Christian Psychological Research and the Post-Postmodern Future P. J. Watson Christian scholars constantly confront the new challenges of a relentlessly changing intellectual environment. The Christian theologian Millard J. Erickson (2001) essentially offered a sketch of that challenge when he recently recommended, “We must work toward a postpostmodernism, not simply ignoring the phenomenon of postmodernism, and reverting to a prepostmodernism, but also not merely halting with postmodernism” (p. 293). The Christian writer Robert C. Greer (2003) has similarly argued that Christians should work toward a “newly developing paradigm [of] postpostmodernism” (p. 229). What would a Christian post-postmodernism look like? Pre-postmodern options are ruled out by definition. Any simple reassertion of premodern Christian traditions, therefore, seems to be precluded. For many, the broader cultural viability of that option collapsed with the failure of premodern Christianity to avoid the violence of the Reformation and the Thirty Years’ War (Toulmin, 1990). The trauma of those times apparently demanded the creation of “a vocabulary whose sense did not depend upon prior agreement about the nature of God and the structures of cosmos and society ordained by him” (Stout, 1988, p. 161). Modernism sought to supply that “vocabulary.” Beginning with the Cogito that Descartes discovered at the foundations of his doubt, the modernist hope was to achieve order through the clear and distinct ideas of a rational self that could see the world with a vision undistorted by traditional commitments. “Good sense is the most evenly shared thing in world” is how Descartes began his Discourse on Method (Descartes, 1637/1968, p. 27). He then went on to conclude “that the diversity of our opinion does not spring from some of us being more able to reason than others, but only from our conducting our thoughts along different lines and not examining the same things” (p. 27). The violence produced by differences presumably could be eliminated through a “modern” reliance upon reason proceeding along the same lines and examining the same things. This modernist confidence in the universal and unifying rationality of the self expressed itself politically in the rise of democracy and epistemologically in the scientific methods of disciplines that came to include psychology. Psychology, nevertheless, went on to put limits on any Cartesian optimism about the rational self, and whereas his clear and distinct ideas led Descartes to “rationally” prove the existence of God, later modernist thought increasingly moved the self away from any theistic belief at all (Taylor, 1989, pp. 401-410). For some, the bloodshed of the 20th Century was as powerful in falsifying the modernist paradigm as the Thirty Years’ War had been in overturning a supposedly Christian cultural order. Rather than eliminating violence, modernist rationality had made the killing more technologically efficient (Appleyard, 1992). Actually, the philosophical movement away from modernism had already begun during the previous century. Nietzsche (1887/1967) at that time began to articulate the postmodern argument that the seeing and rationality of every self is always positioned in history and thus operates from a perspective that is invariably “distorted” by one tradition of understanding or another. No trans-historical framework could ever be identified for definitively adjudicating among the diverse perspectives of humanity. The modernist scientist was as naïve as the medieval Christian in believing in “truth.” Postmodernists concluded instead that all so- called “truth” is always as much a social construction of power as of so-called “reality” (e.g., Foucault, 1972). For those wedded to the “truth” of some pre-postmodern perspective, postmodern skepticism will necessarily be met with skepticism. Some of the conceptual problems will perhaps be almost too obvious in that they could lead to overly facile rejections of legitimate postmodern insights. If the postmodern dismissal of “truth” is the “truth,” for instance, then the position must be rejected as self-refuting. If the postmodern dismissal of “truth” makes no appeal to some notion of “truth,” then no obvious grounds can be supplied for supporting the position. Moreover, any rigorous postmodern reduction of social life to the dynamics of power seems to result in a radical relativism that in no obvious way brings humanity closer to solving the problem of violence. For many, and not just for Christians, commitment to “truth” will require some post-postmodern response (e.g., Kahn & Lourenço, 1999). Christians clearly will be among those wedded to a pre-postmodern idea of “truth.” Though unable to fall back to any simple premodern position, a Christian postpostmodernism obviously must remain committed to Christian traditions. The advantages of modernist political and epistemological innovations presumably must be defended as well, but without the loss of faith that can develop out of Cartesian skepticism. A postmodern sensitivity to diversity and pluralism also seems essential in a world of increasing globalization, but without embracing radical relativism. A Christian postpostmodernism, therefore, seems to require a premodernism that is not premodern, a modernism that is not modern, and a postmodernism that is not postmodern. How is that even possible? Again, Erickson (2001) suggests one answer, “We must transcend postmodernism, in part by not tying ourselves too closely to the ideology of any given period” (p. 293). This recommendation captures exactly the underlying implications of the Ideological Surround Model of the relationship between psychology and religion (Watson, 1993). This model assumes that all religious and social scientific perspectives are unavoidably “ideological.” As defined by MacIntyre (1978), an “ideology” is a somewhat non-empirical, normative, and sociological system of belief. The Christian assumption that God created the universe and the naturalistic assumption that He did not are both somewhat nonempirical because each can find support in empirical observations, yet neither can be falsified scientifically. Ideologies, nevertheless, have normative implications in that they have an impact on “morals, politics, and other guides of conduct” (MacIntyre, p. 6). Christian commandments and the naturalism of evolutionary psychology, for example, have very different ethical implications in at least some circumstances. Finally, an ideology is sociological in “that it is not merely believed by the members of a given social group, but believed in a way that it at least partially defines for them their social existence” (MacIntyre, p. 6). Within an ideological surround, a Christian post-postmodernism will understand that premodern Christian traditions will have to “speak” within a pluralistic postmodern culture that has no common “vocabulary.” In a postmodern world, followers of all traditions will tend to dismiss other traditions as “merely” ideological, without seeing their own somewhat non-empirical, normative, and sociological foundations. Still, for all pre-postmodern traditions that believe in “truth,” the effort to communicate will be essential. For these people, words of different ideological languages will not be trapped in an infinite regress of definitions that make no contact with reality, as postmodernists sometimes argue. Among other things, words instead will signify human problems that require “truthful” languages that can discover “truthful” solutions. Violence will be just one of those problems. With their work framed within an ideological surround, Christian psychological researchers can use modernist social scientific methods to empirically demonstrate the somewhat non-empirical assumptions of both Christian and non-Christian perspectives (e.g., Watson, 1993, 1994). Empirical procedures can illustrate, for example, how the modernist psychological language of self-actualization can be translated into a more orthodox language based upon Christian norms (Watson, Milliron, Morris, & Hood, 1995). Modernist and postmodernist languages of rationality can also be evaluated empirically within a Christian ideological framework. As this research has made clear, psychological and Christian “rationalities” exhibit many commonalities; but in some instances, Christian “rationality” is superior (e.g., Watson, Milliron, Morris, & Hood, 1994). Behind all of this research activity, Christian commitment will be seeking to understand how to articulate itself in a faithful and compelling manner within the ideological complexities of postmodern pluralism. More generally, a Christian post-postmodernism will need to be interdisciplinary, ecumenical, and inter-ideological. The community of Christian scholars will need to be responsive to Christian understandings of history, including historical insights into violence and other problems. Christians in many other disciplines, including for example literary criticism, will have important contributions to make as well. Moreover, the entire post-postmodern enterprise will need to rest upon clearly articulated Christian assumptions. Attempts to interact with other ideological perspectives, for instance, could perhaps be justified in terms of a Christian epistemology of love (Watson, in press), but this and all other suggestions that address the challenges of post-postmodernity will need to be tested by the theology and philosophy of all Christian traditions. And of course, the effort to develop a common vocabulary of “truth” will require cooperation with other traditions, even in what seem to be difficult inter-ideological circumstances (Watson & Ghorbani, 1998; Ghorbani, Watson, Ghramaleki, Morris, & Hood, 2002). In short, Christian psychologists could confront a post-postmodern future with the intention of offering a culturally sensitive reassertion of Christian traditions. The challenges of present circumstances presumably will require cooperation with other disciplines, interactions among scholars representing the full range of Christian traditions, and efforts to make connections with advocates of completely different ideological perspectives. Pre-modern commitment and post-postmodern innovation presumably will be essential as Christians work to develop a “vocabulary” that will allow them to speak Truth to the powers of modernity and postmodernity. References Appleyard, B. (1992). Understanding the present. New York: Doubleday. Descartes, R. (1968). Discourse on method and the meditations. New York: Penguin Books. (Original works published in 1637 and 1641) Erickson, M. J. (2001). Truth or consequences. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press. Foucault, M. (1972). Power/Knowledge. New York: Pantheon Books. Ghorbani. N., Watson, P. J., Ghramaleki, A. F., Morris, R. J., & Hood, R. W., Jr. (2002). Muslim-Christian religious orientation scales: Distinctions, correlations, and cross-cultural analysis in Iran and the United States, The International Journal for the Psychology of Religion, 12, 69-91. Greer, R. C. (2003). Mapping postmodernism. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press. Kahn, P. H., Jr., & Lourenço, O. (1999). Reinstating modernity in social science research - or - the status of Bullwinkle in a post-postmodern era. Human Development, 42, 92-108. MacIntyre, A. (1978). Against the self-images of the age. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. Nietzsche, F. (1967). On the genealogy of morals. In W. Kaufman (Ed.) On the genealogy of morals and ecce homo (pp. 1-163). New York: Vintage. (Original work published 1887) Stout, J. (1988). Ethics after Babel. Boston: Beacon Press. Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Toulmin, S. (1990). Cosmopolis. New York: Free Press. Watson, P. J. (1993). Apologetics and ethnocentrism: Psychology and religion within an ideological surround. The International Journal of the Psychology of Religion, 3, 1-20. Watson, P. J. (1994). Changing the religious self and the problem of rationality. In T. M. Brinthaupt & R. P. Lipka (Eds.), Changing the self: Philosophies, techniques, and experiences (pp. 109-139). Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Watson, P. J. (In press). After postmodernism: Perspectivism, a Christian epistemology of love, and the ideological surround. Journal of Psychology and Theology. Watson, P. J., & Ghorbani, N. (1998). Ravanshenasi din dar javame Moslemin. [Psychology of religion in Muslim society.] Qabasat, 3 (2, 3) 52-72. (In Persian) Watson, P. J., Milliron, J. T., Morris, R. J., & Hood, R. W., Jr. (1994). Religion and rationality: II. Comparative analysis of rational-emotive and intrinsically religious rationalities. Journal of Psychology and Christianity, 13, 373-384. Watson, P. J., Milliron, J. T., Morris, R. J., & Hood, R. W., Jr. (1995). Religion and the self as text: Toward a Christian translation of self-actualization. Journal of Psychology and Theology, 23, 180-189.