Article type: Commentary Title: Legitimate Compassion or Compassionate Legitimation? Reflections on the Policy for Prosecutors in Respect of Cases of Encouraging or Assisting Suicide Author Name: Hazel Biggs, Professor of Healthcare Law and Bioethics Author affiliation: School of Law, University of Southampton, HEAL (Centre for Health Ethics and Law) Author addresses: School of Law University of Southampton Highfield Southampton SO17 1BJ 1 The final publication is available at www.springerlink.com Legitimate Compassion or Compassionate Legitimation? Reflections on the Policy for Prosecutors in Respect of Cases of Encouraging or Assisting Suicide Hazel Biggs Abstract This article explores the background to, and implications of, the recently published DPP guidelines for prosecutors in respect of cases of encouraging or assisting suicide. It considers the extent of the provisions and questions the legitimacy of their focus on the compassionate motivation of the assistant, and the apparent prohibition on healthcare professionals providing such help. It concludes by suggesting that a permissive change in the provide better safeguards for those who seek assisted dying. Key words Assisted suicide, DPP, Purdy, compassion Introduction A series of legal cases, mostly brought by women or on their behalf, across several jurisdictions, has ensured that assisted dying, and particularly assisted suicide, has been a topical and controversial issue in recent years.1 In the UK in 2009, in its last ever judgment, the House of Lords delivered its ruling in the case of Purdy. 2 As a victim of incurable and progressive multiple sclerosis, Debbie Purdy contemplated a situation where she would ultimately decide to end her life but would require assistance to do so. In those circumstances she would opt to travel to the Dignitas clinic in Zurich to end her life, but she would require her husband to accompany her and assist with travel and other practical arrangements. However, under s2 (1) of the Suicide Act 1961 it was, at the time, an offence to ‘aid, abet, council or procure the suicide of another’. This wording has since been amended by the Coroners and Justices Act 2009, s 59, so that liability now attaches 1 Examples include, Re Karen Quinlan 355 A 2d 644 (NJ, 1976), Rodriguez v British Columbia (A-G) [1993] 3 SCR 519, Lindsell case (unreported) The Times, 29 October 1997, Pretty v UK [2000] ECtHR 1, Re Z (an adult: capacity) [2004] EWHC 2817 (Fam). 2 R (Purdy) v DPP [2009] UKHL 45 2 to ‘acts capable of encouraging or assisting the suicide or attempted suicide of another person’. Although literal interpretation of the statutory wording suggests that prosecution would follow from any act of assistance, when Ms Purdy brought her case more than 100 British nationals had been assisted to commit suicide in Switzerland, and none of their helpers had faced criminal charges (Joffe, 2008). Consequently, Debbie Purdy brought her case in order to obtain clarification as to whether her husband could expect to be prosecuted if he helped her to travel to Switzerland for an assisted suicide. The Suicide Act 1961 provides that ‘no proceedings shall be instituted ... except by or with the consent of the Director of Public Prosecutions’ (s2(4)). The Director of Public Prosecutions (DPP) therefore has discretion to decide whether and when prosecution of such cases is in the public interest. Purdy invited him to clarify which factors would be considered in deciding whether or not to prosecute, but the DPP declined. Accordingly, Purdy alleged that the lack of transparency in the application of prosecutorial policy infringed her right to respect for private life under Article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights (Purdy, 2008, para 11). The House of Lords ultimately agreed, and required the DPP to issue and disseminate guidance that would enable prospective suicide assisters to know the circumstances that would be likely to result in their prosecution. To this end the DPP published an interim policy in September 2009 (CPS, 2009), which included provisional lists of factors that would tend towards prosecution, and those that would not. A public consultation was launched to gauge attitudes to these factors and inform the final policy. It generated more than 5000 responses and resulted in the publication of a significantly revised policy (the Policy) in February 2010 (CPS, 2010(a)). This policy, and its implications for those who seek and assist suicide, is the subject of this article. The Policy The Policy guidelines set out sixteen public interest factors in favour of prosecution and six against. None of the individual factors is regarded determinative, and none carries greater weight than the others. Procedurally, these factors will only be considered after a thorough police investigation has been conducted (the evidential stage) and determined that there is sufficient evidence to justify a prosecution. It is notable that the Policy applies to acts performed after 1st February 2010, and charges relating to conduct 3 prior to that date will be brought under the wording and procedures that pertained prior to the amendment of the Suicide Act 1961. Regardless of the timing, these offences relate only to situations where the victim has performed the final act that leads to death herself. The law of homicide (murder or manslaughter) will apply if the assistant performs the acts that result in death, even where this amounts to merely completing the actions of the suicidal person. The law on assisted suicide remains unchanged by the introduction of the DPP’s policy for prosecutors, but its implications for those seeking assisted suicide and anybody who might provide that assistance are profound. Voluntary victims Although the DPP acknowledges that it is contentious, the policy adopts the terminology of victim and suspect, since this is believed to be ‘the most suitable term to use’ in the context of criminal prosecution (CPS, 2010(a), para 7). Accordingly six of the 16 factors tending in favour of prosecution relate to characteristics of the so-called victim; specifically, that s/he was under 18 years of age, lacked mental capacity, and ‘had not reached a voluntary, clear, settled and informed decision to commit suicide’ that was clearly and unequivocally communicated to the suspect (CPS, 2010(a), para 43 (3 and 4)). By comparison, all but one of the factors tending against prosecution, focus on the suspect. The use of criminal law terminology is inevitable once assisted suicide cases reach the courtroom, but until that time those involved do not intrinsically assume the characteristics of victim and suspect. In reality those who are assisted in suicide are often willing participants who seek suicide entirely voluntarily as a means of taking control of the situation within which they find themselves. In these circumstances, where a person is physically incapable of performing the final act herself, but has acted upon a settled and determined wish to die and has not been pressurised into fulfilling that desire, she is certainly not a victim in the usual sense. Instead such persons would be better characterised as acting autonomously having exercised a considered choice. Indeed the European Court of Human Rights acknowledged this approach in Pretty, and Mrs Pretty failed to secure the right to be assisted only because the court was concerned that to allow her to succeed under Article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights could be contrary to ‘…the protection of the rights and freedoms of others’ (Article 8 (2), Biggs, 2003). 4 Nevertheless it is commonplace for those who might typically seek assisted suicide to be described as victims of the medical condition from which they suffer. Furthermore, factor 10 of those tending in favour of prosecution specifies that prosecution will be more likely if ‘the victim was physically able to undertake the act that constituted assistance him or herself’ (CPS, 2010(a), para 45 (10)). By implication then, physical incapacity is a relevant public policy consideration in determining when a person should be prosecuted for assisting another to commit suicide despite its overt denial in the policy. However, whilst the interim policy included factors relating to the health of the assisted person, regarding the existence of terminal illness, sever, incurable or degenerative physical illness as factors tending against prosecution, the published policy is rightly devoid of reference to the assisted person’s medical condition. Its removal is a direct consequence of the fact that more than 1500 responses to the consultation identified its inclusion as potentially discriminatory (CPS, 2010(b)). In those terms, restricting access to assisted suicide to those suffering terminal illness, or at least looking more favourably on those who assist people who are terminally or incurably ill or suffering from extreme symptoms, flies dangerously close to labelling some lives as less worthy of protection than others, with potentially eugenic overtones. But it is difficult to reconcile this omission with the great emphasis in the Policy on the compassionate motives of the assistor. Compassionate but criminal suspects The sixth of the factors tending in favour of prosecution holds that prosecution is more likely if the assistor, labelled ‘the suspect’, was ‘not wholly motivated by compassion’ (CPS, 2010(a), para 43 (6), my emphasis). Similarly the fact that ‘the suspect was wholly motivated by compassion’ features prominently in the factors tending against prosecution (CPS, 2010(a), para 45 (2)). Compassion is thereby recognised as a key factor in deciding whether or not it will be in the public interest to prosecute somebody who assists in the suicide of another. Contextually this is not surprising since colloquially compassion has long been associated with assisted dying in the guise of mercy killing. Moreover, appeals to compassion as the impetus behind a mercy killing have sometimes also prompted a sympathetic response from juries and professional bodies in criminal trials involving doctors, as was evidenced in the case of Dr Cox (Dyer, 1992, 5 Boyd, 1995). It is rather disconcerting however that the assistant’s compassionate motivation is emphasised in the absence of any reliance on the medical circumstances of the person being assisted. If the suicidal person’s health status is not to be considered, the basis upon which the assistor is expected to feel compassion is rather unfathomable. Despite this, the policy clearly emphasises the role of compassion in the motivation of the assistor. Motive however is not traditionally regarded as determinative in criminal law where, as long as the suspect is shown to have performed the requisite actus reus and demonstrably exhibits the mens rea for the offence, her motive is largely irrelevant (Horder, 2000). By contrast, motive is often regarded as relevant in mitigation of sentence, particularly where emotions such as compassion are present. The recent case of Frances Inglis3 who was convicted of the murder of her severely disabled son provides a clear example. Whilst this was not a case of assisted suicide, Mrs Inglis argued that it was a mercy killing and that she did not regard such an act as murder due to the absence of malevolent motivation. She was convicted regardless of motive and received a mandatory life sentence with a recommendation that she should serve a minimum of nine years. On appeal however, the term imposed by the trial judge was reduced to five years, in recognition of the compassionate, if misguided, motivation and the mental state of the defendant. Motive was also a key factor in the case of Kay Gilderdale, also decided this year, but prior to the introduction of the Policy.4 Mrs Gilderdale’s daughter had suffered with ME for more than 16 years and had previously tried to kill herself. Kay Gilderdale admitted assisting her daughter to commit suicide, but was also charged with attempted murder. Following her acquittal the trial judge reportedly praised the jury for showing ‘common sense, decency and humanity’ in their verdict (Gammell, 2010). In relation to liability for assisted suicide under the amended Suicide Act 1961, so long as the perpetrator has performed acts capable of encouraging or assisting the suicide or attempted suicide of another person, and done so intentionally, they may be criminally culpable. From this viewpoint the introduction of compassionate motivation in deciding whether or not to prosecute appears to be a departure from the usual standards of criminal law. 3 4 R v Inglis [2010] EWCA Crim 2637. R v Gilderdale 2010 (unreported). 6 However, closer examination of recent cases shows that this was an important consideration in prosecution decisions even prior to formal its inclusion in the published Policy. It was revealed in Purdy that since Reginald Crewe became the first Briton to do so in 2003, 115 British nationals have travelled to Switzerland for assistance with suicide.5 No prosecutions followed despite the fact that most required at least minimal assistance. Eight of the cases were referred to the DPP who found there to be insufficient evidence to secure a conviction in six of them. Even though the evidential hurdle was crossed in the remaining two, the DPP decided that it would not be in the public interest to pursue them. But when in 2008 the parents of 23 year old Daniel James helped their son to go to Switzerland for an assisted suicide, it seemed possible that this trend might be broken. Daniel had been a promising rugby player when he suffered a severe spinal injury whilst training for the game. He was left permanently tetraplegic and subsequently tried to kill himself three times, without success. His parents continuously tried to persuade him against using the services of Dignitas, but eventually relented and reluctantly agreed to assist him. The media furore that erupted after the circumstances of his death became known indicated a strong possibility that this case would be the first to see a prosecution (Brown, 2008, BBC, 2008). However, despite Daniel’s young age and the fact that he was not terminally ill, the DPP again decided that prosecution would be contrary to the public interest (Mullock, 2009). The extreme reluctance, care and compassion Mr and Mrs James displayed was highly influential in this decision, and demonstrates that the existence of compassionate motivation has been influential in the prosecutorial decision-making process for some time, despite its denial in criminal law doctrine. The reluctance of the assistant Reluctance to assist, combined with efforts to dissuade the person from suicide in the face of a determined wish to die, is a prominent factor in the DPP’s Policy, as it was in the cases of James and Gilderdale (CPS, 2010, para 45 (5)). In practice one might expect that anyone who is emotionally attached to a suicidal person would usually be reluctant to help them die. This reluctance would stem 5 R (Purdy) v DPP [2009] UKHL 45, at para 30, per Lord Hope. 7 not just from a desire to avoid losing their loved one in spite of feelings of empathy and compassion for their plight, but possibly also from fear of prosecution. On this point, John Coggon argued prior to the DPP’s formulation of these policy guidelines, that some who might seek suicide could instead feel compelled to choose life rather than place the burden of potential criminal prosecution upon their carers (Coggon, 2008). His argument is entirely credible even though it flies in the face of conventional thinking in opposition to assisted suicide, which often implies that making assisted suicide legal would lead vulnerable people to feel obliged to choose it in order to avoid becoming overly burdensome on their carers (McPherson et al, 2007). One way to avoid imposing the burden of guilt upon friends and family who are prepared to assist in suicide, is to seek professional assistance. The role of healthcare professionals In recent decades dying has become an increasingly medicalised process (Clark, 2002) and in this environment it is understandable that those who are unable to end their own lives might turn to medical professionals for assistance. Where this is the case the obvious route to suicide would be the provision of toxic medications that are not readily available to members of the public. Death caused by medication is likely to be more humane, and certainly less violent, than many of the methods readily available to the lay public. It may also have less extreme, and less costly consequences than methods seen in some recent cases. For example, in 2002, Sir Derek Bibby elected to kill himself rather than die from prostate cancer and leukaemia. He chose not to seek assistance but, mindful of the fact that many suicide attempts fail and sometimes leave the suicidal person in a worse condition, he opted for a sure fire method. Entering his home sauna he poured rat poison over the hot coals to produce a deadly toxic vapour, which he then inhaled. He alerted his daughter to the danger by a pinning a note to the sauna door, and was subsequently rescued by fire fighters wearing breathing apparatus as protection from the fumes. Sir Derek was dead on arrival at hospital but concerns about the toxicity of his body caused the closure of the emergency department and five hospital staff suffered breathing problems as a consequence (Carter, 2002). Aside from avoiding incriminating or endangering loved ones, the involvement of personnel with clinical knowledge and access to pharmaceutical methods may also give greater certainty of 8 outcome. But the DPP’s Policy firmly discourages assistance from healthcare professionals and others who have caring responsibilities for the deceased (CPS, 2010, para 43 (14)). This is out of step with public preferences and the approach taken in jurisdictions where assisted dying has been legalised.6 It has also caused consternation amongst doctors groups. As a result the Medical Defence Union has recently reiterated that its ‘advice to its members remains that doctors approached by patients for advice about suicide should not engage in discussion which assists patients to that end’ (MDU, 2010). Since the impetus behind the publication of the DPP’s Policy was to clarify the circumstances within which an assistor might be prosecuted for complicity in the suicide of a person travelling abroad to die, this has been taken to include providing access to medical records, which is usually required by Dignitas. Denying such access may however be contrary to established patient’s rights of access to their own healthcare records as supported by Article 8 of the Human Rights Act 1998. Moreover, although assisted suicide remains a crime, the potential criminalisation of healthcare professionals for offering such limited assistance, and in relation to something that patients are entitled to by right, is problematic. Conclusions: Retrospective decisions, ineffective protections and inadequate rights The DPP’s Policy for prosecutors in respect of cases of encouraging or assisting suicide was introduced to provide transparency as to the factors that will, and should, be considered when deciding whether or not to bring a prosecution against a person who has helped another to commit suicide. It has the potential to offer some comfort to Debbie Purdy and others in similar positions, but that is all it does. It does not provide immunity from prosecution, nor does it decriminalise assisted suicide (CPS, 2010(a), para 6), and is therefore largely ineffectual in the broader context of the debate about assisted dying. Whilst substantively the Policy appears to include sensible factors capable of affording safeguards for those who might be vulnerable to being pressurised into committing suicide, in reality it offers scant protection. Decisions on whether or not to prosecute can only ever be taken after the fact, and merely invoking the established power of the criminal law to punish perpetrators retrospectively seems unlikely 6 For example doctors are central to the provision of assisted suicide in Oregon and to the administration of assisted dying in the Netherlands 9 to provide additional safeguards for those who may be vulnerable to abuse, coercion or exploitation. The retrospective assessment of circumstances and motives amounts to too little too late for anybody who may have been the victim of a criminal act. In addition, the Policy is likely to encourage people seeking assisted suicide to travel abroad to more sympathetic jurisdictions. Not only does it effectively outlaw the kind of professional assistance available in Switzerland, it also includes provisions designed to actively discourage the formation of organisations like Dignitas in England and Wales. For instance, paragraph 43 (16) includes the fact that persons were acting as members of organisations or groups whose purpose ‘is to provide a physical environment (whether for payment or not) in which to allow another to commit suicide’ as a factor in favour of prosecution. By seemingly encouraging Britons who seek assisted suicide to travel overseas to access services, this approach, like the current prohibition on assisted suicide, is likely to result in premature death and introduces the risk that some may act upon hasty and poorly considered choices. With this in mind Clive Seale has voiced concerns that cases in Switzerland ‘entail more women than men, and one in five has no fatal condition but rather, for example, arthritis, osteoporosis, “general weakness”, blindness, or mental disorders, usually depression’ (Seale, 2010). Seale’s comments raise issues in themselves about whether and when assisted dying ought to be permissible, but that being so, it would seem preferable to enact legislation in the UK that prescribes the parameters within which assisted dying is regarded as acceptable and imposes robust and enforceable safeguards, rather than effectively turning a blind eye to practices that might be questionable. As it stands the Policy appears to do little more than reflect the kind of reasoning that presumably led to decisions not to prosecute the parents of Daniel James and the relatives and carers of numerous other Britons who have been assisted to die in Switzerland. Compassionate motivation has clearly been an influential factor in previous prosecutorial decisions, and it has been argued that the reliance on compassion in the published Policy may place many who assist beyond the reach of the criminal court (Mullock, 2010). Whether or not this is true remains to be seen, but it is already clear that focusing on the motives of the accused is out of step with criminal law doctrine. The compassionate motives of a person who assists 10 in the suicide of another may be understandable, but it is debatable whether it is legitimate for those motives to determine that there is no case to answer and result in a failure to prosecute. However, on a human level, the recognition that those who help may do so with compassionate motives rather than with malevolent intentions is all to the good. Similarly, despite the fact that it will only be evidenced after the suicide has occurred, the insistence in the Policy on the voluntary nature of the suicidal person’s intentions is to be welcomed. If suicide is regarded as a mechanism for those who seek it to exercise their autonomy and independence, then so long as they are competent they should be enabled to make their own choices about how and when to die. And, if acting upon their choices necessarily involves the assistance of others, then access to that help should be available and permissible within the law. Within this it is of course right and proper for the law impose safeguards to protect those who are vulnerable, but it should also be remembered that the women whose cases have informed this Policy were not in that category. Both Debbie Purdy and Diane Pretty before her, sought clarification of the legal impact upon those who might assist them to die, but the decision about whether to opt for assisted dying was their own and neither was vulnerable to abuse or exploitation. They would certainly not be victims as envisioned in the Policy. Similarly, in Re Z it was held that in spite of her potential vulnerability Mrs Z had made a considered and autonomous choice and was entitled to act upon it. The Policy acknowledges the centrality of ascertaining information about the mental capacity of the person who has committed suicide, but it is difficult to determine how this will be determined with certainty once that person is dead. This is particularly worrying if the so-called suspect is the person best able to provide such evidence. Accordingly, not only does the Policy fail to promote the autonomy of people who wish to have an assisted suicide, it also fails to adequately protect the interests of those who might fall prey to unscrupulous assistants. The DPP was bound by legal precedent to construct this Policy. In doing so it was acknowledged that only Parliament can change the law on encouraging or assisting suicide (CPS, 2010(a) para 5). Given the shortcomings identified here it is time for Parliament to act. 11 References BBC. 2008. Mother defends rugby suicide son. http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/england/hereford/worcs/7677706.stm. Accessed 1st October 2010. Biggs, Hazel. 2003. A pretty fine line: Life, death, autonomy and letting it B. Feminist Legal Studies 11: 291-301. Boyd, K. 1995. Euthanasia: Back to the future. In Euthanasia Examined, ed. John Keown, 72-81. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brown, David. 2008. Rugby Star Dan James in ‘Assisted Suicide’ after Training Injury. The Times, 18th October. Available at: http://www.timesonline.co.uk/tol/news/uk/health/article4962436.ec e. Accessed 1st October 2010. Carter, Helen. 2002. Millionaire’s rat poison suicide closes A&E unit. The Guardian 1tth October. Available at http://www.guardian.co.uk/society/2002/oct/11/health.healthandwel lbeing. Accessed 13th October 2010. Clark, Davis. 2002. Beyond hope and acceptance: medicalisation of dying. British Medical Journal 324: 905-6. the Coggon, John. 2008. Assisting ‘death tourism’: possible prosecution or pragmatic immunity? http://www.ccels.cf.ac.uk/archives/issues/2008/coggon.pdf. Accessed 1st November 2010. CPS, 2008. Decision on prosecution: Death by suicide of Daniel James. London: UK Gov. Available at: http://www.cps.gov.uk/news/articles/death_by_suicide_of_daniel_j ames/ . Accessed 21st November 2010. CPS. 2009. Interim policy for prosecutors in respect of cases of assisted suicide. UK Gov available at www.cps.gov.uk. Accessed 13th October 2010. 12 CPS. 2010(a). Policy for prosecutors in respect of cases of encouraging or assisting suicide. London: UK Gov. Available at, http://www.cps.gov.uk/publications/prosecution/assisted_suicide_p olicy.html. Accessed 21st November 2010. CPS. 2010(b). Public consultation exercise on the interim policy, Annex B – Equality and Diversity Impact Assessment, para 25. Available at www.cps.gov.uk . Accessed 1st October 2010. Dyer, Claire. 1992. GMC tempers justice with mercy in Cox case. British Medical Journal 305: 1311. Gammell, C. 2010. Mother Kay Gilderdale found not guilty of murder attempt on ME sufferer daughter. The Telegraph, 25th January. Horder, Jeremy. 2000. On the irrelevance of motive in the criminal law. In Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, ed Jeremy Horder, 171195. Oxford: OUP. Joffe Joel, 2008. Debbie Purdy deserves a less terrible choice. The Times, 30th October. Lindsell case (unreported) The Times, 29 October 1997. McPherson, Christine, Wilson, Keith, Murray Mary Ann. 2007. Feeling like a burden to others: a systematic review focusing on the end of life. Palliative Medicine 21 ( 2): 115-128. MDU. 2010. MDU’s concerns over CPS’s new policy on assisted suicide. Press release. 25th February 2010. Available at: http://www.themdu.com/section_gps_and_primary_care_professionals/topnav_N ews_3/hidden_Article.asp?articleID=2143&contentType=Media+rel ease&articleTitle=MDU%26%23039%3Bs+concerns+over+CPS% 26%23039%3Bs+new+assisted+suicide+policy. Accessed 23rd November 2010. Mullock, Alexandra. 2009. Prosecutors making (bad) law?. Medical Law Review 17: 209-299. Pretty v UK [2000] ECtHR 1. 13 Re Karen Quinlan 355 A 2d 644 (NJ, 1976). Re Z (an adult: capacity) [2004] EWHC 2817 (Fam). Rodriguez v British Columbia (A-G) [1993] 3 SCR 519. R(on the application of Purdy) v DPP [2008] EWHC 25655. R(on the application of Purdy) v DPP [2009] UKHL 45. R v Gilderdale 2010 (unreported). R v Inglis [2010] EWCA Crim 2637. Seale, Clive. 2010. Do it properly or not at all. British Medical Journal 340: c1719. 14