AS Philosophy Module 2 Philosophy Of Religion Unit 4 The Problem Of Evil 1 The Problem of Evil History The problem of evil was first discussed by the Greek philosopher Epicurus (371-270 BC). Since then, many philosophers and theologians have wrestled with the problem, causing some - such as the French philosopher Jean Paul Sartre (1905-1980) - to state that God does not exist (Sartre actually called the idea that there was actually no God "a colossal joke"). Defences of God's goodness and omniptoence in view of this problem - called Theodicies - also stretch back to the beginnings of Christianity. St Augustine (354-430) put the problem most concisely: "Either God cannot abolish evil, or he will not; if he cannot then he is not all-powerful; if he will not then he is not all good." Types of Evil For the purposes of the Philosophy of Religion the word "evil" has a broader definition than that possessed by human or supernatural agents. So, although Hitler and Satan would undoubtedly be included in such a discussion, evil also covers so-called "Acts of God" - such as earthquakes, floods, famines, etc. - as well as other imperfections in the world and it's creatures. There are two main types of evil: 1. Moral evil - This covers the wilful acts of human beings (such as murder, rape, etc.) 2. Natural evil - This refers to natural disasters (such as famines, floods, etc.) Of these two types, we may further divide both of them into the following two classes: 1. Physical evil - This means bodily pain or mental anguish (fear, illness, grief, war, etc.) 2. Metaphysical evil - This refers to such things as imperfection and chance (criminals going unpunished, deformities, etc.) The problem itself arises because of certain qualities which religious believers grant to God, and the consequences of these given certain observations about the world. To illustrate these consider three qualities that most religious believers would not want to deny to God: absolute goodness (omnibenevolence), absolute power (omnipotence) and absolute knowledge (omniscience). Now, add to this the observation that there is evil in the world. Setting aside for the moment the question of how a good God could create a world with evil in it, ask yourself why such a deity does not do something to help combat such evil. Many theologians and philosophers over the centuries have asked this question and we will now look at some of the answers they have given. Exercise Try to think of 3 examples of each of the four types of evil. 2 Theodicy In the book of Job in the Old Testament, Job himself is the victim of numerous misfortunes. Although there is no apparent reason for any of these events - at least none known to Job - a number of people seek to give possible explanations (these people are known as "Job's Comforters"). Such an attempt to account for evil without altering the conception of God is known as a Theodicy. So, in Job's case, the comforters give various possibilities as to why his family should die, his animals be stolen and he himself should be afflicted with illness: they ask if he has angered God by some act or thought; perhaps there is some sin that he is not aware of? The thing to note about theodicy is that none of the main aspects of the problem change: God is still all-good, omniscient and omnipotent; evil still seems to exist. The difference is, however, that some reason is given to explain how all of these things can be true at the same time. The Irenaen Theodicy St Irenaeus (130-202 AD) thought that the existence of evil actually serves a purpose. From his point of view, evil provides the necessary problems through which we take part in what he calls "soul-making". From this point of view, evil is a means to an end in as much as if it did not exist, there would be no means of spiritual development. Irenaeus' view has been put forward in modern times by such philosophers as John Hick (Evil and the God of Love, 1966) and Richard Swinburne. According to this view the pains and sufferings of the world are meant by God to act as a means of producing a truly good person. This view of suffering as a means to good is rejected famously by the Russian novelist Fyodor Dostoevsky in The Brothers Karamazov. One of the characters, Ivan, rejects this view on the grounds that the suffering of one child can never be justified in terms of what good results. Questions 1. Does this argument justify evil? 2. Can we judge any action only on its consequences? 3. Do the means justify the ends? What sort of good might the Holocaust justify? Would it be worth it? 4. The idea of "soul-making" supposes that an individual may be given enough time to learn. Where infants die, or children, how can we view their chances against someone who lives, say, to the age of 80? 5. Does this view imply that some souls are more important than others? 6. Can the justification of soul-making be used when we can't prove if the soul exists or not? 3 The Augustinian Theodicy St. Augustine proposed a solution to the problem by blaming it on the Fall of humanity after the disobedience in the Garden of Eden. From this view, Man is responsible for evil by being led astray by Satan. This not only absolves God of creating evil but also allows Him to show the world His love by bringing Christ into the world. A modern advocate of Augustine's view can be found in Alvin Plantinga (God, Freedom and Evil, 1974) who claimed that for God to have created a being who could only have performed good actions would have been logically impossible. This view was later criticised by Anthony Flew and J.L.Mackie, who both argue that God could have chosen to create "good robots" who still possessed free-will. The Free-Will Argument Perhaps the most common theodicy is the so-called free-will argument - very similiar to Augustine's argument - which goes something like this: 1. Evil is the result of human error 2. Human error results from free-will (the ability to do wrong) 3. If we didn't have free-will we would be robots 4. God prefers a world of free agents to a world of robots 5. Evil is therefore an unfortunate - although not unavoidable outcome - of free-will 6. For God to intervene would be to go take away our free-will 7. Therefore, God is neither responsible for evil nor guilty of neglect for not intervening Questions 1. If Satan and his angels led Man astray, how can we account for the fact that Satan himself exists? Isn't God here responsible for creating an evil being? 2. Are well-behaved robots better than ill-behaved free agents? 3. If God cannot intervene without harming free-will, does this mean that he cannot intervene at all? Would this then make him not as powerful? 4. What would be the difference between a God who could not intervene and a God who did not exist? 5. Does the fact that God sends Christ to redeem the world make up for the existence of evil? Could God have expressed His love any other way? 4 6. Does the fact that evil exists still cause problems for these arguments? Process Theodicy Process theology argues that the reality of God is not fixed and that God himself is still developing. From this point of view, God is "dipolar" - that is, has two "poles", one mental and one physical. The physical pole is the material world itself, which acts almost as God's "body". Because of this relationship, God is partly distinct and partly immersed in the world - just as we are in our bodies. As a result, any suffering in creation is also undergone by God, and creation itself is seen as a cooperation between God and all other beings. Whether this cooperation actually takes place is thus up to humanity - in other words, God cannot force humans to do His will, but can only influence them. History Process philosophy is the idea that reality is in a state of change and development. From this point of view, no opinion of how the world is can always be true. Although the idea can be traced back to the Greek philosopher Heraclitus (lived around 500 BC), the idea again became popular in the nineteenth century with the advent of the theory of evolution. However, the philosophy is now most commonly associated with the English philosopher, Alfred North Whithead (1861-1947), and his book Process and Reality: an Essay in Cosmology (1929) is considered one of the most important expositions of process philosophy. The main application of Whitehead's position was put forward by his pupil, the American philosopher Charles Hartstone (1897- ), whose main works include The Divine Relativity (1948) and The Logic of Perfection (1962). Questions 1. The view that God is part of the world and suffers with it an unconventional view of God (theologians have argued for centuries that God is unchanging). This being so, would such a changeable being be God at all? 2. If God is part of the world, why can't he just cause whatever he wants to happen? 3. If reality is changing, does this mean that we can never really know anything - and therefore never know God? 5