AMEY U4423598 A211/03 Is the free-will defence a convincing solution to the problem of evil? If God is wholly good and God is omnipotent, then evil cannot exist. Because evil manifestly does exist in the world, God is not both good and omnipotent. This is the problem of evil, simply stated, and it is a problem for various religions which hold the existence of a good and omnipotent God as one of their central tenants, such as Judaism, Christianity or Islam. The problem of evil is an attempt at a knock-down argument showing that this type of God cannot exist. The most popular family of attempted rebuttals has come from exposing the hidden premise in the logic above: that a wholly good and omnipotent God would create a world without evil. It is this premise which has been most attacked, and it is this premise that the free-will defence argues against. The free-will defence says that a wholly good and omnipotent God would create a world with free-will. This would give people the opportunity to live good lives and to find God, but would also necessarily give people the opportunity to commit evil. The ills of the world are created by people straying from the path laid out by their religion, but evil can be defeated if people are good. However, even if all people everywhere were good then the world might not be the utopia you would expect from a wholly good and omnipotent God; virtues such as forgiveness and charity can only exist in a world where people are wronged and unequal, and if the world has been created to give people a chance at virtue, then iniquity is necessary. But only by people abstaining from evil can the imagined utopia even be approached. 1 AMEY U4423598 A211/03 The use of the word ‘evil’ in the name of this argument implies a deliberateness of intent. As such, the free will defence seems to provide a good explanation, that people can perform evil actions because God has granted free will, which He must do in order to allow people to choose goodness. In this way suffering arises because of the evil actions of people, and people suffer due to their evil actions. But it is the suffering in the world that the problem of evil highlights, whether or not it has intent. When evil is seen in this broader light, as relating to suffering, the free will defence becomes less certain. Two questions immediately appear: what about suffering from non-human causes, and what about non-human suffering? Earthquakes, tidal waves, epidemics and drought; all these things bring about huge suffering. They strike seemingly at random, with no link between those affected and their goodness or otherwise. They are features of the world, and would be present with or without human free will. The arbitrariness of the world which a benign creator is supposed to have brought into being is not explained by the free will defence. San Francisco is particularly afflicted with the first of the disasters listed but, while San Francisco may be a very evil place by some people’s reckoning, there must be many other more evil places that deserve treatment as harsh. Not only is the existence of evil a conundrum, the apparently arbitrariness of its distribution is also a problem. Even while granting free will, God could have built an appearance of justice into the world. The free will defence can give no answer as to why God would create a world where this was the case. A further problem is the area of animal suffering. Animals have no hope of improving their souls, nor of acting in a good way as opposed to an evil way. If suffering exists 2 AMEY U4423598 A211/03 in the world from the choice of rational beings to do evil rather than good, it would seem to follow that beings who cannot make that choice should not be able to suffer. Mountains, rivers and all inanimate objects fall into this category of things that cannot choose and cannot suffer, but animals do not. They can suffer, but they cannot follow a religious path to save themselves. That suffering in the animal world can be as bad or worse as anything experienced by humans is now widely accepted by the public, and it becomes even more evident to biologists who have studied further. Charles Darwin wrote: I cannot persuade myself that a beneficent and omnipotent God would have designedly created the Ichneumonidae with the express intention of their feeding within the living bodies of Caterpillars, or that a cat should play with mice… (Darwin in Book 6, p104) There are several possible answers to this. Descartes saw animals as nothing more than clockwork, which could suffer no more than clockwork could suffer. This highly counter-intuitive, absolute denial of animal feelings is a consequence of Cartesian Dualism and suffers from all the flaws of that ideology. In this century the philosopher John Hick put forward a less radical denial of the nature of animal suffering, saying that animals have no anticipation of the future, nor memory of the past, both of which are integral parts of suffering. While it seems reasonable that the memory and anticipation of pain can cause as much suffering as the pain itself, it is not clear why animals are so blind to anything but the present. That laboratory rats can be trained by electric shocks implies a memory of pain in the past, and a desire to 3 AMEY U4423598 A211/03 avoid situations that cause pain. Likewise the image of a dog cowering under his brutal master’s hand suggests the dog has a good grasp of what the future holds in store for him, and is bracing himself for the pain of a beating. Hick’s arguments seem unsound in this respect, and also unconvincing with regard to pain felt in the present moment. He does raise the valuable point that pain is “within the general system whereby organic life is able to survive” (Hick in Book 6 p171). That is, that pain is sometimes necessary to show animals and, for that matter, people, unwise courses of action. However, the sheer amount and nature of suffering within the animal kingdom goes vastly beyond what is necessary for any teaching purposes, and Hick does not counter that point. A further objection to the free will defence says that although God could have granted us free will and the chance to choose evil, He could have put in safeguards to protect people. Teachers allow children freedom in the playground, and they have the chance to break the rules or to follow them. But if bigger children start hurting others even in minor ways, let alone to the extent of maiming and death, teachers step in to protect those who cannot protect themselves. In God’s playground he has allowed us the same freedom but with no safeguards. The evil committed by people is not checked and its consequences are felt indiscriminately. Two points can be made for the free will defence. First, the consequences of actions may be necessary for the evildoer to see the effects of his actions and fully understand them. Second, any intervention by God would have to restrict the freedom of the evildoer, and that would lessen any value of any subsequent faith and well doing, which was the purpose of giving people free will in the first place. Still, despite those two counter-arguments, the scale and ferocity of pain man can unleash on man would strongly suggest some minimum 4 AMEY U4423598 A211/03 safeguards should be put in place. Their absence is a puzzle and one which the free will defence cannot explain. Despite these very damaging objections, the biggest problem the free will defence faces is from a two part argument levelled at the very conception of free will it relies upon. God could have created people with free-will who always chose to do good. There have been, after all, some people who have chosen always to do good, and they, as people, must have had free-will just like the rest of us. From this it follows that people can exist who both possess free-will and always choose to do good. Because they could exist, it follows that an omnipotent God could have populated the world with such people, thereby allowing free-will but without creating evil. This train of logic has been argued against, again by John Hick. He replies that while from the human perspective there would be both free-will and total goodness, from God’s point of view this goodness would be valueless because He would know He had created it. This is equivalent to A loving and devoting him/herself to B, and of B valuing this love as a genuine and free response to himself whilst knowing that he has so constructed or manipulated A’s mind as to produce it. (Hick in Book 6, p168). 5 AMEY U4423598 A211/03 Hick’s point is that even if there was free will from our side, God would know the outcome that would always be produced, and so any goodness that was chosen would be valueless. While seeking to give an explanation of why God would not have created a universe where everyone was free but chose God, Hick raises a more fundamental problem with the free will defence: the conception of free will being used. Any goodness in the perfectly good world is worthless, Hick argues, because God caused it Himself. But how is our own world any different? The traditional conception of God being defended here is as an all powerful, benign creator. Even in our own imperfect world, any goodness would have come from God and so would be as worthless as the goodness in the perfectly good world. The free will defence ‘seems to depend on a conception of free will that seems to be incoherent’ (Blackburn (1999), p174). It imagines that while we ourselves are part of the world and are affected by it, there remains a part of us, the ‘Real You’ inside your head, who can intervene and make decisions. Separating the free will part of thinking seems to save it from the deterministic universe we live in every day, where every effect has had its cause. The problem is that the determinism will effect the ‘Real You’ just as much as it does your body; the stimuli you see and hear, the people you meet and the opinions you encounter will have just the same affect wherever the decision making takes place. From this view, if God created the universe he is responsible for any goodness or otherwise in it, and He cannot be surprised. So He might as well have made the world full of good people; their worship would have been as worthless as ‘A’s love for ‘B’, but as least there would have been more of it. 6 AMEY U4423598 A211/03 In total there seems to be very little to recommend the Free Will Defence. From its foundation on a suspect conception of free will to its applications in the cases of suffering from non-human causes, and of suffering inflicted on non-human animals, the Free Will defence is found wanting on every level. Therefore the free-will defence is not a convincing solution to the problem of evil. Word Count: 1852 Bibliography: Book 6 Simon Blackburn (1999) Think, Oxford Univeristy Press 7