony expressive composure, confidence, and readiness for action. Indeed, she fails to attribute any organized array of features to the statue; it is, for her, just a lifeless piece of marble. To aid Barbara in forming an appropriate belief, Carol calls Barbara’s attention to the way the left leg is bent, the bend and slight turn at the waist, and the way the head is turned directing the gaze to the left and exhibiting the muscles of the neck; and he could ask her to try to see all these as combining to express concentration and readiness for movement. The essential point is that Carol can aid Barbara by directing attention to publicly accessible features of the statue. This is possible in many—but we do not claim all—cases. One can often refer to publicly accessible features when trying to assist others to form an appropriate first-person authoritative belief. Compare the wine example. Imagine that Barbara neither smells the cherry aroma and touch of smoke, nor tastes the tannins, red fruit, spice, and earth. To help her detect these features, Paul, a wine connoisseur, could have her taste other wines with similar but more easily detectable features; after sufficient practice with these wines, Barbara might be able to detect the features that initially eluded her. Paul does not, however, typically direct 55 Barbara’s attention to publicly accessible features of the wine. He might call her attention to the wine’s color and viscosity, but this aid Barbara little, if any, in detecting the aromas and tastes that elude her. One may well object that aromas and tastes are “publicly accessible” features of wines. They are in the sense that there is remarkable agreement among wine experts—welltrained sommeliers, for example—on aromas and tastes. We have no wish to deny this. Our point is that such features are less accessible in the sense that reliably detecting them typically requires considerable specialized experience and training. It matters whether one can refer to generally publicly accessible features when trying to assist others to form an appropriate first-person authoritative belief. Iris Murdoch emphasizes similar point about art: The accessible existence of art, its ability to hang luminously in human minds at certain times, depends traditionally upon an external being, a fairly precise and fixed sensory notation or ‘body’, an authority to which the client intermittently submits himself. . . Art experience . . . is something we can self-evidently and identifiably have and enjoy, in various ways in various materials.3 We think a similar point holds for beauty: the “ability [of beauty] to hang luminously in human minds at certain times, depends [in a range of central and important—but not all—cases] upon an external being . . . an authority to which the client intermittently submits himself.” The publicly accessible features (accessible with out specialized experience and training) provide an “external authority,” shared external point of reference around which communities of like b-enjoyers may readily form. Iris Murdoch, Metaphysics As A Guide To Morals (Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, 1993). 3 56 We do not, however, wish to overemphasize the role of publicly accessible features. By way of counterpoint, consider the conversion of M. Alphonse Ratisbonne, a Jew by birth and, for the first part of his life, an atheist by conviction. When Alphonse entered a chapel devoted to the Virgin Mary, he had a vision of the Virgin and was instantly converted to Catholicism. Alphonse described his state immediately after the conversion: I did not know where I was: I did not know whether I was Alphonse or another. I only felt myself changed and believed myself another me; I looked for myself in myself and did not find myself. In the bottom of my soul I felt an explosion of the most ardent joy; I could not speak; I had no wish to reveal what had happened . . . All that I can say is that in an instant the bandage had fallen from my eyes, and not one bandage only, but the whole manifold of bandages in which I had been brought up. One after another they rapidly disappeared, even as the mud and ice disappear under the rays of the burning sun. I came out as from a sepulchre, from an abyss of darkness; and I was living, perfectly living. But I wept, for at the bottom of that gulf I saw the extreme of misery from which I had been saved by an infinite mercy.4 One can readily imagine that, as part of the “explosion of the most ardent joy,” Alphonse b-enjoyed the vision of the Virgin and judged the vision beautiful. There are of course few publicly accessible features that one might indicate to help others b-enjoy a similar vision. There is the chapel and its adornments, but few who experience them experience visions. V. Beauty’s Power We can now deliver on our promise to explain beauty’s power to compel our attention and appreciation, to unite us in shared visions, and to divide us with different ones. B-enjoyment is the source of these powers. It compels our attention and appreciation in three ways. To see how, suppose 4 William James, Principles of Psychology 57 one forms the belief that x has an array A of features and b-enjoys x as having that array; then, first, the belief is active reason to enjoy x as having A, a reason that motivates and justifies continued enjoyment. Second, the operation of the active reason is reinforced by the conviction that the belief is a normative reason to enjoy x as having A. That is, one not only has an active reason to enjoy x, one also believes that one should have the reason. Third, the b-enjoyer is not only in the grip of a causal feedback loop, that loop typically enriches the conception of the relevant array of features and thereby renews the enjoyment in a more complex form. Judgments of beauty unite us in communities of like b-enjoyers, communities in which each member shares the belief that his or her benjoyment has revealed a particular normative reason that transcends life’s contingencies. Judgments of beauty, however, also divide us into distinct communities of b-enjoyers, communities from which, as a practical matter, many are simply forever barred from entry. Bobby Fischer played many beautiful chess games, but, since the vast majority of people lack the expertise to b-enjoy the complex chess relationships in which their beauty consists, the vast majority are forever barred from the community that benjoys them for those relationships. Similar examples abound, as the earlier discussion of Wallace Steven’s Sunday Morning illustrates. Guanglei will never become sufficiently immersed in Christian culture to join Vicki and others in the community that b-enjoys the poem for its portrayal of Christianity-rooted concerns over purification, suffering, forgiveness, communion, and immortality. Vicki on the other hand will never join 58 Guanglei in the community that enjoys classical Chinese landscape paintings. In each case, group members believe their b-enjoyments reveal a normative reason that transcends life’s contingencies, but the two groups have profoundly different conceptions what that contingency-transcending reason is. 59