An Argument for Robust Metanormative Realism by David Enoch A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy New York University May, 2003 _______________________________________________ Co-Advisors: Hartry Field, Thomas Nagel and Derek Parfit © David Enoch All Rights Reserved, 2003 ii To Naomi, Rakefet and Ronnie, three generations of women in my life, with love. iii Acknowledgments My committee members – Hartry Field, Tom Nagel and Derek Parfit – have been extremely helpful in all stages of my work on my thesis. Their encouragement, generosity with their time, and comments on earlier drafts have been invaluable. Almost as valuable were discussions with other professors, and even more so with fellow students and friends, at the NYU philosophy department and elsewhere. For such discussions and comments I want to thank Stephanie Beardsman, Hagit Benbaji, Thérèse Björkholm, Paul Boghossian, Cian Dorr, Ernesto Garcia, Pete Graham, Ulrike Heuer, Peter Kung, Andrei Marmor, John Richardson, Josh Schechter, Mark Schroeder, Sigrún Svavarsdóttir, Crispin Wright and Masahiro Yamada. Of these, I am especially grateful to Paul Boghossian, for his major part in recreating the PhD program at NYU, which – for me – was the ideal philosophical environment. iv Abstract In this essay, I defend a view I call “Robust Realism” about normativity. According to this view, there are irreducibly, perfectly objective, normative truths, that when successful in our normative inquiries we discover rather than create or construct. My argument in support of Robust Realism is modeled after arguments from explanatory indispensability common in the philosophy of science and the philosophy of mathematics. I argue that irreducibly normative truths, though not explanatorily indispensable, are nevertheless deliberatively indispensable, and that this kind of indispensability is just as respectable as the more familiar explanatory kind. Deliberative indispensability, I argue, justifies belief in normative facts, just like the explanatory indispensability of, say, theoretical entities like electrons justifies belief in electrons. In the introduction I characterize the view I will be arguing for and sketch the main argument of this essay. In chapter 1 I draw the analogy between explanatory and deliberative indispensability, and argue that there is no non-question-begging reason to take the former but not the latter seriously. Here I also present the master-argument of the thesis, and clarify the argumentative work that needs to be done by each of the following chapters. v In chapter 2 I address the worries of the antirealist who is willing to reject arguments from explanatory indispensability as well. In other words, in this chapter I try to justify the move from indispensability (of whatever kind) to belief. In chapter 3 I develop an account of deliberation that supports the premises about deliberation needed for my master-argument to go through. In chapter 4 I reject some alternative views, showing that none of them can allow for sincere deliberation. In this chapter, in other words, I support the indispensability premise: I argue that it really is impossible to deliberate sincerely without believing in irreducibly normative truths. In the conclusion I draw the threads from all previous chapters together. Here I also address worries about the robustness of my Robust Realism and about the intelligibility of the metanormative (or metaethical) discourse of which this essay is a part. vi Table of Contents Dedication iii Acknowledgments iv Abstract v Introduction: Robust Realism – The View, the Motivation, the Argument 1 (i) Normativity 2 (ii) Robust Realism 6 (iii) “Robust Realism” 13 (iv) The Argument 15 Chapter 1: The Indispensability of Irreducibly Normative Truths 25 1.1 Harman’s Challenge 27 1.2 Coping with Harman’s Challenge: Two Strategies 37 1.3 Parsimony 42 1.4 Indispensabilities 44 1.5 Metaphysical Naturalism Again 50 1.6 Instrumental and Intrinsic Indispensability 51 1.6.1 Instrumental Indispensability 53 1.6.2 Intrinsic Indispensability 57 1.7 Deliberation 60 1.8 Explanatory Role After All? 62 1.9 Scorekeeping 66 1.A Appendix: Previous Attempts at the Second Strategy 69 1.A.1 Lycan 70 1.A.2 Wiggins 71 1.A.3 McDowell 72 vii 1.A.4 Nagel 73 1.A.5 Dworkin 75 1.A.6 Platts 77 1.A.7 Korsgaard 79 1.A.8 Sayre-McCord 80 Chapter 2: How Does Indispensability Justify Belief 83 2.1 Explanatory Indispensability Again 84 2.2 Where Epistemic Justification Comes to an End 89 2.3 The Need for a Vindication 93 2.4 A Pragmatic Account of Vindication: The General Idea 96 2.5 Some Details 98 2.5.1 Non-Optional Projects 99 2.5.2 The Modalities 101 2.5.3 Extensional Adequacy 105 2.6 Deliberation (and Explanation) Again 106 2.7 A Remaining Worry about Truth and Reliability 110 2.8 Scorekeeping 114 2.A Other Ways of Rendering Unavoidability Useful 116 2.A.1 Nagel and Self-Defeat 116 2.A.2 Dretske and Ought-Implies-Can 119 2.A.3 Velleman and Constitutive Aims 121 Chapter 3: Deliberation 124 3.1 Deliberation Phenomenologically Characterized 128 3.2 The Instrumental Indispensability of Normative Truths 134 3.3 The Intrinsic Indispensability of Deliberation 141 3.4 Objections 148 3.4.1 Do We Explicitly Invoke Normative Truths viii 149 When Deliberating? 3.4.2 Aren’t Your Desires (or Your Ends, or Your 152 Identity) Sufficient? 3.4.3 Can We Not Be “Heroic Existentialists”? 159 3.4.4 Am I Conflating “What-Shall-I-Do” with 161 “What-Should-I-Do” Questions? 3.4.5 Is Deliberation Illusory After All? 164 3.4.6 Have We Reached Bedrock? 168 3.4.7 Can’t We Deliberate in the Face of (Believed) 169 Incomparability? 3.4.8 Don’t Antirealists Deliberate? 172 3.4.9 What Would We Have Done Had We Found Out 175 that There Are No Normative Truths? 3.4.10 Does the Argument Prove Too Much? A Quick 176 Note on Freedom 3.4.11 What Exactly is Indispensable? 179 3.4.12 Does Deliberation Incur Explanatory Commitments? 182 3.4.13 Had We Not Been Deliberative, Would There Have 186 Been Normative Truths? 3.4.14 Am I Committed to Dummettean Antirealism? 3.5 Kindred Spirits 188 192 3.5.1 Action 192 3.5.2 Conversation 196 3.6 Scorekeeping 198 Chapter 4: Rejecting Alternatives 199 4.1 The Field 201 4.2 Error Theory 206 4.2.1 Error Theory, Eliminativism, Instrumentalism, and ix 207 Revisionary Accounts 4.2.2 Against Instrumentalism 216 4.2.3 Against Eliminativism 220 4.2.4 A Way Out? 222 4.2.5 Error Theories and Softer Interpretations 225 4.3 Noncognitivism 227 4.3.1 Noncognitivism, Nonfactualism, Expressivism 228 4.3.2 Why Emotivism Will Not Do the Job 234 4.3.3 Why More Sophisticated Versions of Noncognitivism 237 Will Do No Better 4.3.4 Why Quasi-Realism Is beside the Point 4.4 Normative Naturalism 245 249 4.4.1 Normative Naturalism 250 4.4.2 Why Normative Naturalism Will Not Do 259 4.4.3 A Final Worry about Property Identity 269 4.5 Constructivism 271 4.5.1 Constructivism 273 4.5.2 Interesting Constructivism 278 4.5.3 The Constructivist Fallacy 286 4.6 Publicity 293 4.7 Softer-Interpretation Theories: A Final Thought Experiment 295 4.8 Hybrid Views 296 4.9 Other Options? 298 4.9.1 Sensibility Theories 298 4.9.2 Practical Reasoning 301 4.9.3 Internal Realism 303 4.10 Scorekeeping 304 Conclusion: How Robust is Robust Realism? x 306 1. Robustness 307 2. Quietism 317 References 329 xi Introduction Robust Realism: The View, the Motivation, the Argument In this essay I argue for a view that takes normativity seriously. This view – the one I call “Robust Realism” – states, very roughly, that there are irreducibly normative truths, truths about what we should do, what we should believe, how we should reason, what we should care about. These truths, or at least some of them, are perfectly objective, universal, absolute. They are independent of us, our desires and our (or anyone else’s) will. These normative truths are truths that, when successful in our normative inquiries, we discover rather than create or construct. They are, in other words, just as respectable as empirical or mathematical truths (at least, that is, according to scientific and mathematical realists). The view is not new. Indeed, insofar as there is a commonsensical view of normativity, I think this is it, despite its current less-than-orthodox status in philosophical circles1. As far as I know, however, the argument I am about to offer 1 In their survey of metaethical views on the scene today, Darwall, Gibbard and Railton (1992) do not even mention anything like Robust Realism. In a footnote (ibid, 40, footnote 59), they imply that the only live issues about such a view are where it goes wrong, whether ordinary moral discourse is committed to it, and the like. (See also ibid., 34.) 1 for this view is new; at least, it is an original attempt at making explicit and precise an intuition the force of which realists have always felt. In this introduction I do the following: First, in section (i), I briefly clarify what the normativity I am a Robust Realist about is. In section (ii), I say more about what Robust Realism comes to. Though I do not say much – for reasons that are explained in that section, I find it useful to leave some of this discussion to the concluding chapter – I hope I say enough to facilitate the discussion in the ensuing chapters. Section (iii) is a terminological apology in which I explain why I found it necessary to introduce a new term, “Robust Realism”, to the metaethical debate that is already overflowing with “ism”s. Section (iii) can thus be safely ignored by readers impatient with terminological discussions. In section (iv) I sketch my argument for Robust Realism, the argument that is then developed in following chapters. In this section I also give an outline of the rest of the essay. (i) Normativity Robust Realism is a view of, or about, normativity. Before proceeding to say something about Robust Realism, then, let me say a few words about the normativity I am a Robust Realist about. Normative truths (or facts, propositions, properties, claims, sentences and the like) are, at a first approximation, those that fall on the ought side of the isought distinction, the value side of the fact-value distinction, and the analogous side of analogous distinctions. These distinctions admit of vagueness and 2 borderline cases, and they are not, of course, uncontroversial. But the controversies regarding them are mostly about how best to make theoretical sense of them, not about whether they have any intuitive content. This intuitive content – vague though it is – will suffice for now. Not much more than this first approximation will be given here – none, I think, is needed at this stage, and if the argument of this essay is sound, there is no reason to expect that one can be given. Paradigmatic examples may, however, help clarify the kind of things I refer to as normative. That we ought to give money to famine relief is a normative proposition (and, given that it’s true, it’s also a normative truth, and a normative fact); so are that I should go on a diet, that you have a reason to read Kant, that pursuing graduate studies in philosophy is the thing it makes most sense for her to do, that he is a good person, that you shouldn’t form your beliefs on the basis of wishful thinking, that if he has inconsistent beliefs he’s irrational, that it’s unreasonable to expect everyone to convert to your religion, that we should all care more for our own children than for other people’s children, that it’s your duty to obey the laws of your country, that I have a moral right to free speech, and so on. These examples should suffice, I think, to give an intuitive feel of the normative realm about which I’m a Robust Realist. But many of them can be misunderstood in a relevantly important way. As Korsgaard (1996, 42) notes, different thinkers use different terms as their “normatively loaded words” – roughly, those for which it is analytically true that they carry normative force. 3 Thus, a word that is understood as normatively loaded by one may be understood differently by another. Consider, for instance, the word “good” in “She is a good person”. One may treat this as a normative claim; but one may – treating “good” as normatively unloaded, and, say, “reason” as normatively loaded – treat this as a perfectly descriptive claim, one that leaves the relevant normative question – Do I have reason to be a good person, or to be (relevantly) like her? – completely open. So in characterizing the normative I should say – somewhat vacuously, of course – that it is the discourse that comprises of propositions (sentences, truths, facts) of the kind of the examples given above, when these are understood as normatively loaded. Before proceeding to Robust Realism, let me preempt misunderstanding by noting three things I will not be discussing when I discuss normativity. First, I will not be discussing ethics or morality (In this essay I use these terms interchangeably). As the examples above show, some paradigmatic normative propositions are naturally classified as moral, and others are not. For the most part, I will be concerned with the more general phenomenon of normativity, not with morality, its particular instance. When this particular instance is nevertheless especially relevant, I note so explicitly. Second, as I will often be using “reason” as a normatively loaded term, it is important here that the reasons I’ll be talking about are normative, not motivating, reasons. Normative reasons are the reasons that count in favor of whatever it is they are reasons for. Motivating reasons are those that actually motivate the agent, 4 or bring her to action. This distinction is sometimes put in terms of the distinction between the reason for which an agent acts (those she takes to be normative reasons), and the reasons why she acts (motivating reasons)2. Now, whatever your view about the relation between normativity and motivation – not a simple issue, and one that will be discussed in several different contexts in what follows – and even if you think there are some necessary connections between normativity and motivation, surely you should not “support” this view by equivocating on “reason”, thus blurring the conceptual distinction between normative and motivating reasons. This conceptual distinction is, it seems, clearly there to be acknowledged, whatever else one then proceeds to argue about it. And the reasons I will be discussing in this essay are – unless otherwise noted – normative, not motivating, ones. Third, I will not be discussing the interesting topic of intra-normative reductions. Some, for instance, think that all normative discourse is reducible to talk of reasons.3 Others think that normative discourse is reducible to talk of the good.4 Others may come up with other suggestions for such reductions, and yet others may deny any such reduction, arguing that the normative is irreducibly pluralistic. I will remain neutral on such proposed reductions, so long as they are intra-normative – so long, that is, as the reducing as well as the reduced are normative. I will be discussing normativity, as it were, from above – Robust 2 See, e.g., Dancy (2000, 117). See, for instance, Raz (1975, chapter 1). 4 This may have been Plato’s view; and it may have been Moore’s as well. 3 5 Realism is a metanormative thesis – and will not here concern myself with the internal structure of the normative. (ii) Robust Realism Different philosophers mean different things when they use the word “realism”. Let me start my characterization of Robust Realism with what Rosen (1994, 281) calls “minimal realism”. Minimal realism about a discourse amounts to the following conjunction: Sentences in that discourse are truth-apt, and some of them are (non-trivially) true. It seems plausible to assume that – whatever exactly your favorite way of understanding “realism” is – it is a necessary condition to qualify as a realist to reject all versions of noncognitivism or nonfactualism about the relevant discourse (such as Ayer’s about the moral and Gibbard’s about the normative), and it is another such necessary condition to reject an error-theory about it (such as Mackie’s about the moral, the Churchlands’ about the mental and Field’s about mathematical objects). Robust Realism is committed, then, to Rosen’s minimal realism. As Sayre-McCord notes (1988c, e.g. at 16), however, such minimal realism is compatible with a kind of relativism or subjectivism that Robust Realism is clearly meant to exclude. Let us add, then, that, in addition to satisfying the requirements of minimal realism, Robust Realism is an objectivist, or universalist, or absolutist, view of normativity. Unfortunately, these characteristics are themselves hard to characterize (and once properly understood, important 6 distinctions between them may emerge). The intuitive idea – for which I will settle for now – seems to be that of observer-independence5: Whether or not a given normative statement is true does not depend on what attitudes regarding it – cognitive or otherwise – are entertained by those judging that it is (or is not), nor does it depend on the attitudes in their society. There is a complication here. The attitudes of those making the relevant judgments may be among the normatively relevant circumstances. For instance, when pronouncing the normative judgment “I am not irrational”, its truth may depend on my attitudes regarding it, for inconsistency in my beliefs – the one expressed by this very sentence included – may make this normative judgment false. But such judgment-dependence does not threaten the objectivity or absoluteness of the normative (in the intended sense of these words). Similarly, it may be wrong to spit at the direction of a person in some societies but not in others, simply because in the former, but not the latter, such an act would be interpreted as an expression of contempt and will thus cause humiliation, and it is (universally, objectively) wrong to express contempt and cause humiliation. Such sensitivity to normatively relevant circumstances – circumstances which often include people’s attitudes – again does not threaten universality or objectivity in the sense we are after. Let me use here, then, Darwall’s (1998, 65) distinction between the context of (the making of) the judgment and the context of the See Svavarsdóttir (2001, 162). See also Milo’s (1995, 192) discussion of “stance-independence” as a necessary condition for realism. 5 7 evaluated object. The latter – but not the former – is the context relevant to what the judgment is about. Robust Realism is objectivist in that it states that the truth of normative judgments does not depend in any way on the context of judgment. It depends only on (normatively relevant) features of what is being evaluated (such as, in the examples above, whether or not my beliefs are consistent and whether or not spitting causes humiliation). Robust Realism is, then, an objectivist, non-error-theoretical, cognitivist or factualist position, it states that some normative judgments are objectively nonvacuously true. But Robust Realism goes further than that. It asserts that some normative truths are irreducibly normative. Again, it is not completely clear what a reduction is (I discuss this in more detail below, in chapter 4, section 4.4). But it seems clear that a reduction claim includes an identity thesis (of the reduced and the reducing) or something very close to an identity, and some asymmetrical condition – perhaps something about the characterization of the reducing being more basic than that of the reduced6. The details of the second conjunct need not bother us here, for Robust Realism denies the first: Normative facts – or at least some of them – are not, according to Robust Realism, identical with any natural (not obviously normative) facts; normative facts are just too different from nonnormative, natural, ones. Robust Realism is thus the thesis that there are objective irreducibly normative truths. 6 For a discussion of what this basicness could possibly consist in, see Fine (2001). 8 Notice that Robust Realism is an existentially quantified thesis. It only states that there are some irreducibly normative truths. It does not say, for instance, that all (apparently) normative propositions are objective and irreducibly normative. It will become clearer as my argument unfolds (especially in chapter 4) that it cannot support this stronger thesis. (Furthermore, it is not clear to me that we should want to support such a strong thesis.) If you want to be strict about classifying facts (or whatever) as normative, you may say that any purportedly normative fact that is not objective and irreducibly normative is not really normative. With the terminology thus used, it is trivially true that all (really) normative facts are objective and irreducibly normative. Robust Realism then becomes the view that there is at least one (really) normative fact (or truth, or whatever). As already mentioned, I will be arguing for Robust Realism about normativity, not about ethics or morality. Given that Robust Realism is merely an existential thesis, it is clear, then, that it is compatible with any kind of metaethical antirealism. Even if there are no moral facts, for instance, Robust Realism may still be true, if there are other, non-moral, kinds of normative facts. And even if morality is observer-relative, there may be other normative truths which are not. But, though it is possible consistently to accept Robust Realism and metaethical antirealism (of some kind or another), it is hard to see why one would go for such a combination of views. The standard objections to either of these views are also (once suitably modified) objections to the other, and it seems that having accepted 9 irreducibly normative truths, one can have little reason to deny that some of them are moral7. Indeed, the literature often fails clearly to distinguish between the metaethical and the more general metanormative questions, views and arguments, and I will be regularly generalizing points made in the metaethical literature so as to make them directly relevant to my metanormative discussion. Nevertheless, morality may have unique features that make antirealism about it an attractive position even accepting Robust Realism about normativity more generally. I do not know whether this is so; whether or not it is, Robust Realism is not directly committed to Robust Metaethical Realism. Notice further that Robust Realism as characterized above is prima facie neutral on the epistemology of the normative, and is thus compatible with even the most thoroughgoing metanormative skepticism. This, I think, is as it should be: At least since Descartes’ realist skepticism about the external world and Berkeley’s idealist (and, we would say, antirealist) reply to this skepticism, skeptical positions have been motivated by realist intuitions (and antirealist retorts have been motivated by anti-skeptical convictions). It would thus be a mistake to use the term “realism” so as to make realism incompatible with skepticism. Arguing for Robust Realism and defeating the normative skeptic8 are thus two different, though 7 For a similar point, see Sayre-McCord (1988a, 278). The sentence in the text may seem false because of different understandings of the terms “normative skeptic” or “moral skeptic”. Such terms are sometimes used to depict relativists, subjectivists, error theorists, amoralists, and perhaps others as well. I use it in the text in the more precise epistemological sense: A normative skeptic is someone who questions our entitlement to claim the status of knowledge or justification or warrant (or any other privileged epistemological 8 10 related, tasks: Different, because Robust Realism is compatible with skepticism; related, because if the apparatus needed for a rejection of normative skepticism is unavailable to the Robust Realist, and if normative skepticism is highly implausible, this may count as a reason to reject Robust Realism after all. For now, then, let me note the compatibility of Robust Realism and skepticism, and postpone discussion of the epistemological problems to which Robust Realism may give rise to another occasion. I’ve been characterizing Robust Realism in terms of propositions, properties, facts, truths and the like. But these too are not, of course, beyond metaphysical controversy. Some people do not believe in facts, some do, but not in propositions, yet others don’t believe in properties. At the end of the day, there may be interesting relations between a metanormative view and a view of, say, the metaphysics of properties. But I think it best not to build such relations into the very characterization of Robust Realism. I want to remain neutral, then, on such metaphysical issues. Let me say, then, that according to Robust Realism, and general doubts about properties aside9, there are irreducibly normative properties; similarly, general doubts about facts aside, there are irreducibly normative facts; and so on. It seems to me I can afford this metaphysical nonchalance: For even a nominalist about, say, facts, must account for our everyday use of fact-talk; by status) for our normative beliefs. Brink (1989, 155) also notes that realism is compatible with skepticism (thus understood). 9 I thank Cian Dorr for introducing me to such connectives. Brink (1989, 16, footnote 1) has a similar disclaimer about facts. 11 doing that, she will have already accounted for our talk of normative facts. And this nonchalance will allow me to speak rather loosely – sometimes about normative facts, sometimes about normative truths, and so on. The crucial point is that, in whatever sense there are physical facts, there are normative ones; in whatever sense there are truths in biology, there are in normative discourse; in whatever sense in which there are mathematical properties, there are normative ones; and so on. When, in following chapters, I talk about ontological commitment to facts and properties, this talk should be understood as subject to the metaphysical nonchalance explained here: If you’d rather avoid such entities, feel free to substitute “a commitment to a kind of truths” (or whatever) for “ontological commitment”. It is not as clear, however, whether I can afford a different metaphysical nonchalance – one specifically about the status of normative facts and properties, of reasons, values, duties, rights, and the like. Are these, according to Robust Realism, entities in any interesting sense of this word? Are they, as is sometimes said, part of the fabric of the universe? Is Robust Realism, in other words, ontologically heavy? This question merits serious – and rather long – discussion for a number of reasons, two of which being the prominence of a somewhat surprising – and often unsupported – negative answer among contemporary realists (whose views are 12 close in spirit to Robust Realism)10, and the feeling that it’s not entirely clear what exactly the question comes to. I present a preliminary discussion of this question in the Conclusion of this essay, and I hope to discuss it in more detail on another occasion. Let me settle here for the following point: A heavy ontology is not, I stipulate, a part of what I mean by “Robust Realism”. The possibility remains, of course, that a commitment to Robust Realism is already a commitment to a heavy ontology, but this would be a result that has to be argued for. Before concluding this section, let me note that the characterization of Robust Realism given here is importantly incomplete. One can find in the literature, for instance, several criteria for drawing the realist-antirealist line11, and I haven’t even mentioned them so far. And some seem to think that no such line exists, at least not if understood as a meta-discourse line, rather than in terms of the very discourse meta-which it is supposed to be. I have said nothing to address worries associated with this view (often referred to as “quietism”). These are important issues, and I address them in this essay’s Conclusion. Postponing the discussion until that point will allow me to address these issues when already equipped with a better understanding of Robust Realism and the argument supporting it. This, I hope, will make the discussion easier. So much at this stage, then, for a characterization of Robust Realism. 10 See Nagel (1986, 139; 1997, 101); Dworkin (1996); Scanlon (1998, 2-3); and Parfit (forthcoming, chapter 6). 11 An important and influential example here is Wright (1992). 13 (iii) “Robust Realism” I take the term “Robust Realism” from Boghossian (1989, 547), who uses it in the context of a discussion of meaning-skepticism to refer to a position about meaning analogous to mine about normativity12. (Boghossian does not develop the view in detail, and so I do not know to what extent this analogy can be pursued). In this section I want to explain why I found it necessary to introduce (yet) another “ism” to the metanormative and metaethical literature. First, and uninterestingly, given the ambiguity and lack of clarity that accompanies many of the other possibly relevant “isms” – like objectivism, realism, absolutism and the like – I thought it a good idea to coin a term for which I am almost completely at liberty to stipulate a reasonably precise meaning. Second, I found all existing terms I could think of unsuitable for my purposes. “Realism”, as already mentioned, is dangerously ambiguous, serving at times also objectivist ethical naturalists, at times even relativists and subjectivists. “Non-reductive Realism” won’t do, because this term too has been appropriated by some metaphysical and ethical naturalists who use the term “reduction” in a way that excludes the kind of (I would say) naturalist reduction they believe in. 13 “Nonnaturalist Realism” is problematic, first, because it is not clear what exactly it is I thank Sigrún Svavarsdóttir for the suggestion to use “Robust Realism” as a name for my view of normativity. 13 See, for instance, Sturgeon (1984, 58-9). Railton (1993, 317) mentions a neglected option in logical space – one according to which normative facts are sui generis, but they nevertheless “pull their weight” in scientific explanations. If such a view can be defended, it would be (as Railton notes) a (metaphysically, methodologically) naturalist position, though a non-reductive one. Seeing that this is not my view, this is yet another reason for me to avoid the term “non-reductive realism”. 12 14 for a realism to be naturalist, and second, because the logical relations between my view and naturalism (of whatever sort) should not, I think, be understood as a part of what the view is, but rather as a consequent of its nature. “Platonism” suggests two commitments I want my view – at least at the outset – to avoid: one regarding the historical connection to Plato’s relevant views, one regarding a heavy ontology. Similarly, “Rational Intuitionism” suggests a historical connection with the Rational Intuitionists in England of the 18th century, a historical commitment I want to avoid. More importantly, “Rational Intuitionism” suggests an epistemological characterization of the view. Perhaps – though I doubt it – Robust Realism is committed to some kind of an intuitionist epistemology. Even if this is so, though, this should not be read into the very characterization of the view. That Robust Realism is committed to such an epistemology is something that should be argued for.14 For these reasons, then, I thought it best to label my view “Robust Realism”, and stipulate a reasonably precise meaning for this term. (iv) The Argument “Rational Intuitionism” is possibly misleading for another reason: In the ethics literature, this term is sometimes used to name a first-order, normative, or perhaps a methodological, view, one often associated with the work of Ross on prima facie obligations. Very often (perhaps also in Ross’s work) this term is used alternately to name the first-order position, the metaethical one, and some combination of the two. This is how it is used, I think, in Sidgwick (1906, xviii) who implicitly notices the ambiguity when he says that, even rejecting intuitionism (as a general methodology) he found himself needing to accept it (as, I would say, a metaethical position) as underlying his utilitarianism. 14 15 Often when reading a philosophical text one gets the feeling that, though the author gives an argument for a position the truth of which she deeply cares about, the two – the reason for believing the view supposedly supplied by the argument, and the author’s reason for caring about the view’s being true – are largely independent of each other. Thus, often one gets the feeling that if the author’s argument fails, this will not shake her confidence in its conclusion; rather, she will just go on looking for another argument for the position the truth of which she – for largely independent reasons – cares about. There is, of course, nothing wrong with such arguments. Some of them are good arguments, some bad, and this – not the motivations of their authors – is what we (should) care about. Nevertheless, there is something to be said for the kind of transparency that results when an author presents her concerns in clear view, and develops an argument that is more directly sensitive to them. This is what I try to do in this essay. My argument for Robust Realism – the one shortly to be sketched and then to be developed in later chapters – presents not only a suggested reason to believe that Robust Realism is true, but also my reason to believe that it is true, and my reason to care about its truth, to hope that it is true. I have two concerns that make me want – indeed, need – Robust Realism to hold, and lead me to believe that it does. (This may sound disturbingly close to wishful thinking, but once suitably understood, I don’t think it is. A suitable understanding of this need – as giving rise to an indispensability argument – is shortly to emerge.) One of them – a broadly speaking political one, having to do 16 with the justification of coercion and the restriction of liberty – I will have to leave for another occasion. The other concerns what happens – and what seems to me to be the case – when I try to decide what it is that makes most sense for me to do, when, in other words, I deliberate. Often, of course, I act without deliberation – out of habit, for instance. But often I do deliberate, and when I do I assume, it seems to me, that the questions I ask myself have answers, answers I try to discover, not invent. But as at least some of the questions I ask myself when deliberating – including the one about what it makes most sense for me to do – are normative ones, if the questions I ask myself have answers, then there are normative truths. So normative truths, or perhaps belief in normative truths, are indispensable for deliberation. Furthermore, any other, non-Robust-Realist, view of these truths seems to me to undermine their role in deliberation. This, I think, is at least some reason to want Robust Realism to hold. But, with some further assumptions, it is also a reason to believe that it does hold, for indispensability should sometimes be taken – and often is taken – to justify belief. This is the case, perhaps most clearly, with indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics, arguments that proceed from the (purported) indispensability to science of quantifying over numbers and other mathematical objects to (some version of) Mathematical Platonism. This is also the case in all instances of Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE), which proceed, if I understand them correctly, from the explanatory indispensability of something being the case to a belief in it being the case. And just as in these cases 17 explanatory indispensability suffices to justify belief, so too, I argue, indispensability to deliberation – deliberative indispensability – suffices to justify belief. Presenting an argument from deliberative indispensability to Robust Realism, I thus put forward an argument for my view that is directly sensitive to my reason for caring about the view’s truth. It is very common to find in the metaethical literature expressions of the idea that realism of a rather robust sort is the metaethical view that is most loyal to the phenomenology of moral thought and discourse. A similar point surely applies to the loyalty of metanormative realism to the phenomenology of normative thought and discourse more generally. And in a way, my argument is a development of this common thought, for it relies – in establishing the claim of deliberative indispensability – on the phenomenology of deliberation. But my argument does not amount merely to a statement of confidence in what this phenomenology seems to imply. It uses the phenomenology as a part of an indispensability argument for Robust Realism. Even if you find traditional realist appeals to phenomenology unsatisfying, my argument can thus still convince you, and I think it should. My argument can be seen as a development of another common thread in the thought of realists (not even just about ethics or normativity): It is that the very engagement in the relevant first-order discourse already commits you to a realist second-order view of that discourse. According to my argument, engaging in a privileged part of normative discourse – the first-personal part of trying to decide 18 what it makes best sense for you to do – already commits you, via an indispensability argument, to Robust Realism about normativity. Again, though, the route to this commitment according to my argument is not as direct as some may have thought, as it proceeds via an indispensability argument. I do not argue that, accepting (as I’m sure you do) that you have reason to avoid your own future pain, you’ve already committed yourself to Robust Realism, or that the proposition I have reason to avoid my pain entails Robust Realism. Rather, I argue that by engaging in the activity of deliberation you commit yourself to Robust Realism15. I discuss the notion of commitment here involved in Chapter III, in section 3.2. The canonical version of my argument for Robust Realism – the archargument of this essay – thus runs as follows: Irreducibly normative truths are deliberatively indispensable; therefore, there are irreducibly normative truths. Of course, in this argument both the single premise and the move from it to the conclusion need support, and I try to give this support in the rest of this essay. Before outlining, though, how (and where) I do that, let me quickly note another – very close – argument, one that for most purposes is equivalent to mine. This other argument has two premises: Irreducibly normative truths are deliberatively indispensable; if something is deliberatively indispensable, (we are justified in believing that) it exists; therefore, (we are justified in believing that) there are In this respect, my indispensability argument is closely analogous to Resnik’s (1995, 171) pragmatic version of the indispensability argument in the philosophy of mathematics, because – as he emphasizes – this version of an indispensability argument does not depend on the truth of the relevant scientific theory, but, it seems, on the very engagement in the scientific project. See also the discussion in Colyvan (2001, 13-16). 15 19 irreducibly normative truths. Though, as mentioned, this argument is for most purposes equivalent to mine, it is not equivalent to mine for all purposes. For reasons that are hinted at in Chapter II – reasons that have to do with the priority of basic belief-forming methods over basic beliefs – I think there is something more basic about the canonical version of my argument. We are only justified in believing the second argument’s second premise or a suitably modified version thereof – if indeed we are – because, I think, we are justified in following a rule of inference that licenses arguments from deliberative indispensability. And if this is so, we can infer directly from the first premise to the conclusion. The canonical version of my argument makes this fact more clearly visible. It may be helpful to give here a brief overview of the chapters of this essay. In chapter 1 I develop the theme of the analogy between explanatory and deliberative indispensability, indicating on the way the false – and completely arbitrary – assumption underlying what is commonly thought of as a serious challenge realists face. This is the challenge according to which moral (and other normative) facts play no appropriate role in the best explanation of anything worth explaining, and so we have no reason to believe they exist. In chapter 1 I also present an account of indispensability, one that is employed in later chapters in developing my indispensability argument for Robust Realism. If all goes well, by the end of chapter 1 you should be convinced that it is at least prima facie arbitrary to take explanatory indispensability seriously but refuse to take (at least some) other kinds of indispensability seriously. But at this 20 point you are at liberty to reject all indispensability arguments, explanatory ones included. You are at liberty, in other words, to reject IBE and scientific and mathematical realism with it. Chapter 2 is an attempt to convince you that this too is not a promising move. Chapter 2 thus puts forward a perfectly general epistemological argument, one that is not restricted to metaethics or metanormativity. If you are not interested in such general epistemological concerns, or if you are but are also very confident that at least explanatory indispensability should be taken seriously, you may want to skip chapter 2. Given the central place of deliberation in my argument for Robust Realism, I found it necessary to discuss deliberation in some detail. I do that in chapter 3. In this chapter I argue that deliberation satisfies the conditions necessary for deliberative indispensability to justify ontological commitment, thus completing the justification – the first part of which presented in chapter 2 – of the move from the indispensability premise to Robust Realism. Also in this chapter, I begin to defend the indispensability premise itself, by arguing that normative truths or something very close to them are indispensable for deliberation. If some other – non-Robust-Realist – view of normativity can allow for deliberation, the indispensability premise is false. This is why it is necessary – in order to support the indispensability premise – to reject alternative metanormative views. This is the task of chapter 4. By the end of chapter 4, my positive argument for Robust Realism has been fully developed. But if the defense of Robust Realism is to be complete, one 21 further task remains. Traditional objections to similar metaethical and metanormative views must be dealt with. Regrettably, I must postpone discussion of these objections for another occasion. Realists are sometimes accused of writing mostly negatively – having little to say about their realism, the normative truths they are realists about, and their reasons for being realists, they engage primarily in rejecting objections to their views, and in criticizing alternative views.16 And some realists warmly endorse this characterization of their philosophizing.17 Some of this negativity remains in my own argument as well – this is clearest in chapter 4. But, as I hope is by now clear, my argument is a positive argument for Robust Realism, one that – if sound – gives you strong reason to believe that Robust Realism is true. These negative parts thus play a role in what is on the whole a positive argument for Robust Realism. And so I hope this negativity-charge – whatever its merits in other cases – fails to apply to my argument. Another matter I have to postpone for another occasion has to do with the historical influences on my argument for Robust Realism, and in particular a discussion of Kant’s views and the relations between them and Robust Realism and my argument for it. Though in this essay I do not discuss historical texts, and though Robust Realism and my argument for it are inspired by historical 16 17 See Korsgaard (1996, 31) (referring to Clarke and Price). See Nagel (1986, 143-4); Parfit (fothcoming, chapter 5). And see also Sidgwick (1906, 25). 22 philosophical figures other than Kant as well18, a number of reasons lead me to believe that a discussion of Kant is especially relevant. Let me just briefly note them here. First, I first came to think of the general line of my argument by reading Kant (and on Kant). Second, and more importantly, much in my argument still follows – or is at least inspired by – Kant. This is especially clear, I think, in my view of deliberation and of us as essentially deliberative creatures (in chapter 3), in the rather strongly anti-Humean philosophy of action implied by these views, and in the argument of chapter 2, which is inspired by Kant’s arguments for the postulates of practical reason. Third, it might be interesting to discuss Kant in some detail because, despite such important affinities between my views and his, still he rejects Robust Realism, or so at least it seems. Indeed, the idea of normative truths the existence of which – and, as is sometimes said, the normative power of which, their being binding on our will – does not depend in anyway on our will seems to be in direct conflict with the idea of Kantian autonomy, undoubtedly so central to Kant’s practical (and perhaps also theoretical) philosophy. This conflict – a very Kantian argument, an apparently anti-Kantian conclusion – calls, I think, for an elaborate discussion of the relations between my views and Kant’s. As the soundness of the main argument of this essay is Perhaps especially worth mentioning here are the Rational Intuitionists of the 18 th century – people like Clarke, Price, and to an extent Reid – whose views Robust Realism resembles in important ways. But there are somewhat more surprising inspirations as well. Pufendorf, for instance, a voluntarist and a Natural Law theorist – certainly no 17th-century Robust Realist – emphasized that his moral entities had no causal-explanatory role, but were needed only for their justificatory work. He thus seems to anticipate a major part of my argument for Robust Realism, the part I call in chapter 1 the second strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge. See Schneewind (1998, chapters 7, 15, and 18). 18 23 independent of this discussion, though, and because of considerations of space and time, I do not engage in this discussion here, and I hope to do it elsewhere. As I said at the outset, Robust Metanormative Realism takes normativity seriously. Indeed, it is taking normativity seriously that leads me to believe that Robust Realism is true. If the argumentation in this essay is sound, it should lead you to a similar conclusion. 24 Chapter I The Indispensability of Irreducibly Normative Truths1 In this chapter I lay down the framework of my argument for Robust Realism – an argument from deliberative indispensability. The argument has one premise: Irreducibly normative truths are deliberatively indispensable. The argument then concludes that there are irreducibly normative truths. Of course, both the premise and the transition from it to the conclusion need defense. In this chapter I do not defend the premise. Nor do I offer here a complete defense of the transition from the deliberative indispensability of irreducibly normative truths to belief in their existence. Here, rather, I partially defend a weaker claim. I argue that this transition is justified if another kind of transition – the one underlying familiar and relatively uncontroversial arguments from explanatory indispensability – is justified. The opponent of Robust Realism is thus faced at the end of this chapter with a choice of either conceding the legitimacy of the transition from the (still to 1 For comments on previous drafts and helpful discussions, I am grateful to Stephanie Beardman, Hagit Benbaji, Thérèse Björkholm, Hartry Field, Ernesto Garcia, Pete Graham, Peter Kung, Tom Nagel, Derek Parfit, Josh Schechter, and Mark Schroeder. Versions of this chapter were presented at the Distinguished Graduate Student series at NYU, the colloquium series at the Hebrew University in Jerusalem Philosophy Department, and a graduate student conference at Columbia University. I thank the participants for the helpful discussions. 25 be argued for) deliberative indispensability of irreducibly normative truths to Robust Realism, or denying the legitimacy of other intuitively rather compelling arguments. It will be convenient to start the discussion with a familiar challenge to Robust Realism (and to other forms of realism; I get back to this point below): This is the claim, roughly, that normative facts have no role to play in the explanation of anything worth explaining, and that we therefore have no reason to believe they exist. The discussion of this challenge – the one I’ll label “Harman’s Challenge” – will be primarily instrumental. My main concern here is not in coping with it, but rather in using it in order to introduce my argument for Robust Realism. I present Harman’s Challenge and trim it better to fit my purposes in discussing it in section 1.1. In section 1.2, I distinguish two broad strategies of coping with Harman’s Challenge, and then proceed tentatively to reject one. The rest of the chapter – and, indeed, the thesis – is an elaboration of the second strategy, which insists on rejecting the explanatory requirement underlying Harman’s Challenge. The second strategy may give rise to an immediate worry regarding ontological profligacy. In sections 1.3 and 1.4 I show how profligacy can be avoided consistently with employment of the second strategy. After briefly discussing the relation between my way of arguing for Robust Realism and Metaphysical Naturalism in section 1.5, I then proceed to offer an account of indispensability in section 1.6. Such an account is needed if it is to be determined 26 whether irreducibly normative truths are indispensable for our deliberative project, and whether, if they are, that suffices to justify belief in them. In section 1.7 I pick up a point made in section 1.4, arguing that deliberative indispensability is at least as respectable as explanatory indispensability, and that, consequently, the former can justify ontological commitment if the latter can. Then, in section 1.8, I briefly revisit the possible explanatory role of normative truths, considering ways in which the success of the second strategy may bear on the plausibility of normative truths playing such a role. In the concluding section (1.9) I do some score-keeping: I clarify what I take to have been established in this chapter, and what remains to be done if the defense of my argument for Robust Realism is to be completed. 1.1 Harman’s Challenge Seeing a vapor trail in a cloud chamber, a physicist thinks to herself: “There goes a proton”. That she makes the observation that she does is at least some evidence for there having been a proton in the cloud chamber, Harman argues plausibly, because the best explanation of her observation involves the fact that there really was a proton in the cloud chamber at the relevant time. If the physicist’s observation is best explained by an alternative explanation, one that does not involve the proton in an appropriate way, her observation gives no reason to believe that there was a proton in the cloud chamber. Seeing a few children set a cat on fire you think to yourself “That’s wrong”. How is the fact that you immediately make this judgment best explained? 27 Harman argues that it is best explained by psychological, sociological, historical, cultural and other such facts about you. Whether or not what the children are doing really is wrong is not at all relevant, Harman says, for the best explanation of your immediate moral judgment. Seeing that the relevant observation or judgment is best explained without assuming the existence of the relevant purported moral fact, Harman concludes, we have no reason to believe there are such moral facts. Realism refuted2. What is the argument Harman puts forward? I think it is this: 1. 2. 3. The no-explanatory-role thesis: Moral facts do not play an appropriate role in the best explanation of moral observations or judgments. The explanatory requirement: We have reason to believe that facts of a certain kind exist only if facts of that kind play an appropriate role in the best explanation of the relevant kind of observations and judgments. Therefore, we have no reason to believe (and are unjustified in believing) that there are any moral facts. For my purposes, it will be necessary to refine and generalize this argument in several ways3. The first way in which Harman’s Challenge should be generalized in order to fit the purposes of my discussion of it stems from the details of the thesis I want 2 For his original statement of the problem, see Harman (1977, chapter 1). Harman does not claim originality for the general problem his text tries to capture. 3 As mentioned, my primary interest is not in coping with Harman’s Challenge, and certainly not in Harman-exegesis. What follows is my way of making Harman’s Challenge more precise and more suitable for my purposes, and I have no opinion regarding Harman’s exact views about what follows. I use the term “Harman’s Challenge” merely as a convenient label. 28 to defend. I want to defend Robust Realism about normativity, not necessarily about ethics or morality. It is compatible with my Robust Realism, then, that there be no moral or ethical facts, so long as there are other, non-moral, irreducibly normative truths. If Harman’s Challenge is to pose even a prima facie threat for my Robust Realism, then, it must be modified so as to entail the conclusion that we have no reason to believe in any normative facts4. Second, it must be asked what the relevant explananda ought to be, such that failure to explain them is declared as sufficient for the conclusion of the argument. Which possible explananda, in other words, count in shouldering the burden of the explanatory requirement? Harman seems preoccupied with observation. But if some of our normative beliefs do not qualify as observational, but are nevertheless best explained by invoking normative facts, it seems in accordance with the spirit of Harman’s explanatory requirement to conclude that we do have reason to believe in normative facts. Furthermore, if something else – not a belief – is best explained by invoking moral facts, that too would suffice, I think, to give reason to believe in moral facts5. It has been suggested, for instance, that the best explanation of some desires may invoke moral (and so, normative) 4 A generalization along these lines has been suggested by Sayre-McCord (1988a, 278; 1992, 70, footnote 21). It is also clear that normativity – and not just morality – is at stake in Nagel’s (1986, chapter 8) and Dworkin’s (1996) relevant discussions. 5 Interestingly, Wright (1992, 197-8) argues, in a slightly different context, that in order to settle the realism-antirealism debate in favor of realism the explanatory requirement must be satisfied with things other than beliefs or observations as explananda. I need not discuss the details of this suggestion here. 29 facts6, and that the best explanation of some social changes may invoke moral (and so, normative) facts directly, not via any of the involved persons’ moral beliefs 7. I do not here want to commit myself to these suggestions; what is important here is that if there is any truth to them, that would suffice to satisfy the explanatory requirement that underlies Harman’s Challenge (or the intuition it is meant to capture)8. It seems, then, that Harman’s Challenge is better understood as stating that normative facts do not play a role in the best explanation of anything worth explaining, and that we therefore have no reason to believe there are such facts9. This too needs to be qualified. Purported normative facts undoubtedly do have a role to play in the best explanation of some other (purported) normative facts: The best explanation – in some sense of “explanation”, at least – of the fact that setting the cat on fire was wrong is, roughly, that it caused tremendous pain for no (good) reason, and that causing tremendous pain for no reason is wrong; clearly, a normative explanation. But that doesn’t seem to give reason to believe in normative facts. Some purported facts about, say, witches, presumably have a role to play in the best explanation of some other purported facts about witches, but that doesn’t give reason to believe that there are witches. So it seems the argument should be understood, still somewhat roughly, as follows: Purported normative 6 See Lycan (1986, 89). See Railton (1986a, 192); Brink (1989, 188-9); Sayre-McCord (1992). 8 I am not here implying that that would suffice to vindicate Robust Realism. I mention some relevant doubts in section 1.2, below. 9 That such a generalization of the no-explanatory-role thesis is better in line with the naturalist leanings underlying Harman’s Challenge has been widely acknowledged in the literature. See, for instance, Sturgeon (1984, 54-5) and Brink (1989, 186-7). 7 30 facts have no role to play in the best explanation of any non-normative facts, and we therefore have no reason to believe they exist10. Interestingly, though, it is not easy to make the argument thus modified explicit and precise. If, as seems appropriate, the modified first premise reads: 1*. Normative facts do not play an appropriate role in the best explanation of any non-normative facts. then how is the second premise best modified? One suggestion is as follows: 2*. We have reason to believe that facts of a certain kind exist only if facts of that kind play an appropriate role in the best explanation of some non-normative facts. But there is something strongly ad hoc about 2*. In an argument that is supposed to show that normative facts are not as respectable as non-normative ones, assuming from the start that explanatory work only counts if the explanandum is non-normative comes dangerously close to begging the question11. On the other hand, 2**. We have reason to believe that facts of a certain kind exist only if facts of that kind play an appropriate role in the best explanation of facts of some other kind. seems both too weak and too strong: Too weak, because it would vindicate both normative facts and witch-facts if they explained each other; too strong, because if Brink (1989, 182-3) makes a similar point in discussing Harman’s Challenge. Brink (1989, 182-3) notices this point. Nagel (1986, 146) seems to suggest that normative facts explain other normative facts, and that that is enough to confer respectability on them. But Nagel’s view is more complex than that, and I briefly discuss it in the appendix. 10 11 31 natural facts are the only facts there are, natural facts could not explain facts of some other kind, and so on 2** we would have no reason to believe in them.12 2*** seems initially promising: 2***.We have reason to believe that facts of a certain kind exist only if facts of that kind play an appropriate role in the best explanation of facts of some privileged kind. But 2*** gains whatever plausibility it has by not saying anything regarding what kind of fact is privileged. It is hard to see how that can be done without resorting to question-begging again13. And even further difficulties await the supporter of 2*** (as well as the supporter of 2**) when she tries to give an account – one she very much needs – of the individuation of kinds of fact. The proponent of Harman’s Challenge thus faces the following task: Find a way of restricting the set of respectable explananda such that, first, the restriction is not ad hoc or question begging, and second, the restriction excludes any facts that normative facts plausibly help in explaining. It is not clear to me how this task can be successfully performed. A further problem with stating the argument is that, once generalized to all normative facts, and given the first premise, the second premise, however exactly it is put, is potentially self-defeating14. For notice that the explanatory requirement 12 In other words, if you accept 2** you had better not be a Metaphysical Naturalist; for, assuming 2**, it follows from the respectability of natural facts that not all facts are natural. I thank Hagit Benbaji for this way of putting things. 13 This problem may be exemplified by Harman himself, when – on rather extreme empiricist grounds, it would seem – he takes the privileged kind of fact to be our observations. 14 Simon (1990, 113 (footnote 27)), Putnam (1995, 71) and McGinn (1997, 13-4) notice this point. 32 does not put forward an explanatory criterion of existence: Had it done that, it would have been obviously indefensible, as surely there can be facts and entities of a kind that plays no role in explaining anything worth explaining. Rather, the explanatory requirement is a distinctly normative one, it puts forward an explanatory criterion for what we have reason to believe or are justified in believing15. But then, if there are no normative facts, it seems that the explanatoryrequirement-premise cannot itself be true. Now, perhaps this problem can be avoided in some way16. All I want to note here is that it must be avoided somehow if a coherent challenge is to be presented at all. To be made fully precise and explicit, the explanatory requirement needs even further work. What kind of role must normative facts play in the best explanation of some respectable explanandum if normative facts are to be vindicated? What, in other words, does it take for an explanatory role to be appropriate? Must normative facts be strictly ineliminable in that explanation, or would some other, weaker, explanatory role suffice? Would pragmatic indispensability (as when alternative explanations are too lengthy or cumbersome) Claims about what kinds of facts there are are plausibly classified as metaphysical. Do metaphysical (and, for that matter, other philosophical) facts play an appropriate role in the best explanation of any respectable explanandum (say, observations)? If not, then, as Quinn (1986, 539) argues, the proponent of the explanatory requirement is haunted by a self-defeat problem closely analogous to the one that haunted verificationists. 15 The following quote from a later text makes this especially clear: “So our moral beliefs do not provide us with evidence for such an independent realm of values and obligations, and we must choose between skepticism, noncognitivism, and relativism.” (Harman, 1984, 32-3) 16 As I am about to argue, a naturalist reduction of normative facts may be all that is required in order to cope with (one version of) Harman’s Challenge. If this is so, then one possible way of avoiding the self-defeat problem would be to argue for a naturalist reduction of the normative judgment incorporated in the explanatory requirement. 33 suffice, or must it be an in-principle-indispensability17? Does only an appropriate role in the best explanation suffice for the vindication of normative facts, or is, as Wright (1992, 197) suggests, an appropriate role in a good enough explanation sufficient too? As already mentioned, my main concern here is not Harman’s Challenge per se. I will therefore avoid further refinements of the argument and leave the problems mentioned unsolved. Despite them it is clear, I think, that the worry Harman’s Challenge attempts to explicate is a serious one. To see that, consider an analogy Harman (1984, 44-7) mentions: It seems clear that if we need invoke no God-related facts in explaining anything – if, for instance, there are no miracles, the argument from design fails, and the best explanation of purported revelation is in terms of only the psychology of the person God purportedly reveals herself to – surely that should count against belief in God. Indeed, isn’t this at least partly why those of us who are atheists are atheists? Harman’s Challenge calls upon the realist to distinguish between normative facts and such purported God-facts18. Despite the problems with an exact statement of Harman’s Challenge, then, the worry that underlies it is genuine. For my purposes, an intuitive, less than fully precise and explicit, statement of the challenge will suffice (this is especially true of the exact details of the explanatory requirement, seeing that I am about to reject it, whatever its precise details). Let me settle, then, for the following way of stating I get back to this distinction, and to Field’s and Brink’s ways of putting it, later in the text. Harman’s second example in this context is that of facts about the mind. But I find this example very problematic, for reasons that I return to in footnote 35, below. 17 18 34 it: Normative facts do not play an appropriate role in the explanation of any respectable explanandum. What reason do we have, then, to believe that they exist? It is important not to conflate this challenge with another – distinct but related – one19. Moral and more generally normative propositions seem to quantify over entities like values and reasons. These are supposedly abstract, causally inefficacious entities, so we cannot causally interact with them. But then, how can we come to know anything about them? How can we even refer to them? This is an important challenge the realist must face. But this is a different challenge from the one under discussion here. The question at hand is whether we have any reason to believe that normative facts exist, not how – or even whether – we can know anything more about them20. This difference has not always been noticed in the literature21. Indeed, it is at times not clear whether Harman himself puts forward one challenge or the other: recently (1998, 207-8) he has written that he had 19 Parfit distinguishes between the two challenges in his Rediscovering Reasons (forthcoming), chapter 6. 20 There is a way of reading Harman’s Challenge as more closely related to this other worry: If the best explanation of my normative beliefs is not in terms of their truth but rather (say) my upbringing, then plausibly even had the normative facts been different, (so long as my upbringing stayed reasonably similar) I would still have the normative beliefs I actually have. So my normative beliefs do not counterfactually track the truth. And this, it may be thought, is sufficient to rule them out as possible candidates for knowledge. Needless to say, this argument assumes a controversial thesis about the nature of knowledge. Furthermore, it relies on evaluations of highly problematic counterfactuals (in some cases, counterfactuals with necessarily false antecedents). Be that as it may, it is worth further discussion, one that I have to postpone for another occasion. 21 Thomson (in Harman and Thomson, 1996, 74-78), for instance, seems to conflate the two challenges. 35 always only been interested in the second challenge22, so what I dub “Harman’s Challenge” may never have been truly Harman’s (not that it matters for my purposes). Of course, the two challenges are not unrelated, and more needs to be said on behalf of the realist regarding the second one as well. But the two challenges are clearly distinct23, and I will not discuss the second one further in this chapter. Harman’s Challenge is usually presented as a challenge to metaethical – or, more generally, metanormative – realism. But it is important to note that it puts forward two different challenges, depending on the relevant kind of realism. For a robust realist such as myself, the challenge seems simple: Given that irreducibly normative facts don’t play an appropriate role in the explanation of any respectable explanandum, what reason do we have to believe they exist? But this challenge is one naturalist realists can easily cope with. For they think that moral and other normative facts are reducible to, or at least identical with, or at least constituted by, natural facts. Now these natural facts are presumably vindicated by the explanatory role they play. And this, in turn, seems to confer respectability – by reduction, identity, constitution, or even just entailment – on the normative facts themselves. As Quinn (1986, 526-7) makes clear, the explanatory requirement, if it is to be at all plausible, has to be modified so as to accommodate such 22 Harman says that in replying to Railton (1998, 177) and Sturgeon (1998, 199) who (think they) diagnose a shift in Harman’s presentation of the problem over the years, from what I call Harman’s Challenge to the epistemological problem discussed in the text in this paragraph. 23 For this point made in the philosophy-of-mathematics context, see Field (1989, 26). 36 respectability-by-entailment24. And, with the explanatory requirement suitably modified, naturalist realists should have no problem coping with the challenge Robust Realists face25. It seems to me, then, that the more serious challenge facing naturalist realists here is very different: If normative facts just are (or are constituted by) natural facts, why don’t they participate in the best explanation of any respectable explanandum? If this (on naturalist assumptions, surprising) fact cannot be satisfactorily explained, there doesn’t seem to be reason to buy into the claim that some natural facts are identical with normative ones; it may then seem preferable to opt for an anti-realist metanormative view. It is this challenge that the massive literature written by naturalist realists discussing Harman’s Challenge addresses (implicitly, at times)26. This is why such realists reject the noexplanatory-role premise, and don’t settle for relying on the (perfectly sound) respectability-by-reduction (or by entailment) line. Be that as it may, the challenge Robust Realism faces is clear enough. How can it be coped with? 1.2 Coping With Harman’s Challenge: Two Strategies 24 For a similar point, see McDowell (1985, 118). This point has been widely acknowledged (see, e.g., Quinn (1986); Brink (1989, 193)), but only Brink (1989, 191), as far as I know, gestures at the suggestion that Harman’s Challenge is really not even prima-facie threatening for the naturalist realist. 26 For a similar point, see Sencerz (1995, 375). 25 37 Broadly speaking, two realist strategies suggest themselves27. The realist can, first, reject the no-explanatory-role premise. This can be done by coming up with examples of uncontroversially respectable explananda and arguing that normative facts have an appropriate role to play in their explanation, or by coming up with an example of a contested explanandum, arguing that it is respectable and that normative facts have an appropriate role to play in its explanation. Either way of pursuing the first strategy will typically involve – and has typically involved – the proponent of the first strategy in more general epistemological discussions about what an explanation is and what makes one explanation better than another. Or, and this would be the second strategy, the realist can concede, at least for the sake of argument, the no-explanatory-role premise, but argue that we nevertheless have reason to believe in normative facts. Doing so will involve rejecting the explanatory requirement, the claim that we are justified in believing that facts of a certain kind exist only if they play an appropriate role in the best explanation of some other, undisputedly respectable, facts. The former strategy – arguing that normative, and in particular moral, facts do explain respectable explananda – has been far more common in the literature28. Indeed, except for mostly unsystematic and very brief comments (discussed in the 27 Zimmerman (1984, 81-2) and Leiter (2001a, 88) draw a similar distinction between two strategies of coping with Harman’s Challenge. 28 And an extensive literature it is. For some of it, see: Audi (1997, chapter 5); Blackburn (1991a; 1991b); Brink (1989, 182-197); Copp (1990); Harman (1977; 1984; 1986; 1998); Harman and Thomson (chapters 6, 9 and 10); Leiter (2001a); Lycan (1986); McDowell (1985, 117-120); Moore (1992); Quinn (1986); Railton (1998); Sayre-McCord (1988a; 1992); Sturgeon (1984; 1986a; 1991; 1992; 1998); Wiggins (1990); Wright (1992, chapter 5); Yasenchuk (1994); Zimmerman (1984). 38 appendix), the second strategy has been completely neglected. Now, I will be pursuing the second strategy and so my defense of Robust Realism will depend neither on the first strategy’s success nor on its failure. Fortunately, then, there is no need here to discuss it in detail. Nevertheless, in order better to motivate the second strategy, it may be useful briefly to survey my reasons for not following the first. These are, first, that I doubt whether normative facts do play an appropriate role in the best explanation of relevantly respectable explananda; second, that even if they do, that would not suffice as a defense of Robust Realism; and third, that even if they don’t, that doesn’t seem to compromise their respectability in any way. Let me elaborate on each of these reasons in turn. Examples can easily be found where we cite what seem to be normative facts in explanations. We may cite, for instance, Hitler’s moral depravity in explaining his behavior, or a society’s injustice in explaining its instability29. One tempting way of rejecting such explanations as not genuinely normative is by arguing that such ways of speaking are elliptical for other, non-normative, explanations, explanations in terms of normative beliefs or of (other) nonnormative facts the relevant normative facts supervene on30. Nevertheless, as has 29 The examples are both taken from Sturgeon (1984). As the discussion of the first strategy has focused on moral, and not more generally normative, realism, the examples I discuss are all moral. But examples of non-moral normative facts serving a purportedly explanatory role are just as easy to come up with. 30 See, for instance, Blackburn (1991a, 13), Wright (1992, 195) and Thomson (in Harman and Thomson, 1996, 69-94). A related way of thinking of normative explanations as less than fully genuinely normative (one for which I am indebted to Josh Schechter), is to argue that the language that contains such normative explanations is a conservative extension of the language without them, in the sense developed, for instance, by Field (1980) in the context of the philosophy of 39 been widely noticed31, unless we are willing to discard all special-sciencesexplanations, we must find a way of acknowledging explanations in terms of supervenient facts and properties as genuine, and so if purportedly normative explanations are to be ruled out there must be a principled way of distinguishing between them and other explanations in terms of supervening facts and properties. The following may be a way of doing just that: As has been argued by Quinn (1986), Sayre-McCord (1988a) and Copp (1990), purportedly moral explanations seem to leave the normative force of morality out32. As Blackburn (1991a, 13) writes: “I can assent to the [purportedly moral] explanation without endorsing the verdict you pass on the feature.”33 This characteristic of purportedly moral explanations is not shared by, say, biological explanations, and it strongly suggests that purportedly moral, and more generally normative, explanations are best understood as elliptical for non-moral and non-normative ones. And there may be other reasons to suspect that it is not easy to reject the no-explanatory-role premise. Leiter (2001a, 94) points out, for instance, that no scientist (or, for that matter, anyone else) seems to be doing any serious explanatory work using distinctively moral (or normative) explanations. This fact mathematics. For my purposes, this suggestion can be treated as a variant of the one discussed in the text. 31 By, e.g., Sayre-McCord (1988a, 274-7); Brink (1989, 193-7); Sturgeon (1991, 27-30; 1998, throughout the paper); Railton (1998, 177-80). 32 See also the relevant discussion in Johnson (1998). 33 See also Gibbard (1992, 978). 40 seems to call for explanation, and at least one plausible explanation of it is that there simply are no normative explanations to be found34. Now, these considerations are certainly not conclusive, but what has been said is enough, I think, to cast serious doubt on the prospects of rejecting the noexplanatory-role thesis. Even if these problems with rejecting the no-explanatory-role thesis can be solved, that would not suffice for a defense of Robust Realism. For surely such explanations cannot give reason to believe in irreducibly normative truths. Biological facts appear, it seems, in explanations, and perhaps this gives some reason to believe in biological facts, but surely it gives no reason to believe in irreducibly biological facts (at least not with reduction liberally enough understood. I characterize reduction in section 4.4, in chapter 4). For my purposes – defending Robust Realism – the first strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge is, even if successful, simply not powerful enough. This is no criticism of this strategy, of course; it is merely an explanation of why I won’t be pursuing it. Most importantly perhaps, even if the first strategy fails, this seems to me in no way to compromise the respectability of irreducibly normative facts. I have the strong intuition that even had we known without a doubt that no normative fact 34 This is by no means the only explanation. Perhaps, for instance, scientists do not do serious work with normative explanations simply because of some bias against normative facts. Still, I believe Leiter’s point is suggestive – I, for one, do not expect such scientific work to emerge after biases are removed. Do you? 41 played an appropriate role in the explanation of any respectable explanandum, we would still have had reason to believe in normative facts35. If I am right about this intuition, this suggests that some version of the second strategy must be successful. Let me put the first strategy to one side, then, and focus on the second. 1.3 Parsimony A worry immediately threatens: What underlies the explanatory requirement is, after all, a highly plausible methodological principle of parsimony: Kinds of entities should not be unnecessarily multiplied, redundancy should be avoided.36 And, it seems, without such a principle it is exceedingly hard – perhaps even impossible – to justify many of our negative existential beliefs. Taking this methodological principle as given, then, how can the explanatory requirement be consistently rejected? Assuming that (irreducibly) normative facts play no appropriate explanatory role, are they not redundant, and then isn’t belief in them unwarranted? This is why – as mentioned above in footnote 18 – I think Harman’s example of the mental is highly problematic. I have the strong intuition that even had we known with certainty that nothing mental is needed in order to explain any respectable explanandum, we would still have had sufficient reason to believe that we have – at least in our own case – beliefs, desires, pains, pleasures and so on. 36 As mentioned in the Introduction, I wish to avoid at this stage the topic of how ontologically “heavy” my Robust Realism has to be. Talk in this section and in the sections that follow about ontological profligacy, ontological parsimony, ontological commitment, kinds of entity, normative facts, and so on should be understood in this light way. If you do not like this ontological parlance here, feel free to put everything in terms of, say, “kinds of truths” instead of kinds of facts and entities. Nothing much will then have to be changed. Notice, for instance, that the appeal of the parsimony requirement survives such a paraphrase. 35 42 In order to allay this worry, it is necessary to distinguish two different requirements of parsimony. First, there is the most general requirement not to multiply ontological commitments without sufficient reason. This requirement places the burden of argument on the party arguing for a belief in the existence of certain disputed entities or facts. It states, roughly, that if we have no good reason to believe in the disputed entities (for instance), then we ought not to believe that they exist. Call this the minimal parsimony requirement. Often, though, more is packed into the methodological principle of parsimony than the minimal parsimony requirement. It is often assumed that the only way of satisfying the minimal parsimony requirement is by showing that the relevant kind of fact is explanatorily useful.37 With this assumption, the minimal parsimony requirement becomes the explanatory requirement. I want, then, to reject the explanatory requirement while adhering to the minimal parsimony requirement. And, as is by now clear, the way to do this is to reject the assumption that the minimal parsimony requirement can only be satisfied by explanatorily indispensable facts, truths, properties and entities38. In 37 In a somewhat different context (that of characterizing the realist-antirealist debate, not that of deciding it), Wright (1993, 73) notices this often-made assumption (explicitly referring to Harman), and expresses his doubts about it. 38 Slors (1998, 243) makes a similar point about the mental, when he writes: “But why shouldn’t mental regularities have some other function than a causal-explanatory one? It might just be possible that the mental justifies its place in our ontology by other means than its causal efficacy.” And here is Grice (1975, 31): “My taste is for keeping open house for all sorts and conditions of entities, just so long as when they come in they help with the house-work. Provided that I can see them at work, and provided that they are not detected in illicit logical behaviour … I do not find them queer or mysterious at all. To fangle a new ontological Marxism, they work therefore they exist, even though only some, perhaps those who come on the recommendation of some form of transcendental argument, may qualify for the specially flavoured status of entia realissima. To 43 other words, I suggest we restrict, in accordance with the minimal parsimony requirement, our ontological commitment to just those things that are indispensable. But I suggest that we consider other – non-explanatory – kinds of indispensability as satisfying this requirement. So the line I’m about to take does not have the unacceptable counterintuitive result of admitting these objectionable – and completely, not just explanatorily, redundant – things into one’s ontology. 1.4 Indispensabilities39 Why should we believe in, say, electrons? One common answer runs like this: There are many inferences to the best explanation the conclusion of which entails the existence of electrons; our best scientific theories quantify over electrons. We ought to believe that these theories are at least approximately true (they are, after all, our best theories, our best explanations of numerous phenomena), and so we ought to believe that electrons exist. If electrons play an appropriate role in the best explanation of respectable explananda – and it seems they do – we’re justified in believing that electrons exist. Of course, Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE, for short) is not uncontroversial, and much more will be said regarding it in what is exclude honest working entities seems to me like metaphysical snobbery, a reluctance to be seen in the company of any but the best objects.” Honest working entities are, of course, those that satisfy the most general parsimony requirement. And I would add only that explanatory work is not the only kind of work around the house that needs doing. 39 A terminological apology: My use of the word “indispensability” (and related words) is without a doubt a stretch of ordinary usage. Seeing, however, that my use of these terms is not completely discontinuous with ordinary usage, that I explicitly explain my way of using them, and that my way of using them echoes the way they are already used in the context of indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics, I hope this stretch is not too misleading. 44 to come (mostly in chapter 2). For now, though, let us assume that IBE suffices to justify ontological commitment. As I understand inferences to the best explanation, they are really particular instances of indispensability arguments40. (Whether this is so, and indeed whether this statement is not merely vacuous, will be determined by what exactly is meant by “indispensability”. I discuss just that in section 1.6.) Electrons are indispensable for our best explanations; so, by IBE, electrons exist. It is important to note here, that instances of IBE are arguments from explanatory indispensability. Electrons are indispensable for our explanatory project, and for this reason we are justified in believing they exist. As has already been argued, the availability of the second strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge depends on there being other, non-explanatory, kinds of indispensability that suffice to justify ontological commitment41. In section 1.7 I suggest one such other kind, deliberative indispensability. For the moment, though, I want to make the following preliminary point: Given some other purportedly respectable kind of indispensability, the proponent of the explanatory requirement (who is also a proponent of IBE) must find a non- 40 This relation between IBE and indispensability arguments has been noticed by Field (1989, 14) and Colyvan (2001, 7-8, especially footnote 17). Interestingly, Harman (1977, 10) mentions indispensability arguments for mathematical realism as support for his disanalogy between mathematical and ethical facts. If I am right in what follows, these arguments in fact supply the material for an important analogy between the two. 41 Field (1989, 14) and Collyvan (2001, 6) have noticed that there may be other kinds of indispensability that can ground prima facie respectable indispensability arguments. Resnik (1995; 1997, chapter 3) puts forward what seems to be an argument from a different (pragmatic) kind of indispensability, but his is still indispensability to the scientific project, broadly understood. 45 arbitrary way of distinguishing between explanatory and that other kind of indispensability. She must show, in other words, why it is that explanatory indispensability ought to be taken seriously, but other kinds of indispensability ought not to be so taken42 (or perhaps that there are no other kinds of indispensability; or perhaps that other kinds ought to be taken seriously but nothing is (or could be) indispensable in those ways; these three ways of shouldering the burden may be merely terminological variants, depending on what exactly is meant by “indispensability”). In other words, she must present a reason for taking explanatory indispensability as a sufficient reason for ontological commitment that does not generalize to other kinds of indispensability. Now, my way of justifying the move from indispensability to belief – presented preliminarily in section 1.7, and then in more detail in chapter 2 – will not be of that sort. It will apply to explanatory indispensability just in case it applies to other, non-explanatory, kinds of indispensability, and in particular to deliberative indispensability. This does not show, of course, that no rationale can be given for restricting respectable status to explanatory indispensability alone. So think of my point here as a challenge: Can you think of any reason for grounding ontological 42 Thus, I think Simon (1990, 105-6) accurately characterizes the dialectical situation when he writes: “What one would like from the anti-realist is an argument for using explanatory necessity as a criterion of reality which is more compelling than the absence of a better one. On the other hand, what one would like from the realist is, if not an alternative criterion, at least some indication of how one is to go about evaluating claims concerning the reality of different purported existents.” My argument in this chapter and the next can be seen as an attempt to give Simon what he wants from the realist. Later on, Simon writes (1990, 108): “And, one might ask, is not the necessity of saving morality as compelling as explanatory necessity? Perhaps it is a necessity which itself warrants multiplying entities.” It is not entirely clear to me what Simon has in mind, but he may very well be anticipating here my argument from deliberative indispensability. 46 commitment in explanatory indispensability that is not really more general, a reason for grounding ontological commitment in indispensabilities of other kinds as well? If there is no reason for taking explanatory indispensability seriously that is not a reason for taking some other kinds of indispensability seriously, then the move from the minimal parsimony requirement to the explanatory requirement is arbitrary and therefore unjustified43. If any other kind of indispensability can be defended, then, the second strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge becomes promising: All that is then left to do is to show that (irreducibly) normative truths are indispensable in this other, non-explanatory, way. I can, however, think of one possible way of distinguishing explanatory indispensability from other kinds of indispensability. In the literature on the philosophy of mathematics, it is often noted that indispensability arguments rest in part on the assumption of the metaphysical doctrine of Naturalism44. Now, it is notoriously difficult to state exactly what this doctrine comes to, but for my purposes the following familiar and vague way of putting things will suffice: According to Metaphysical Naturalism, science is the final arbiter of beliefs about the world; all inquiry is – or at least ought to be – (continuous with) scientific I suspect this is what McGinn has in mind when he accuses Harman’s explanatory requirement of being arbitrary and dogmatically empiricist (1997, 13; see also at 17, 36). For a similar point, see Putnam (1995, 70). 44 See, e.g., Resnik (1997), Colyvan (2001, chapter 1). 43 47 inquiry45. Assuming Naturalism, then, and further assuming that scientific inquiry is essentially explanatory46, there is a reason to consider explanatory indispensability unique in the relevant way: For if the explanatory project is the only final arbiter of beliefs about the world, then explanatory indispensability seems to be the only kind of indispensability that justifies ontological commitment. The problem with this way of defending the uniqueness of explanatory indispensability is that in the current context it is question-begging47. Robust Realism does not claim to be a naturalist metanormative position. Indeed, it is explicitly non-naturalist (though I reconsider this judgment in the next section). If Robust Realism is true Metaphysical Naturalism ought to be rejected. Obviously, then, if Naturalism can be taken as an assumption, Robust Realism ought to be rejected. That not only Robust Realism, but also my argument for it, can be rejected on naturalist assumptions is of very little interest. In the absence of some independent, non-question-begging argument for Metaphysical Naturalism (and so against Robust Realism), I conclude, Naturalism cannot be interestingly invoked 45 The view characterized in the text is sometimes referred to as Methodological Naturalism, to be distinguished from Metaphysical Naturalism, the view according to which (very roughly) all facts are natural facts. In the text I ignore this distinction – as will become evident later on, my Robust Realism is compatible with neither version of Naturalism. 46 If science has (necessarily) other purposes besides explanation, then – even assuming Naturalism – there may be other, non-explanatory, respectable kinds of indispensability. In that case, even Naturalism cannot bridge the gap between the minimal parsimony requirement and the explanatory requirement. 47 There may be other problems with it too. As Rosen (1998, 401) notes, science does not claim for itself the kind of completeness metaphysical naturalists claim on science’s behalf. The “and that’s all there is”-clause is part not of the scientific description of the world, but of the naturalist philosopher’s. 48 here as a way of rejecting my argument for Robust Realism by privileging explanatory indispensability.48 This leaves one other, different, worry: If Metaphysical Naturalism is needed in order to support indispensability arguments, then putting forward an indispensability argument in order to support a thesis that is incompatible with Naturalism is not a promising strategy. I won’t deal with this worry here. In the next chapter I put forward a justification for indispensability arguments that does not depend on Naturalism. If my argumentation there is sound, this worry can be set aside. In the remainder of this chapter I intend only to argue (somewhat preliminarily) that deliberative indispensability is just as respectable in the relevant ways as explanatory indispensability, that if explanatory indispensability justifies ontological commitment, so does deliberative indispensability. I will not in this chapter argue for the antecedent of this conditional, the claim that explanatory indispensability justifies ontological commitment, and so I will not here argue for the (unconditional) claim that indispensability – and, in particular, deliberative indispensability – ever justifies ontological commitment. I argue for these claims in chapter 2. 48 Justifications, we all know, come to an end somewhere. And metaphysical naturalists sometimes sound as if they honestly believe that Naturalism is where they do. But this is highly implausible, for Naturalism is not a commonsensical, intuitive, claim. It is a highly theory-laden abstract philosophical position. And this makes it an implausible candidate for where justifications come to an end. I thank Josh Schechter for discussions relevant to this note. 49 1.5 Metaphysical Naturalism Again Before doing that, though, I want briefly to revisit the relation between Robust Realism and Metaphysical Naturalism. Now, as already mentioned, it is not at all clear what exactly Metaphysical Naturalism amounts to49. It is, however, often mentioned as at least one tenet of this doctrine that all inquiry is continuous with scientific inquiry. It then follows from what has already been said that Robust Realism, or at least my way of arguing for it, is deeply anti-naturalist. For arguably, the empirical sciences do not study facts that are explanatorily useless. By arguing for the existence of explanatorily useless facts, and by basing my argument on a method radically different from IBE, I am as far from Naturalism as is possible. Indeed, this explains why metaethical or metanormative realists who are also Metaphysical Naturalists typically employ the first strategy in coping with Harman’s Challenge: Being Naturalists, they cannot consistently reject the explanatory requirement. This may be so: If my argument convinces you that there is no reason for taking explanatory indispensability, but not some other kinds of indispensability, seriously, perhaps it will thereby have convinced you that Metaphysical 49 It is sometimes thought sufficient for Metaphysical Naturalism that all facts supervene on natural facts (that is, on the kind of facts studied by the empirical sciences). I believe the normative – and, plausibly, everything else – supervenes on the natural. Does this make me a Naturalist? The answer, I think, is “no”. The supervenience criterion for Naturalism is clearly too weak: In order to qualify as a Naturalist, it is necessary to believe that all facts are natural. If I believe, say, in scientific-inquiry-impenetrable demons, but that all demon-facts supervene on natural ones, I do not qualify as a Naturalist. In the context of the metaethical literature, it is worth mentioning (as Audi (1997, 114) does) that Moore, an anti-naturalist if ever there was one, accepted some kind of a supervenience thesis (see, for instance, his “Reply to Critics” in Schilpp (1942, 588)). 50 Naturalism is false.50 But I want to note here that my argument is not all that antinaturalist. True, my inquiry is not continuous with scientific inquiry, in the sense that it does not employ the method scientific inquiry does (roughly, IBE). But my inquiry is not completely discontinuous with scientific inquiry. If I am right, both the scientific method and my method are particular instances of a more general mode of reasoning: Scientific inquiry proceeds by arguments from explanatory indispensability; mine will proceed by an argument from some other kind of indispensability; both are particular instances of indispensability arguments. So, though my argument is not sufficiently continuous with scientific methodology to merit being called naturalist, it is not completely discontinuous with it either. And if I am right in stating that there is no non-arbitrary way of distinguishing explanatory from other indispensabilities, my argument captures what should have been appealing about Naturalism all along. 1.6 Instrumental and Intrinsic Indispensability Let us take stock. In response to Harman’s Challenge, I propose to pursue the second strategy, that of rejecting the explanatory requirement. I propose to avoid ontological profligacy by nevertheless restricting our ontological commitment to those entities, facts, properties, truths that are indispensable, those that our best In the Treatise, Hume restricts – by stipulation, almost – Reason to just deductive and inductive reasoning. IBE is one plausible account of our inductive reasoning. So my rejection of Naturalism, my claim that there is something arbitrary about taking explanatory – but not, say, deliberative – indispensability seriously, can be read as a rejection of Hume’s restriction of Reason as arbitrary. A remark of Tom Nagel in a seminar helped me see things this way. 50 51 theories quantify over. But I suggest that there is more to indispensability than explanatory indispensability, that our best theories include more than just our best explanatory theories. In order to argue for Robust Realism, then, what needs to be done next is to suggest another kind of indispensability, one that is respectable enough to justify ontological commitment, and to show that irreducibly normative facts are indispensable in that way. But in order to do that, it is necessary to discuss in some detail what indispensability comes to. Now, as has been noted in the philosophy-of-mathematics literature51, where discussions of indispensability are typically located, indispensability is always indispensability for or to a yet-to-be-specified purpose or project. Quantifying over numbers and sets is arguably indispensable for doing physics. Quantifying over (possibly other) abstracta is arguably indispensable for doing metalogic52. Of course, one thing may be indispensable for one purpose or project but not for another. Once this is noticed, it becomes clear that in order fully to understand what (the relevant kind of) indispensability comes to two distinct questions must be answered. First, it must be determined what it takes, given a purpose or a project, for something to be indispensable for it. As I will put things, the first thing that is needed is an account of instrumental indispensability. Second, it must be determined which purposes or projects are such that indispensability for them 51 52 See, e.g., Field (1989, 14), Colyvan (2001, 6). See Field (1991, 1). 52 suffices to ground ontological commitment. That is, an account of intrinsic indispensability53 is likewise needed. (I use this terminology hoping that the analogy with intrinsic and instrumental value will help to make it clear: Something is of intrinsic value just in case, roughly, it is itself of value, independently of its relations with other things. Something is of instrumental value just in case, roughly, it is instrumental to something that is of (intrinsic or instrumental) value. And, of course, something is of value just in case it is of either intrinsic or instrumental value (or both)54. Analogously, in my suggested terminology, something is indispensable just in case it is either intrinsically or instrumentally indispensable, and something is instrumentally indispensable just in case it is indispensable for something that is (intrinsically or instrumentally) indispensable.) 1.6.1 Instrumental Indispensability Given a purpose (such as explaining) or a project (such as the scientific project), what does it take for something to be indispensable for it, in the sense relevant for ontological commitment? Of course, being helpful is not enough. If, for instance, mathematical objects are only used in scientific theories as a means of simplifying inferences “Intrinsic indispensability” is – so I stipulate – just a placeholder for whatever it is that makes projects or purposes respectable in the relevant sense. It is here, then, that the terminological apology from note 39 above is most relevant. 54 The sentence in the text is not true as it stands, for – as Korsgaard (1983) argues – something can be of extrinsic (and so not intrinsic) yet not instrumental value. For my purposes, though, this point can be safely ignored. 53 53 which could be drawn without numbers as well, then, it seems, mathematical objects are not indispensable for the scientific project in the relevant sense. What is needed here is something like Field’s (1989, 59) distinction between being useful in, e.g., facilitating inferences on the one hand, and, on the other hand, being useful in being theoretically indispensable55. However exactly the latter is to be understood (the details of Field’s way of explicating this notion need not concern us here), it seems intuitively clear that the former cannot justify ontological commitment, even assuming that the relevant project is intrinsically indispensable; it is perfectly compatible, for instance, with a fictionalist attitude towards mathematics and a nominalism about abstract objects. Mere usefulness does not suffice for instrumental indispensability. Nor does what I will call (merely) enabling indispensability. Presumably, we cannot engage in the scientific project without sufficient sleep. But sleep is not indispensable to the scientific project in the sense that suffices for the justification of ontological commitment. Of course, if we cannot engage in the scientific project without sufficient sleep, then that we have in fact engaged in the scientific project is evidence that we did get sufficient sleep. But our engaging in the scientific project – though evidence for sufficient sleep – does not commit us to any claims about us having had sufficient sleep. The account of instrumental indispensability I 55 Brink (1989, 192) makes a similar distinction in the metaethical context between pragmatic and in-principle indispensability. As will be made clear in chapter 2, I think Brink’s terms are potentially misleading. 54 am after should have this result. So enabling indispensability is not what I am after. An initially attractive recourse is to restrict instrumental indispensability – indispensability for a theory, for now – to just those things that are ineliminable from the theory. However, as Colyvan (2001, 76-7) argues, this too will not do, for the following two reasons. First, it is not entirely clear what ineliminability is. Surely, just noting that once the disputed entities are eliminated the theory that is left is different from the one we started with is not sufficient for ineliminability, for this requirement is satisfied by all entities a theory invokes or talks of. Second, it may very well be the case that no entity is strictly ineliminable for any theory, because the theory can be reformulated and reaxiomatized such that any given entity is eliminated.56 Ineliminability as a criterion for instrumental indispensability thus also fails. I want to follow Colyvan in offering the following criterion for instrumental indispensability. If a scientific theory T1 quantifies over, say, electrons, and T2 is the theory we get after eliminating all references to electrons from T1, and if T2 is all-things-considered at least as attractive as T1 (or is, at least, sufficiently attractive), then it seems clear that electrons are not instrumentally indispensable for our scientific project57. The relevant criteria of attractiveness are, 56 Colyvan (2001, 77) argues that that such a reformulation is possible (with certain qualifications) follows from Craig’s Theorem. 57 This is a reformulation of Colyvan’s (2001, 77) criterion. The term “instrumental indispensability”, as well as the (explicit) distinction between instrumental and intrinsic indispensability are mine. Field nowhere puts an explicit definition or characterization of what it 55 of course, explanatory. An entity is explanatorily indispensable just in case it cannot be eliminated from our explanations without loss of explanatory attractiveness. Colyvan’s condition is intuitively appealing, and may be considered simply a result of the policy of inferring only to the best explanation58. For my purposes, of course, Colyvan’s condition is not good enough as it stands, for I am interested in more than just explanatory indispensability, and in more than just indispensability to a theory. Luckily, though, Colyvan’s condition – and its appeal – generalize nicely. Something is instrumentally indispensable for a project, I suggest, just in case it cannot be eliminated without undermining (or at least sufficiently diminishing) whatever reason we had to engage in that project in the first place; without, in other words, thereby defeating whatever reason we had to find that project attractive. The intuition underlying this criterion for instrumental indispensability is simple: The project itself is (intrinsically) indispensable for a reason, and if the only way to engage in it in a way that doesn’t defeat that reason involves an entity (or a fact, or a belief, or whatever), then the takes for an entity to be indispensable to a theory, but at times he says things that suggest that he too acknowledges something like Colyvan’s condition. Colyvan (2001, 76, footnote 16), for instance, quotes the following sentence from Field (1980, 8): “we can give attractive reformulations of [the theories of modern physics] in which mathematical entities play no role” (Colyvan’s emphasis). In the metaethical context, Wiggins (1990, 84) hints at such a condition. 58 Simplicity, it is almost universally agreed, is an explanatory virtue. But then doesn’t Colyvan’s condition commit him to taking even the kind of usefulness that is involved in facilitating inferences as respectable instrumental indispensability, because theories with the facilitating apparatus are simpler than those without it? No, because simplicity is only one explanatory virtue among others. Ontological parsimony is also an explanatory virtue. The all-things-considered explanatorily most attractive theory may very well be – and in the cases where the relevant apparatus is only needed to facilitate inference and the like, probably is – the ontologically more parsimonious one, even if it involves more complicated calculations (or some facilitating apparatus we can be fictionalists about). See Colyvan (2001, 78-81). 56 respectability of the project confers respectability on that entity (or whatever). Colyvan’s condition is a particular instance of this condition, with the relevant project being the scientific one, and the relevant criteria of attractiveness being explanatory. What kind of thing can be instrumentally indispensable? Certainly, entities can: electrons and, (even) more controversially, numbers are arguably indispensable for our scientific project. Note, however, that with instrumental indispensability thus understood, no restriction to entities is implied. Other things may also be instrumentally indispensable. Examples may include properties, facts, truths, and cognitive attitudes. Indeed, even the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument for Mathematical Platonism is often presented as primarily an argument for the indispensability (to science) of the belief in (or assumption of) mathematical objects, and only derivatively for the indispensability of the mathematical objects themselves59. 1.6.2 Intrinsic Indispensability That something is (instrumentally) indispensable for a project surely cannot justifiably ground ontological commitment without some restriction on the set of acceptable projects. Believing in evil spirits, for instance, may be indispensable for 59 This is explicitly noted by Resnik (1997, throughout the paper), and Colyvan (2001, 10, footnote 18), and implicitly endorsed by Field (1989, 14), when he characterizes indispensability arguments: “An indispensability argument is an argument that we should believe a certain claim (for instance, a claim asserting the existence of a certain kind of entity) because doing so is indispensable for certain purposes (which the argument then details)” (emphasis added). I return to this point in section 3.4.11, in chapter 3. 57 the project of sorcery, but this is no reason to believe in evil spirits (if anything, it is a reason not to engage in sorcery). And God may be indispensable for the project of achieving eternal bliss, but this does not give reason to believe in God – unless, that is, the project of achieving eternal bliss is of the kind that can justify ontological commitment; unless, in other words, it is an intrinsically indispensable project. It has been noted in the philosophy-of-mathematics literature that some restriction on the set of admissible purposes is needed. Nevertheless, to the best of my knowledge no criterion for intrinsic indispensability has been suggested. Colyvan (2001, 7), for instance, asks the right question, but fails to answer it: Which purposes are the right sort for cogent [indispensability] arguments? I know of no easy answer to this question. Nor does he suggest an answer to this question that is not easy. Now, in discussions of the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument for Platonism regarding mathematical objects, the neglect to offer a criterion for intrinsic indispensability is not a serious dialectical flaw: As is often noted60, the argument is put forward by the mathematical platonist in an attempt to convince scientific realists. And with these as the major interlocutors, both parties to the debate are happy to assume that, whatever the criterion for intrinsic indispensability, at least the scientific project satisfies it, at least the scientific project is respectable enough to justify ontological commitment. (Indeed, when both parties are also 60 See, e.g., Colyvan (2001, e.g. 25), see also note 70, below. 58 metaphysical naturalists, both are happy to assume also that the scientific project is the only one that is intrinsically indispensable.) The parties are typically so comfortable with such an assumption that it remains implicit61. In our context, though, more needs to be done62. I am willing to grant that the explanatory project is intrinsically indispensable (indeed, I argue for this claim in chapter 2). But I am not willing to grant that it is the only intrinsically indispensable project. And in order to establish the claim that our deliberative project is also intrinsically indispensable, it is necessary to answer the question Colyvan leaves unanswered. Which projects, then, are intrinsically indispensable? Think of the explanatory project again. What is it that makes it – as we assume, for now – intrinsically indispensable? Why is it that if it is indispensable for our explanatory project that p we are justified in believing that p? What distinguishes the explanatory project from, say, sorcery, such that indispensability to science, but not to sorcery, justifies ontological commitment? Chapter 2 is in large part dedicated to answering this question. For the moment, then, let me just put forward in a preliminary and somewhat dogmatic way the answer I argue for there. 61 Colyvan (2001, 7) is a welcome exception, in that he explicitly notes this assumption. It may seem that more needs to be done also by Field, as he too discusses indispensability to projects other than the explanatory one, namely indispensability to (modal) logic and to metalogic (1991, 1). But, seeing that Field then proceeds to reject the indispensability premise – he argues, in my terms, that abstracta are not instrumentally indispensable to these projects either – I think he is best understood as merely assuming for the sake of argument that the logic and metalogic projects (and, for that matter, the scientific-explanatory one as well) are intrinsically indispensable. If that is so, he is under no obligation to develop a substantive criterion for intrinsic indispensability. 62 59 The explanatory project is intrinsically indispensable because it is one we cannot fail to engage in, it is unavoidable for us; we are essentially explanatory creatures. Of course, we can easily refrain from explaining one thing or another, but we cannot stop explaining altogether. In an important sense, the explanatory project is not one that, like sorcery, is optional for me: I have no option of stopping (or not starting) to engage in it63. If God (or believing in her, or both) is indispensable for the project of achieving eternal bliss, the rational thing to do seems to be either to believe in her or to abandon the project of achieving eternal bliss. But with essentially unavoidable projects like the explanatory one, there is no real option of abandoning them. If something is indispensable for such a project, it seems belief is the only rational way to go. And this line applies to all and only essentially unavoidable projects. This is, then, my (as yet largely unargued-for) suggestion for a criterion of intrinsic indispensability: A project is intrinsically indispensable if (and only if, quite plausibly; but my argument doesn’t rely on the following condition being also necessary) it is essentially unavoidable. Instances of IBE are justified, then, because they are arguments from indispensability to the explanatory project, which is essentially unavoidable. 1.7 63 Deliberation What exactly are the modalities involved here? I discuss this question in chapters 2 and 3. 60 But if that is right, it seems clear that our deliberative project is likewise intrinsically indispensable. For we are also essentially deliberative creatures. We cannot avoid asking ourselves what to do, what to believe, how to reason, what to care about. We can, of course, stop deliberating about one thing or another. But we cannot stop deliberating altogether. The deliberative project is not one we can opt out of, it is not optional for us64. If I am right, then, about what makes projects intrinsically indispensable, the deliberative project is intrinsically indispensable. Even if I am wrong, though, if you want to exclude deliberative indispensability as not-quite-as-respectable as explanatory indispensability, you face the challenge of distinguishing between the two. What reason is there, then, to take the explanatory project seriously that is not equally a reason to take the deliberative project seriously? I cannot think of one. And so I tentatively conclude that the deliberative project is intrinsically indispensable if the explanatory one is, that the explanatory project is in no way privileged compared to the deliberative one. Indeed, the deliberative project may be privileged compared to the explanatory one. For, when trying to explain, we necessarily deliberate; we ask ourselves which explanation is better than another, which one is to be believed. Evaluation is thus necessarily a part of the explanatory project. But in deliberating we do not necessarily explain (though very often we do). Explanation is thus not necessarily a part of the deliberative project. If this is right, it follows that there is something more basic about the deliberative 64 I discuss these matters in more detail in chapter 3. 61 compared to the explanatory project. The explanatory project presupposes the deliberative one. And so if the explanatory project is respectable, if it is (intrinsically or instrumentally) indispensable, so must the deliberative project be.65 The deliberative project is, then, intrinsically indispensable (or at least – it is intrinsically indispensable if the explanatory one is). If it is instrumentally indispensable for the deliberative project that p, we are justified in believing that p. At least, we are every bit as justified in so believing as we are in believing the conclusions of inferences to the best explanation. If, then, it can be established that irreducibly normative truths are deliberatively indispensable, we are every bit as justified in believing in them as we are in believing in, say, electrons.66 1.8 Explanatory Role After All? In section 1.2 I have tentatively rejected the first strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge, that of accepting the explanatory requirement and arguing that normative facts satisfy it. And in the rest of the chapter I have outlined what I take to be our reason for believing in (irreducibly) normative facts, namely, their deliberative indispensability. Now, though, I want to reconsider the possibility that normative facts have an explanatory role to play. This will not be a reconsideration 65 A similar point is made by Sayre-McCord (1988a, 277-281) and by Wiggins (1990, 66, footnote 5). I discuss their views in more detail in the appendix. 66 As will be made clearer in the following chapters, this is not a precise statement of the analogy. Its precise details will be made clearer later on, especially in chapter 2. 62 of the first strategy. Rather, the discussion in this section is conducted on the assumption that the second strategy is successful and that we therefore already have sufficient reason to believe in normative facts, reason that does not depend on the explanatory role they may or may not play. I want quickly to suggest three reasons why this assumption may change the verdict regarding the explanatory role of normative facts. On the substantive issue – whether or not normative facts do play an appropriate role in the best explanations of respectable explananda – I want to remain neutral. What follows are just ways in which the deliberative indispensability of normative facts may have consequences relevant to the debate regarding their explanatory role. First, if it is indeed true that irreducibly normative truths are deliberatively indispensable, this fact itself may very well call for explanation. And it may qualify as a respectable explanandum. But then, perhaps normative facts would have to be invoked in the best explanation of this very fact. If so, the success of the second strategy will entail that normative truths do play an appropriate role in the best explanation of a respectable explanandum.67 A second way in which the supposed success of the second strategy may bear on the explanatory-role debate has to with the criteria for what makes one explanation better than another. One of the features relevant for the evaluation of explanations is the extent to which they are committed to kinds of entities or facts we had no independent, prior reason for believing in. Other things equal, an 67 I thank Josh Schechter for this suggestion. 63 explanation in terms of, say, electrons would be better than one invoking some new kind of particles, a kind we had no prior reason to believe in. This means that one and the same explanation can be better against the background of some (logically) prior commitments and worse against the background of others. Now take an explanation in terms of normative facts. It will be better against background commitments that include an independent commitment to normative facts than against background commitments that do not include such a commitment. My argument from deliberative indispensability, if sound, supplies reason for belief in normative facts that does not depend on their explanatory role. So, now that we know we have independent reason for believing in normative facts – indeed, now that we know there are normative facts – explanations in terms of them can be seen more favorably: Their commitment to normative facts is now no longer an explanatory liability, no longer a commitment to a kind of entities or facts we had no independent reason to be committed to. It thus follows that even if normative explanations would never have been the best explanations had it not been for the deliberative indispensability of normative facts, they may very well be the best explanations given the deliberative indispensability of normative facts. If so, the success of the second strategy may help to decide the issue of the explanatory role of normative facts in favor of those arguing that normative facts do play such a role68. 68 For the point made in this paragraph I am indebted to Peter Kung. 64 A third reason why the deliberative indispensability of normative truths may have implications regarding their explanatory role is as follows. It may be argued that it is a necessary condition for taking one’s deliberation seriously, and so for deliberating sincerely, that one believe that the best explanation of one’s behavior will be in terms of the normative reasons for which one has acted. Or perhaps some other tight connection between deliberation and explanation can be defended69. I don’t want to discuss the plausibility of this suggestion further here: I begin to do so in section 3.4.12 (in chapter 3). What I want to note here is that if this suggestion is true, then it is not only deliberatively indispensable to believe in irreducibly normative truths; it may also be deliberatively indispensable to believe in their explanatory role. What is the relation between what has been suggested in the last three paragraphs and the reasons given in section 2.1 – and other reasons to be found in the literature – for doubting the availability of the first strategy for coping with Harman’s Challenge? First, the major reason for believing in normative facts remains the deliberative one. Therefore, even if – for the reasons discussed here, or for other reasons – normative facts do play the appropriate explanatory role, this is 69 I thank Ulrike Heuer for making this point to me in a different context. Many have put forward some claims about the necessary relation between normative reasons and the explanation of action claims that are relevant in this context. Such claims are central, for instance, to Dancy’s theory in Practical Reality (2000) (see mainly his so called explanatory and normative constraints) and to Velleman’s in Practical Reflection (1989). See also Darwall (1992, 166-7). Joseph Raz (1975, 16) seems to suggest a similar point when he writes: “Reasons can be used for guiding and evaluating only because they can also be used in explanation…”, as does Williams in “Internal and External Reasons” (1980, 102 and 106). It is much harder to find in the literature an argument for such claims (Dancy, Velleman, Darwall, Raz and Williams do not, as far as I know, supply one), perhaps because they are considered (by some) so intuitive. I’m not sure that they are, but cannot discuss this further here. 65 compatible with the intuition mentioned in section 2.1 that our reason to believe in normative facts does not depend on such an explanatory role. Second, some of the reasons to doubt the explanatory role of normative facts are reasons to believe that whenever a normative explanation is available, a non-normative one is going to be both available and better as an explanation. What has been said in this appendix shows, though, that the deliberative indispensability of normative truths may very well make a difference as to whether this is so. One kind of possible reason for doubting the explanatory role of normative facts is, however, incompatible with the suggestions in this appendix. If normative facts are by their very nature not suitable to play an explanatory role, then the fact that we have independent reason to believe in them cannot change the verdict on their explanatory role. Peacocke (unpublished), for example, argues that the modal status of moral (and, I suspect, more generally normative) judgments makes them unsuitable to serve in explanations. If that is indeed so, no independent reason to believe in normative facts can support the attribution to them of an explanatory role. 1.9 Scorekeeping The conclusions of this chapter are very tentative: Much more needs to be done in order to complete my defense of Robust Realism. Nevertheless, the discussion so far should have made the framework of my argument for Robust Realism clear. 66 I want to present an indispensability argument for Robust Realism. As in all indispensability arguments, one thing that needs to be done is to support the indispensability premise. This would involve, in the case of my argument, showing that irreducibly normative truths (or believing in them) indeed are instrumentally indispensable for the deliberative project, and that that project is intrinsically indispensable, that is, essentially unavoidable. Very little has been said in this chapter to establish this premise. My support for it is presented in chapters 3 and 4, where I present an account of deliberation (chapter 3) and then argue that all other – non-robust-realist – views of normativity undermine deliberation (chapter 4). If my defense of Robust Realism is to be complete, another task needs to be performed: The transition from indispensability to belief has to be vindicated. So far, it will be remembered, my presentation of deliberative indispensability and its respectability was parasitic on the presumed respectability of explanatory indispensability. And, though this move may be dialectically powerful, I want eventually to discharge the assumption that (for instance, explanatory) indispensability justifies ontological commitment by directly arguing for it. I do that in chapter 2. The argument in this chapter, then, helps to demarcate the tasks I try to perform in the following chapters. And it also serves to motivate the discussion in the rest of the thesis: It shows, I hope, why the line I take in the rest of the thesis is one it is reasonable to try to pursue. 67 But the argument in this chapter does more than that. At the very least, it places a serious dialectical burden on the metaphysical naturalist: She must give reason to take explanatory but not deliberative indispensability seriously. And this reason had better not be question-begging, one that presupposes Metaphysical Naturalism. If that cannot be done, she must either abandon her commitment to taking explanatory indispensability seriously, thus becoming, it seems, a scientific antirealist; or else, she must accept deliberative (and possibly other kinds of) indispensability as a guide for ontological commitment, in which case she may have already abandoned her Naturalism. This result is to a large extent independent of the argument in the rest of the thesis, and it is not without interest. For most who reject irreducibly normative truths do not wish to reject electrons and quarks with them70. Harman can again serve as the typical naturalist, one who wants to maintain the respectability of electrons but reject irreducibly normative facts. And one way of seeing the force of what has already been established is to consider Harman’s Challenge again. It is now clear, I hope, that unless the naturalist can introduce a non-question-begging, non-arbitrary, distinction between explanatory and deliberative indispensability, Harman’s Challenge is rendered powerless 70 The point in the text parallels a point widely noted with regard to indispensability arguments for Mathematical Platonism: They place the nominalist who is a scientific realist in an awkward position: Unless she can somehow show a relevant distinction between the role abstract objects and concrete theoretical entities play in our best scientific theories, a distinction that will prove the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument powerless, she is committed to the existence of the former just in case she is committed to the latter. This, of course, is no threat for the scientific antirealist. But it is of interest nevertheless, for most nominalists don’t want to pay the price of scientific antirealism. They want to be both nominalists about numbers and realists about electrons. 68 independently, to a large extent, of the arguments of the other chapters in this thesis. For unless such a distinction can be defended, the explanatory requirement underlying Harman’s Challenge is – whatever its exact details, and in contrast with the minimal parsimony requirement – completely unmotivated. 1.A Appendix: Previous Attempts at the Second Strategy As mentioned in section 1.2, the second strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge – that of rejecting the explanatory requirement – has not, to the best of my knowledge, been systematically developed in the literature. But it has been gestured at – with more or less detail and argumentation – by several writers71. To an extent, then, the argument in this chapter – and indeed, in this thesis – is an attempt fully to develop, explicate and defend what may already have been an intuition or a (largely implicit) conviction of several writers. In this appendix I survey the attempts and hints at attempts at this second strategy. Two preliminary points: First, I do not discuss in this appendix the work of writers (like Thomson (in Harman and Thomson, 1996), Wright (1992, chapter 5) and Audi (1997, chapter 5)) who, though they reject the exact explanatory requirement Harman seems to presuppose, reject it only to put forward another largely explanatory requirement in its place. I only discuss attempts at rejecting any explanatory requirement, whatever its exact details. Second, most of the 71 For a comment by Pufendorf that lends itself to a reading according to which Pufendorf already anticipated the second strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge, see the Introduction, footnote 18. 69 writers I am about to mention discuss moral, and not more generally normative, facts and explanations. In the discussion that follows I ignore that, assuming the points made apply to the more general case as well. 1.A.1 Lycan Lycan (1986) explicitly adheres to (a version of) the explanatory requirement, and his general sympathies are naturalistic. It thus comes as no surprise that his official way of coping with Harman’s Challenge is along the first strategy, that of showing that normative facts satisfy the explanatory requirement. However, among the respectable explananda Lycan includes not just the fact that we have the moral intuitions we do, but also their content (89). Now, depending on what exactly is meant by “explaining the content of our intuitive judgments”, Lycan may here be bypassing – not satisfying – the explanatory requirement. For the content of our normative judgments is, of course, normative. Lycan thus may be committing himself to normative facts being respectable explananda. And this move is, as has been argued in section 1.1, antagonistic to the intuitions underlying the explanatory requirement (though it is not clear how it can be non-question-beggingly rejected). Lycan may be even closer than that to my argument. For when discussing the explanation of normative facts, the distinction between explanation and justification becomes blurred. Asked to explain why setting the cat on fire was wrong, most of us would come up with what amounts, in effect, to a justification 70 of that moral judgment. Now, if in order to satisfy Lycan’s version of the explanatory requirement it is sufficient to show that normative facts play a role in what is in fact the justification of normative judgments, Lycan’s version of the explanatory requirement is broad enough to include other – not strictly explanatory – kinds of indispensability. It is then possible that normative facts should be admitted because of their justificatory, not their (strictly speaking) explanatory, role. And this, of course, is the line I pursue. 1.A.2 Wiggins Wiggins’ (1990) discussion of Harman’s Challenge focuses on what he labels “vindicatory explanations”, and on his claims that moral beliefs, and, even more, convergence of moral beliefs, can be given vindicatory explanations. Wiggins too, then, pursues primarily the first strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge. Nowhere, as far as I know, does he explicitly reject the explanatory requirement. And his metaethical view is certainly not Robust Realism. But Wiggins’ adherence to the explanatory requirement, like Lycan’s, is softened by his broad understanding of what explananda are respectable. Wiggins emphasizes that one of the things the theorist is out to explain are the internal points of views of thinkers. And value properties may be indispensable for those explanations, because, it seems, they are indispensable to the internal point of view: 71 Value properties are real, if they are, because he who would understand norms and valuations and the strivings and choices in which they issue, denies or ignores values at his peril. At risk, that is, of failing to understand fully what can be fully understood. (85) This passage seems to suggest (to me, at least) that normative facts are deliberatively indispensable, and furthermore that their explanatory indispensability is – to a certain extent, at least – parasitic on their deliberative indispensability. 1.A.3 McDowell McDowell (1985) too does not explicitly reject the explanatory requirement when discussing Harman’s Challenge (which he attributes mostly to Mackie). But, drawing attention to the distinctly normative nature of the beliefs and attitudes relevant to Harman’s Challenge, he suggests that “we should be raising that question [whether normative facts take part in explanations] about explanations of a different kind.” (118).72 Discussing an analogy with the explanation of fear as a response to danger he says: But if what we are engaged in is an ‘attempt to understand ourselves’, then merely causal explanations of responses like fear will not be satisfying anyway. What we want here is a style of explanation that makes sense of what is explained Before saying that, McDowell modifies the explanatory requirement in a way that is – though of significant independent interest – irrelevant for my discussion here. 72 72 (in so far as sense can be made of it). This means that a technique for giving satisfying explanations of cases of fear … must allow for the possibility of criticism; we make sense of fear by seeing it as a response to objects that merit such a response … (119) Much like Lycan (only more explicitly), McDowell invokes here, I think, an understanding of explanation (at least of explanation of actions and attitudes of agents) that is already normative through and through.73 The kind of explanation of fear that involves claims about the relevant object meriting a fearful response is really a justification of that response. But then, despite the use of the word “explanation”, McDowell in effect rejects the first strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge and the narrow explanatory requirement underlying it 74. McDowell seems to suggest that our reason for believing in values and the like is not the role they play in explanations (narrowly understood), but rather in justification (which is an essential part of explanations more broadly understood). And this, of course, is highly suggestive of the deliberative-indispensability line I pursue.75 1.A.4 Nagel Nagel (1986, chapter 8) discusses Harman’s Challenge attributing it to, apart from Harman, Mackie (in discussion). Now, although he thinks that the explanatory 73 See also Hurley (1989, 96-101) for a similar point, made even more explicitly. Hurley refers to McDowell in a similar context (1989, 285). 74 Perhaps this is why he refers to his suggestion as the “disarming of a supposed explanatory argument for unreality…” (176). And see also McDowell (1987, 223). 75 I thank Hagit Benbaji and Josh Schechter for discussions relevant to this section. 73 requirement can be met by irreducibly normative truths (145), and although he is suspicious regarding the compatibility of normative realism with “the hypothesis that all our normative beliefs can be accounted for by some kind of naturalistic psychology” (145), he is also clear about rejecting the explanatory requirement altogether: Mackie meant that reasons play no role in causal explanations. But it begs the question to assume that this sort of explanatory necessity is the test of reality for values. The claim that certain reasons exist is a normative claim, not a claim about the best causal explanation of anything. To assume that only what has to be included in the best causal theory of the world is real is to assume that there are no irreducibly normative truths. (144) Now, as has been noticed by Brink (1989, 182 (footnote 2)) and Zimmerman (1984, 82), Nagel argues for neither of the claims packed into this condensed passage. He gives no reason to reject the explanatory requirement, nor does he explain how doing so is compatible with an intuitive parsimony requirement76. And he doesn’t say why accepting the explanatory requirement amounts to begging the question against the normative realist. Furthermore, as has already been mentioned, Nagel does not abandon the first strategy: I have already mentioned his suspicion that realism is incompatible 76 In conversation, Nagel has expressed doubts regarding the general parsimony requirement as well. He agrees, of course, that we shouldn’t believe in new kinds of entities with no sufficient reason, but he thinks this is merely a particular instance of a more general truth, namely that we shouldn’t believe anything without sufficient reason. Parsimony, he thinks, has no special status here. For reasons I cannot detail here, I disagree. Be that as it may, perhaps his suspicion towards the parsimony requirement explains why he doesn’t bother to show how what he says is compatible with it. 74 with all normative beliefs being explainable by some naturalistic psychological explanations. And at times he writes as if the explanatory requirement can be satisfied with other normative facts playing the roles of the explananda77. So Nagel’s strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge is a complex one. He certainly does not limit himself to the second strategy. Nevertheless, Nagel’s emphasis – in this as well as other contexts – on the need to take the first-personal perspective seriously, and allow a place for it in an objective worldview, seems to suggest a line of argument supporting the claims in the quoted passage. Indeed, the line of argument they suggest (to me) is the one I pursue in this essay. 1.A.5 Dworkin In discussing (his understanding of) Harman’s Challenge, Dworkin (1996, 119122) explicitly rejects the explanatory requirement (as well as the viability of the first strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge). He says: If the “best explanation” causal test is universally sound, therefore, no moral (or aesthetic or mathematical or philosophical) belief is reliable. But we can reverse that judgment: if any moral belief is reliable, the “best explanation” test is not universally sound. Either direction of the argument … begs the question in the same way. (119) And it is clear which direction Dworkin favors, when three pages later he discusses a somewhat narrower explanatory requirement: 77 See above, footnote 11. 75 … it is only dogmatism to insist that the only reasons that can support a moral conviction are reasons of that [a specific explanatory] kind. (122) Not only does Dworkin reject the explanatory requirement, he also seems to suggest that the role normative facts play in deliberation is what gives us reason to believe in them: So the epistemology of any domain must be sufficiently internal to its content to provide reasons, viewed from the perspective of those who begin holding convictions within it, for testing, modifying or abandoning those convictions. (120) In these respects, then, my view and Dworkin’s are very close. It is important, though, to notice the following features that distinguish Dworkin’s view from mine: First, Dworkin understands Harman’s Challenge very differently from me. He understands it as a challenge to the reliability of our normative beliefs. This is the different epistemological challenge, distinguished from Harman’s Challenge in section 1.1. Furthermore, as can be seen from the first quote above, Dworkin – much like Nagel – understands the explanatory requirement as restricted to only causal explanations. But no such restriction need be assumed, and in fact Harman himself would reject it, as he accepts some noncausal explanations78. But, more importantly than the differences in the understanding of Harman’s Challenge and the explanatory requirement, Dworkin – again, like Nagel – gives no account of an alternative way of justifying ontological commitment, nor does he argue for the rejection of the explanatory requirement. 78 See, e.g., Harman (1970). 76 He just states his (plausible and, if I am right, true) conviction that it must be rejected. 1.A.6 Platts Platts (1980b) does not discuss Harman’s Challenge, and his views are in important respects different – indeed, incompatible – with my own (more on that shortly). But his paper is highly suggestive of the argument of this chapter, and, indeed, of this thesis. Now, Platts does not distinguish between normative and motivating reasons, and so his discussion of normativity is couched in terms of desires. This is one of the points where we differ. Nevertheless, what he says about desires is – once translated to talk of normativity – highly relevant here. Platts wonders what explains the motivating force of desires. For appetitive desires like the desire to eat when one is hungry he suggests that their phenomenological feel explains their motivating force. But this explanation does not apply to other, more reflective, desires, desires that do not have a distinctive phenomenological feel. For these, he argues, the only explanation of their motivating force is that we believe that the relevant thing is independently desirable. This claim is confirmed by the observation of the fact (explicitly taken by Platts as brute) that when we cease to believe that something is (independently) desirable, we cease to desire it. But then, rejecting all facts about independent desirability would lead to us not being able to have these (reflective) desires. Platts thus concludes: “the price of abandoning 77 moral realism can be the end of desire.” (79). It is clear that Platts takes this as a reason to be a moral realist (though nowhere does he say so in so many words). It is not clear what exactly Platts means by “desires”. He cannot be using this word to refer to all and only motivating states, because then his question (How do desires have motivating force?) makes little sense. He seems to use it in a broader sense, standing for whatever state can move a person to action. And so his desires – certainly his reflective desires – are closely related to deliberation (more on that in chapter 3). What Platts seems to suggest is that by abandoning moral realism we give up on the possibility of, put Kantianly, determining our will. In my terms, Platts seems to be presenting an argument from deliberative indispensability to moral realism. The similarity between Platts’ line and mine notwithstanding, some important differences remain. One – Platts’ apparent conflation of normativity and motivation – has already been noted. Another follows from what seems to be Platts’ reliance on empirical psychology. His support for the claim that once we cease to believe something independently desirable we cease to desire it is that it is “a brute fact about human motivation and human desires” (79). My argument will not rely on such empirical (and, for that matter, empirically questionable) claims, and so will not be vulnerable to empirical refutation. 78 Despite these differences it is clear, I think, that Platts’ insight is – to a large extent, at least – an anticipation of my argument79. 1.A.7 Korsgaard In The Sources of Normativity (1996) Korsgaard not only puts forward a constructivist account of normativity; she also explicitly criticizes realist views such as my own (“substantive realists”, she calls us). Nevertheless, at times, at least, she says things that sound very much like adopting the second strategy for coping with Harman’s Challenge and rejecting the explanatory requirement it is based on. Furthermore, Korsgaard is very clear about the need for reasons being a deliberative need. Thus she writes: [Giving scientific explanations for what people think and do] is not, in the first instance, what we need [reasons] for, but that does not show that they are not real. We need them because our reflective nature gives us a choice about what to do… reasons exist because we need them, and we need them because of the structure of reflective consciousness… (96)80 Now, Korsggard thinks this line saves some kind of (procedural, constructivist) normative realism, but not Robust (substantive) Realism (46), for reasons that I need not discuss here (my argument for why such a line does vindicate Robust 79 This means, of course, that Platts is prima facie vulnerable to analogous objections to the ones my argument is prima facie vulnerable to. In particular, two objections come to mind: First, the reason his argument gives to be a moral realist seems to be merely a pragmatic reason (Zimmerman (1985, 95) seems to raise such an objection to Platts). Second, many antirealists seem to have reflective desires, and it is not clear how Platts can account for that. Unfortunately, Platts doesn’t address – or even mention – these problems. I discuss the (analogue of the) first in chapter 2 and the (analogue of the) second in section 3.4.8 in chapter 3. 80 See also Korsgaard (1996, 45-7). 79 Realism is just the argument of my thesis). And it is very hard to see how what Korsgaard says in the paragraph I just quoted about reasons existing because we need them is consistent with her major criticism of the substantive realist, the one she puts in the following sentence: “Having discovered that he needs an unconditional answer, the realist straightaway concludes that he has found one.” (33) More needs to be said, then, on Korsgaard’s views and argumentation, and I discuss them in more detail in section 4.5, in chapter 4. 1.A.8 Sayre-McCord In the last section of his (1988a) Sayre McCord presents – in just four pages – what is by far the most detailed and careful attempt at the second strategy I know of. Despite its lack of crucial details, this section clearly anticipates my line of argument for Robust Realism. Sayre-McCord starts by noticing that the explanatory project – indeed, the explanatory requirement itself – is normative through and through, for it requires, at the very least, that we evaluate explanations, and choose the best one. He notes that there is little to recommend a view that is realist about some normative facts but not about moral ones, and so he concludes that our engagement in the explanatory project already commits us to evaluative, and so to moral, facts. There is just no way of engaging in explanation without relying on normative facts. 80 Sayre-McCord goes even further than that. He argues that the respectability of normative (and in particular moral) facts and properties does not depend on their indispensability to the explanatory project: The legitimacy of moral theory does not require any special link between explanatory and moral justification. (280) Instead, what guarantees the respectability of moral and other normative facts are their justificatory, not their explanatory, role: Just as we take the explanatory role of certain hypotheses as grounds for believing the hypotheses, we must, I suggest, take the justificatory role of certain evaluative principles as grounds for believing the principles. (278) This is, I take it, an explicit rejection of the first strategy of Harman’s Challenge, a rejection of the explanatory requirement, and the beginning of an argument for normative realism from a different kind of indispensability. Though SayreMcCord does not use the term “indispensability argument”, he does often say that evaluative facts are indispensable (e.g., 279). And he suggests that we talk in this context, instead of an inference to the best explanation, of an inference to the best justification (ibid.). Now, Sayre-McCord does not give some crucial details here (details which I try to give in this chapter and in the rest of this essay): What exactly does indispensability amount to? Why does indispensability to the explanatory and the justificatory projects justify ontological commitment? Why is there a justification- 81 related need to invoke irreducibly81 evaluative facts and not just, say, psychological ones about one’s brute desires or preferences? Furthermore, in some important respects the line he seems to suggest is different from mine: For one thing, I cannot see how anything like inference to the best justification can be made to work82. More generally, it seems to me the justificatory work normative facts do matters to us because of the deliberative indispensability of justification. What is intrinsically indispensable, in other words, is the deliberative project, not the justificatory one. The latter only matters because the former does. This is why I think the argument for Robust Realism is better put in terms of deliberative rather than justificatory indispensability. Despite the lack of details and these differences, and despite SayreMcCord’s commitment to Metaphysical Naturalism, it is clear, I think, that his suggestions anticipate – in broad outline, at least – my indispensability argument for Robust Realism. 81 Though Sayre-McCord considers himself a Metaphysical Naturalist, he denies the reducibility of normative facts. See his (1997). As will be made clear in chapter 4, the reduction he denies is stricter than the reduction claim I take to be the defining feature of all normative (or ethical) naturalist views. 82 As Tom Nagel suggested to me, Sayre-McCord’s emphasis on justification may give rise to another worry. Namely, that the relevant justificandum is always already normative – an action, for instance, normatively described. If this is so, then Sayre-McCord may be vulnerable here to a worry raised earlier in the text – it may not be enough, in order to confer respectability on normative facts, to show that they participate in (either the justification or) explanation of other normative facts. 82 Chapter II How Does Indispensability Justify Belief?1 Assume the soundness of (most of) the argument in the previous chapter. Assume further the yet-to-be-argued-for (in chapters 3 and 4) indispensability premise (that irreducibly normative truths really are indispensable for deliberation). Still one can object to my argument for Robust Realism by rejecting the move from indispensability to belief as unjustified, or at least as epistemically unjustified. “Even granting you all this,” my interlocutor can say, “all you’ve shown is that, in some sense, we need normative truths. But how is this any reason at all to believe there are such things? Perhaps you’ve established that it would be nice if there were normative truths, or that we deeply want them to exist. But concluding from this to the belief in normative truths is a clear instance of wishful thinking.”2 It is to answering this objection that this chapter is devoted. 1 Much of the discussion in this chapter follows rather closely the argumentation in Enoch and Schechter, “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods Justified?” (unpublished). Obviously, then, I am most indebted here to Josh Schechter, with whom I co-authored that paper. For comments on previous drafts and helpful discussions, I am grateful also to Paul Boghossian, Cian Dorr, Hartry Field, Pete Graham, Tom Nagel, Derek Parfit, John Richardson, Mark Schroeder, and Masahiro Yamada. 2 Here is a similar accusation from Korsgaard (1996, 33): “Having discovered that he needs an unconditional answer, the realist straightaway concludes that he has found one.” (Korsgaard doesn’t, of course, address my argument; this sentence is taken from her criticism of realists 83 In section 2.1 I argue that proponents of arguments from explanatory indispensability face the same initial objection. The rest of this chapter can thus be seen as a reply to the problem they face as well. In section 2.2 I introduce the idea of taking indispensability arguments to be basic belief-forming methods, where epistemic justification comes to an end. This line leaves the challenge of distinguishing between methods that we are and those we are not justified in employing as basic. In section 2.3 I say a bit more about this remaining challenge, and describe what it would take satisfactorily to cope with it. I then go on to present a way of coping with the challenge – the pragmatic account of the vindication of basic belief-forming methods. I present it first, in section 2.4, very generally, and then, in section 2.5, in more detail. In section 2.6 I return to arguments from deliberative indispensability, applying to them the criteria developed in the previous sections, concluding that we are justified in relying on them as basic belief-forming methods. After discussing a remaining worry in section 2.7, I again do some scorekeeping (in section 2.8). In an appendix I briefly discuss other ways of employing indispensability or unavoidability in antiskeptical discussions, in order to distinguish between them and my argument and to explain why I find the latter more promising. 2.1 Explanatory Indispensability Again (primarily Nagel) whose views and arguments are – though distinct from – nevertheless closely related to mine.) And Zimmerman (1984, 95) makes a similar point in criticizing Platts. 84 In Chapter 1, I’ve emphasized the analogy between deliberative and explanatory indispensability, and so between my argument from deliberative indispensability and standard instances of Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE). It is not surprising, then, that the proponent of IBE has to face a similar worry to the one I will address here. For the interlocutor of the IBE-ist can say: “Even granting you the explanatory indispensability of numbers, or electrons, or whatever, all you’ve shown is that, in some sense, we need there to be electrons and numbers if we are going to make sense of the world. But how is this any reason at all to believe that there are such things? Perhaps you’ve established that it would be nice if there were electrons, or that we deeply want them to exist (because we want the world to make sense to us). But concluding from this to the belief in electrons is a clear instance of wishful thinking.” Let me try and make this point more precise. We seek understanding, we try to make the world intelligible to us, and so we seek explanations. All we know when we know that our best explanation of some relevantly undisputed phenomenon quantifies over electrons is that, roughly, if the world makes sense, if it is intelligible to us, if the universe is explanationfriendly, then there are electrons. That the universe would be more intelligible, more orderly, more explanation-friendly if there were electrons is reason to believe in electrons only, it seems, if we are antecedently justified in believing that the universe is at least reasonably intelligible, orderly, explanation-friendly.3 “Suppose the world isn’t unified, what then?” (Kitcher, 1989, 494-5). For a similar point, see Railton (1989a, 228). 3 85 Otherwise, all that seems warranted is at most a hope that there are electrons, never a belief in them. Here is Lipton’s (1991) way of making what is essentially the same point: Whatever makes one explanation better than another – and I’ll have nothing to say on that here – surely the “best” in “Inference to the Best Explanation” cannot be understood merely as picking out the explanation that is already, on independent grounds, most likely to be true. Had it been so understood, IBE would have been epistemically useless, directing us only to believe what we already have independent reason to believe. So, if IBE is going to be an interesting epistemic rule, one that makes an epistemic difference, “Inference to the Best Explanation” cannot mean “Inference to the Likeliest Explanation”.4 And, from surveying the literature that makes explicit use of IBE it is indeed clear, that when trying to determine what the best explanation is, writers do not merely look to considerations of antecedent likelihood, but also to how well competing explanations exemplify the relevant explanatory virtues: Simplicity is, of course, chief among these virtues, but is not the only one. Often mentioned are also conservativeness, predictive power, ontological parsimony, unification of many phenomena under fewer principles, avoidance of claims which are ad hoc, and so on.5 (Again – I have no opinion as to the exact list of the explanatory virtues, and how they interact. Nothing in what follows depends on these details.) Say that an 4 5 For a similar point, see Railton (1989a, 226-7). For one attempt to give a systematic account – and a list – of these virtues, see Thagard (1978). 86 explanation is more lovely than another just in case it scores better on the list of explanatory virtues (whatever exactly they are) than the other. Inference to the Best Explanation – the rule of ampliative inference we do in fact often use – is thus best understood as Inference to the Loveliest Explanation.6 But now why think that loveliness is any guide to truth? 7 Why assume that the explanatory virtues of a theory are good indicators of its likelihood to be true? Such thoughts would be warranted, of course, if we had some independent reason to believe that the universe is simple, that it is unified in the right way, that it is parsimonious; in short, that the universe is lovely, or explanation-friendly. But what reason do we have to believe this?8 And if we don’t, aren’t we unjustified in inferring to the loveliest explanation? There may perhaps be good pragmatic reasons to prefer (e.g.) simple theories, but we should be careful not to conflate 6 Lipton (1991, chapter 4). This question is often raised in the literature concerning IBE. Even when raised by proponents of IBE, though, it is not as often answered. See, for instance, van Fraassen (1980, 90; 1989, 285), Lycan (1985, 142), Lipton (1991, 122-132), Fumerton (1992, 207-209), Niinikuoto (1999, 448). Nietzsche makes this point (or what I think is this point) especially forcefully. In The Will to Power, he says: “That we do not make our “desiderata” judges of being!” (1967, section 709); “But this [Descartes’ clear-and-distinct-conception as a criterion for certain truth] is a crude confusion: like simplex sigillum veri [simplicity is the seal of truth]. How does one know that the real nature of things stands in this relation to our intellect? – Could it not be otherwise? that it is the hypothesis that gives the intellect the greatest feeling of power and security, that is most preferred, valued, and consequently characterized as true? – The intellect posits its freest and strongest capacity and capability as criterion of the most valuable, consequently as true—” (ibid., section 533). And then again: “…to suppose that clarity proves anything about truth is perfect childishness—” (ibid., section 538). And in The Gay Science: “…my eye grew ever sharper for that most difficult and captious form of backward inference in which mistakes are made: the backward inference from the work to the maker, from the deed to the doer, from the ideal to those who need it, from every way of thinking and valuing to the commanding need behind it.” (1887, section 370). 8 Lipton (1991, 74) labels this “Voltaire’s Objection”. 7 87 these with epistemic reasons to believe in them.9 It is hard to see how we could have these without first having reason to believe that the world is (reasonably) simple. The analogy, I hope, is clear: Without an antecedently justified belief in the loveliness of the universe, arguments from explanatory indispensability look like cases of wishful thinking, or at least of conflating merely pragmatic with fullblooded epistemic justification. Similarly, without an antecedently justified belief in the deliberation-friendliness of the universe, my argument from deliberative indispensability looks like a case of wishful thinking, or at least of conflating merely pragmatic with full-blooded epistemic justification.10 Before proceeding to address this worry, let me briefly note one way of “addressing” it that is not open to me. As some of the literature on indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics makes clear, the indispensability arguments there are often grounded (sometimes explicitly, more often implicitly) in a general naturalistic metaphysics.11 If science is, as is sometimes said, the final arbiter in matters of truth and existence, then if numbers are indispensable for science – if our best scientific theories quantify over them – we are justified in “…but is simplicity not a reason to use a theory whether you believe it or not?” (van Fraassen, 1980, 22). And see also van Fraassen’s insistence on the distinction between pragmatic and epistemic justification in (1980, chapter 4). 10 Velleman also notices this worry with regard to explanation and theoretical beliefs, and draws the analogy with similar worries in the practical sphere (1989, Chapter 10). But the details of the analogy he draws between the two cases, and the way he chooses to allay the worry, are significantly different from mine. 11 See, for instance, Resnik (1997, chapter 3) and Colyvan (2001, throughout; e.g. at 25). 9 88 believing that numbers exist. From within a committed naturalistic metaphysics, the worry addressed in this chapter doesn’t arise. Of course, this way of dismissing the worry is not available to me, as I reject Metaphysical Naturalism (mostly for the reasons made clear in the previous chapter). And this is not, I think, a significant loss anyway. For this line of thought dismisses the worry by fiat, simply by introducing Metaphysical Naturalism as an assumption. But Metaphysical Naturalism is, as it were, further down the stream from the worry at hand – we cannot in good conscience consider science the final arbiter in matters of truth and existence without first vindicating its method12, which is – by and large – that of IBE. And it is this method the worry above is concerned with. It’s true, then, that someone who is already committed to Metaphysical Naturalism will no longer worry about why it is that we are justified in employing arguments from explanatory indispensability. But this doesn’t show that Metaphysical Naturalism solves this problem (ipso facto it doesn’t show that it is the only thing that can solve it). Rather, Metaphysical Naturalism simply assumes that the problem has already been solved. 2.2 Where Epistemic Justification Comes to an End When I wonder what time it is, usually I turn to my watch. If my watch says it’s 2:24 I update my time-belief accordingly, coming to believe that it’s 2:24. 12 Here, of course, I am in shameless breach of Quine’s “no-first-philosophy” principle. So be it. 89 Deferring to the watch, in other words, is my method for forming beliefs about the time of day. If a watch-skeptic comes along and requires some epistemic justification for this method of mine, I am not without words: I might be able to explain to her the watch’s mechanism and why it is that it is very likely, once set to the right time, to keep at least reasonably accurate time thereafter; I can just note that my watch has never failed me before and that I have no reason to believe it will start now; and so on. If she asks about the belief-forming methods I’m using in giving this reply – the deductive or inductive rules of inference, for instance, or relying on my memory – and why it is that I am epistemically justified in employing them, I may again have something to say. But sooner or later (most often, it seems, embarrassingly sooner) justifications come to an end. Some beliefforming methods are just basic for me, they are fundamental in how I think: I don’t employ them because I employ other methods, but rather I employ other methods because they are licensed by these basic ones. For inferential belief-forming methods, relying on the rule known as Modus Ponens (From p and If p then q infer q) seems like a plausible candidate for a belief-forming method that is basic for most of us. For non-inferential beliefforming methods, plausible candidates for basicness are relying on perception and on memory. These and other basic belief-forming methods are where epistemic justification comes to an end13, and if the most radical kind of skepticism is to be 13 Why say that justification comes to an end with methods, and not with some beliefs, including perhaps beliefs about the reliability of some methods? In “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods 90 avoided, noticing this fact should not compromise our warrant in using them. If we are ever justified in any of our beliefs, then, there must be basic belief-forming methods we are epistemically justified in employing even though we do not – and perhaps cannot – possess an epistemic justification for so employing them. (One way of making this point is to think of these basic methods as default-reasonable, methods that are, roughly, reasonable in the absence of a case either for or against them.14) If total inductive skepticism is to be avoided, there had better be some rules of ampliative inference we are justified in using. And, given the desperate prospects of grounding such rules in purportedly more basic rules of deductive inference, it seems clear that there is going to be some rule of ampliative inference that is going to be basic for us. Arguably, IBE is just such a rule. We infer to the best explanation, not because doing so is licensed by some other, more basic, belief-forming method, but rather basically. Indeed, other rules of inductive inference – such as some version of Enumerative Induction – can plausibly be seen as based on, derived from, some version of IBE.15 If this is so, then IBE is one place where epistemic justification comes to an end. And this would mean, it seems, that there is something wrong about asking Justified?” we hint at some reasons. But for my purposes here it is not necessary to recite them. As noted in the Introduction, I prefer the version of the argument from deliberative indispensability that has just one premise, rather than a version of it that has an additional premise, one about the legitimacy of a move from indispensability to belief. If you want belief in the legitimacy of such transitions to be basic, you just have to move to the latter argument. Nothing else, it seems to me, needs to be changed. 14 For some discussion of default-reasonableness, see Field (2000). 15 For such claims, see, for instance, Harman (1965), Lycan (1985). 91 for further justification for employing IBE. The question “Why are you epistemically justified in employing IBE?” is then – like “Why are you epistemically justified in using Modus Ponens or relying on perception?” – one I cannot give a non-trivial answer to without taking back my commitment to them as basic belief-forming methods. Something, it seems, is wrong with the question, or at least with understanding it literally16. If IBE is a basic belief-forming method for me, and if furthermore it is one I am justified in employing as basic, then it is not required, for me to be justified in employing it, that I antecedently form a justified belief regarding the loveliness of the universe17. And this is undoubtedly a piece of good news, for it is hard to see how we could arrive at a justified belief in the world’s loveliness without being antecedently justified in employing some method of ampliative inference. 18 (This is, of course, an analogue of the observation that underlies Hume’s critique of induction.19) Indeed, if I can justifiably employ IBE without being antecedently Lycan (1985), to whose discussion I’m very much indebted in this context, therefore suggests reading the question differently, as a request (somewhat roughly) for a pragmatic justification of employing IBE. 17 A worry remains, one that is perhaps best put in terms of the doubtful reliability of IBE, or the doubtful connection between epistemic justification (if IBE is indeed justified) and truth. I address this worry in section 2.7, below. 18 Unless, that is, we are willing to follow Leibniz and argue that God, in His perfection, has created the world which is simplest in hypotheses (1686, section 6). I assume we are not. An analogous line may be taken by some idealists or Kantians, who may argue that it is guaranteed a priori that the world is lovely because we confer loveliness on it. (For an example of a contemporary view of this sort, see Kitcher, 1989, 494-500). Whatever the merits of such a line, clearly it will not do for the purpose of arguing – partly by analogy – for Robust Realism. 19 Fumerton (1992) explicitly notices this similarity. 16 92 justified in believing that the world is lovely, perhaps I can then come to have a justified belief that the universe is lovely by employing IBE20. My main concern here is not with IBE but rather with arguments from deliberative indispensability. Instead of giving a full argument for the basicness of IBE, then, let me assume it for now, and return to arguments from deliberative indispensability. 2.3 The Need for a Vindication In chapter 1 I’ve argued that deliberative indispensability has to be taken seriously if explanatory indispensability does. Now we can add the assumption that IBE is a belief-forming method we are justified in employing as basic. If the analogy is not going to break down, then, I should now argue that we are also justified in employing arguments from deliberative indispensability as basic belief-forming methods. But how does one argue for such a claim? In the case of IBE – a reasonably well-known mode of reasoning, and arguably one we all have an intuitive feel for – there is at least some intuitive support for taking it to be a method we are justified in employing as basic. But surely no such support exists in the case of arguments from deliberative indispensability, the first explicit instance of which is presumably to be found in this essay. Nevertheless, if I was right in Here’s a sketch of such an instance of IBE: We’ve been using – when doing science, and also in our everyday commonsensical reasoning – IBE; and we’ve been tremendously successful in our endeavors; but, if the world is not lovely, this success of ours would be utterly mysterious. So, by IBE, the world is lovely. 20 93 chapter 1, there would be something objectionably arbitrary in taking arguments from explanatory, but not from deliberative, indispensability as justified basic belief-forming methods. What is needed, it seems, is a principled way of drawing the distinction between belief-forming methods we are justified in employing as basic, and those we are not justified in so employing. If you like to think of some methods as default-reasonable, what is needed is a principled way of distinguishing between methods that are, and those that are not, default reasonable.21 And this, I think, is something we need anyway, regardless of the main argument of this thesis. For among the many different possible belief-forming methods (even possibly basic ones) that could be employed some, such as Modus Ponens, IBE, and relying on perception, we are presumably justified in employing. Others, such as Affirming the Consequent, Counter-Induction, and Inference to the Worst Explanation we would presumably not be justified in employing.22 It is highly implausible that the only thing distinguishing justified from unjustified basic belief-forming methods is their justificatory status. It seems much more plausible that there is some other, deeper, difference in virtue of which some basic methods are, and some are not, 21 Boghossian (2000, 239) makes this point as an objection to the idea of default-reasonableness, because he sees no way in which the proponents of default-reasonableness can cope with this challenge. 22 Affirming the Consequent is the rule of inference that licenses the inference from q and if p then q, to p. Counter-Induction is the rule of inference that licenses the inference to the denial of any claim (some reasonable version of) Enumerative Induction licenses, given the same initial beliefs. Inference to the Worst Explanation licenses inferences to the worst explanation of some initially believed propositions. 94 justified23. And ideally, we would want this distinction to be principled, one that we would be reasonably happy to consider the ultimate justification-relevant distinction. Perhaps such a distinction cannot after all be found. Perhaps we would have to settle for a “brute-list” view of justified basic belief-forming methods. But I see no reason for giving up so soon. And if a brute-list view can be avoided, if a principled way of drawing the relevant distinction can be found, then equipped with it we can turn back to arguments from deliberative indispensability and see whether relying on them as basic satisfies the criteria for justification of basic belief-forming methods. If such a unified account of justified basic belief-forming methods can be found, and if, furthermore, it presents belief-forming methods we’re justified in employing as basic in a positive light, such that we’re happy to treat the account as zeroing in on the ultimately justificatorily-relevant features of a belief-forming method, I will say that the account is a vindication of our basic belief-forming methods24. It will not be, of course, an epistemic justification of the employment of these methods – nothing will be that, for they are methods we employ as basic. Epistemic justifications really do come to an end somewhere, and basic belief23 This is a point made by Boghossian (unpublished). Notice that I do not here commit myself to any reductive meta-epistemological view, according to which the property of being epistemically justified is reducible to a non-epistemic, non-normative, property. The point in the text is meant to be read as a point about a necessary connection – perhaps supervenience of some sort – between the property of being epistemically justified and the nonepistemic property – presumably, not an objectionably disjunctive one – in virtue of which some methods have the property of being justified. 24 I borrow the term from Feigl (1952) who coins it in a very similar context. Nevertheless, there are some important differences between his use of the term and mine, differences I cannot discuss here. 95 forming methods are where they come to an end. But that doesn’t mean there’s no legitimate concern to be addressed about them. The concern is that of vindicating them, by drawing a principled distinction between them and methods we are not justified in employing as basic, a distinction that presents them in a positive light. Extensional adequacy is going to be one adequacy constraint on such a purported vindication: If relying on perception and memory, or using Modus Ponens, are not vindicated by a suggested account, or if relying on clairvoyance or Affirming the Consequent are, this would count strongly against the suggested account. So we’re looking for a non-ad-hoc, not list-like, vindication of basic belief-forming methods that is at least reasonably extensionally adequate. In what follows, I present such a vindicating account – the one developed in more detail in Enoch and Schechter’s “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods Justified?” – proceeding then to show that according to it arguments from deliberative indispensability are ones we are, as a matter of a basic belief-forming method, justified in relying on. 2.4 A Pragmatic Account of Vindication – The General Idea25 The view sketched here – and developed in much more detail in “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods Reliable?” – is interestingly related to, and in thinking about it I am indebted to, Carnap's distinction between internal and external questions in his (1956); Dretske's discussion of beliefforming methods that are justified in virtue of being unavoidable in his (2000); Feigl's distinction between validation and vindication in his (1952; 1954 and 1963); Kant’s arguments for the postulates of practical reason (mostly, but not only, in the Second Critique and the Canon of the First Critique); Lycan’s discussion of ultimate epistemic norms in his (1985); Nagel's emphasis of the unavoidability of basic logical and mathematical truths as a response to skepticism in his (1997); and Reichenbach's pragmatic justification of Enumerative Induction in his (1938 and 25 96 Here is the intuition underlying the pragmatic account: What’s common to all the examples of basic belief-forming methods is that their possible success is our only (relevant) hope of successfully engaging in some extremely important project. Think again of IBE. Now, the explanatory project is one of tremendous importance for us. We are – essentially, in some sense – explaining, understanding, creatures, creatures that try to make sense of themselves and the world around them. Perhaps, then, the explanatory project is even a project we cannot disengage from (so long as we are physically able to think). But even if we can, it seems we shouldn’t. In an important sense, the explanatory project is non-optional for us. Now, at least given our constitution, it seems our only hope of ever succeeding in making the world intelligible is if (some version of) IBE is reliable. So, even independently of an antecedently justified belief in the reliability of IBE, we are pragmatically justified in employing it. This is so simply because if not even IBE works, all is lost. This, then, is the idea: Given a project which is non-optional in a relevant sense, and given a belief-forming method that we, given our constitution, have to employ if we are to have any chance of successfully engaging in that non-optional project, we are prima facie epistemically justified in employing it as basic. 1949). In the more specific context of indispensability arguments, the view has some affinities with Resnik’s understanding of indispensability arguments (in the philosophy of mathematics), in his (1995) and (1997). I cannot, of course, pursue the relations between the suggested view and all these sources in detail here (in the appendix, though, I do discuss Nagel and Dretske). 97 Notice that the suggested account, although it doesn’t epistemically justify the use of our basic belief-forming methods, nevertheless does justify them pragmatically. And, given the rational weight of pragmatic justification (and given the non-optionality of the relevant project), this line of thought also justifies the rational force of our basic belief-forming methods. So the suggested account amounts to a vindication in the above given sense: It draws a principled distinction between methods that we are and those that we are not justified in employing as basic in a way that presents the former in a rationally positive light. Note also that this (initial) pragmatic account of the justification of basic belief-forming methods is an account of a sufficient condition for epistemic justification. All the underlying intuition directly supports is the claim that if a basic belief-forming method is one we cannot avoid using if we are successfully to engage in some non-optional project, then it is justified. I suspect that the pragmatic account of vindication yields also a necessary condition for the justification of basic belief-forming methods. But, seeing that the underlying intuition as stated does not (directly) support the necessity requirement, and that the sufficiency is all that is needed for my argument for Robust Realism, I will not pursue this point further here. 2.5 Some Details If the pragmatic vindication above is to be more than a sketch, some details need to be filled in. Let me fill in here just two crucial kinds of detail: an account of the 98 non-optionality of projects, and a clarification of the modalities involved in the “otherwise-all-is-lost” intuition.26 2.5.1 Non-Optional Projects Facing a valuable project, and a method without the success of which the project is bound to fail, how are you (pragmatically) justified in proceeding? Of course, the answer may depend on the likelihood of the relevant method actually succeeding and on the value of the project (and on other factors as well). If, for instance, the only method that could possibly lead to your successfully engaging in the relevant project is itself highly unlikely to succeed, and if the project is not of that much value anyway, it seems the rational thing to do is to discard the project. If, on the other hand, the method is at least somewhat likely to succeed, the project of sufficient value, and engaging with it not too costly, then the rational thing to do is to employ the method (and hope for the best). What does not depend on these factors, though, seems to be this: Given such a project and such a method, you are pragmatically justified in either employing the method, or discarding the project. Now, the pragmatic account invokes the non-optionality of the relevant project in order to block the second 26 Further details can be found in “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods Justified?”. 99 disjunct, thus leaving only the first: If discarding the project is (in some sense) not an option, then employing the relevant method is the only rationally open option.27 With this as the role of the non-optionality condition, what is its precise characterization? Two kinds of case come to mind in which discarding a given project is not a rationally open option. One sufficient condition for ruling out the option of discarding the project is if the project is one we just (at least psychologically, but perhaps metaphysically) cannot discard. So, for instance, if persons are essentially thinking creatures, if we cannot (with our constitution and abilities held fixed) discard the reasoning project, then the reasoning project is a non-optional project in the relevant sense. And if without employing Modus Ponens we cannot succeed in this project, we are pragmatically justified in employing MP. Essential unavoidability is thus sufficient for the non-optionality of projects. In “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods Justified?”, we go on to discuss another way for a project to be non-optional – a project is non-optional in the relevant sense also if it is rationally non-optional, if it is such that, though we can discard it, we rationally ought not to. But this is not something we need to worry about here. For – as will become clearer later on – it is the previous way of being non-optional, or being essentially unavoidable, that will be relevant for the Here is an argument with a similar structure, attributed to Hobbes by Darwall (1992, 162): “As agents, unavoidably viewing the world sub specie the end of self-preservation, our conclusions regarding how our lives are “best preserved,” give rise to dictates, to ‘ought to do’s. Of course, could we give up this end, the most we could conclude would be that we ought either to do what is necessary for self-preservation or renounce it as end, but the latter, Hobbes believes, is not an option that is open to us.” 27 100 justification of the move from indispensability (explanatory and deliberative alike) to belief. 2.5.2 The Modalities When stating the intuition underlying the pragmatic account, I said that one is pragmatically justified in employing a method when it is the only one that has any chance of making one’s relevant non-optional endeavor successful. But what exactly does this “the only one that has any chance” come to? The intuitive idea can be understood as involving two requirements: First, employing the relevant method, it must be possible successfully to engage in the relevant project. Second, it must be impossible successfully to engage with it otherwise.28 If a method satisfies these two requirements – and, it seems, only if it satisfies them – then employing it gives a chance, and the only chance, of succeeding. But now it is evident that, for the pragmatic account to be made explicit, we need to say what the modalities involved are. Let’s start by saying what they cannot be. They cannot be epistemic possibilities. This is so, first, because having epistemic possibilities and 28 This needs to be qualified so as to take into account the following possibility: Assume two distinct methods M1 and M2 that would each allow successful engagement with the relevant project. Now suppose that if M2 is successful, M1 is likewise guaranteed to be successful (but not the other way around). Then, though it is not impossible successfully to engage with the relevant project without employing M1 (one can employ M2, which may also succeed), one is still pragmatically justified in employing M1, for it is at least guaranteed to work if anything does. Strictly speaking, then, what is needed is not the impossibility of success without employing the relevant method, but the impossibility of success if that method fails. (This point mirrors Reichenbach’s arguments, which were designed to show, not that Enumerative Induction is the only predictive method that might succeed, but rather that it succeeds if any method does. See his 1938.) For my purposes here I think I can safely ignore this complication, and so in what follows I do. 101 impossibilities in our account may render it objectionably circular 29; and second, because an epistemic understanding of the modalities may very well render the pragmatic account extensionally inadequate. For if, in order to be justified in relying on (e.g.) perception, it must be epistemically possible for me successfully to engage in the explanatory project using perception, this may very well require – depending on the details of an account of epistemic possibility – that I have some beliefs about the explanatory project, perception, the possibility of my success, and the like. But surely I need have no such higher-order beliefs just in order to be justified in my reliance on perception. A further constraint on the relevant modalities is as follows: The impossibility of success without employing the relevant method must be at least as strong as psychological impossibility. If it is even psychologically possible for me to succeed in the explanatory project without employing IBE, the otherwise-all-islost pragmatic justification of IBE cannot stand. Other than these two constraints on the relevant modalities – they cannot be epistemic, and the relevant impossibility must be at least psychological – it is not entirely clear how best to characterize them. Let me nevertheless make a It doesn’t have to render it circular. Whether it does depends on how exactly one understands epistemic possibilities and impossibilities. I do not know, for instance, whether there is a way of explicating epistemic modalities that does not invoke the notion of epistemic justification. Even if the account is rendered circular, however, it is not clear it is objectionably circular. Whether such circularity is objectionable depends on the purposes of the pragmatic account. If it is read as having reductive inspirations the circularity should be considered objectionable, but I do not intend it to be so read. Be that as it may, invoking epistemic possibilities and impossibilities in an account of how basic belief-forming methods are epistemically justified does at least threaten to be objectionably circular, and so such modalities should be avoided if possible. 29 102 concrete suggestion here, one that manages, I think, both to avoid extensional inadequacies, and to maintain the intuitive appeal of the original account (though at a cost of significant vagueness). I suggest, then, that both modalities be read as qualified metaphysical modalities or, as I will say, as pragmatic possibilities and impossibilities. Thus, I suggest that for a belief-forming method to be such that without it all is lost, there must be a sufficiently close metaphysically possible world in which one successfully engages in the relevant project employing the method; and there must be no sufficiently close metaphysically possible world in which one successfully engages in the project without employing the method. (More on the closeness metaphor shortly.) The qualification to sufficiently close possible worlds is needed both for extensional adequacy and in order to maintain the initial intuitive appeal of the pragmatic account. Consider the case of IBE and the explanatory project. It seems fairly clear that there are some – very far, perhaps – possible worlds in which very different belief-forming methods render our explanatory endeavor successful. Perhaps, for instance, some version of mystical contemplation can – on a sufficiently far possible world – make everything intelligible for us in a flash. But we want IBE to be a method we are justified in employing as basic. So if the pragmatic account is to be extensionally adequate, a qualification to sufficiently close possible worlds is in order. Furthermore, the very distant possibility of success without employing the relevant method doesn’t seem to undermine the otherwise-all-is-lost intuition. And if, even employing the method, the possibility 103 of success is extremely distant, this does seem to undermine some of the force of the intuition that pragmatically justifies us in employing the relevant method. So the qualification is needed also in order to preserve the pragmatic account’s intuitive appeal. My account here relies on the obviously metaphorical apparatus of a “closeness” metric between worlds. And there is no denying that this apparatus gives rise to vagueness and (other) indeterminacy. But the sufficiently-close qualifier is meant to capture an intuitive idea: In the context of a pragmatic justification, we are only interested in those metaphysically possible worlds that are not so far as to be rendered pragmatically irrelevant. So, for instance, it seems plausible in this context to consider only those possible worlds in which our constitution is held more or less fixed: other worlds are, of course, possible, but they do not seem to be relevant for pragmatic considerations. Furthermore, the closeness-metric is highly context-sensitive: for our (perhaps I should say my) purposes here, a world that is very much like ours except a different sperm cell “won the contest” and so not I but a genetic brother of mine was born, may be further from the actual world than a world in which I exist, but that is otherwise as different from the actual world as is possible.30 30 I owe this example to Tom Nagel. In the text I assume (as many today do) that (genetic) origin is essential. I have my doubts about this doctrine, but will not pursue them here. 104 Nevertheless, the idea of a sufficiently close possible world is, though vague and highly context-dependent, not without content. And it will do, I think, for my purposes here.31 2.5.3 Extensional Adequacy Here, then, is the more precise formulation of the pragmatic criterion for beliefforming methods we are justified in employing as basic: A thinker T is prima facie epistemically justified in employing a belief-forming method M as basic if there is for T a non-optional project P such that it is pragmatically possible for T to succeed in engaging in P using M, and it is pragmatically impossible for T to succeed in engaging in P without using M. We are, it seems, essentially reasoning creatures. The reasoning project is essentially unavoidable, and so non-optional, for us. And it seems that, if we cannot even use Modus Ponens (or some other deductive rule close enough to it), this project of ours is doomed from the start to systematic failure. There is no pragmatically possible world in which we successfully engage in the reasoning project but do not use Modus Ponens. On the other hand, using Modus Ponens it does seem possible to reason at least somewhat successfully. So according to the suggested account, we are justified in using Modus Ponens as a basic rule of inference. Affirming the Consequent, on the other hand, is not needed for successful engagement with the reasoning project. Nor is it necessary, it seems to 31 If you dislike the closeness metaphor, feel free to speak of pragmatically relevant worlds instead. 105 me, for successful engagement with any other non-optional project. So the pragmatic account does not yield an unwanted result that justifies employing Affirming the Consequent as a basic rule of inference. (If the pragmatic account supplies also with a necessary, and not just sufficient, condition for the justification of basic belief-forming methods, then we can conclude that using Affirming the Consequent as basic is unjustified.) Perhaps it is not essential to us that we try to find out what is going on in the world outside our minds, though I doubt it. But even if this project is not essentially unavoidable, it is certainly rationally non-optional, and so non-optional. If we rely on perception, there is at least some chance we can succeed in this project. If we don’t, all is lost. So according to the suggested account we are justified in employing as basic the method of relying on perception. I will not discuss any further examples. More can and should be said here, of course.32 But for my purposes here what has been said seems sufficient to give a feel for how the account would apply to natural candidates for belief-forming methods we are justified in employing as basic. It is time, then, to return to arguments from deliberative indispensability. 2.6 Deliberation (and Explanation) Again 32 Particularly important here is the suspicion that this pragmatic account is vulnerable to the difficulty that devastated Reichenbach’s pragmatic justification of induction, namely, that it lacks the resources to distinguish between infinitely many different possible deductive and inductive rules of inference and focus just on the (intuitively) right ones. We do what we can to address this worry (and several others as well) in “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods Reliable?”. 106 How does the pragmatic account of the vindication of basic belief-forming methods apply, then, to arguments from explanatory and deliberative indispensability? Take explanatory indispensability first. (But remember that I discuss it here for heuristic purposes; all that is needed for my argument for Robust Realism to go through are arguments from deliberative indispensability. So even if you have reservations about some of the details that follow – even if, for instance, you think that the explanatory project is not essentially unavoidable but is rather rationally non-optional, or perhaps is not even that – this does not threaten my main argument.33) The explanatory project, it seems plausible to suppose, is essentially unavoidable for us. We are, so it seems, essentially explaining creatures, we cannot avoid trying to understand the world around us. But if even our best explanations do not succeed in describing the world at least reasonably accurately because the world is explanation-unfriendly, our explanatory project is bound to fail. Unless arguments from explanatory indispensability – instances of IBE – are at least somewhat successful, then, we cannot successfully engage in the explanatory project. If, on the other hand, they are at least reasonably successful, we can. So we are pragmatically justified in using arguments from explanatory indispensability and, if the pragmatic account of vindication of basic belief- This is also why I don’t discuss some well-known critiques of IBE, such as van Fraassen’s (1989, chapters 6-7). 33 107 forming methods is true, then we are also epistemically justified in using such arguments as a basic method. We are also, it seems plausible to say, essentially deliberative creatures. We cannot avoid wondering what to do, asking ourselves what it is that makes most sense for us to do. The deliberative project is plausibly considered to be essentially unavoidable for us (and quite possibly for all rational creatures). Now, this claim needs support, and it will get some support in chapter 3, after an account of deliberation is presented. For now, though, let us assume that the deliberative project is indeed essentially unavoidable for us.34 Now, if some things – entities, properties, kinds of fact – that are indispensable for deliberation do not exist, we cannot successfully engage in the deliberative project. So, if arguments from deliberative indispensability systematically fail because the universe is not deliberation-friendly, all is lost35. If, on the other hand, arguments from deliberative indispensability are at least reasonably successful, it does seem possible – pragmatically possible – for us successfully to deliberate. So, given the pragmatic vindication of basic belief-forming methods, and assuming that the deliberative project is essentially unavoidable, we are epistemically justified in Remember – even if the deliberative project is just rationally non-optional, this should suffice for my argument to go through. But in chapter 3 I argue that it is essentially unavoidable. 35 Suppose we realize that there are no normative truths after all. Is really all lost? Can’t we deliberate by pretending that there are? I return to this question in chapter 3. Let me just quickly state here that I think we cannot. We can, of course, pretend to deliberate (and this is why sometimes I make the deliberative-indispensability point by saying that normative truths are necessary for sincere deliberation). But the project that is (I argue) essentially unavoidable is the deliberative, not the pretend-deliberative, one. 34 108 employing arguments from deliberative indispensability as basic belief-forming methods. Think again of the objection with which I started this chapter. By showing that something is needed for deliberation (or explanation), my interlocutor said, I showed at most that it would be nice if it were the case, or that we are pragmatically justified in acting as if this was the case; what I didn’t do, the objection continued, was give any reason – any epistemic reason – to believe this was the case. We are now finally in a position to answer this objection: Indispensability arguments – arguments from deliberative as well as explanatory indispensability – are basic belief-forming methods. They are (one of the places) where epistemic justification comes to an end. So no reason needs to be given why we should take them seriously. Being justified belief-forming methods, they give reasons to believe their conclusion, and there is no need to give a further argument supporting them. Still, we do need a way of drawing a principled distinction among (possible) basic belief-forming methods, between those we are, and those we are not, justified in employing. Only with such a distinction at hand, can we evaluate the claim that arguments from deliberative indispensability are justified as basic belief-forming methods. And, given the plausibility of the pragmatic account of the vindication of basic belief-forming methods, arguments from deliberative (and plausibly also explanatory) indispensability do enjoy this status. In short: Relying on arguments from deliberative indispensability is a belief-forming method we’re justified in employing as basic, and so one we do not 109 owe an epistemic justification for using; and, being a method we’re justified in employing, it is (epistemic) reason-giving. So by presenting an argument for Robust Realism from deliberative indispensability I will – pace my interlocutor – have given an epistemic reason to believe Robust Realism. 2.7 A Remaining Worry about Truth and Reliability A worry remains. For whatever exactly epistemic justification comes to, surely it has to be at least closely related to truth and reliability. And now it may seem as if I’ve saved the status of indispensability arguments as epistemically justified only at the price of severing the necessary tie between epistemic justification and truth. “You may use words as you wish,” someone may argue, “and so you can present the pragmatic account as a stipulation for a technical term ‘epistemic justification’. But don’t pretend this is the justification we have been concerned about all along. For a method can satisfy the conditions of the pragmatic account without being at all reliable, without being at all likely to yield true beliefs. Perhaps you’ve shown that there is some sense in which we are rationally justified in relying on indispensability arguments. But this is not a sense that entitles us to the belief that their conclusions are true.” There are here, really, two distinct objections. The first can be dealt with fairly quickly: It argues that all I’ve shown, at most, is that we are pragmatically justified in employing indispensability arguments, but that I haven’t shown that we are epistemically justified in so doing. But this is not how the pragmatic account is 110 to be understood. True, I have emphasized the pragmatic value of employing a method when doing so is your only chance of avoiding failure. But this story was not meant as an (epistemic) justification of the relevant belief-forming methods, but rather as a vindication of them, as showing that they are belief-forming methods that do not need justification in order to be justified. The second, related, objection is more troubling. This is an objection to the pragmatic account as a purported vindication, and it proceeds by drawing attention to an important feature of epistemic justification that seems inconsistent with the pragmatic way of drawing the distinction between belief-forming methods we are and those we are not justified in employing as basic. This is the relation – whatever exactly its details – between epistemic justification and truth. True, on the pragmatic account the relation between epistemic justification and truth is not as straightforward as may be thought. Nevertheless, the pragmatic account is consistent with the thought that, at least in reasonably fortunate circumstances, epistemic justification and truth are reliably correlated. (And we wouldn’t want a stronger relation anyway: Think, for instance, of your Brain-in-aVat counterpart, whose beliefs are presumably justified if yours are, but are nevertheless radically unreliable36,37.) 36 In her or his world, at least. Depending on how you individuate belief-forming mechanisms and on your understanding of reliability, and assuming that the methods you and your BIV-counterpart use are at least reasonably reliable in the actual world, you may want to say that your BIVcounterpart is using reliable mechanisms alright, but she’s radically unlucky in using them (hers are, as it were, exactly the rare circumstances in which these reliable mechanisms fail). I find it more natural to say that her methods are unreliable, and her misfortune consists in this being so through no (epistemic) fault of hers. But I cannot seriously discuss these matters here. 111 Let us suppose creatures whose essentially unavoidable projects are doomed to fail, no matter how they go about engaging in them.38 Having one’s most important essentially unavoidable projects systematically fail cannot be, it seems plausible to speculate, conducive to survival and reproduction.39 If this is so, we should not be surprised not to find too many such creatures around. And we should expect the creatures we do find to have been lucky, in that their essentially unavoidable projects are not doomed from the start to systematic failure. 40 So we would expect such creatures to have reasonably successful methods of engaging with these projects. Given the pragmatic value of having reasonably reliable beliefs, we would expect their belief-forming methods to be at least reasonably reliable. Again, this is so simply because the creatures whose basic belief-forming methods were radically unreliable are probably no longer with us. The same applies, it seems, to us as well. We have this (speculative) evolutionary reason to believe that our basic belief-forming methods are at least reasonably reliable.41 Otherwise, we wouldn’t have been doing as well as we do. If Putnam’s semantic-externalism reply to Brain-in-a-Vat skepticism works, then the beliefs of the Brain-in-a-Vat in Putnam’s scenario are not unreliable after all. But then we can think of some of your other BIV-counterparts, those in scenarios to which Putnam’s reply does not apply (such as when you’ve only recently become a BIV). 38 Perhaps this is even true of some of our own projects, such as perhaps that of self-preservation. Derek Parfit suggested to me that Hobbes’ view is that this is a project doomed from the start to failure that we nevertheless cannot avoid engaging in. 39 The speculative evolutionary story here is inspired by – though it is also importantly different from – the discussions by Lycan (1985) and by Lipton (1991, 122-132). 40 Notice that I do not here assume a relativism of sorts about essentially unavoidable projects. For all I say here, it is quite possible that some projects – again the deliberative and explanatory ones look like the obvious candidates – are essentially unavoidable for all rational creatures. 41 An evolutionary story such as the one in the text does not support a claim about the optimality of our belief-forming methods, but that is perfectly all right, as we don’t have any reason to think they 37 112 Notice that although relying on (speculations based on) empirical science, I am not here making my argument – a vindication of, among other things, the very method of empirical science – objectionably circular. For remember the dialectical position: I have already argued for the pragmatic account of the vindication of basic belief-forming methods. I am here facing an objection to that account, a claim that it cannot accommodate something that needs accommodating, namely, the relation between epistemic justification and truth. If I can show – now already assuming the account – that the relevant data can be accommodated from within the pragmatic account, the objection is rendered powerless. Had I relied on the evolutionary speculations here as positive support for the pragmatic account, circularity would have ensued. Using it as I do only as a reply to an objection that is, as it were, further down the road from the positive argumentation supporting the pragmatic account, no circularity threatens.42 The relation between epistemic justification and reliability gestured at above is not, you will notice, just compatible with the pragmatic account of beliefforming methods we are justified in employing as basic; it naturally flows from it. are optimal. As Lycan (1985, 158) puts it: “All’s for nearly the best, in this next best of all possible worlds.”. 42 The speculative story in the text may after all be seen as lending the pragmatic account some positive support, in the following two ways: First, had the scientific method – vindicated as it is by the pragmatic account – yielded results that are incompatible (or even just in serious tension) with it, there would have been something self-defeating about the pragmatic account. The speculative reasoning in the text begins to show that such self-defeat is unlikely. Second, the reasoning in the text relies on the scientific method, plausibly taken to be a basic belief-forming method. What else is needed for epistemic justification of the relevant belief (here, in the correlation between epistemic justification and truth)? Circularity would have been a problem here if the pragmatic account had been suggested as an epistemic justification of, for instance, the scientific method. Seeing that it is not so offered, there is no danger of circularity. 113 So it is simply not true to say that the pragmatic account severs the tie between truth and epistemic justification. Still, it may be thought that this relation between epistemic justification and truth is not quite as intimate as we would expect. Perhaps, for instance, we would expect the relation to be analytic, or a priori, or at least necessary, whereas on the suggestion above it depends on the contingencies of natural selection. But we already know that the relation between epistemic justification and reliability can be held hostage to the contingent facts – the example of your epistemically justified but radically unreliable BIV-counterpart suffices to show that. So the pragmatic vindication of basic belief-forming methods gives just the tentative relation we should expect between epistemic justification and truth. 2.8 Scorekeeping Relying on indispensability arguments is thus a belief-forming method we are justified in employing as basic. In other words, if something’s being the case is instrumentally indispensable to an essentially unavoidable (and so intrinsically indispensable) project, that is (epistemic) reason to believe it is the case. So what remains to be done if my argument for Robust Realism is to be complete is to present an account of deliberation that will show that the deliberative project is essentially unavoidable for us, and that irreducibly normative truths are instrumentally indispensable for it. This is the task of the two following chapters. 114 Before concluding, though, I want to mention two fallback positions. Assuming you are not convinced by the argument in this chapter, what remains of my argument for Robust Realism? First, given the argument of chapter 1, you still face the choice between accepting arguments from deliberative indispensability and rejecting even arguments from explanatory indispensability. So even if you don’t accept the argument in this chapter regarding how it is that indispensability arguments confer epistemic justification on their conclusion, still you’re not at liberty to discard my argument from deliberative indispensability unless you are either willing to discard IBE with it43, or to defend a principled distinction between the two modes of reasoning. Second, even if unconvinced about the status of indispensability arguments as conferring epistemic justification on their conclusion, you may very well be convinced by the force of the otherwise-all-is-lost reasoning that we are at least pragmatically justified in employing indispensability arguments. So, even if unconvinced by my argument that we are epistemically justified in believing Robust Realism, you may still agree that we are at least pragmatically justified in believing, or in accepting or assuming, or in acting as if we believe, Robust 43 And notice that all instances of IBE (that are not subsumable under some other, purportedly acceptable, rule of inference) are at stake. So if you think – following what seems to have been van Fraassen’s view in his (1980), but no longer in his (1989) – that IBE is all well and good so long as the conclusion is only about observables, you already accept some indispensability arguments, and unless you’re willing to take Robust Realism on board, you have already incurred the commitment to defend a distinction between explanatory indispensability (in the cases where IBE is legitimate) and deliberative indispensability. 115 Realism. Now, this is much weaker than the conclusion I want. But it is not without significance altogether.44 2.A Other Ways of Rendering Unavoidability Useful The unavoidability of the deliberative (and explanatory) project thus plays an important role in my argument. In this appendix, I briefly discuss other attempts at making epistemological use of unavoidability, distinguishing them from mine, and explaining why I think mine is the more promising one.45 2.A.1 Nagel and Self-Defeat In The Last Word (1997) Nagel repeatedly accuses sufficiently ambitious skeptics of something like self-defeat. Nagel rightly notes, for instance, that in order to launch a skeptical attack on logic, the skeptic is going to have to use some logic. Nagel then argues that the skeptic’s dialectical position is thus rendered unstable. Logic, and – perhaps more generally – Reason herself, are simply unavoidable; even the skeptic, while launching her skeptical attack, still reasons. So skepticism about logic and Reason is unstable. So our use of logic is immune to global skeptical challenge.46 The fallback position in this paragraph is especially powerful, of course, against someone – like Harman – who wants to give an ultimately pragmatic account of epistemic justification. 45 Lycan (1985, 146) also quickly distinguishes his view – to which mine is fairly close – from views of the kind of the first two I discuss below (he doesn’t discuss the specific texts I do; they were written after his 1985). Lycan does not discuss the third view I discuss below. 46 Price seems to have entertained a line of thought rather similar to Nagel’s. See the discussion in Schneewind (1998, 383). 44 116 An analogous line can be pursued with regard to deliberation (though nowhere, as far as I know, does Nagel pursue it; in The Last Word he targets only global skeptics, skeptics about reason or thought in general). Even as my interlocutor launches arguments against the deliberative project or the beliefs engaging in it commits us to, she cannot avoid deliberating (in a somewhat generalized, but naturally generalized, sense): She still asks herself normative questions, questions about what theory we have most reason to believe, what view it makes best sense to take on these things, and so on. So – so it may be argued in a Nagelean spirit – skepticism about the prospects of successfully engaging with the deliberative project is unstable. The deliberative project and the commitments it comes with are immune to skeptical challenge.47 For Nagel, then, the unavoidability of certain modes of thinking makes skepticism about them unstable. In my argument, on the other hand, unavoidability plays a role in supporting positive arguments from indispensability (and other basic belief-forming methods), with no need to mention possible skeptical positions. Furthermore, for Nagel’s line to work it is necessary that the relevant skeptical position be rendered (loosely speaking) incoherent. My use of unavoidability commits me to no such thing.48 47 In the context of debates over IBE, Churchland (1985) makes a similar point against van Fraassen. 48 The presentation of Nagel’s view and the discussion of the differences between our views are based on my reading of his (1997). The differences between my view and Nagel’s actual (and current) views on these matters are in fact – as has become clear to me in conversation – much less significant. 117 And this, I think, is a significant advantage of my use of unavoidability compared to Nagel’s. For it is simply not true that the skeptic’s position is rendered unstable by the use skeptics make of methods they end up arguing against. Skeptical arguments – some, at least, including the ones most relevant here – are best seen, I think, as ad hominem arguments, with all of us as the relevant homini. The skeptic is entitled to use in her argumentation all beliefforming methods I am committed to accepting as legitimate. And if, using these methods, she can support a conclusion I am not willing to swallow – one stating, for instance, that the very methods she used are not ones we are justified in using – then it is I who am in trouble, not her. Think of the situation as an analogue of a reductio ad absurdum: A good reductio argument assumes a certain claim only to prove it false. And just like a sound (reductio) argument establishing that a certain claim is false may suppose that claim, a sound argument concluding that a certain method is incorrect or unjustified may employ that very method. If a beliefforming method can be turned against itself in this way, surely this is a problem for its proponents, not its enemies. That the skeptic cannot avoid using the relevant controversial method only shows that she is in the same epistemological boat as the rest of us (surely, not a surprise). It doesn’t show that that method is reliable or justified.49 Here is Nietzsche again: “The subjective compulsion not to contradict here is a biological compulsion: the instinct for the utility of inferring as we do infer is part of us, we almost are this instinct – But what naiveté to extract from this a proof that we are therewith in possession of a “truth in itself”! – Not being able to contradict is proof of an incapacity, not of ‘truth.’” (1967, section 515). 49 118 The same goes for deliberation. If the (somewhat generalized) deliberative project can be turned against itself in a similar fashion – as would be the case if the theory it made most sense to believe was one incompatible with the commitments of all normative thought – this would be a problem for me, not for the deliberationskeptic. So Nagelean unavoidability cannot yield the positive results I am after. 2.A.2 Dretske and Ought-Implies-Can Dretske (2000) argues that certain methods of forming beliefs are unavoidable. He emphasizes that, for instance, forming beliefs in accordance with our perceptual experiences is not something we can avoid doing. Of course, in special circumstances – if, for instance, we believe we’re hallucinating – we may be able to screen off the influence of perception on our beliefs. But unless the circumstances are special, when we (apparently) perceive a computer monitor in front of us, we cannot but “move” to the belief that there is a computer monitor in front of us. This is – even if true – only a psychological fact about us. To get the normative conclusion he is after – namely, that we are justified in relying on perception, using MP, and so on – Dretske relies (598-9) on an ought-implies-can principle: We cannot avoid relying on perception in forming beliefs; but ought 119 implies can; so it is not the case that we (epistemically) ought to avoid relying on perception; so relying on perception is (epistemically) permissible.50 Two differences between Dretske’s use of unavoidability and mine immediately suggest themselves51: First, all that Dretske can account for is – as he explicitly concedes – the permissibility of employing the relevant methods. An ought-implies-can principle can never support a judgment of requiredness, only of permissibility. My argument, if sound, supports a stronger conclusion: It doesn’t just show that us Robust Realists are not blameworthy for our belief in Robust Realism formed on the basis of an unavoidable argument from deliberative indispensability. Rather, it aspires to show that everyone ought to believe Robust Realism, or at least has strong reason so to believe. So this is one reason why Dretske’s use of unavoidability won’t do for my purposes. Second, Dretske’s argument essentially relies on a highly questionable ought-implies-can principle. Notice that the principle he needs for his argument to go through is something like an epistemic-ought-implies-psychological-can principle. It is difficult to see what the justification for this principle is. I suspect that this principle is – Dretske’s claims to the contrary notwithstanding – A similar ought-implies-can principle is what does the underlying work in Boghossian’s meaning-based account of the justification of Modus Ponens, or so, at least, Schechter and I argue in “Meaning and Justification: The Case of Modus Ponens” (unpublished). 51 A third difference, one not discussed in the text, is that in Dretske’s account the unavoidability is a part of the epistemological story regarding the justification of the relevant belief-forming methods, whereas in my account the epistemological story comes to an end with basic beliefforming methods, and the unavoidability of certain projects comes in only as a part of the vindication of those methods. But this difference – important though it is for general theoretical purposes – is not as important in order to understand why it is that Dretske’s account cannot be used for my purposes. 50 120 pragmatically motivated after all52. If so, then there is something more basic about the pragmatic account, and the move via an ought-implies-can principle is an unnecessary weakening of the argument. For these reasons, then, I think that the pragmatic account presented above puts unavoidability to better use than Dretske’s. Nevertheless, if the specific ought-implies-can principle Dretske needs for his argument to go through can be defended (and, as mentioned above, I doubt this is the case), then his line is an important fallback position for me: Even if my pragmatic vindication of arguments from deliberative indispensability does not work, still it may at least be permissible for us to employ them and believe their conclusions. 2.A.3 Velleman and Constitutive Aims In a series of articles53 Velleman develops an account of reasons for action and belief that grounds them in what he labels action’s and belief’s “constitutive aims”. Belief, for instance, has truth as its constitutive aim: Beliefs are governed by mechanisms aimed at the truth. A state that is not so governed, that does not have truth as its constitutive aim, cannot qualify as a belief, however similar to belief it may be in other respects. And similarly for action, whose constitutive aim is self-knowledge of a very specific kind. So long as you believe, or act, Velleman 52 Dretske considers the option of going pragmatic and rejects it in a quick paragraph (2000, p. 598), because he does not think pragmatic justification can ever give rise to epistemic justification. With “giving rise” properly understood, I, of course, differ. 53 Many of the papers collected in Velleman (2000a) are relevant here, as is the introduction to this collection. See especially “The Possibility of Practical Reason” and “On the Aim of Belief”. 121 argues, you are necessarily guided by belief’s and action’s constitutive aims. And this is the source of the reasons for belief and action that apply to you.54 But why, it seems reasonable to ask, should I “play the game” of belief and action in the first place? Why not play other games, or not play any game at all? What reason can Velleman give me to play these games, given that these games are the source of all reasons? Nowhere that I know of does Velleman explicitly address this question.55 But the following answer suggests itself (and indeed, it is one Velleman himself hinted at in conversation and correspondence). The “games” of belief and action, Velleman can argue, are ones we cannot avoid playing, they are unavoidable for us. Opting out of them is just not an option for us. So unavoidability again comes to the fore, and moreover in order to play a role rather similar to the one it plays in my own argument. Let me, then, assume for the sake of argument that the details in Velleman’s argument can be (and perhaps already have been) filled in successfully, and draw attention to just one important difference between Velleman’s way here and mine56. In Velleman’s account unavoidability plays a metaphysical role, whereas in mine its role is purely epistemological. For I believe Gewirth’s view is rather similar to Velleman in the ways relevant here. This is perhaps clearest in Gewirth (1993, 502-3). And Korsgaard (1999, e.g. at 15) pursues a very similar line (though I am unsure as to how this squares with her official Constructivism discussed in secton 4.5, in chapter 4). 55 Railton (1997, 75-79), when considering a similar line to Velleman’s, does raise this question. If I understand him correctly, though, he eventually despairs on giving it a fully satisfactory answer (ibid., 79). 56 For discussions relevant to the point about to be made in this paragraph I am much indebted to Pete Graham. 54 122 Velleman hopes to ground reasons in constitutive aims of unavoidable activities, he believes (if I understand him correctly) that reasons’ very existence depends on these constitutive aims and on the unavoidability of the relevant activities. If we hadn’t been unavoidably thinkers and agents, or if belief and action hadn’t had constitutive aims, we would not have had any reasons for belief and action. Unavoidability plays a completely different role in my account, according to which all that depends on the unavoidability of the relevant project is our reason to believe that there are reasons and normative truths, not their very existence. Had the deliberative project not been unavoidable in the relevant sense, my argument for Robust Realism would not have gone through, and so presumably we would have had no reason to believe in irreducibly normative truths (not this reason, anyway). But they would still have existed. Again the analogy with explanatory indispensability is helpful: Had the explanatory project not been a non-optional one for us, we would not, perhaps, have been justified in inferring to the best explanation, and so we would have had no reason to believe that there are electrons. But the electrons themselves would still have been there.57 Thus, on my account reasons and normative truths are metaphysically on firmer grounds. And this, I submit, is a reason to prefer my account here to Velleman’s. 57 More on this in section 3.4.13, in chapter 3. 123 Chapter III Deliberation1 My argument for Robust Realism makes rather bold assumptions about deliberation. In this chapter I try to support them by developing an account of deliberation that shows them to be true. Two things need to be true of deliberation if the argument for Robust Realism is to go through: First, deliberation must be intrinsically indispensable for us. If the argument of the previous chapter is sound, sufficient for establishing that would be to show that deliberation is essentially unavoidable; that we are such that we – at least psychologically, and possibly also metaphysically – cannot avoid deliberation. (In chapter 2 I also briefly mentioned the possibility of a project’s rational unavoidability – being such that, even if we can, we ought not to avoid engaging in it – as sufficient for intrinsic indispensability. Although this could be a relevant fall-back position for my argument – even if deliberation is not essentially unavoidable, it may still be rationally unavoidable – I’ll put this possibility to one side, and argue for deliberation being essentially unavoidable.) Second, irreducibly 1 For helpful conversations and comments I thank Stephanie Beardsman, Pete Graham, Tom Nagel, Derek Parfit, Josh Schechter and Mark Schroeder. 124 normative truths must be indispensable for deliberation. The task of this chapter, then, is to develop an account of deliberation that satisfies both these desiderata. Unfortunately, these desiderata seem to pull in opposite directions. The thicker one’s account of deliberation – the more one is willing to build into it as necessary conditions – the more plausible it is that irreducibly normative truths are indispensable for deliberation, but the less plausible it is that we are essentially deliberative; the thinner one’s understanding of deliberation, the more plausible it is that we’re essentially deliberative, but the less plausible it is that deliberation requires irreducibly normative truths. In this chapter I try to steer a middle course. I try to develop an account of deliberation that is both sufficiently thick (to require irreducibly normative truths) and sufficiently thin (so that it is plausible that we’re essentially deliberative). My discussion will be phenomenological in character: Both in characterizing deliberation and in arguing for the relevant theses of intrinsic and instrumental indispensability, I will rely primarily on first-personal considerations, considerations of what it is like to deliberate. It is here, then, that my argument for Robust Realism is – as promised in the introduction – a descendant of traditional claims that only realism (of one kind or another) is compatible with the relevant phenomenology. Different people mean different things by “deliberation”, and so it is necessary to start by clarifying what I’ll mean by it. This is what I do in section 3.1. The characterization of deliberation to be presented may be treated by the 125 skeptical reader as a stipulation – regardless of how others use the term, this is how I’ll use it throughout. It is deliberation-thus-understood that I will argue requires irreducibly normative truths, it is deliberation-thus-understood that I will argue we cannot avoid engaging in. Nevertheless, I think my phenomenological characterization of deliberation bears sufficient similarity to our pretheoretical understanding of deliberation (and to some other theoretical suggestions) so that it need not be seen as a mere stipulation, and so that previous discussions of deliberation are not rendered irrelevant. Having characterized deliberation, I then move on to argue for the claims of instrumental and intrinsic indispensability in sections 3.2 and 3.3 respectively. In section 3.4 I address several objections to my understanding of deliberation and what follows from it, filling in along the way some details of my understanding of deliberation. In section 3.5 I briefly mention two other argumentative strategies that resemble mine, mostly in order to distinguish them from mine and explain why I think the latter is the better way to go. In the concluding section (3.6) I again do some scorekeeping, noting what has already been done, and what remains to be done if the defense of Robust Realism is to be completed. Two further preliminary points: First, the phenomenological discussion will focus on deliberation about action, on (roughly speaking) attempts to decide what to do. I will not discuss here other possible cases of deliberation, most notably attempts to decide (in some sense of “decide”) what to believe. This is not because I am convinced that analogous points cannot be made regarding that case 126 as well. Indeed, I tend to believe that the phenomenology of attempts to decide what to believe is – though different from that of trying to decide what to do in important ways – similar to it in the crucial ways for my argument to go through. But the case of belief involves several complexities that the case of action does not involve (like the purported implausibility of belief-voluntarism, and the possibility of suspension of judgment), and so the discussion of deliberation about actions promises to be simpler (for my purposes, at least). As Robust Realism is merely an existential thesis – stating only that there are some irreducibly normative truths – I think focusing on the case of action should not be objectionable. Second, I want to emphasize that relatively little work needs to be done by this chapter, and that even less work needs to be done by the arguments in sections 3.2 and 3.3. These two sections need not do more than support the claim that our commonsensical understanding of deliberation satisfies the two desiderata mentioned above. If they succeed in doing that, then unless there is some reason to reject this commonsensical understanding, we should take it at face value. And it is the task of section 3.4 to show that there is no such reason. (This, by the way, explains the somewhat cumbersome structure of this chapter, with a rather brief positive argument and a very large number of objections. For this structure reflects the real nature of the argument. In the first three sections I give what seems to me to be a straightforward understanding of what goes on when we deliberate. These sections place the burden on those arguing against the straightforward understanding of deliberation. Unless some objection to the straightforward 127 account succeeds, then, we should take deliberation and its phenomenology at face value.) Even the chapter as a whole, though, need not establish that deliberation requires irreducibly normative truths. For at the end of this chapter the possibility remains that some other, non-robust-realist, view can somehow allow for genuine deliberation. This possibility is not challenged until chapter 4. The current chapter thus need only establish the qualified result: Unless some alternative view can allow for what is needed for deliberation – normative truths, or something very close to them – Robust Realism will have been successfully defended. 3.1 Deliberation Phenomenologically Characterized Law school turned out not to be all you thought it would be, and you no longer find the prospects of a career in law as exciting as you once did. For some reason you don’t seem to be able to shake off that old romantic dream of studying philosophy. It seems now is the time to make a decision (though, as your own experience shows well enough, there is no guarantee that a decision now will be the end of the matter). And so, alone, or in the company of some others you find helpful in such circumstances, you deliberate. You try to decide whether to join a law firm, apply to graduate school in philosophy, or perhaps do some other thing altogether. The decision is of some consequence, and so you resolve to put some thought into it. You try to find answers to the questions you ask yourself: Will I be 128 happy practicing law? Will I be happier doing philosophy? What are my chances of becoming a good lawyer? A good philosopher? How much money does a reasonably successful lawyer make, and how much less does a reasonably successful philosopher make? If I go into philosophy, will the price I’ll pay in economic comfort be outweighed by better intellectual fulfillment and a lifestyle which suits me more? Does the academic lifestyle suit me more? Am I, so to speak, more of a philosopher or more of a lawyer? As a lawyer, will I be able to make a significant political difference? How important is the political difference I can reasonably expect to make? How important is it to try and make any political difference? Should I give any weight to my father’s expectations, and to the disappointment he will feel if I fail to become a lawyer? Am I willing to put the necessary effort into pursuing graduate studies in philosophy at this stage of my life? How strongly do I really want to do philosophy? And so on, and so forth. Even with answers to most – even all – of these questions, there remains the most important question of all. “All things considered”, you ask yourself, “what makes best sense for me to do? When all is said and done, what should I do? What shall I do?”2 When engaging in this deliberation, when asking yourself these questions, you assume, so it seems to me, that they have answers. These answers may be very vague, allow for some indeterminacy, and so on. But at the very least you assume that some possible answers to these questions are better than others. You try to 2 More on the distinction between “What should I do?” and “What shall I do?” in section 3.4.4. 129 find out what the (better) answers to these questions are, and how they interact so as to answer the arch-question, the one about what it makes best sense for you to do. You are not trying to create these answers. Of course, in an obvious sense what you will end up doing is up to you (or so, at least, both you and I are supposing here). And in another – less obvious sense – perhaps the answer to some of these questions is also up to you. Perhaps, for instance, how happy practicing law will make you is at least partly up to you. But, when trying to make up your mind, it doesn’t feel like just trying to make an arbitrary choice. This is just not what it is like to deliberate. Rather, it feels like trying to make the right choice. It feels like trying to find the best solution, or at least a good solution, or at the very least one of the better solutions, to a problem you’re presented with. What you’re trying to do, it seems to me, is to make the decision it makes most sense for you to make. Making the decision is up to you. But which decision is the one it makes most sense for you to make is not. This is something you are trying to discover, not create.3 Or so, at the very least, it feels like when deliberating. This, then, is the kind of process I’ll use “deliberation” to denote. It is the process of trying to make the decision it makes most sense for one to make. And, as the discussion above suggests, it has a distinctive phenomenological feel. “In deliberation we are trying to arrive at conclusions that are correct in virtue of something independent of our arriving at them.” (Nagel, 1986, 149). 3 130 It will be helpful – in clarifying how I understand deliberation, in preempting misunderstanding, and in facilitating the discussion of later sections – to distinguish deliberation from other, related, processes. One has already been alluded to: It is the making of an arbitrary choice. You’re in the supermarket, intending to get a cereal. You may have good reasons to pick Mini-Wheats rather than Raisin Bran (you just don’t like Raisin Bran that much), perhaps even one brand over another (the Kellogg’s one is usually fresher). But you have no reason, it seems, to pick one package of Kellogg’s Mini-Wheats over another, and you know you don’t. Of course, you have reason to pick one rather than none at all. But you’ve already decided you’ll pick one rather than none at all. All that remains to be done now is just to pick a specific package arbitrarily. I take it to be uncontroversial that sometimes we just pick4. And it is one lesson of the unfortunate fate of Buridan’s ass that picking arbitrarily may often be the rational thing to do5. But it is clear, I think, that the phenomenology of arbitrary picking is very different from that of deliberation, of trying to make the right decision. Just compare what it is like to deliberate about whether to practice law or to apply to graduate school in philosophy to what it is like to just pick one For a discussion of such cases – and for references to some who question what I say in the text is uncontroversial – see Ullmann-Margalit and Morgenbesser (1977), from which the example is taken (though somewhat modified). They also introduce some helpful terminology: They suggest a distinction between choosing (for reasons) and picking (arbitrarily, in the kind of case described in the text), with “selecting” being the generic term. For similar distinctions see Darwall (1983, 69), Kolnai (1962, 213) and Railton (1997, 64, fn 12). 5 The interesting questions regarding Buridan’s ass are, I think, not whether we can just pick (we obviously can), and not whether cases of just picking can be beneficial (they obviously can), but rather how it is that, rational creatures that we are, we can just pick, and how it is that just picking can be the rational thing to do. 4 131 package of Mini-Wheats over another. Granted, the difference in phenomenology is partly due to the significance of the decision. But, as can be seen from considering other examples, it is not due only to this factor. Even considering the very same two possible actions, it is one thing to try to decide which it makes most sense for one to perform, and quite another to just pick one, believing there’s nothing to be said for one over the other. There may be interesting relations between cases of genuine deliberation and cases of just picking, some of which I discuss in what follows. But for now it is sufficient to note that the phenomenology of deliberation is very different from that of just picking, and that it is the former, not the latter, that I discuss in this chapter. Deliberation should also be distinguished from trying to predict one’s own behavior6. Suppose I offer you a bet when you still haven’t made up your mind about whether to practice law or to apply to graduate school in philosophy. I am willing to bet a dinner on you deciding to practice law (because, say, I know that you find it exceedingly hard to disappoint your father). You need to decide whether to accept the bet. Now, if you find winning the bet important enough, you can assure your victory by accepting the bet and deciding to apply to graduate school in philosophy. But the bet is not nearly as important as are all the other considerations relevant to this major decision. So there’s no quick way of winning the bet. You just have to decide – much as you would if I offered the bet regarding someone else’s decision – whether it is more likely that you’ll decide to practice 6 For this distinction see also Kim (1998, 70-71) and Rawls (2000, 139-140). 132 law or to apply to graduate school. There is, of course, something atypical – and perhaps also somewhat discomforting – in asking this question about oneself. But I see no general reason that precludes such situations. After all, my offer is still on the table, and you have to decide whether to accept. So we can, I think, sensibly try to predict our own behavior. And there may be interesting relations between trying to predict one’s own behavior and trying to decide what to do7. Perhaps, for instance, if you are reasonably convinced that I’m right, and that when all is said and done you will indeed decide to practice law, it doesn’t make sense to continue agonizing trying to make up your mind on the option that is already practically inevitable. But regardless of all this, the phenomenology of deliberation is very different from that of predicting one’s own behavior. When, in the middle of a friendly conversation in which you seek my advice about what to do, I offer you the bet, and when you seriously consider it, we bring about a shift in perspective, and with it a shift in what the relevant mental process is like. And it is important for what follows that deliberation be distinguished from this other process of predicting one’s own behavior. 7 Such relations are central to the work of David Velleman. See his (1989). Velleman suggests a conception of deliberation according to which what we ask ourselves is not just, and not even mostly, what the solution to our predicament is, but also what shall our predicament be. We don’t just face situations; we invent them (258). It may seem, then, that his understanding of deliberation is incompatible with mine. I cannot discuss in detail Velleman’s conception of deliberation here. I do want quickly to note, though, that it need not be incompatible with what I say in this chapter. Deliberation as I understand it can incorporate a creative, inventive, process, so long as there are some normative criteria that govern such creation; so long as, in other words, there are predicaments it makes better – and worse – sense to create or invent. 133 The phenomenology of deliberation is very different, then, from that of merely picking, and from that of predicting one’s own behavior. It is worth noting, though, how similar the phenomenology of deliberation is to that of trying to find an answer to a straightforwardly factual question: When trying to answer a straightforwardly factual question (like what the difference is between the average income of a lawyer and a philosopher) you try to get things right, to come up with the answer that is – independently of your settling on it – the right one. When deliberating, you also try to get things right, to decide as – independently of how you end up deciding – it makes most sense for you to decide. In both cases, the possibility of error is crucial. If whatever you believe regarding a topic will be right simply in virtue of you believing it, and if you know that this is so, it does not seem as if you can genuinely wonder what the case is within that topic. Similarly, if whatever you decide to do will be the thing it makes best sense for you to do simply in virtue of you deciding to do it, and if you know as much, it does not seem as if you can genuinely deliberate about whether or not to do it8 (though, as already mentioned, you can arbitrarily pick one option). 3.2 The Instrumental Indispensability of Normative Truths In the supermarket, you have no reason to pick one package of Mini-Wheats rather than another. With the only relevant decision to be made being which one to pick, there is no one option it makes most sense for you to pursue. More than that, it 8 Korsgaard (1996, e.g. 35) often emphasizes this point. 134 isn’t even the case that one option is at all better than any other. And you know all this. Now, as mentioned before, this doesn’t preclude your just picking a package of cereal. Though, if you come to reflect on your situation, you may feel some discomfort (and I’ll have more to say about this discomfort later on), we are not typically – certainly not always – paralyzed in such situations. We can just pick in the face of a known (or believed) absence of reasons. But we cannot, it seems, deliberate in the face of a believed absence of reasons. Knowing that there is no decision such that it makes most sense for us to make it, we cannot – not consistently, anyway, in a perfectly commonsensical sense of “consistently” – try to make the decision it makes most sense for us to make. Deliberation – unlike mere picking – is an attempt to eliminate arbitrariness by discovering reasons, and it is impossible in a believed absence of reasons to be discovered. If there are no reasons, then, our deliberative project is doomed from the start to systematic failure. As far as our deliberative project is concerned, all is lost. Thus, in deliberating, you commit yourself to there being reasons relevant to your deliberation. Now, this sense of commitment need not entail an explicit belief (in your “belief-box”, as it were) that there are such reasons, and it certainly doesn’t preclude an explicit belief in their non-existence. Nevertheless, in a perfectly good sense of “commitment”, by deliberating you’ve already committed yourself to the existence of reasons. What is this sense of “commitment”, though?9 9 I thank Stephanie Beardsman and Derek Parfit for pressing me on this issue. 135 Think about a reasoner who routinely infers to the best explanation. Now, she may not be a very reflective reasoner, and so she may not have any beliefs about which inductive inferences are valid and why. Or perhaps she’s been convinced by some of the literature criticizing IBE, and she now explicitly believes that IBE is not a good rule of inference. Nevertheless, by routinely inferring – even non-reflectively – to the best explanation, she commits herself to IBE being a good rule of inference. If she believes that IBE is not a good inference-rule, she is being inconsistent (though perhaps in a somewhat generalized sense of this term) – unless, that is, she has some story available to her explaining how her use of IBE is compatible with her explicit rejection of it (perhaps, for instance, by showing that IBE is, though generally fallacious, actually harmless in a privileged class of cases, and by restricting her own use of IBE to such cases). Similarly, I want to argue, by deliberating you commit yourself to there being relevant reasons; if you also believe there aren’t any, you are being inconsistent in exactly the same sense, and just as irrational, too. And notice, by the way, that in neither case will agnosticism get you off the hook, for routinely inferring to the best explanation is also, barring some further story, inconsistent (in the relevant sense) with professing agnosticism about whether or not IBE is a good inference-rule. And, I want to argue, sincerely deliberating is similarly inconsistent with professing agnosticism about whether there is anything to be said for or against any of the relevant alternatives. 136 Notice that no such commitment is involved in cases of mere picking. Neither by picking one package of Mini-Wheats from all the others nor by going through some mental process beforehand, do you commit yourself to there being any reason that makes your package more worth picking than the others (you may commit yourself to there being reason to pick some package rather than none at all, but this is a different matter). It is, then, a result of the nature of deliberation – an attempt to eliminate the arbitrariness so typical in cases of mere picking – that by deliberating, by asking yourself which choice it would make most sense for you to make, you are committing yourself to there being, or at least to there possibly being, reasons relevant to your choice. Suppose a friend of yours seems to undergo a process of deliberation, but then – when asked, perhaps – says that it really doesn’t matter one way or another, that there is absolutely nothing to be said for or against any of his relevant alternatives, that there are no considerations counting in favor of any of his possible decisions. You would treat him either as having changed his mind (“Oh, he thought, until just a moment ago, that there was a point to his deliberation, but now he understands that this is not so.”), or as being inconsistent. You would treat him as you would someone who professes to reject IBE and nevertheless infers to the best explanation – he has either changed his mind about IBE (“Oh, he thought, until just a moment ago, that we should not infer to the best explanation, but now he sees that he was wrong about that.”), or he is being inconsistent. What explains this attitude of yours, I argue, is precisely that both are being inconsistent. And this is also why, upon coming to believe that 137 there are no relevant reasons, deliberation stops (though a decision may remain to be made). A similar point applies, I think, to the more complex case where deliberation is initially possible. You are still in the process of deliberating about whether to join a law firm or pursue graduate studies in philosophy (or maybe do something else entirely), when suddenly you come to believe – for whatever reason, or for no reason at all – that it just doesn’t matter. You believe either that there is just nothing to be said for one of these options rather than the other, or – much more plausibly – that the reasons for the different options are evenly balanced. Now, coming to believe that still doesn’t settle the issue. You still haven’t decided what to do. But so long as you are confident that there is nothing you have all-things-considered reason to do, you no longer deliberate. You may, of course, lose your confidence; you may wonder “But aren’t there some important considerations I’ve left out?” And in cases where weighty considerations are involved, we typically find it very hard to maintain our confidence in judgments of no all-things-considered reasons (this is why we find it so hard simply to toss a coin when we just don’t know what to do on an important matter, even as we feel that tossing a coin would be the rational thing to do). But so long as you are reasonably confident that there is no alternative you have all-things-considered 138 reason to choose, you do not, it seems to me, deliberate; rather, you engage in mere picking.10 Now, that something is a reason for you to join a law firm, a consideration that counts in favor of so doing, is a paradigmatically normative claim, as is that pursuing graduate studies in philosophy is the thing that makes most sense for you to do. So, by deliberating, you commit yourself to there being relevant reasons, and so to there being relevant normative truths (you do not, of course, commit yourself to the reasons being the normative truths, or anything of this sort. I return to this point shortly). Normative truths, or at least belief in them11, are thus indispensable for deliberation12. This may seem too quick, for at least two related reasons. First, even accepting my interpretation of the examples, they do not show that we cannot deliberate in the face of a believed absence of reasons. They only show that we I return to this point – and mention a fallback position for me here – in section 3.4.7, below. I return to the distinction between normative truths and belief in them being indispensable for deliberation in section 3.4.11. 12 “The ordinary process of deliberation, aimed at finding out what I should do, assumes the existence of an answer to this question.” (Nagel, 1986, 149) For similar points, see Bond (1983, 60), Darwall (1983, 224) (though Darwall doesn’t make this point regarding the deliberation of agents in general, but rather only regarding his “ISIS”, an internally self-identified subject), Kolnai (1962) (though Kolnai, being a skeptic of sorts regarding normative truths, draws skeptical conclusions about deliberation as well), and Pettit and Smith (1998, e.g. 97) (who argue that deliberation is a kind of conversation one has with oneself, and that adopting this kind of conversational stance – to oneself as well as to others – involves assumptions, one of which is rather close to the one in the text. I discuss their view in more detail in section 3.5.). A word of caution: These authors talk of what they understand by “deliberation”, and – especially given my willingness to see my characterization of deliberation as a stipulation – it is possible that they think normative truths are indispensable for deliberation-as-they-understand-it, not for deliberation-as-I-understand-it. Now, I only refer here to philosophers whose understanding of deliberation is, I think, close enough to mine so as not to make the reference misleading. But still, I acknowledge that in order to enlist these writers for my cause – even just for the part of my cause supported in this section – further work may very well be needed. 10 11 139 cannot consistently deliberate in such circumstances, as deliberation commits us to the reasons we now assume are absent. But then normative truths haven’t been shown to be indispensable for deliberation, but at most indispensable for consistent deliberation. And this, it may be thought, is not sufficient for the argument for Robust Realism to go through. A second, related, reason to think that the deliberative indispensability of normative truths doesn’t follow from the above considerations starts from the observation that, in general, it may be possible to try to do something one takes to be impossible. Can’t one show to one’s friends that – as one already knows – a rock is too heavy to be moved by trying, and failing, to move it 13? But if it’s possible to try to do something one takes to be impossible, it should be possible to try to make the decision it makes most sense for one to make even while believing that it is impossible to do so (because there is no decision that it makes most sense for one to make). At the very least, so the argument goes, nothing has been said so far to rule out this possibility. And this means that it hasn’t been established that deliberation in the face of a believed absence of reasons is impossible. Both these objections raise interesting issues I would prefer to bypass here. And, luckily, I can afford to do just that. Recall the account of instrumental indispensability I endorsed – following Colyvan – in chapter 1: For something to be instrumentally indispensable for a project it is not necessary that it cannot be eliminated from that project. Rather, it is sufficient that it cannot be eliminated 13 I owe this example to John Gibbons. 140 without defeating whatever reason we had to find that project attractive in the first place. Now, perhaps it is not literally impossible for you to deliberate whether to join a law firm or to apply to graduate school in philosophy while believing that you have no (all-things-considered) reason to do one rather than the other. But believing this is so at the very least undermines whatever reason you may have had to find deliberation here attractive. So believing, would you still have resolved to put much thought, time and effort into the deliberative process? Should you have so resolved? I think it reasonably clear, then, that normative truths (or belief in them) cannot be eliminated from the deliberative process without rendering it unattractive. And this suffices in order to conclude that normative truths are instrumentally indispensable for deliberation. 3.3 The Intrinsic Indispensability of Deliberation That normative truths are indispensable for deliberation is already a victory – though perhaps a small one – for the realist (a reminder: this is not yet a victory – not even a small one – for the robust realist, because for all that’s been thus far said it is still possible that some other, non-robust-realist, metanormative theory can account for normative truths, or for something that can do their work in deliberation). For if the conclusion of the previous section is correct, the following choice seems unavoidable: either admit some normative truths (or something sufficiently close to them to do their work), or conclude that deliberation (as I 141 characterized it) is – necessarily, it seems – illusory14. Seeing that the latter option comes with a considerable intuitive price, the instrumental indispensability of normative truths for deliberation already places some burden on the shoulders of the anti-realist (though I’ll have to discuss the possibility that deliberation is illusory in more detail in section 3.4.5 below). But what we have here can again be seen as an instance of the tension I mentioned at the beginning of this chapter between the two desiderata an account of deliberation must satisfy if my argument for Robust Realism is to go through. For an antirealist can argue that the account of deliberation presented thus far is so strong, so much has been packed into it, that the result regarding the instrumental indispensability of normative truths is no longer of any interest. Yes, he can argue, the process I insist on calling “deliberation” requires normative truths, but this is not a process we ever engage in. Certainly, it is not a process we cannot but engage in, and not one we should be concerned about being necessarily illusory. The pressure is put, then, on the claim that is to be supported in this section: We are essentially deliberative creatures. Before arguing for this claim, I want to emphasize that I won’t be arguing for much stronger – indeed, unacceptably strong – claims, namely, that whenever we act what we do is a result of deliberation, or that we cannot avoid deliberating in each particular moment. I take it to be clear that often we do not engage in deliberation, and that almost as often we act without deliberating. Some things, for instance, we just do out of habit without giving them a second thought. Some 14 For similar points see De Sousa (1974, 539) and Bond (1983, 54). 142 things we may do for no reason at all, and, it seems to me, even much of what we do for a reason we do without first going through a mental process that has the distinctive feel of deliberation characterized above. Only a highly tendentious (and implausible) account of action would rule out all such doings as anything but proper actions. My claim, then, is not that in any particular instance of action we cannot but deliberate. Indeed, I don’t even claim that in each such instance we do in fact deliberate. Rather, I claim that we cannot avoid deliberation altogether, that the deliberative project is one we cannot disengage from. In support of this claim, I can offer little more than introspection and a raw intuition (though not nothing more; I return to this shortly): Can you stop engaging in deliberation altogether? Can you just stop trying to make the decision it makes most sense to make? It seems to me I cannot. Even assuming I had strong reasons to stop deliberating, and even assuming I could, it seems to me I’d deliberate about whether or not to stop deliberating. Not deliberating at all is just not an option for me. Is it for you? Note that deliberation need not be about highly important matters. It is possible, I guess, for a person never to deliberate about her career choice (because she’s always just accepted that she’d follow in her father’s footsteps and become a doctor) or about major political decisions. The deliberation I claim is unavoidable can be much more mundane. It can involve decisions as simple as whether to spend the 143 afternoon working or playing15. Is it possible for you never to engage in deliberation even about such things? As I said, more than just introspection (and an un-argued-for generalization) is involved here. What is also involved is the intuition that we are just not like that. I, for one, cannot imagine a person who never deliberates. I have the strong intuition that this is not a possibility. Not only, mind you, that this is psychologically impossible for us, though it is that too; but also that, at least holding our constitution fixed, it is metaphysically necessary that we are deliberative. To the extent that you share this intuition, you’re committed – as I am – to the intrinsic indispensability of the deliberative project. Given the nature (and thinness) of the support for this claim offered thus far, it may be worth mentioning that the intuition and introspective judgment alluded to are by no means idiosyncratic. Many authors – varying in theoretical background as well as in metaethical or metanormative commitments – make similar points. I refer to some of them in a footnote16. This example is Korsgaard’s (1996, 94). Such points are often attributed to Kant, and often made by scholars influenced by Kant and sympathetic to his thinking. Perhaps one way of putting the point in the text somewhat Kantianly is that, as a matter of our essence, we have a will (and not just desires). Another may be as follows: We are essentially rational creatures. An example of a Kantian philosopher who emphasizes our deliberative, reflective, nature – and to whom I am indebted here – is Korsgaard (1996, e.g. at 967). Another example of a philosopher obviously inspired by Kant – though not as obviously Kantian as Korsgaard – is Velleman, who seems to endorse both the thesis of the essential unavoidability of deliberation and that of the instrumental indispensability of normative truths (or something very close to them) to deliberation when he writes (1989, 10): “… I locate an agent’s autonomy in his capacity for deliberation, and deliberation essentially involves value judgments.” But one need not be a Kantian – certainly not one who is loyal to Kant’s letter rather than merely inspired by selections from his writings – in order to appreciate the point made in the text. For similar points without obvious reliance on Kant, see Kim (1998, 85-6), Pettit and Smith (1993, 54; 15 16 144 Let me offer, though, something more by way of argument for the intrinsic indispensability of deliberation. Consider again the supermarket case, and suppose that, standing there in the cereals aisle, you become, for some reason, highly selfreflective. You are now thinking about the fact that you have no reason to choose one Mini-Wheats rather than any other. You know, of course, that soon enough you’re just going to pick one and that’ll be the end of it, and you may be impatient with yourself for failing to do so right away (we are almost always, it seems, impatient with others in such situations17). But you may very well feel some discomfort. You may feel – as I often have in such circumstances – that the situation is atypical in an important and somewhat unpleasant way. What, I now want to ask, best explains this feeling of discomfort? Why is it that, facing a situation in which mere picking is called for, we feel – when in a highly reflective mood, at least – that the situation is unpleasantly atypical? At least one explanation of this feeling is that we think of ourselves as essentially deliberative creatures, and that when we reflect on a situation where we have to act without deliberation, where we have temporarily to disengage from the deliberative project which is very much ours, we feel discomfort. I cannot think of a better explanation, and so I 1998, in passim), Rosati (1995, 61), Kolnai (1962, 215), Bond (1983, 60), Jacobs (1989, 1-2), Brink (1997, 266) and Railton (1992, 42-3). 17 Stephanie Beardsman drew my attention to our being less patient with others being slow about picking than with ourselves. Perhaps this is further evidence that the situation of picking is more problematic when viewed from the first-person perspective, because it is our conception of ourselves that is in some tension with what in the circumstances is called for. 145 tentatively suggest this as the best explanation of the described feeling of discomfort.18 For another phenomenon the best explanation of which may very well support the intrinsic indispensability of deliberation, consider the type of cases discussed by Velleman (1989) and Kim (1998): As you are making your way down the stairway from your study, you suddenly realize that you have no idea why you are going downstairs. Are you getting the day’s mail? Are you going to pick up the evening’s paper? To take a break from your work and listen to some music? To feed the cat? You aren’t sure, and your steps slow down – perhaps you will come to a complete stop. Perhaps, you will continue to proceed downstairs, hoping that you will remember your reason for going down. Or you see no point in continuing your descent and decide to return to your study. (Kim, 1998, 67) Such cases may be interesting for a number of reasons, at least one of which relevant here. What best explains your steps slowing down, and the distinctive phenomenological feel that accompanies this process, I want to suggest, is that you find it very hard to act for no (known) reason19, and that what best explains this is 18 As Derek Parfit pointed out to me, some may very well feel relieved when they find out that mere picking rather than deliberative choice is called for. This piece of psychological data is not, I think, incompatible with the point in the text: For isn’t this relief best seen as a result of the very atypicality mentioned in the text? In such cases we are given the opportunity to shed, as it were, our full responsibility as agents, and just pick. Thinking of this as a vacation of sorts is thus compatible with – indeed, it may support – the claim that typically, when not on vacation, we are deliberative, and that this is how we see ourselves. 19 What exactly do you find hard here – acting for no reason, or acting without knowing your reason? Suppose you find yourself – as the protagonist in the movie Memento constantly finds himself – doing something (not just beginning or preparing yourself to do it, as in Kim’s case, but actually doing it) without knowing your reason for doing it. How comforting would you find the thought – even one in the truth of which you’re absolutely confident – that you have thought these things through, and that there is a reason, albeit one unknown to you now, for your doing it? 146 that you think of yourself as essentially deliberative, essentially responsive to reasons in a reflective way20. These considerations are by no means conclusive. In each kind of case alternative explanations may be suggested, and if the argument is to survive criticism it must be shown that the explanations I suggest above are indeed the best ones. Nevertheless, I think what I’ve said should be at least suggestive of how committed we typically are to our being essentially deliberative, reflectively responsive to reasons. And, though this is still not enough to establish that we are indeed essentially deliberative (for the relevant commitment of ours may be ungrounded or erroneous), it nevertheless is sufficient to show the profound intuitiveness of this claim. And this, in turn, should suffice in order to place the burden on someone rejecting it to show why such an intuitive claim should indeed be rejected. This, it will be remembered, is all I set out to do in this (and the previous) section. And note, by the way, that these inferences to the best explanation support more than just the thesis of the intrinsic indispensability of deliberation. They support the conjunction of this thesis with the one defended in the previous section, namely, the thesis of the instrumental indispensability of normative truths for deliberation. For only if we cannot deliberate in a believed absence of reasons Velleman’s and Kim’s discussions (and perhaps also the feeling one gets from watching Memento) seem to suggest that not very much. For myself, I am unsure about this question. Be that as it may, in the text I only rely on the weaker claim, that thinking of yourself as acting for no reason at all is (almost) paralyzing. 20 Kim himself seems to suggest something along these lines (1998, 69). 147 can our taking ourselves to be essentially deliberative explain the relevant unease in the two examples described above. 3.4 Objections Some strong reason must be given, then, if we are to accept that deliberation is less than intrinsically indispensable, or that normative truths (or something sufficiently close to them) are less than instrumentally indispensable for deliberation. In this section, I try to anticipate attempts at giving such reasons. I suspect that this is not a full list of the relevant objections. But perhaps answering these objections can suggest how others are to be addressed. Of the fourteen objections that I discuss in this section, the first five attempt to uncover specific flaws in the argumentation of the previous three sections by arguing, in effect, that I have mischaracterized the relevant phenomenology or that I have taken it to imply things it does not imply. The next five objections (3.4.6 – 3.4.10) are attempts to give reason to believe that something must be wrong with the argument of the previous sections, because the conclusions it purportedly supports and the way in which it supports them entail unacceptable results. The last four objections (3.4.11 – 3.4.14) are more general attempts at discrediting the argumentation or the conclusions it is meant to support. Though distinct, the objections are not all completely independent, and some of the discussion may therefore be somewhat repetitive. 148 I do not distinguish here between objections to the intrinsic indispensability of deliberation and objections to the instrumental indispensability of normative truths for it, for a reason that has already been mentioned: Depending on how strong or how weak one’s understanding of deliberation is, one can get one of these two theses for cheap, at the price of making the other exceedingly hard to defend. Objections to my account of deliberation are thus best understood as objections to the conjunction of the two theses, and in what follows this is how I try to present them. 3.4.1 Do We Explicitly Invoke Normative Truths When Deliberating? Recall your deliberation about whether to apply to graduate school in philosophy or to join a law firm. The questions you were asking yourself were not – not all of them, certainly – put in (clearly) normative terms. You were wondering, for instance, which lifestyle suited you more, what occupation would make you happier, which would be more intellectually fulfilling. Though you may have also entertained distinctly normative thoughts (Is it important to make a political difference? Are my father’s expectations a reason to join a law firm? What does it make most sense for me to do?), this doesn’t seem to be a necessary feature of deliberation. Surely, the phenomenological feel alluded to is there already when you ask yourself questions of the first kind, and no argument has been given (nor will any be given) to support the claim that when deliberating you necessarily think to yourself, as it were, normative words. But then, so the objection goes, the 149 only questions you need to assume have answers when you deliberate are nonnormative ones, questions like which career-choice would make you happier. And if all of this is right, then deliberation does not after all require normative truths or belief in them.21 Notice that a person putting forward this objection need not deny the claim that deliberation in the face of a believed absence of reasons is impossible. All that she needs to argue is that not all reasons are normative truths. That you will find philosophy more intellectually fulfilling than practicing law is not a normative truth, but it is certainly a reason to apply to graduate school in philosophy rather than join a law firm22. The obvious thing to say here is that your reason – finding philosophy more fulfilling than practicing law – is not a normative truth, but that it is a reason is a normative truth23; and so, when, in deliberation, you take this to be a reason to apply to graduate school in philosophy, you commit yourself at least to one normative truth – namely, that this consideration is a reason, that it counts in favor of you so doing. Suppose you take the intellectual-fulfillment-reason to be conclusive, and you thereby end your deliberation by deciding to apply to graduate school in philosophy (or by forming the intention to do so, or by actually applying; for my purposes it doesn’t matter where exactly one takes deliberation to end). 21 I thank Mark Schroeder for pressing me on this point. Dancy (1995, 6) emphasizes that not all reasons are normative truths, and gives a similar example. 23 See, for instance, Scanlon (1998, 57). 22 150 Though you may have never thought to yourself “That doing philosophy will be much more intellectually fulfilling is a decisive reason to apply to graduate school in philosophy”, you nevertheless take it to be such a decisive reason. We can support the attribution of this implicit belief or commitment to you in the same way we support other attributions of similar attitudes: by noting that the attribution may explain your stopping deliberating, or forming the relevant intention, or whatever; by noting that if you then said “But I don’t take that to be a reason to do philosophy” we would be puzzled at the unintelligible conjunction of your behavior and proclamation; by noting that if asked at that point “Ah, so you take that to be a reason to apply to graduate school in philosophy?” you will most likely answer “Of course”, and it will feel like articulating a commitment you have already made, not like the making of a new one; and so on. Even before being prompted by such a question, then, you believe that that doing philosophy will be more intellectually fulfilling is a reason for pursuing philosophy, it counts in favor of so doing. And as already said, this is a normative claim. So, though your reason need not be a normative truth, by treating it as a reason you already commit yourself to a normative belief, namely, that the purported reason really is a reason. Deliberating without any normative beliefs is thus still impossible.24 So, just as according to a Humean account of action and deliberation, even though desires “fuel” deliberation, the deliberating agent need not think explicitly in terms of desire-satisfaction, so on my account of deliberation, even though normative beliefs “fuel” deliberation, the deliberating agent need not think explicitly in terms of such normative beliefs. I thank Stephanie Beardsman for drawing my attention to this analogy. 24 151 It is, of course, controversial what taking something to be a reason comes to, and my claim that it comes to a normative belief (implicit or otherwise) is not obviously true. I support it in chapter 4 (in section 4.3), when rejecting Noncognitivism. 3.4.2 Aren’t Your Desires (or Your Ends, or Your Identity) Sufficient? So far, though, desires have hardly been mentioned at all. And this may seem a severe flaw. For surely desires have a crucial role to play in the bringing about of actions, and so also in deliberation. Furthermore, it may be thought that desires are not merely some further factor that needs to be accounted for, but rather that once they are, there will no longer be any need for normative truths and belief in them. Desires, so this objection goes, guide deliberation and bring it to its conclusion. And if desires can do this work, normative truths and belief in them are not indispensable after all.25 It is no coincidence, of course, that desires have not so far been discussed. The discussion in this chapter presents a first-person-perspective, phenomenological, account of deliberation, and from this perspective desires are not as central as they purportedly are from a third-personal, explanatory, perspective26. For all that’s been said so far, desires may very well guide deliberation and bring it to its conclusion in one sense of “guiding” and 25 I thank Pete Graham for many helpful discussions on this and related points. This, I take it, is at least one point Pettit and Smith (1990) are making when they “background desires”. 26 152 “bringing”: The best explanation of why you will have deliberated as you did and why you will have stopped deliberating when and in the way that you did may very well invoke desires, perhaps even only desires (and some factual, nonnormative, beliefs). Nothing has been said to rule this out (though I’ll have to return to this point in section 3.4.11). And it is certainly possible (and indeed seems very plausible) that desires play a central role in bringing about actions that are not preceded by deliberation (the so-called appetitive desires and some actions they may help in causing are the examples that come to mind). Nevertheless, from your first-person-perspective as you deliberate about what to do, desires do not play that central a role. Your reasons – the considerations relevant to your deliberation from your point of view while deliberating – are not that you desire intellectual fulfillment or that you desire not to disappoint your father, but rather that pursuing philosophy will be intellectually fulfilling, and that abandoning a career in law will disappoint your father27. Had you been trying to predict your behavior, perhaps desires would have been as central as the objection suggests. But we already know that deliberation is importantly different from trying to predict one’s own behavior. From the deliberative perspective, then – the only Can’t desires enter the picture as part of an analysis of what it is to take something to be a reason? Perhaps they can, though I think they do not. But anyway, even if they do, this poses no threat to my argument in this chapter. Here I just want to argue for the instrumental indispensability of normative judgments for deliberation and for the intrinsic indispensability of deliberation. People who accept these claims but offer a desire-based account of accepting a normative judgment (noncognitivists, say, or other belief-internalists) are, as far as this point is concerned, on my side. They are on the other side regarding Robust Realism, of course, and so also regarding some parts of my argument for it, but not the part argued for here. I argue against such views in chapter 4. 27 153 perspective directly relevant for the discussion in this chapter, and indeed for my argument for Robust Realism – the role of desires is not all that central. Nevertheless, it may seem like desires do have a role to play in deliberation. It seems one can explicitly take one’s desires as reasons for action, as when one chooses an entrée from a menu “simply because this is what I want”. Now, such cases can be understood in more than one way – perhaps, for instance, the reason implicitly invoked is that I would enjoy this entrée more, not that I want it more28. But let me assume for now – with the person objecting to my argument – that in such cases we do explicitly take our desires as reasons for action. And perhaps at times some considerations one takes into account, considerations that do not invoke desires explicitly, do implicitly invoke desires, perhaps desires too common to be worth mentioning, even to oneself (like a desire for one’s own happiness). Can the account of deliberation presented here accommodate this (purported) role of desires? Now, one way one could go in addressing this worry, a way with impressive historical credentials, would be to give an account of desires that itself necessarily involves normative commitments on the part of the desirer29. If desires are themselves responses to reasons or to what are thought to be reasons, if we can 28 See the discussion in Scanlon (1998, 41-8) and the references in footnote 27 (on page 378). The idea goes back, of course, to Aristotle and today is often associated with the work of Davidson. Other contemporary writers who endorse an account of desires in this general spirit, are Platts (1980b), Scanlon (1998, 38), Dancy (2000, e.g. at 38) and Darwall (1983, chapter 6) (though Darwall only argues that the best way to make sense of the axioms of decision theory is to take preferences to be (or to entail) normative judgments; Darwall does not commit himself here in so many words to the thesis that preferences do indeed entail normative judgments). 29 154 only desire something we take to be good, or such that we have reason to have or do, then no role desires play in deliberation can threaten the deliberative indispensability of normative truths and belief in them. Indeed, desires can then help secure the indispensability of normative truths for deliberation – desires are indispensable for deliberation, normative truths or belief in them are indispensable for desires, and so, by the transitivity of indispensability, normative truths are indispensable for deliberation. I shall resist the temptation to reply to the objection in this way. Though some desires may very well be responses to reasons, and some desires may very well be caused by normative beliefs, I find the claim that all desires necessarily involve normative reasons or judgments highly implausible, for reasons I cannot adequately discuss here30. I would certainly not want my argument to hinge on this implausible claim. I therefore want to argue in a different way for the claim that desires do not render normative truths and belief in them deliberatively dispensable. Frankfurt’s (1971) unwilling addict, who desires his fix, but desires not to have this desire and (thus) doesn’t value his fix should be enough to raise suspicions regarding the purported necessary connection between desires and evaluative judgments. And Velleman’s (1992) discussion of the person who desires to do the bad thing precisely because it is bad should be enough to strengthen this suspicion. For some writers arguing against the purported necessary connection between desiring and, roughly, believing desirable, see Pettit and Smith (1993), Railton (1997, 65), Velleman (1989, 25; and his 1992), and Bond (1983; In Bond’s classification of four kinds of desires, it is only those of the fourth kind – reflective desires – which involve evaluative judgments). 30 155 Now, some cases of deliberation lend themselves to a desire-based reading less easily than others. In particular, cases of moral deliberation31, and cases of deliberating about what desires to have, cultivate, avoid and so on, seem like particularly hard cases for the desire-based account of deliberation. But perhaps the desire-theorist can somehow accommodate them, and perhaps – more importantly in our context – these particular cases of deliberation are not essentially unavoidable in the way that the deliberative project as a whole is (though I suspect that they are). Luckily, I don’t have to settle these matters here, because of a point already made in section 3.4.1: When concluding your deliberation because of a desire of yours, you commit yourself to the normative judgment that this desire of yours (or your having it, or something of this sort) is a relevant reason for you. Desires cannot, then, help you avoid a commitment to normative truths. Of course, desires may also lead to action in another, strictly causal, way, one that may bypass deliberation altogether. But this is not the case relevant here. Here, rather, we talk of cases where desires presumably settle deliberation (this is why they may be thought to render normative truths deliberatively dispensable). In these cases, though, by taking the relevant desire as reason you already commit yourself to a normative judgment.32 31 I thank Ernesto Garcia for insisting that moral deliberation is especially problematic here for the desire-theorist. 32 Nagel (1997), to whose discussion I am indebted here, emphasizes similar points: “And I would contend that either the question whether one should have a certain desire or the question whether, given that one has that desire, one should act on it, is always open to rational consideration.” (102- 156 The intuition underlying this point can be made clearer in the following way. As creatures which act on reasons, we have the ability – one we cannot fail to exercise, at least some of the time – to step back from the desires we find ourselves with, gain some reflective distance from them, treat them as merely desires we find ourselves with, and ask whether they give us reasons to perform the relevant action. When we exercise this ability, desires can no longer bring our deliberation to its conclusion. As the phenomenological evidence indicates rather clearly, I think, only a normative commitment can.33 3); “Once I see myself as the subject of certain desires, as well as the occupant of an objective situation, I still have to decide what to do, and that will include deciding what justificatory weight to give to those desires.” (109); “It is only when, instead of being pushed along by impressions, memories, impulses, desires, or whatever, one stops to ask “What should I do?” or “What should I believe?” that reasoning becomes possible – and, having become possible, becomes necessary. Having stopped the direct operation of impulse by interposing the possibility of decision, one can get one’s beliefs and actions into motion again only by thinking about what, in light of the circumstances, one should do.” (109) “It is not enough to find some higher order desires that one happens to have, to settle the matter: Such desires would have to be placed among the background conditions of decision along with everything else. Rather, even in the case of a purely selfinterested choice, one is seeking the right answer.” (110) I am not sure, but I think Scanlon’s discussion of desires and the claim that they lack “authority” (1998, 55) is also closely related to the point made in the text. 33 This idea is very Kantian. Interestingly, the idea may not be limited to Kant’s practical philosophy. In the Prolegomena, when addressing the (unstated) question of why we need the noumena in his metaphysical picture given that we know nothing about them, Kant says: “The world of sense contains merely appearances, which are not things in themselves; but the understanding must assume these latter ones, viz., noumena, because it knows the objects of experience to be mere appearances.” (section 59, my italics). At the risk of taking things out of context, I would suggest the following analogy: We need normative truths even if, viewed from a third-person-perspective, our desires suffice in order to cause our actions and then explain them, because, when deliberating, we know our desires are merely our desires. Be that as it may, the idea that the ability to step back from our desires and ask ourselves whether we should act on them is central for human agency and freedom is, though Kantian, not uniquely Kantian. Consider the following quote from Locke’s An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (Book II, Chapter 21, section 47): “… the mind having in most cases, as is evident in experience, a power to suspend the execution and satisfaction of any of its desires, and so all, one after another, is at liberty to consider the objects of them, examine them on all sides, and weight them with others. In this lies the liberty man has …” For a more recent statement of similar ideas, see Bond (1983, e.g. at 54, 60) (“If valuing is really nothing but wanting, then deliberative rationality is a delusion.” (ibid., 54)). 157 Notice that this reply generalizes nicely: Following the initial objection, the reply was put in terms of desires and their insufficiency, but it also applies to, for instance, an objection stated in terms of ends and instrumental reasoning.34 Can’t facts about what will best promote my given ends do all the deliberative work, thus rendering normative truths dispensable? No, because, first, some cases of deliberation (most notably, again, cases that involve moral considerations and cases in which you ask yourself what ends it makes most sense to pursue) are not as this objection seems to suggest they are; and second, because we are not satisfied with just taking our ends as given, we can’t avoid stepping back and viewing them as merely our ends35. Which is why, when concluding your deliberation because one of the options will better promote your ends (or a specific end), you already commit yourself to a normative judgment, namely, that this is a reason for you to choose the relevant option. An exactly analogous point can be made (and, has, I think, been made by Rosati (1995, 53-60)), in reply to similar suggestions put this time in terms of taking one’s identity or self (whatever exactly these are) as given36. By bringing your deliberation to its conclusion because of features of your practical identity, For some of these analogous objections, the first line of reply – rejected earlier in the text – may be more promising. Perhaps, as Korsgaard argues (1997, 250), “willing an end” necessarily involves a normative commitment of the kind that having a desire does not. Depending on what “willing an end” exactly comes to, this reply may be very close to the one I pursue in the text. 35 So, pace Aristotle (Eth. Nic., Book III, 1112b ), and with Kolnai (1962), deliberation is not merely of means. Of course, whether or not there is a real disagreement here with Aristotle depends on whether what he meant by “deliberation” (or rather by its Greek counterpart) is what I mean by it. Kolnai’s discussion suggests that it is. 36 For related points see also Gowans (2002) and Levin (1987, 180). 34 158 you commit yourself to these features of your identity being reasons for you to act. In deliberation, you cannot arbitrarily accept even your identity as given. Rather, you need a normative commitment, one that may involve your identity in an interesting sense, but that cannot be replaced by it. Desires, then, and ends, and identities, do not render normative truths and belief in them deliberatively dispensable. 3.4.3 Can We Not Be “Heroic Existentialists”? Perhaps, then, when deliberating we need normative truths. But can’t we generate these normative truths by performing what Korsgaard (1997, 251) labels a “heroic existentialist act”, in which “one … just take[s] one’s will at a certain moment to be normative, and commit[s] oneself forever to the end selected at that moment, without thinking that the end is in any way good …”? If we can, then my argument for Robust Realism fails. But the first thing to note here is that the argument of this chapter does not. Normative truths that we create in this way are – if there are any – still normative truths. Whether this existentialist or constructivist37 account of the kind of normative truths 37 There is some irony here. Korsgaard, though she says she has no conclusive argument against the heroic existentialist, ends up arguing against him. And her unwillingness to accept this view is central, it seems to me, to much of her theory of normativity. But her own, constructivist, view seems vulnerable to the same problem the heroic existentialist’s is. For she too seems committed to at least one radical, heroic, and so arbitrary, choice, the choice of a practical identity in which all reasons originate. I think this unearths a crucial inconsistency in Korsgaard’s account of normativity. I discuss Korsgaard’s view, and constructivism more generally, in section 4.5 (in chapter 4). 159 indispensable for deliberation is successful – and so, whether the argument for Robust Realism ultimately fails – is something to be evaluated in the next chapter. This is not enough, though, because the heroic existentialist act – if there can be such acts – can be considered a counterexample to my claim about the impossibility of deliberation in the face of a believed absence of reasons. If a choice as dramatic as that of what ends to endorse (or what identity to have, or what desires to have or to take as normative) for ever and ever can be made in the face of a believed absence of reasons, surely simpler cases of deliberation in such circumstances are possible. And if this is so, the argument for the instrumental indispensability of normative truths is undermined. But the heroic existentialist story, it seems to me, lacks any phenomenological plausibility38. Imagine yourself about to make the heroic existentialist choice of (say) what ends to pursue. At this point, so the story goes, there are no normative truths that apply to you, and you know as much. But then how are you supposed to make your existentialist, radical, choice? It seems the best you can do is just pick. But, if that’s what you do, this is no counterexample to the claim that in the believed absence of reasons deliberation is impossible, for deliberation is distinct from mere picking. So the objection must then become the claim that deliberation is not unavoidable, because of the possibility of heroic existentialist cases of picking. But remember that according to this story what you This, I take it, is one of the major theses put forward by Wiggins in his “Truth, Invention, and the Meaning of Life” (in his 1998, 87-137). 38 160 end up merely picking are your ends which, in future deliberation, you are supposed to take as normative, as reason-giving. Knowing that these ends were merely picked by you, that there was not (indeed, there could not have been) anything to be said for them, they could not have been chosen for a reason because they are the source of all your reasons, can you seriously take them as reasongiving in future deliberation? It seems to me clear that you cannot. This is again the point emphasized in section 3.4.2: When deliberating, we need more than merely the desires we find ourselves with. And we need more too than the ends we know we just happened to pick39. And if this is right, it means that mere picking cannot do the work of deliberation, and that the intrinsic indispensability of deliberation faces no danger here. The answer to the question “Can we not be heroic existentialists?” is therefore simply “No, we cannot.”. 3.4.4 Am I Conflating “What-Shall-I-Do” with “What-Should-I-Do” Questions? Asking oneself “What shall I do?” (in the sense of making a decision, not a prediction) is different from asking oneself “What should I do?”. As mentioned above, in cases of mere picking, you have to decide what to do, and so may ask yourself “What shall I do?” even when you’re convinced that there is nothing you 39 Similar points are made by Kolnai (1962, throughout the paper), Wiggins (1998, 89) and Korsgaard (1997, 251) (though she – for a reason not entirely clear to me – doesn’t think such considerations rule out the heroic existentialist story). 161 should do (rather than any of the other relevant alternatives), and you know that, and so you do not ask yourself “What should I do?”. And, as Bond (1983, 151) emphasizes, often after settling on an answer to the question “What should I do?” you still have to “decide what to do and do it, or do nothing at all.”. Furthermore, again as Bond (1983, 154) notes, we often wonder about should- or oughtquestions which are not possible candidates for shall-questions, as when we wonder about what we ought to have done in the past or about what others should do. This is all evidence that should-questions and shall-questions are different questions. But then the difference between them can be used in order to mount the following objection against my argument: Shall-questions, it may be argued, may very well be essentially unavoidable, and so answering them an intrinsically indispensable project. But, as cases of mere picking show, normative truths are not instrumentally indispensable for answering shall-questions. Normative truths may, however, be instrumentally indispensable for answering should-questions. But should-questions are not intrinsically indispensable. There is no one project, the objection continues, that satisfies both desiderata mentioned at the beginning of this chapter. When talking about deliberation in terms of “trying to make the decision it makes most sense for me to make”, the objection concludes, I was guilty of equivocation: There is no one way of understanding deliberation that makes both parts of the argument sound. 162 I agree, of course, that should-questions and shall-questions are different questions. And asking oneself the two kinds of question may have rather distinct phenomenologies. I agree also that answering shall-questions need not involve commitment to normative judgments. Where I disagree is regarding the claimed dispensability of asking oneself should-questions. The first thing to note here is that very often the relevant phenomenologies are not all that different, sometimes not even distinct. When deliberating about your career choice, have you been asking yourself a shall- or a should-question? It seems you’ve been asking both, without distinguishing the two. Phenomenologically speaking, then, the distinction is often blurred40. This is not a superficial feature of the phenomenology. In cases of deliberation – as opposed to cases of mere picking – the distinction between the two kinds of question partly collapses. The two questions are still distinct, but the way we answer the shall-question is often (partly) by answering the shouldquestion. Indeed, as rational and deliberative creatures, often we cannot answer the shall-question except by answering the should-question41. This claim, besides being loyal to the relevant phenomenology, is also the conclusion of a plausible inference to the best explanation. For what best explains the seriousness with 40 Perhaps this is why shall- and should-questions are often conflated. Richardson (1994, 41) writes, for instance: “This [the most general “ought”, the “ought” of practical reasoning] is the “ought” sans phrase …, which is involved when one decides what one ought to do – or, more simply, what to do.”. 41 So when Nagel (1986, 149) characterizes deliberation as “The … process … aimed at finding out what I should do”, and when Brink (1997, 274) says “To be a rational agent is to deliberate about what is best to do.”, perhaps they should be read not as conflating shall- and should-questions but rather as emphasizing the role the latter typically play in answering the former. 163 which the relevant questions are addressed, the willingness to put time and effort into answering them, the obvious attempt to get things right – what best explains these phenomena is that when we deliberate about what to do, we often deliberate about what we should do. And it is this kind of deliberation – the one that involves the attempt to answer should-questions – that, as I argued in section 3.3, is essentially unavoidable and so intrinsically indispensable. 3.4.5 Is Deliberation Illusory After All? Perhaps one may concede that the phenomenology of deliberation suggests a commitment to normative truths in roughly the way described in section 3.1-3.3, but nevertheless insist that it would be too quick to conclude from that to there being such truths. For the phenomenology of deliberation may very well deceive us – it may simply be illusory.42 It wouldn’t do, in replying to this objection, just to note the persistence of it seeming to us in deliberation that there are normative truths. We know from other illusions that they can be rather strongly immune to belief and knowledge. Consider the Mueller-Lyar illusion: Even after measuring the two line segments and concluding that they are equally long, still, when just looking at them, the one with the arrows pointing outwards seems longer. We know better, of course, and so the impression doesn’t penetrate our beliefs, but nor do our beliefs penetrate the impression – the line still seems longer. Similarly, it may be argued, even though 42 I thank Tom Nagel and Mark Schroeder for pressing me on this and related points. 164 we know (based on independent reasons, perhaps) that there are no normative truths, still when deliberating we cannot but feel as if there are. But this is an illusion, one we should isolate from our cognitive goings-on, in a way similar to our treatment of the Mueller-Lyar illusion.43 Treating the phenomenological discussion above as one would an illusion of this sort, one can then, it seems, in good conscience even engage in deliberation while still disbelieving in normative truths, without thereby being at all inconsistent, just as one can indulge in one’s impression that one of the two line segments is longer than the other without taking back one’s belief that they are equally long. This, it may now be argued, is a way of continuing to engage in deliberation, while avoiding the commitment to normative truths. Let me make, then, three points in reply to this objection. First, as it stands the objection is incomplete. For in order to accept a seeming – certainly a persistent one – as an illusion, we usually require (and justifiably so) some reason to mistrust the relevant seeming. In the Muller-Lyar illusion, we have very strong reason to believe that the line segments are equally long – we’ve measured them in favorable conditions, and perhaps we even have an explanation of why it is that, when just casually looked at, one seems longer. Without such reasons, of course, we would be justified (if mistaken) in trusting our impression of relative length. For another plausible example of a phenomenon of this kind, consider Sidgwick’s (1906, 28) distinction between moral and quasi-moral sentiment, the latter being what remains after you no longer believe a moral judgment you once held, but when you still can’t help being psychologically influenced by your previous moral beliefs. 43 165 But if this is so, in order to have a serious objection here to my argument what we need is more than is given by the objection as specified: What is needed is a positive reason – one that is at least reasonably strong – to reject what, when deliberating, seems to us to be the case. Again we are in the position I anticipated at the beginning of this chapter: The burden is now on those rejecting my view of deliberation to present a reason why deliberation cannot be what we feel it is. So the objection in this section is not so much an independent objection, as it is a promissory note, to be made good when some other objection (to my account of deliberation, or perhaps to other parts of my argument for Robust Realism, or perhaps even just to Robust Realism, the view itself) can be made to work. And the discussion in the rest of this section, and indeed the rest of this essay, is meant to suggest that this is not likely to happen. A second, closely related, point worth making here, is this: We have come to realize that the mere possibility of mistake doesn’t suffice to undermine warrant. The possibility that we are deceived when we (think we) perceive something is not sufficient to undermine the warrant such perceptual evidence confers on our perception-based beliefs. But this applies in the case of the phenomenological evidence I cite as well: The mere possibility of phenomenological illusion may undermine a claim to infallibility in such matters (and it goes without saying that no such claim is entailed by Robust Realism or by my argument for it), but it certainly does not suffice to undermine the warrant such phenomenological evidence confers on our commitment to normative truths. Here 166 too, then, what is needed is not the mere suspicion that things may have gone wrong and that the phenomenology may deceive us, but rather some reason to believe that this is indeed so. Third, and perhaps most importantly: Perhaps it may after all be possible to deliberate while at the same time viewing the commitments deliberation suggests as an illusion (or so at least let us assume for the sake of argument). Even if such deliberation is possible, though, so deliberating will inevitably change one’s view of one’s deliberation. No longer the search for answers to the normative questions one asks oneself, it will become a kind of intellectual indulgence, a mere game. Just like the casual look at the line segments of the Mueller-Lyar illusion changes its character once we are familiar with the illusion from an honest attempt to assess relative length to an act of intellectual (and perhaps perceptual) playfulness, so too deliberation changes if one comes to believe that the suggestion of a commitment to normative truths is a mere illusion. Indeed, the modified mental process is so different from deliberation sincerely engaged in that it may not even merit being called “deliberation”. But regardless of how it is best called, so viewing this mental process undermines whatever reason we had to find the deliberative project attractive in the first place. Recall now my account (following Colyvan) of instrumental indispensability: For something to be instrumentally indispensable for a project it is sufficient that it cannot be eliminated without defeating whatever reason we had to find that project attractive in the first place. So, even if it is true that people can engage in the deliberative project while avoiding a commitment to 167 normative truths (by treating deliberation as illusory), normative truths and belief in them are still indispensable for deliberation, because without them deliberation is – even if possible – utterly unattractive. For these reasons, then, the possibility of treating the phenomenology of deliberation as illusory does not, I think, pose a serious threat to my argument. 3.4.6 Have We Reached Bedrock? Justifications, we know, come to an end somewhere. Knowing that, you may, even while deliberating, be inspired by Wittgenstein’s (1953, section 217) comment: If I have exhausted the justifications I have reached bedrock, and my spade is turned. Then I am inclined to say: “This is simply what I do.” You may be tempted, then, to take a this-is-simply-what-I-do claim to settle your deliberation and bring it to its conclusion. And, if an obviously non-normative claim like “This is simply what I do” (isn’t it, after all, a part of Wittgenstein’s point that this claim is not normative?) can settle a deliberation, then normative truths are not indispensable for deliberation after all, and so something must be wrong with the arguments of sections 3.1 – 3.3. Part of my answer to this worry has already been given: If you take that this is simply what you do to settle the deliberation, you – being a rational creature – already commit yourself to it being a reason, and so to at least one normative truth. 168 Very often, though, you are not willing to commit yourself to this normative judgment, you are not willing to take that this is simply what you do to be any reason for doing it44. In the terms mentioned above, you treat this fact as merely a fact about what you do. But then what of where justifications come to an end? If you’re not willing to take that this is simply what you do to be a reason, what could possibly do the work Wittgenstein thinks this fact does? Justifications do come to an end somewhere. What the argument of this chapter (and indeed the rest of the argument for Robust Realism) establishes, though, is that they come to an end with normative truths. Faced with a sufficiently persistent skeptic, you may very well reach bedrock. But then, it seems to me, you will (and should) be inclined to say, not “This is simply what I do”, but rather “This is simply what I should do.”.45 3.4.7 Can’t We Deliberate in the Face of (Believed) Incomparability? Sometimes, it seems plausible to think, we have to choose between incomparable options. We have to choose between two alternatives, that is, when it is not the 44 In fairness to Wittgenstein it should be noted that the context the quote is taken from is the discussion of rule-following, and that the case of following a semantic or syntactical rule – the case Wittgenstein is primarily interested in in this context – seems to be a case where we would be perfectly happy to commit ourselves to this normative judgment: That this is simply how I (or perhaps we) use language does seem to be a good reason to use it in this way. I do not know whether what I say here has any interesting bearing on the rule-following problem or on what Wittgenstein says about it. Indeed, as Cavell (1990) emphasizes, Wittgenstein only notes that he is inclined to say “This is simply what I do” – he stops short of actually saying so. So perhaps Wittgenstein could agree with what I say in the text. I am grateful to Tom Nagel for this reference (also see Nagel, 1997, 48). 45 Nagel (1997, 106) makes, I think, a very similar point when he says: “Only a justification can bring the request for justification to an end.” And earlier in the book (49), he makes an analogous point about mathematics, explicitly referring to Wittgenstein’s remark. 169 case that the first is (all-things-considered) better than the second, nor is it the case that the second is better than the first, nor is it the case that the two are just as good (nor does any other positive comparative relation, if any exist, hold between them). And rather often, it seems, we know as much. But coming to realize that two alternatives we are considering are incomparable, it doesn’t seem like we stop deliberating. And this shows, it seems, that we can deliberate in a believed absence of reasons, and so that the argument of sections 3.1 – 3.3 fails. Now, incomparability is a controversial issue, and opinions about it differ. It is not uncontroversial even that the phenomenon exists46. But I want to note here how, if it does, and if we nevertheless deliberate in the face of believed incomparability, my view of deliberation can accommodate this data.47 One thing that can serve as a reply here has already been mentioned: Just like in the case of perfectly balanced reasons, our continuing to deliberate may betray inconsistency in our belief (we believe that there is no all-things-considered reason, but also that there is) or our lack of confidence in the no-all-thingsconsidered-reason-judgment; so too our continuing to deliberate in the face of believed incomparability may betray an analogous inconsistency or lack of confidence. I want to mention here, though, a further possible reply (one that may also be considered a fall-back position regarding the case of perfectly balanced 46 For discussion and a survey of some of the relevant literature, see Chang (1997). The points that follow apply also, mutatis mutandis, to deliberation in the face of (believed) indeterminacy. 47 170 reasons). It may be argued that deliberation does not require all-things-considered judgments or reasons, but rather that prima facie reasons suffice for deliberation. According to this suggestion, deliberation is still thought of as an attempt to eliminate arbitrariness, and so reasons are indeed indispensable for deliberation, but so long as there are reasons – considerations counting for and against the relevant alternatives – deliberation is possible, even if there is no (unique) solution to the problem we face in deliberation. It is important to note here that this suggestion is not committed to the possibility of a rational, justified, choice in such cases. Whether such choice is possible is yet another controversial issue I would prefer not to address here48. But whether or not justified choice in such circumstances is possible, deliberation may be. More may very well be necessary for justified choice than for deliberation. An analogy may help to make my point clearer. Intentional action, it is often thought, is action for reasons. When weak-willed, we intentionally act contrary to our own judgment about reasons. Given that intentional action is action for reasons, it is hard to see, then, how akrasia is possible. One influential account of akrasia thus begins by noticing that action can be done for reasons, and so intentional, even when it is not done for the (perceived) greater reason 49. Being done for any reason at all suffices for the intentionality of the action. Regardless of the merits of such a view of akrasia and action, I want to use it as a structural 48 49 See Chang (1997, 10-13) for discussion and some relevant references. This, I take it, is Davidson’s (1970) view, seriously oversimplified. 171 analogue for the suggestion regarding the relation between deliberation and reasons: According to this suggestion, deliberation requires, not all-thingsconsidered reasons, but simply reasons, just like intentional action requires (according to this view of akrasia) not being done for the greatest reason, but just being done for reasons50. If so, then deliberation in the face of believed incomparability poses no threat to the indispensability of reasons for deliberation. For even if a situation where two incomparable values or reasons pull in opposite directions is one where there is no all-things-considered reason either way, it is not a situation where reasons are absent. And given their existence, that deliberation in such cases is possible is no counterexample to reasons being instrumentally indispensable for deliberation. 3.4.8 Don’t Antirealists Deliberate? Not everyone is a realist about normativity. Certainly, not everyone is a robust realist. Now, I have argued that deliberation is essentially unavoidable, and that a commitment to normative truths is indispensable for deliberation. And eventually (after rejecting the alternatives in chapter 4) I will have argued that irreducibly normative truths are indispensable for deliberation. But then the existence – and In Davidson’s philosophy of action, “reasons” are plausibly understood as motivating reasons, whereas in this essay I talk of normative reasons being deliberatively indispensable. But this difference – important though it is in many contexts – does not undermine, I think, the structural analogy drawn in the text. 50 172 abundance – of people who reject Robust Realism (for now, I’ll call them antirealists) can give rise to the following objection, best presented in the form of a dilemma51. Either antirealists deliberate, or they do not. If they do, then, given that they don’t believe in normative truths, normative truths are not instrumentally indispensable for deliberation. If they do not deliberate, then, given that they are just as much persons or agents as the best of realists are, deliberation is not essentially unavoidable. Either way, the objection concludes, my argument fails. The existence of antirealists (mind you – even the possible existence of antirealists would suffice here) shows that there is no way of giving an account of deliberation that satisfies both desiderata guiding the discussion in this chapter. The way out of the dilemma is to attribute to antirealists inconsistent commitments. I take antirealists’ on their word regarding their belief that there are no normative truths. But their deliberation commits them also to there being some such truths. The case need not be – though it certainly can be – one in which, to paraphrase Railton (1997, 63), antirealists “are actually kidding themselves. Their deliberation and action reveal their nihilism to be no more than a posture.”. They may genuinely believe their antirealism. But their deliberation (and perhaps, though less likely, also their action) reveals not necessarily the insincerity of their antirealism, but rather that they are also committed to there being some decision it 51 This objection and objections very close to it have been pressed upon me by Hartry Field, Derek Parfit and Mark Schroeder. 173 makes best sense for them to make. From this realism follows. And so antirealists are inconsistent. Consider the analogy with explanation again. If the argumentation of the previous chapter is sound, then by inferring to the best explanation you commit yourself to the loveliness, or explanation-friendliness, of the universe. Of course, some may believe that the universe is not lovely, or that even if it is we cannot know as much. If, however, they continue to infer to the best explanation, there is at least prima facie reason to attribute to them inconsistent commitments. Similarly, people who accept the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument for mathematical Platonism, believe that nominalists who nevertheless accept current scientific theories are committed – inconsistently – both to the existence of mathematical objects and to its denial52. As these examples show, it is not uncommon in philosophy that one attributes to rival theories mistaken views of what even those holding them do (explain, deliberate, perceive, remember, and so on), nor is it uncommon, consequently, to attribute to rival theories inconsistent commitments53. The fact that I have to attribute such mistakes and inconsistencies to antirealists should not, then, count strongly against Robust Realism or my argument supporting it. 52 53 See, e.g., Putnam (1971, 347). I thank Tom Nagel for helping me see this point clearly. 174 3.4.9 What Would We Have Done Had We Found Out that There Are No Normative Truths? Suppose God whispered in your ear that there are no normative truths. Another dilemma then threatens: Either you will thereby stop deliberating, or you will not. If you do, deliberation is not essentially unavoidable. If you do not, normative truths (or belief in them) are not indispensable for deliberation. Either way, then, my argument fails54. If I am right and there are (irreducibly) normative truths, we cannot come to know or find out that there aren’t any, because “knowing” and “finding out” are success terms that imply truth. Similarly, if God is supposed to be perfectly reliable, the hypothetical situation in which the dilemma arises is impossible. So, in order to avoid begging the question against me, the objection should be rephrased. Suppose, then, that an extremely (but not necessarily perfectly) reliable source whispered in your ear that there are no normative truths, and that you thereby came to believe that there aren’t. The dilemma arises as before. Questioning the possibility of the hypothesis no longer seems plausible: Surely a reliable source may be mistaken, and surely I can come to believe that there are no normative truths. (Though, appreciating the strength of my argument for Robust Realism, one of the things that I may do when that source tells me there are no normative truths is come to think she is not as reliable as I had previously thought, or that this is one of the rare occasions on which she is wrong; in this 54 For this objection and for much helpful discussion regarding it I am indebted to Derek Parfit. 175 respect, the situation is like one in which an extremely reliable source whispers in your ear that there is a largest prime.) Nevertheless, there is, I think, a way out of this dilemma. Indeed, it is the very same way taken in reply to the previous objection. For, having come to believe that there are no normative truths, I have become an antirealist, and my deliberation can then be accounted for as in the previous section. I can still deliberate (indeed, I still cannot avoid deliberating), and this shows that I am still committed to normative truths. Convinced by the reliable source, though, I also believe that there aren’t any. And so I am guilty of inconsistent commitments. 3.4.10 Does the Argument Prove Too Much? A Quick Note on Freedom There may be some reason for concern regarding the strength of my argument (in this and other chapters). For it may seem to prove too much, and, if it does, this is evidence that it is not successful after all. In particular, it may seem that my argument – or one closely analogous to it – can be used in order to support the claim that we are incompatibilistically free. The argument runs as follows: It only makes sense for you to deliberate – to try to decide as it makes most sense for you to decide – if you can (or at least believe you can) decide as it makes sense for you to decide, and if you likewise can make the wrong decision. Otherwise, if it is already determined that you’re going to make the right (or wrong) decision, deliberation seems futile. So, if deliberation is intrinsically unavoidable, and if incompatibilist freedom (or belief 176 in it) is indispensable for deliberation, this is all the justification we need for belief in incompatibilist freedom – or so, at least, I seem to be committed to saying. Now, the first thing I want to say regarding this worry is that it is not completely clear to me that if my argument proves this much, it will have proved too much. Indeed, something along these lines may be what Kant had in mind when writing that “we act under the idea of freedom”55 and when arguing for freedom as a postulate of practical reason56 – a line of argument that, as noted in chapter 2, I find highly attractive, and that inspires much of my own57. More recently, too, there has been some interest in the questions of whether determinists can sincerely deliberate, and what follows regarding freedom if they cannot58. Still, I do not want to commit myself here to any position regarding freedom, and so I want to note that my argument falls short of committing me to the soundness of an analogous argument regarding freedom. I am committed, of course, to the following conditional: If incompatibilist freedom (or belief in it) is indispensable for deliberation, we are justified in believing we’re incompatibilistically free. But nothing in my argument commits me to the antecedent of this conditional, that is, to the relevant indispensability premise. For all I say here, it may well be that there is some other – compatibilist – way of accounting for whatever by way of freedom, if anything, is required for 55 Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (4:448). In numerous texts, but most elaborately, perhaps, in the Second Critique (e.g. 5:132-3). 57 The position and argument Pettit and Smith (1998) put forward regarding freedom closely resemble the Kantian argument referred to in the text. And a similar argument is suggested also by Korsgaard (1996, 96) and Nagel (1997, 115). 58 See, for instance, Taylor (1966, chapter 12). 56 177 deliberation59. If there is such a possible account, incompatibilist freedom is not indispensable for deliberation. And, indeed, much of the discussion of freedom and determinism can be understood as trying to support or reject exactly this indispensability premise.60 Leaving this example, then, and returning to the general worry about proving too much: It seems to me that the intrinsic indispensability of a project is not very easily established; nor is the instrumental indispensability of some thesis to an intrinsically indispensable project. If this is right, and in the absence of other examples, the concern about proving too much is not too worrying. 3.4.11 What Exactly is Indispensable? My argument for the deliberative indispensability of normative truths, it may be said, only supports – at most – another conclusion, one that does not suffice for my arch-argument for Robust Realism. For, the objection goes, all that is indispensable for deliberation is that I believe that there is a decision it makes most sense for me to make (or that some possible decisions make more sense than 59 Pete Graham suggested to me a very different line. According to him, it is determinism (or something very close to it) that may be deliberatively indispensable, because, roughly, deliberation presupposes that one’s decision is going to have real effects in the world, and that one’s decision is not random. As I’m not committing myself to any view regarding freedom, I am exempt, I think, from discussing this very interesting suggestion. 60 Suppose the indispensability premise in the case of freedom can be supported, but that – as is surely epistemically possible – we come across some overwhelmingly strong scientific evidence that we are not after all incompatibilistically free. What then? In such an unfortunate case we would have to conclude that deliberation is illusory after all. The mentioned scientific evidence would be the reason we need in order to support such a judgment – the kind of reason we lack, and perhaps cannot possibly have, in the case of the commitment to normative truths (as I argued in section 3.4.5 above). I thank Tom Nagel for discussions of this point. 178 others); it is not indispensable for there to be such a decision. And so, all that is indispensable is the belief in normative truths, not the normative truths themselves. But this is not enough for my argument for Robust Realism to go through. And note that this may be thought to distinguish my argument from arguments from explanatory indispensability, for what is indispensable for our scientific theories is, it may be argued, the electrons (and perhaps also numbers) themselves, not merely the belief in them.61 I agree that it is the belief in normative truths, not the normative truths themselves, that is directly indispensable for deliberation. But from this it does not follow that normative truths are not indispensable. Though they are not what is directly indispensable, they may be – and in fact, I think, they are – indirectly indispensable for deliberation. And this indispensability suffices for my argument to go through.62 Remember that the argument so far has been first-personal: I have left third-personal questions of explanation behind (though I briefly return to them in section 3.4.12), and focused on the phenomenological character of deliberation. It is this perspective from which my indispensability argument is supposed to work. With this in mind, the gap between the indispensability of the belief in normative truths and the indispensability of the normative truths themselves can, I think, be bridged. The situation is reminiscent of Moore’s Paradox: Though there is no 61 For this and related objections I am indebted to Cian Dorr, Ernesto Garcia, Josh Schechter and Brad Skow. 62 The discussion that follows draws on Resnik (1995) and on Sayre-McCord (2001, 357). 179 incoherence in acknowledging someone else’s commitment to something being the case while at the same time claiming that it is not the case, incoherence (of some kind; more on this shortly) is involved in acknowledging one’s own commitment to something being the case while at the same time denying that it is the case. The commitment to normative truths, the belief in them, has been shown (so we at least assume at this stage) to be indispensable to a project of yours that is essentially unavoidable. Though your having this commitment doesn’t entail, of course, its truth, you are nevertheless not in a position to acknowledge the commitment and still deny its truth. Doing so would involve you in some sort of incoherence. From your own perspective, then, once you’ve acknowledged the deliberative indispensability of normative beliefs, you have already – on pain of incoherence – acknowledged the deliberative indispensability of the normative truths themselves. Now, the kind of incoherence is not strictly speaking logical. And, as the reference to Moore’s Paradox suggests, there seems to be something pragmatic both about the relevant kind of incoherence and, consequently, also about the justification of the move from the indispensability of the belief to the indispensability of the normative truths believed. But, given the discussion in chapter 2 of the relations between pragmatic and epistemic justification in general and as regarding indispensability arguments in particular, I take this to be unproblematic63. 63 Resnik (1995) nowhere explicitly mentions the distinction between pragmatic and epistemic justification, and his discussion, it seems to me, is thus somewhat confused here. Without 180 Even if my argument does support the (indirect) indispensability of the normative truths themselves, however, it may be thought that the disanalogy with arguments from explanatory indispensability remains. For mine at least involves one extra step, one that may detract from its plausibility, thus making it less plausible than paradigmatic (explanatory) indispensability arguments. It is therefore interesting to note that arguments from explanatory indispensability may very well be in a relevantly similar situation, and that no disanalogy need be involved. Field (1989, 14), Resnik (1995, 172) and Colyvan (2001, 10, footnote 18), for instance, when characterizing indispensability arguments generally (though with the mathematical case primarily in mind) make it clear – rightly, I think – that what is directly indispensable for doing science or for explaining is the belief in mathematical objects, the willingness to quantify over them, and so on64. The mathematical objects themselves, or the mathematical truths purportedly about them, are therefore, much like normative truths, only indirectly indispensable. Now, Field does not, as far as I know, explicitly address the need to move from the indispensability of the belief to the indispensability of what is supplying the kind of argument I try to supply in chapter 2, he moves freely from pragmatically justifying belief in mathematical entities (as a result of a pragmatic indispensability argument) to taking the belief to have been epistemically justified. 64 Here, for instance, is a quote from Field (1989, 14): “An indispensability argument is an argument that we should believe a certain claim (for instance, a claim asserting the existence of a certain kind of entity) because doing so is indispensable for certain purposes (which the argument then details).” (Italics added). 181 believed or of the relevant entities65, and Colyvan, who does explicitly mention the move (2001, 10, footnote 18), nevertheless fails to justify it or to acknowledge that it needs justification. But Resnik does address this difficulty more seriously, and his way of justifying this move is the one on which mine is modeled. 3.4.12 Does Deliberation Incur Explanatory Commitments? So far I have been careful not to commit myself to any relevant explanatory claims: I repeatedly emphasized that my argument relies on the deliberative, not explanatory, role of normative truths. And I implied, it seems, that I can remain largely neutral on explanatory questions. But, it may now be argued, the distinction between the deliberative and the explanatory (or between the first- and third-personal) is not as clean-cut as I seem to have been assuming. The deliberative role of normative truths and belief in them, so the argument may go, presupposes or entails an explanatory role for these truths and beliefs. The deliberative stance thus incorporates explanatory requirements, and it may be important to spell out these commitments, not least because if my understanding of deliberation and normativity makes them implausible, this makes it highly suspicious. Many share the intuition (for that is what it typically is; very rarely is an argument offered in support of it) that the role reasons play in deliberation requires 65 This is not necessarily a flaw, as Field ends up rejecting the argument by rejecting the indispensability premise. He can be understood as granting the legitimacy of the relevant move for the sake of argument. 182 that they play an explanatory role as well. Consider, for instance, the following quote from Raz (1975,16): “Reasons can be used for guiding and evaluating only because they can also be used in explanation…”. In order to make a similar point intuitively plausible, Dancy (2000, 171) tells the following story: If we said to the agent: ‘You can tell us as often as you like what your reason was for doing what you did, but we know in advance that that reason can never be the reason why you did it’, I think he would feel rightly insulted – and this even though we are not disputing the truth of what he tells us. The thought seems to be that unless the consideration you took to be reason-giving in your deliberation (that is, your reason for doing what you did) also plays an important role in explaining your action (and is thus the reason why you did it), the explanation is somehow unfit for the actions of an agent. And so, if, when deliberating, you are to take yourself and your deliberation seriously, you must believe that the considerations you take to be reason-giving will also play a role in explaining your action66. If this is so, then by deliberating you already incur an explanatory commitment. And, if my account of deliberation and normativity is roughly right, this commitment is rather problematic, one according to which normative reasons (and maybe also normative truths, facts and properties) play a role in explaining actions67. Regardless of just how plausible this explanatory commitment is, however, it is an explanatory commitment the deliberating agent 66 For similar points, see Williams (1980, 102), Kim (1998, 77), and Darwall (1992, 166-7). Dancy (2000) endorses this commitment, and draws far-reaching conclusions from it regarding the nature of normative as well as motivating reasons. For my purposes here, this part of Dancy’s theory can safely be ignored. 67 183 incurs, and so, the objection concludes, the deliberative is not independent of the explanatory as I assume. Another way of making what I think is essentially the same point is as follows: In understanding the world we seek not just a third-personal understanding, nor merely a first-personal one. One of the challenges we face – according to Nagel’s The View From Nowhere (1986), a central challenge we face – is that of achieving an integrated understanding, one with room in it for both third- and first-personal perspectives. I have been emphasizing the first-personperspective. But in my enthusiasm I have blocked any chance of integrating it with a plausible third-personal, explanatory, perspective. At a first glance, it may not be clear how any of this is relevant for my argument. For having been insulted in the way Dancy suggests in the passage quoted above, you still have to decide what to do, and so – unless it is a case of mere picking – you still deliberate. And it doesn’t seem that Dancy’s insult is going to give you any reason to do one thing rather than another, or nothing at all, or even just to stop deliberating. The explanatory insult Dancy considers and the tension between the first- and third-personal in these circumstances are, then, strictly speaking irrelevant for your deliberation. But this does not render them irrelevant for my argument. If we have reason to believe that there are necessary ties of the sort alluded to between deliberation and explanation, we may extract from them adequacy constraints on an account of deliberation. If the account of deliberation developed in this chapter 184 undermined such connections with explanation, this may then be reason to reject it, and my argument for Robust Realism along with it. So more needs to be said in reply to this objection. I want to make here, then, two related points. I have been focusing, to repeat, on the first-personal role reasons play in deliberation. This is no coincidence, of course – I think this is their primary role, this is what we primarily need them for. Now, if this is so, the deliberative role of reasons may very well be privileged in another way. For even if there are necessary connections of the relevant kind between deliberation and explanation, it may be better to treat them as adequacy constraints on an account of explanation rather than of deliberation. This, then, is my first point: If deliberation has the kind of primacy I attribute to it, it seems reasonable to start with an account of deliberation, and then – if there are necessary connections between deliberation and explanation – tailor our account of explanation to fit our account of deliberation, and not the other way around.68 Nevertheless, if the adequacy constraints thus arrived at for an account of explanation had been extremely unreasonable, still my account of deliberation would have been in danger. My second point here, then, is that these constraints need not be unreasonable at all. Let me hint at a relevant argument that I hope to develop in detail elsewhere. Given a sufficiently complex and plausible account of acting for a reason, the explanatory commitments incurred in deliberation because 68 That we should constrain our explanations to allow for the first-personal is a major theme in Nagel’s The View from Nowhere (1986). His discussion is especially close to my context here on page 142. 185 of the supposed necessary connections between deliberative and explanatory reasons need not be at all implausible. It is, I think, sufficient for A to have Φed for reason R that the belief that R is indeed a reason for Φing plays an appropriate causal role in the bringing about of A’s Φing. If this is right, then the explanatory commitment incurred by the deliberating agent can be rather easily vindicated, and need not involve the explanatory role of the normative truths themselves (unless, of course, normative beliefs are best explained by normative truths; this is the first strategy of coping with Harman’s Challenge, described and tentatively rejected in chapter 1). 3.4.13 Had We Not Been Deliberative, Would There Have Been Normative Truths? The first-personal character of my argument for normative truths may give rise to the following worry: Had our first-personal perspective been very different, had we not been deliberative, would there have been any normative truths? If not, it would seem to follow that the existence of normative truths is surprisingly contingent, and – more disturbingly – contingent on the wrong thing, on our nature. (Such dependence is going to be rejected as unacceptable in chapter 4, because, while deliberating, we often rightly think even of our nature as merely our nature. If my argument for Robust Realism yields a similar dependence, then, it seems to undermine itself.) 186 Now, if the argument of section 3.3 above is right, we are (metaphysically) necessarily deliberative. The counterfactual “Had we not been deliberative, there would not have been any normative truths” – just like “Had we not been deliberative, there would still be normative truths” – thus has a metaphysically impossible antecedent69. As it is hard to make sense of such counterfactuals and to evaluate them for truth, it is fortunate that we can state the relevant worry without them. That we exist is, of course, perfectly contingent, so we should consider the counterfactual “Had there been no deliberative creatures, there would be no normative truths”. Does it follow from my argument? If so, is it objectionable? Some (e.g. Velleman, 2000a, e.g. at 180) assume that reasons only apply to agents, and so, it seems, that in a possible world without agents there are no reasons. Because of the intimate connection between (normative) reasons and normative truths, this view may seem to imply that the counterfactual above is true. If this is so, and if my view entails the mentioned counterfactual, this is then no objection to it. I should say, though, that I find this line intuitively problematic, as I would like to say that some reasons – certainly some normative judgments – apply even to creatures that cannot act for reasons. I would like, for instance, to be able to say that the cat in front of me has a very good reason not to run into heavy traffic, and I would like to be able to mean it literally (though I know this is a controversial view, and I do not intend to defend it here, nor am I sure that I can). I want to note, then, that I need not commit myself to the mentioned counterfactual. 69 Holding our constitution fixed, at least. I ignore this qualification in what follows. 187 Let me briefly repeat, then, a point made in section 2.A.3 (in chapter 2). On my account, the dependence on our deliberative nature is epistemological, not metaphysical. Electrons would have existed even had there been no explanatory creatures around; it’s just that then there (presumably) would have been no creature with reason to believe in electrons. Similarly, normative truths would have existed even had there been no deliberative creatures; it’s just that then there would have been no creature with reason to believe in normative truths. 3.4.14 Am I Committed to Dummettean Antirealism? It only makes sense to deliberate, to try to make the decision it makes most sense for one to make, if there is a decision it makes most sense for one to make. Similarly, it seems, it only makes sense to deliberate if one can find out which decision is the one it makes most sense for one to make. Inaccessible normative truths are deliberatively irrelevant. If my argument, here and in chapter 2, establishes the existence of normative truths, then, can’t a similar argument be constructed in support of the claim that normative truths are (necessarily) epistemically accessible? If so, I am committed to Dummettean antirealism, of which this is the characteristic claim70. How bad is it if this is so? Despite the terms (my “Robust Realism” and Dummett’s “antirealism”), no inconsistency need be involved. As has often been 70 See, for instance, Dummett (1978, 146), Haldane and Wright (1993b, 4). 188 noted71, it is not at all clear that what Dummett means by “antirealism” is incompatible with traditional realist views. Indeed, among philosophers whose views on normativity and morality are considered paradigmatically realist, one can find endorsements of the necessary accessibility of normative truths72. If my argument does commit me to Dummettean antirealism, then, this is no obvious refutation of my view. Nevertheless, I would rather avoid such a commitment, because it seems to me that accepting the (necessary) epistemic accessibility of normative truths makes one vulnerable to the following – less than conclusive, but still threatening – argument: That there can be no unknowable normative truths calls, it seems, for explanation73, and the most straightforward explanations are all in antirealist (not just Dummettean antirealist; really antirealist), or at least anti-robust-realist, terms. If, for instance, normative truths are somehow invented, created, or constructed by us, this would seem the beginning of a promising explanation of why it is that there can be no unknowable normative truths. Similarly, if there are no normative truths, and all we do when we utter normative judgments is express some noncognitive attitude, again it seems less surprising that there are no inaccessible 71 For this claim, as well as a critical evaluation of it, see Haldane and Wright (1993b, 5-6). See Dancy (2000, 57-9, 65-6), Kim (1998, 78-81), Bond (1983, 65) and Nagel (1986, 139). 73 In conversation, Crispin Wright rejected this claim; indeed, he thinks that – for the most general reasons that have to do with concept acquisition and language mastery – it is inaccessibility that calls, when present, for explanation, not accessibility (see Wright, 1992, 151). If this is so, Dummettean antirealism poses no threat to Robust Realism and my argument for it (not this threat, at any rate). I cannot, of course, seriously discuss Wright’s suggestion here. By proceeding to show in the text that I am not committed to Dummettean antirealism, I show that even if Wright is mistaken, my argument is in the clear. 72 189 normative truths (or even inaccessible truths*, where truths* are the noncognitivistically respectable surrogates for truths). Or, if normative truths are reducible to introspection-transparent facts about one’s motivation, it again seems that their necessary accessibility is not too mysterious. It is hard to see, though, how the necessary accessibility of normative truths can be explained in robust realist terms. Perhaps there is such an explanation after all; I cannot rule out this possibility. But I remain suspicious, and so I want to note how I can avoid the commitment to the necessary accessibility of normative truths. Consider the case of explanation again. Most people are Dummettean realists about scientific facts. They think, in other words, that it is quite possible for there to be an unknown, even unknowable, fact of the matter regarding, say, the primitive particles of the universe. There doesn’t seem to be anything in this belief to undermine the endeavor to come up with better and more powerful explanations of many phenomena. For all scientists know, they may never be able to explain a phenomenon they’re trying to explain, because the relevant explanans may be epistemically inaccessible. But, unless they know (or are reasonably confident) that this is so, the mere worry that it might be does not render the scientific-explanatory project futile. Furthermore, the scientific-explanatory project can easily survive the belief that the explanans of a specific phenomenon is inaccessible, for there may be other phenomena the explanans of which is accessible, and so merits being looked for. 190 Analogously, then, so long as you do not know (or are reasonably confident) that the normative truth relevant for your deliberation – that all-thingsconsidered it makes sense for you to pursue graduate studies in philosophy, say – is inaccessible, the mere worry that it might be does not render your deliberation futile. And, even if that normative truth is inaccessible (and so deliberatively irrelevant), others may very well be accessible, and so the deliberative project as a whole has not been rendered useless. I can therefore see no argument from the deliberative indispensability of the normative to Dummettean antirealism regarding it. Still, while deliberating about a specific question, aren’t you at least methodologically justified in assuming that the relevant normative truth is accessible? It seems to me you are, and so you are justified in either believing that it is accessible, or in abandoning the specific deliberation74. As specific cases of deliberation are not unavoidable, again the thesis of the necessary accessibility of normative truths doesn’t follow. Deliberation as a whole is, however, unavoidable. And so I think you (and I) are committed to the following thesis: It is not the case that all normative truths are epistemically inaccessible. And we may even be committed to this thesis being true as a matter of necessity. This result falls short of Dummettean antirealism, but it is significant nevertheless. And Robust Realism still faces the challenge, it seems to me, of explaining how it is that, in all possible 74 Beliefs and their justification come in degrees, and the sentence in the text should be qualified accordingly: The less you’re justified in believing that the relevant normative truth is accessible, the less you’re justified in continuing deliberating. 191 worlds (in which there are deliberators), at least some of the normative realm is epistemically accessible. But this explanatory challenge seems more manageable than the one Dummettean antirealism – if true – poses. These objections, I conclude, do not give strong enough reason to reject the account of deliberation its phenomenology suggests. 3.5 Kindred Spirits In this section I briefly consider two suggestions to be found in the literature, suggestions close to mine in crucial respects. I cannot here discuss them in detail: All I want to do is explain why it is that I find my own suggestion more promising as (a part of) an argument for Robust Realism. 3.5.1 Action It is a constraint on the understanding of action that it be distinct from mere bodily movement (indeed, satisfying this constraint may be considered the central challenge philosophers of action face)75. At least one attempt to satisfy this constraint – one enjoying both intuitive plausibility and some historical credentials – is by noting, very roughly, that action is not merely caused, but rather (also) performed for reasons. Now, action is at the very least possible, and quite 75 The classic statement of the challenge this constraint poses is to be found in Wittgenstein (1953, sec. 621): “What is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm?”. 192 plausibly actual too. So there are reasons for which it can be performed. And so there are normative truths.76 Circumventing deliberation altogether, this argument nevertheless seems to support metanormative realism (though not Robust Realism; more on this shortly). And its premises (that action is distinct from mere bodily movement, that action is performed for reasons, that action is at the very least possible) are intuitively very plausible. Nevertheless, I find it less promising than my argument from deliberative indispensability. The first thing to note here is, of course, that the argument as presented is incomplete. In particular, there is a need for a much fuller account of action, of acting for a reason, of the distinction between reasons and causes, and so on. In other words, what is needed is a philosophy of action. As it is not clear exactly how the details of an acceptable philosophy of action would go, it is hard to assess the sketchy argument above for its plausibility. For instance, the possibility of mere picking suggests that we can act in the absence of (normative) reasons, and this is a fact a fuller account of action is going to have to accommodate; it is hard to know whether, once it does, anything like the argument from the possibility of action can still go through. Furthermore, it is hard to see in advance how different it is from my argument from deliberative indispensability: For it seems plausible In thinking about this argument I benefited from Velleman’s discussion in his (2000b). For a related argument, see Levin (1987). 76 193 that an account of intentional action, action for reasons, is going to be closely related to an account of deliberation. Furthermore, the argument from action to metanormative realism may be relying on an equivocation on “reasons”. For accounts of actions in terms of reasons typically refer to motivating reasons. Now, these are all nice and well, but if we are to argue for realism about normative truths, motivating reasons may not suffice. That something is a motivating reason is not a normative truth. Only that something is a normative reason is. The move from action to motivating reasons may, then, be justified, as is the move from normative reasons to normative truths. But we have yet to see a plausible move from motivating reasons to normative reasons. Without such a move, the argument is simply invalid. Indeed, the availability of what are plausibly considered cases of action not done for normative reasons – the actions of some animals, and perhaps sub-intentional human action – suggests that normative reasons are not indispensable for action. These are reasons, then, to suspect that the argument from action may not be as promising as it initially seems. I want now to suggest two reasons why it is in fact inferior to my argument from deliberative indispensability. First, focusing on deliberation seems phenomenologically more accurate. Phenomenologically speaking, deliberation is, as it were, prior to action (though, as repeatedly emphasized above, it is not temporally prior to all instances of action). For deliberating creatures such as we, if reasons or normative truths are needed for action, this is so only, it seems to me, because they are needed for deliberation. If 194 this is so, there is some reason to prefer an argument that relies on the role of normative truths in deliberation, which, when push comes to shove, does the real work. Regardless of this reason to prefer – in general – my argument to the one from the possibility of action, I want to conclude the discussion of the argument from action by noting why it cannot serve my purposes as well as my argument from deliberative indispensability. For remember that, even granting me all that’s been argued for so far, it still remains to be shown that no other, non-robust-realist, account of normative truths (or something sufficiently close to them) can accommodate their role in deliberation. This is what I attempt to do in chapter 4. And if the argument from action is to support Robust Realism, it too must be accompanied by a rejection of the alternatives. Now, I think the prospects of showing that no non-robust-realist account of normativity can accommodate the deliberative role of normative truths are very good. I do not see, however, how it can be plausibly argued that no non-robust-realist account can accommodate the role of reasons in action. And if such an argument can be constructed, I suspect it will rely on premises regarding the relation between action and deliberation, and the role of normative truths in deliberation, and will thus be parasitic on my argument from deliberation. If this is so, then – regardless of its soundness as an 195 argument for some weak kind of realism about reasons – the argument from action cannot support Robust Realism77. 3.5.2 Conversation Pettit and Smith (1998) emphasize the conversational stance. When we have a distinct, “authorizing”, kind of conversation with someone, they argue, we make a number of assumptions without which having the conversation doesn’t make sense: “It only makes sense to adopt the conversational stance in relation to someone … if three conditions are satisfied. First, there are norms relevant to the issue of what they ought to believe. Second, they are capable of recognizing this to be so. And third, they are capable of responding appropriately to the norms: that is, capable of believing in the way they should.” (Pettit and Smith, 1998, 93) Of these three conditions, it is the first that looks very much like realism about norms of belief (Pettit and Smith then go on to argue for a similar condition regarding desires). Pettit and Smith do not neglect deliberation altogether. Indeed, in a number of places (1998, e.g. at 92) they make it clear that they consider deliberation to be a kind of conversation with oneself. I do not want to deny this relation (or one very close to it) between conversation of this peculiar kind with others and deliberation. Indeed, my phenomenological characterization of deliberation closely resembles 77 This is not, then, a criticism of the argument from action. Rather, it is an explanation of why I won’t be pursuing it. 196 points often made about the phenomenology of interpersonal disagreement. There is much, then, in Pettit’s and Smith’s argument I can agree with.78 The reason I prefer the argument from deliberative indispensability to theirs – which can be read as an argument from conversational indispensability – is again phenomenological. Phenomenologically speaking, it seems to me more accurate to say that conversation (of the kind Pettit and Smith seem to have in mind) is deliberation extended to include others, than to say that deliberation is conversation with oneself. For the concern I start with is that of trying to decide what to do, a decision I am uniquely positioned to make. When I choose to do so, I can invite others to share in this deliberation. But even then, deliberation is phenomenologically prior to conversation in this way. If this is so, a direct argument from deliberative indispensability is to be preferred to an argument from conversational indispensability. I am not confident, though, about this phenomenological point, and it is not clear to me whether much is lost if I am wrong about it.79 78 Depending, of course, on the details, details which they often fail to supply. Never, for instance, do they precisely (and not metaphorically) characterize the conversational stance, and the particular kind of conversation they’re interested in. Furthermore, except for one paragraph (1998, 108), they do not address the worries I address in chapter 2, regarding the move from indispensability to belief and the relation between pragmatic and epistemic justification. And they only discuss the unavoidability of the conversational stance in a very preliminary way. 79 Though realists of sorts, neither Pettit nor Smith endorse Robust Realism. So there is at least some reason to be suspicious that their argument – like the argument from action – cannot do all the work I want done, cannot support Robust Realism. Be that as it may, even regarding paradigmatic antirealist views of normativity Pettit and Smith remain neutral in this paper, noticing explicitly (1998, 97) that it is yet to be shown that these antirealist views cannot allow for their conversational stance. This is the analogous task to the one I embark on in the next chapter. 197 3.6 Scorekeeping I conclude, then, that we are essentially deliberative creatures, and that normative truths (or something sufficiently close to them) are indispensable for deliberation. Given the argument of chapter 1, this suffices to show that normative truths (or something sufficiently close to them) are as respectable as, say, electrons. And given the argument of chapter 2, this suffices to show that they are indeed respectable. All that remains if my argument for Robust Realism is to be completed, then, is to reject the alternatives: If no non-Robust-Realist account can accommodate the role of normative truths (or something sufficiently close to them) in deliberation, Robust Realism will have been defended. It is to this task that I now turn. 198 Chapter IV Rejecting Alternatives Having defended in a preliminary way the analogy between explanatory and deliberative indispensability (in chapter 1), having argued for the respectability of the move from indispensability of either kind to belief (in chapter 2), and having presented (in chapter 3) an account of deliberation according to which normative truths (or something sufficiently close to them) are deliberatively indispensable, it now remains to complete the argument by showing that no alternative – nonrobust-realist – view of normativity or normative discourse can satisfy the deliberating agent. This is the task of this chapter. In terms of my arch-argument – the argument from deliberative indispensability to Robust Realism – the task of this chapter is to complete the defense of the indispensability premise. For if a non-robust-realist view of normativity and normative discourse can supply all that is needed for sincere deliberation, irreducibly normative truths are after all not deliberatively indispensable. Think again of indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics: If a non-platonist view of mathematical discourse and entities can 199 supply all that is needed for scientific explanations, numbers (platonistically understood) are after all not explanatorily indispensable and the indispensability argument (as an argument for Platonism) collapses. In the context of my argument for Robust Realism, rejecting alternative metanormative views is thus not a luxury: It is not merely a further dialectical step, enhancing the plausibility of one view by reducing that of others. Nor is it an instance of the (purported) flaw that is typical of the writing of many realists – that of writing mostly negatively, rejecting other views while having very little by way of positive argument in support of their realism1. Rather, rejecting alternative views is part of the positive argument – the argument from deliberative indispensability – for Robust Realism. The discussion in this chapter proceeds as follows. I begin by drawing a preliminary chart of the metanormative waters, by doing some classificatory work in section 4.1. Next, in sections 4.2-4.5, I discuss four metanormative views (or rather families of views), arguing that none can allow for sincere deliberation. In section 4.6 I discuss a general objection that may be thought to undermine the arguments in sections 4.2-4.5. In section 4.7 I conduct a (brief) thought experiment, one that has some force, I think, against most of the alternative metanormative positions (all, in fact, except for error theories). I then proceed to discuss, in section 4.8, the possibility of hybrid views, views that try to combine the merits of several different metanormative views, arguing that they too cannot 1 See the references in the Introduction, footnotes 16 and 17. 200 succeed. After showing (in section 4.9) that what may seem to be views that resist my taxonomy are not views I need to address in detail, I then do some scorekeeping (in 4.10). 4.1 The Field How are we to make philosophical sense of normative discourse? The following ways seem to exhaust logical space. We might understand normative discourse as – semantically speaking – a fully descriptive, (purportedly) fact-stating discourse. We might understand it, that is, as attempting to say how things are, what reasons (for instance) we have, or what things are of value, or what ought to be done. When engaging in normative discourse, according to this understanding, we typically attempt to describe the normative facts, to express our beliefs about the normative part of the world. Call this view of normative discourse Cognitivism. But we might understand normative discourse in a noncognitivist fashion. We might think, that is, that normative discourse typically has a very different, non-descriptive, function. According to Metanormative Noncognitivism, the primary function of normative discourse is not to describe the normative facts, but rather to express approval or disapproval (or other non-cognitive attitudes), exert conversational pressure on our audience, and so on. Seeing that normative discourse does not attempt to describe normative facts, sincerely engaging in normative discourse does not commit one to the existence of such facts. Endorsing Noncognitivism is a way, then, of claiming 201 exemption from the need to give a metaphysical account of the relevant (here, normative) realm. But cognitivists are not thus exempt, and they may proceed in any of the following three ways: They may, first, deny that normative facts exist. If normative discourse attempts to describe normative facts, and if there are no such facts, then normative discourse is systematically erroneous. So one cognitivist way to go is Error Theory. Another is a reductivist view of normativity2: Perhaps there are normative facts, but they really are – at bottom – perfectly natural (or perhaps super-natural) facts, facts that can be described in terms that are (apparently) nonnormative. Or, and this would be the third option here, we can accept normative facts into our ontology as they are, sui generis, irreducibly normative facts. We thus get the following four families of metanormative views: Noncognitivism, Error Theory, Reductivism, and Non-reductive Realism3. This classification, it seems, is both exclusive and exhaustive: Clearly, no metanormative view can fall within the scope of more than one of these four families of views (unless it is a hybrid view, dividing normative discourse into parts, and endorsing different positions regarding different parts); and that the classification is exhaustive can be seen by considering the following series of questions: Is normative discourse an attempt at stating some (normative) facts? If As will be made clearer in section 4.4, I use “reduction” and its cognates in a fairly broad sense. The relevant classificatory issues (discussed partly here and partly in the following sections) are, of course, perfectly general, and similar classes of views arise in very different contexts as well. In thinking about these classificatory issues, I found Boghossian’s classificatory discussion of talk about meanings (1989) very helpful. 2 3 202 so, does it ever succeed in describing such facts? If so, are these facts basic, are they irreducibly normative? A “no” to the first leads to Noncognitivism. A “yes” to the first and a “no” to the second leads to Error Theory; a yes to the first two and a “no” to the third leads to Reductivism; a “yes” to all three leads to Robust Realism. As each of these questions admits of only two answers, the four metanormative directions mentioned above exhaust logical space. In the following three sections I discuss, then, the three non-robust-realist metanormative options, arguing that none of them – in whatever version – can satisfy our deliberative needs4. In following sections I also go into much more detail regarding the general four positions outlined in this section, and I discuss several examples of more specific views that fall under them. Though I will be primarily interested in exposing the generic flaws of the three families of views mentioned – flaws that any noncognitivist view, say, or any reductivist view, fall victim to – it will be instructive from time to time to engage in a more detailed discussion of a specific noncognitivist or reductivist view. 4 Thus, to an extent I follow what Firth (1952, 317) characterized as common practice some fifty years ago: “It is now common practice, for example, for the authors of books on moral philosophy to introduce their own theories by what purports to be a classification and review of all possible solutions to the basic problems of analysis; and in many cases, indeed, the primary defense of the author’s own position seems to consist in the negative argument that his own position cannot fail to be correct because none of the others which he has mentioned is satisfactory.” I follow the common practice in that my argument relies on rejecting what I take to be all possible alternative views (Firth’s own view – a view he presents as escaping the classifications common in his time – does not, of course, escape mine). But my indispensability argument for Robust Realism is not precisely captured by Firth’s characterization, for it is not an argument from alternatives (though rejecting the alternatives does play a crucial part in establishing the indispensability premise). 203 Despite the argument from the paragraph before last regarding the exhaustiveness of the classification presented, it might be tempting to view some of the views in the literature as escaping my classification (indeed, some writers present their views as a way out of such classifications). For the most part, I suggest that this temptation be simply resisted. I do think, however, that at least in one case – that of Constructivism – it may be of independent interest to see how it fails, even if it is in fact a particular instance of one of the four options above. I therefore discuss Constructivism in a separate section. (I very briefly discuss other metanormative views that may seem to escape my taxonomy in section 4.9.) Before proceeding to the discussion of the different metanormative alternatives, though, several preliminary points are in order. First, most of the writers whose work I shall be discussing present a metaethical view, not a metanormative one. For my purposes, then, it will be necessary to generalize their views and arguments. Whether or not the relevant writer is willing to generalize her view in the manner I suggest is something I will not discuss here. Second, I do not pretend that the discussion in following sections constitutes a comprehensive examination of alternative metanormative views. In particular, I do not examine the arguments writers who hold these views put forward in defense of their views. The discussion that follows is goal oriented: I discuss other views only in the amount of detail that is necessary in order to defend my argument for Robust Realism. 204 Third, it is important to note that though I will be focusing on the deliberative inadequacies of alternative views – their failure to supply something that is deliberatively indispensable – for the purposes of my argument any inadequacy will do. If, for instance, Noncognitivism is devastated by (a version of) the Frege-Geach Problem, Reductivism is ruled out by whatever can be saved from Moore’s infamous Open Question Argument, and a Metanormative Error Theory falls prey to some principle of charity, this will suffice for my indispensability argument for Robust Realism to go through. For if, for instance, Noncognitivism must be rejected (for whatever reason), then the indispensability premise can no longer be rejected by pointing to the noncognitivist understanding of normative discourse as a non-robust-realist alternative that still allows for deliberation. Similarly for other views, and other flaws: If a metanormative view must be rejected for any reason, then it cannot serve to support rejection of the indispensability premise. The reason why I nevertheless focus on the deliberative inadequacies of alternative views is just that these failures are, in the context of an argument from deliberative indispensability, particularly illuminating. Fourth, the classification above and the discussion in the rest of this chapter are conducted mostly in terms orthogonal to the division of metanormative (or metaethical) views into realist and antirealist (or irrealist) ones. However exactly this line is drawn, it is not a line I find theoretically useful here. I return to a discussion of realism (in replying to a worry about the robustness of Robust Realism) in the Conclusion. For the most part, and for a similar reason, I will also 205 ignore the distinction between objectivist and subjectivist (or, more precisely, nonor anti-objectivist5) metanormative views. My objections to Noncognitivism, for instance, apply whether or not noncognitivist views qualify – simply in virtue of being noncognitivist – as subjectivist metanormative views. Nevertheless, I suspect that the issue of objectivity is very much relevant, and that it does much philosophical work behind the scenes, motivating some metanormative views as well as my objections to them. And at one point – in section 4.4 – my argument does rely on an objective-subjective distinction (there characterized). Finally, throughout the discussion of the following sections I assume, when I consider the point of view of the deliberating agent, not only the truth of the relevant metanormative theory (or family of theories), but also that the agent knows that the theory is true. In other words, if the truth of a non-robust-realist metanormative theory is compatible with sincere deliberation, but not with the sincere deliberation of agents who know that it is true, I take it to be reason enough to reject the theory. I thus assume some kind of a publicity requirement. This assumption is not, of course, beyond controversy, and I defend it (in the context of my argument), in a separate section (4.6). 4.2 Error Theory For it is not clear that “objectivist” and “subjectivist” – as applied to metanormative or metaethical theories – are exact opposites. See, for instance, Pettit (2001, 244). 5 206 In what follows, I first (in section 4.2.1) characterize in some detail error theories, distinguishing between different ways in which an error theorist may proceed as regarding the discourse she believes is infested with error. Then, in sections 4.2.2 and 4.2.3, I argue against two such ways, the two I think are the only relevantly important options. I argue against the availability of what may be thought to be a third option in section 4.2.4, and conclude the discussion of error theories in section 4.2.5 with an observation about the relation between error theories and alternative views, like the ones I proceed to discuss in later sections. 4.2.1 Error Theory, Eliminativism, Instrumentalism, and Revisionary Accounts An error theorist about a discourse believes that the discourse is infested with error, and that therefore no sentence belonging to that discourse is non-trivially true. Believing that there exists no God (or anything possessing attributes sufficiently closely resembling those God is traditionally thought to possess), and believing that, say, catholic theological discourse is committed to the existence of God, I believe that catholic theological discourse is systematically erroneous. Now, that doesn’t mean that all sentences that are a part of that discourse are false: Given that “God loves all His creatures” is a part of that discourse, arguably so is “It’s not the case that God loves all His creatures”, but, of course, these sentences cannot both be false. If, because there is no God, the former is false, then the latter 207 is true, only trivially so. This is why an error theorist need only believe that the sentences of the relevant discourse are either false or trivially true. As is clear, one’s views about reference failure are relevant here. If the best understanding of sentences containing reference failure (like “God loves all His creatures”) is along Strawsonian rather than Russelian lines, then error theories may claim not that the sentences of the error-infested discourse are false (or trivially true), but rather just that none of them is true6. For my purposes here it will not matter what theory of reference failure (or of similar flaws) the error theorist endorses, and so I will use a characterization of error theories that is neutral as between different theories of reference failure: An error theory about a discourse claims that no sentence that is a part of that discourse is non-trivially true. This is all that different error theorists about a given discourse need agree on. They may disagree, in particular, about which commitment of the relevant discourse cannot be satisfied, and indeed about what the relevant discourse is committed to. Consider, for example, two error theories about morality. Mackie (1977, chapter 1) believes that moral discourse is committed to metaphysically queer objective values, things that are a part of the fabric of the universe, and that simultaneously make actions right and make agents perform those actions regardless of their prior motivations. He further thinks that there are no such objective values, and that therefore moral discourse is error-infested. He is thus an 6 For a similar point see Pettit (2001, 240-1). 208 error theorist about morality. Smith (1994, 200) does not believe that moral discourse is committed to anything like objective values as understood by Mackie. However, he believes moral discourse is committed to the convergence of all rational agents’ desires (1994, 164-177). Now, Smith is no error theorist, as he is optimistic about satisfying this purported commitment of moral discourse. But we can easily imagine (as he does: 1994, 173-4) what would be the case if no such convergence is to be had. In such a case, an error theory about morality would follow, but one based on considerations very different from Mackie’s. For the purposes of my argument, I need not distinguish between the grounds for different metanormative error theories, and so the two error theories above can be treated together. All we need to know, then, about the metanormative error theorist I will be concerned with is that she thinks – for whatever reason – that normative discourse is infested with error, and so that no normative sentence is non-trivially true.7 Though it will not be of importance in what follows what leads an error theorist to his error theory, it will be of crucial importance how he then proceeds. For having diagnosed a discourse as systematically erroneous, the error theorist still has to answer the question: Should we discard the discourse, or should we continue to engage in it? I’ll refer to an error theorist who advocates abandonment 7 Stephen Schiffer has recently (2002) put forward an antirealist metaethical theory according to which (almost) no ethical sentence is determinately true, apparently remaining open-minded about the possibility of some of them being true in a somewhat less respectable way. For my purposes, Schiffer’s theory can be seen as a variation on the usual error-theoretical theme as characterized in the text, and my arguments against metanormative error theories apply, mutatis mutandis, to the metanormative generalization of Schiffer’s metaethics. 209 of the discourse he is an error theorist about as an eliminativist. It should be clear, then, that Eliminativism about a discourse is in no way entailed by an error theory about it8. Field (1980), for instance, is an error theorist about mathematics, believing that mathematical discourse is committed to the existence of platonic mathematical objects, and that no such objects exist. But he does not advocate the elimination of mathematical discourse. Rather, he gives an account of how it is that engaging in mathematical discourse is of value (to science, for instance), even though it is error-infested. According to Field, doing mathematics (and in particular, quantifying over mathematical objects in the course of doing empirical science) is of tremendous instrumental value, as it facilitates and simplifies calculations and inferences. Crucially, this instrumental value of mathematical discourse does not depend on the non-trivial truth of any mathematical sentences: Field argues that other properties of mathematical discourse, properties that do not require the non-trivial truth of any of its parts (in particular, its conservativeness), account for its usefulness in doing science. So Field is an error theorist about mathematical discourse, but he is not an eliminativist about it. Rather, he is an instrumentalist. This brief discussion of Field’s Instrumentalism about mathematics can illustrate how controversies between instrumentalists and eliminativists are to be decided, and it should be clear that the way – like these controversies themselves – 8 This is one of the main points of Burgess (1998). 210 is pragmatic in nature9. Assuming that there is no God and that therefore (western) religious discourse is error-infested, the question of whether religious discourse is to be discarded is a pragmatic one, about the probable consequences of engaging in it and of failing to do so and their comparative value. If, for instance, engaging in religious discourse is the only way to prevent people from doing morally abhorrent things, this is some reason to continue engaging in it, its systematic error notwithstanding. If religious discourse actually has bad effects – perhaps mostly in terms of international politics – this is some reason to discard religious discourse altogether.10 Whether the non-trivial truth of some sentences in the contested discourse is indispensable for the justification of engaging in it is to be decided – as any pragmatic issue – case by case. It seems like a reasonable requirement, though, that error theorists who want to go instrumentalist have some story to tell why it is useful to engage in the error-infested discourse. In other words, the burden of proof seems to be placed on the instrumentalist’s shoulders (but nothing in my argument against metanormative error theories will depend on this way of placing the burden of proof). 9 Burgess (1998, 541). There is an important difference between the case of religious discourse and that of Field’s Instrumentalism about mathematics. The kind of Meta-religious Instrumentalism hinted at in the text seems to presuppose that those who will continue to engage in religious discourse – or at least most of them – will falsely believe that it is not error-infested, and in particular that God exists. Field’s Instrumentalism about mathematics presupposes no such thing – indeed, it seems Field himself can, consistently and in good conscience, do mathematics – and so Field’s Instrumentalism may be said to satisfy a publicity requirement Meta-religious Instrumentalism fails. (In Burgess’s (1998) terms, Field’s is a translational error theory, whereas the Meta-religious Instrumentalism sketched in the text is a defense of a myth.) I discuss such a publicity requirement in section 4.6, below. 10 211 And so, we all are, it seems to me, not only error theorists about witchdiscourse, but also eliminativists about it: We think that witch-discourse is systematically erroneous (because there are no witches, or anything possessing attributes sufficiently closely resembling those witches are supposed to have according to witch-discourse), and furthermore that nothing of value can be gained (and perhaps much can be lost) by engaging in it. Similarly, Churchland (1984) is an error theorist about folk-psychological mental-states discourse, and also an eliminativist about it: He believes not only that there are no beliefs, desires, and so on (or anything possessing attributes sufficiently closely resembling those these mental states are supposed to possess according to folk psychology), but also that talk of beliefs and desires is dangerously misleading and that it ought to be replaced by scientifically more respectable discourse. Field has already been mentioned as an example of an error theorist who is an instrumentalist11 (about mathematics), and typically so are those who reject scientific realism in favor of a more empiricist epistemology (only their Error Theory and Instrumentalism are about scientific discourse, or perhaps just about theoretical-entities-discourse)12. Before returning to the more specific discussion of Metanormative Error Theory, one more point is worth making. Sometimes people offer a theory as a 11 Field is usually referred to as a fictionalist, not an instrumentalist, but for my purposes Fictionalism can be seen as a particular kind of Instrumentalism: Understanding some mathematical sentences as true-in-the-platonist-fiction and others as false-in-the-fiction and then proceeding to show the usefulness of telling mathematical fiction is just one way in which one can show that engaging in mathematical discourse is of instrumental value. 12 See, for instance, Van Fraassen (1980). 212 replacement thesis, or a revisionary account – even “a reforming definition”13 – of a contested discourse or family of terms. The original discourse is, they either say or assume, highly problematic, and it is very doubtful whether it can be understood as anything but incoherent. But a reasonable and coherent account can be given of how the relevant piece of language can be used, and perhaps also of how it ought to be used. The theory is then not presented as an accurate descriptive account of the relevant discourse, but rather as a suggestion for revision. Of course, the suggestion has to resemble the original discourse, or else it is in no way a revisionary account of that discourse. But close enough to qualify as a revisionary account of a discourse need not be close enough to count as an adequate descriptive account of it. It is important to note, then, that a revisionary account is really a conjunction of two theses. The first is a descriptive error theory: The discourse as it stands – before the suggested revision – is, so we’re told, incoherent or at least badly confused14. If that is so, it seems that no sentence in that discourse can be non-trivially true. The second conjunct is not as clear: It can be seen as either an Instrumentalism of sorts (“Let’s go on talking as we did, but let’s mean something slightly different by our words, for doing so will prove useful.”), or – more plausibly, I think – it is really an Eliminativism, coupled with a suggestion regarding what to do after having eliminated the error-infested discourse (“No The term, of course, is Brandt’s (1979). I discuss Brandt’s revisionary account – though very briefly – below. 14 For a clear example, see Brandt (1979, e.g. at 7). 13 213 point in continuing to engage in that confused discourse; let’s keep the words but change their meaning so that what we then say can actually be – useful or not – non-trivially true.”). And perhaps different revisionary accounts are offered some in the former spirit, some in the latter. The line between revisionary and descriptive accounts may be blurred, as it is not clear precisely how leeway the theorist has in interpreting and precisifying his subject matter while still counting his theory as a descriptive one. And particularly attractive revisionary accounts are represented, revisionary though they are, as nevertheless being able to supply all we ever wanted – or all we ever should have wanted – from the original, non-revised, discourse15. But – and this is the point needed for what it to come – a revisionary account is never an alternative to an error theory, nor does it escape the dichotomy (among error theories) between Instrumentalism and Eliminativism. And the revised discourse – the one our revisionist is not an error theorist about – still calls for a meta-theory, one that will presumably be either reductivist, or robust realist, or perhaps nonfactualist. So revisionary accounts – though perhaps of independent interest – are not alternative metanormative views I have to consider and reject here. Back to normative discourse, then. Metanormative error theorists are very hard to come by16. The one (possible) example I know of17 is Brandt’s (1979) 15 See Johnston (1993, 110). It is much easier to come by people who are error theorists about some part of the normative domain, but not all of it. Some examples – those where the relevant sub-domain of normativity is ethics – are discussed in the text below. If you endorse an error theory about a part of the normative 16 214 theory of rationality, presented under the guise of a reforming definition, and grounded in a loss of hope regarding the prospects of an adequate and coherent descriptive account of normative discourse. Assuming that Brandt takes rationality to be the basic normative concept, his view can be seen as a metanormative error theory – an error theory, that is, about the actual discourse of rationality, that preceding the suggested revision18. But as Brandt is primarily interested in developing his revisionary suggestion, his discussion – and justification – of the error theory itself is rather quick19. In the metaethical literature error theorists are easier to come by. The best known example is, of course, John Mackie’s denial of objective values in chapter 1 of his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (1977)20. It is worth mentioning here that it is not at all clear whether Mackie is an instrumentalist or a revisionary theorist, and what the details of whatever option he takes are. The one thing that does seem clear is that he is not an eliminativist, as he continues to do first-order, domain but not all of it, you seem to endorse a hybrid metanormative view. I discuss such views in section 4.8. 17 There are many cases in which an implicit error theory – even Eliminativism – may be doing some philosophical work in the background of a more explicit theory. One way of understanding Quine’s attempt at naturalizing epistemology, for instance, is as motivated by a general suspicion towards normativity, and towards its manifestations in (non-naturalized) epistemology. But this is not an example of a philosopher explicitly defending a metanormative error theory. 18 Sturgeon (1982, 391, 398-9) suggests that Brandt can be thus understood. It is not clear, however, that this is the only way in which Brandt can be understood. Some of his criticism of unreconstructed moral (and perhaps also more generally normative) discourse sounds less like an accusation of systematic error and more like an accusation of too much vagueness and indeterminacy or (relatedly) of unknowability (Brandt 1979, e.g. at 6). If these are the flaws that ground Brandt’s despair with unreconstructed moral (and normative) discourse, he is not an error theorist in the sense characterized above. 19 See Sturgeon (1982, 402). 20 It seems that Mandeville has anticipated much of Mackie’s error theory. For a discussion of Mandeville’s metaethical error theory, see Schneewind (1998, 323-327). 215 normative, ethics – indeed, as is often noted, he continues to do ethics in the later parts of the very same book. But never, as far as I am aware, does he explain how this is compatible with the error theory advocated earlier. It seems charitable to read him as either defending ethical discourse instrumentally, or perhaps putting forward a revisionary suggestion of how moral language can be used in an errorfree way, then using it himself in that way. But the details of either are not to be found in Mackie’s text.21 Regardless of its historical pedigree (or lack thereof), the error theory I proceed to discuss (and reject) is a Metanormative Error Theory, in either an eliminativist or an instrumentalist form. Even if Metanormative Error Theory – the claim that no normative judgment is non-trivially true – is neither very popular nor very attractive, it certainly is a position in logical space that needs to be ruled out if my argument for Robust Realism is to be complete. And seeing how such an error theory fails will be important for what is to come (as I indicate in section 4.2.5). 4.2.2 Against Instrumentalism An instrumentalist error theorist about (all) normative discourse believes that no normative sentences (like “Pain is bad”, “We ought never to treat others merely as 21 For an example of a metaethical error theorist (or at least someone who endorses an error theory about an important part of ethical discourse) who is also explicit about endorsing Instrumentalism, see Velleman (1989, chapter 10). In correspondence, Velleman has expressed doubts he now has about the error theory he then endorsed. 216 means”, “It is always rational to maximize one’s own desire-satisfaction”, “Correlations of two factors give reason to believe, in the presence of one, that the other is also present”, “Organizing a demonstration is the thing to do now”, and the like) are non-trivially true, but that we nevertheless should not discard normative discourse. Rather, we should continue to engage in it, because doing so has pragmatic advantages that are not eliminated just by the discourse’s systematic error (and perhaps not even by public knowledge of this error22). Now, the details of such an instrumentalist metanormative error theory need to be filled in in a plausible way: How is it that engaging in normative discourse is useful despite the error it incorporates? But we need not worry about these details here, for they (logically) cannot be filled in. In order to be an instrumentalist, one has to defend the usefulness, the instrumental value, of the relevant discourse or of engaging in it. And something can only be of instrumental value if it is instrumental to something that is of value, and ultimately to something that is of intrinsic value. So in order to defend her Instrumentalism, an error theorist about normativity would have to identify a valuable thing or project, argue that it is valuable, and show that normative discourse or engaging in it is instrumental to that thing or project. But judgments of intrinsic value are paradigmatically normative judgments, of exactly the kind our instrumentalist is an error theorist about. By her error theory, she is committed to rejecting the (non-trivial) truth of any such judgments. On pain of inconsistency, 22 Again, I discuss the publicity requirement in section 4.6. 217 then, she cannot defend both an error theory about normativity in general and the normative claim characteristic of Instrumentalism. Notice that this problem arises for the metanormative instrumentalist because of the wide scope of her error theory. This line of argument does not (directly) threaten an Instrumentalism about a sub-domain of normative discourse. In particular, it does not threaten metaethical Instrumentalism. One can be an error theorist about morality, and yet consistently defend Instrumentalism by showing that moral discourse serves some other, non-moral, values23. It is only when one generalizes one’s error theory to all normative discourse that one cannot consistently endorse Instrumentalism. I have already mentioned that an error theorist may endorse a revisionary account of the relevant discourse, and I have also explained why I need not address this line in detail. But it may be useful to see why it does not in particular help in opening up logical space for an instrumentalist position about all normativity. Having noticed something like the inconsistency I point at above (Burgess (1998, 541, 548)), Burgess argues (ibid., 549) that the would-beinstrumentalist can avoid it by putting forward a revisionary suggestion, and then understanding the normative-looking judgments he commits himself to by going instrumentalist as reformed normative judgments, judgments made in accordance with the revisionary suggestion and so not guilty of the original error. Let us use 23 Even then, though, the suspicion remains that this instrumentalist justification of moral discourse is, as Velleman (then an instrumentalist himself) writes (1989, 318), “a skeptical justification” at best. But this worry is one I cannot discuss here. 218 “normativeR” to denote the revised counterpart of any normative term (oughtR for ought, goodR for good, and so on). Then Burgess’s suggestion is, I think, as follows: The consistent metanormative error theorist thinks that no ought-sentence is non-trivially true, and he thinks that we oughtR not discard normative – or at least normativeR – discourse, but continue to engage in it. (If it is normative discourse that we oughtR to continue engaging in, then perhaps this revisionary theorist can be classified as an instrumentalist; if it is only normative R discourse that we oughtR to engage in, then about normative discourse he seems to be an eliminativist. But the argument that follows need not distinguish between these two cases.) Now, this position is indeed consistent, because the rejection of all ought-statements is compatible with the endorsement of an oughtR-statement. But this position, though consistent, will not save the metanormative error theorist. For before we can join him in judging whether or not we oughtR to discard normative discourse, he must convince us regarding the merits of his revisionary account. He must, in other words, convert us from normative to normativeR discourse. If we are willing to conduct the discussion in normativeR terms, his work is already done. The real challenge he faces is exactly to get us to be so willing. And before he has done that, he cannot settle for showing that we ought R to continue using normative discourse, assuming that he has thereby justified his Instrumentalism. At most, he has thereby justifiedR his Instrumentalism, and taking 219 that to settle the issue would beg the question against those not yet convinced of the merits of the revisionary account.24 So proposing his Instrumentalism in the guise of a revisionary account will not save the instrumentalist. And this, of course, is as it should be: If, as argued earlier, revisionary accounts do not offer the error theorist a genuine alternative to both Instrumentalism and Eliminativism, endorsing a revisionary account cannot save the instrumentalist. Instrumentalism, I conclude, is not available to the metanormative error theorist. It seems, then, she must go eliminativist. 4.2.3 Against Eliminativism An error theory about a discourse we pre-theoretically engage in is typically highly counterintuitive. The main appeal of Instrumentalism is that it can serve to alleviate the counterintuitiveness of the error theory. Consider Field’s position again. Having defended his Instrumentalism about mathematical discourse, he is free to appease (some of) our worries about his error theory, by noting that there is nothing bad – and indeed much that is good – in our continuing to engage in mathematical discourse. An eliminativist cannot in this way appease our intuitive worries, and must therefore face the counterintuitiveness of her error theory head on. This does not mean that Eliminativism is never justified (we are all, remember, 24 My point in this paragraph closely resembles a point Sturgeon (1982, 396-9) makes in criticizing Brandt’s method of reforming definitions, except Sturgeon emphasizes the need to choose among different possible reforming definitions (between normative and normative discourse). R1 220 R2 eliminativists about witch-discourse). It just shows that it is going to take more to rationally convince us that an error theory about a discourse we pre-theoretically engage in is appropriate if the best version of the relevant error theory is an eliminativist, not an instrumentalist, one. Given the result of the previous section, this already counts against a metanormative error theory (though it is not clear how conclusively). A potentially more devastating worry about Metanormative Eliminativism should be rather predictable at this point. If Eliminativism is understood as a claim about what we ought to do (in particular, that we ought not to continue engaging in the relevant discourse), then it too is a normative claim, and so one that cannot be consistently endorsed by a metanormative error theorist. But perhaps Eliminativism can be understood not so much as a normative claim (added on top of the error theory both Instrumentalism and Eliminativism are based on), but in some other way – perhaps, for instance, as merely an intention not to engage in the relevant discourse in the future25, or perhaps in some similar way. Let us assume this can be done. It is against such an Eliminativism that the argument of the last three chapters applies directly, and no further argumentative work needs to be done against it at this stage. For Eliminativism thus understood is not really an alternative account of normativity, one that allows it to supply what is 25 Assuming, of course, that intention-discourse is not (necessarily) normative. For what may seem like another non-normative way of understanding Metanormative Eliminativism, see the next section. 221 indispensable for deliberation, but rather a rejection of normativity altogether. Against such Eliminativism, then, the argument of previous chapters is the only argument that need be given: Deliberation is intrinsically indispensable because essentially unavoidable, and normative judgments – though at this stage of the argument, perhaps not necessarily robust-realistically understood – are indispensable for deliberation. So metanormative Eliminativism is not a further option to be ruled out at this dialectical stage. If the argumentation in previous chapters is sound, Metanormative Eliminativism has already been ruled out. And notice again, that this reason for rejecting Metanormative Eliminativism stems from the generality of the suggested view. It cannot serve to rule out an Eliminativism that is more limited in scope, and in particular Metaethical Eliminativism. A more restricted Eliminativism can avoid the deliberative-indispensability-problem by arguing that, say, moral discourse is to be eliminated, but deliberation can still go forward on the basis of some other, nonmoral, normative judgments. It is only Global Metanormative Eliminativism that is ruled out by the argument of previous chapters.26 4.2.4 A Way Out? 26 If, as hinted in the Introduction, it is hard to think of a reason supporting Metaethical Error Theory that does not supply equally strong support for Metanormative Error Theory, then the unavailability of both Metanormative Instrumentalism and Metanormative Eliminativism, and hence of Metanormative Error Theory, should count indirectly against metaethical error theories as well. The point in the text – and the analogous point in the previous section – is just that this indirect way is the only way in which my arguments here bear, if they do at all, on the plausibility of metaethical error theories. 222 It may seem, though, that claiming as I do that a metanormative error theorist – like other error theorists – must be either an eliminativist or an instrumentalist is already a step in the wrong direction, dangerously close to begging the question against the metanormative error theorist. For, it may be argued, an error theorist need not have anything interesting to say about the relevant discourse except for pointing out the systematic error. Of course, error theorists may have many other interesting views, about the relevant discourse as well as about other things, but there is nothing further about the discourse they have to say in their capacity as error theorists. In particular, they need not advocate either discarding the relevant discourse or continuing to engage in it; they need not advocate anything. They only have to assert that the relevant discourse is error-infested, and to argue for this claim. The reason why assuming otherwise may seem like begging the question against the metanormative error theorist (especially against the eliminativist) is that the further step – that of advocating either continued use of the discourse or discarding it – seems to involve the error theorist in normative enterprises and get her engaged in the very normative discourse about which she is an error theorist. And this is the source of the troubles she faces whether she goes instrumentalist or eliminativist, the troubles earlier sections use in order to reject error theories. But, the objection continues, once we see that the metanormative error theorist need have nothing further to say about normative discourse, and in particular need not 223 advocate any attitude towards it, we see that she need not engage in normative discourse, and the arguments of the previous two sections collapse. There is much that is true about this objection: It is the error theorist’s involvement in the very normative discourse she is an error theorist about that gets her in trouble, and perhaps if such involvement could be avoided then Metanormative Error Theory would be an open option. But it cannot be avoided. Faced with an error theory – especially a compelling one – about a discourse we pre-theoretically engage in we cannot avoid asking ourselves how to proceed. And this, of course, is a particular instance of the unavoidability of deliberation. This particular case where deliberation doesn’t seem to be avoidable is especially interesting because in it deliberative needs are incorporated into what we intuitively take to be theoretical virtues (and vices). If a philosopher presented an error theory about, say, folk-psychological discourse, but had nothing interesting to say – indeed had nothing at all he could say – regarding whether or not to discard that discourse, we would treat this fact as a theoretical flaw of his view, and, I think, rightly so. A theory such as his fails to address all our relevant concerns, and this counts against it. Similarly, then, for error theorists about normative discourse. They must have something further to say because otherwise their theory fails to address a relevant and unavoidable concern of ours; but their error theory entails that they cannot have anything further to say, and indeed that the relevant concern of ours cannot be addressed. And this is reason enough to reject their error theory. 224 To conclude, then: Neither Instrumentalism nor Eliminativism is available for the (global) metanormative error theorist, and given that she cannot avoid the choice between them by remaining silent on the relevant issue, (global) metanormative error theory can safely be rejected. 4.2.5 Error Theories and Softer Interpretations As already mentioned, arguments for error theories often proceed by first diagnosing a commitment of the relevant discourse, and then arguing that it is not satisfied. So error theories (or the arguments for them) can be rejected in two kinds of way: One may reject the understanding of the discourse as involving the commitment the error theorist’s argument focuses on, or one may argue that the commitment is in fact satisfied (or both). The latter is the stronger, realist option. In a different context27, I label theories taking the former route “softerinterpretation theories”: They save the relevant discourse, but by weakening its commitments. So, for instance, in the case of the philosophy of mathematics we have (i) platonists, (ii) error theorists like Field who believe mathematical discourse is committed to platonic objects but think these do not exist and that mathematical discourse is thus systematically erroneous, and (iii) softerinterpretation theorists of many different kinds who believe that mathematical discourse can be saved consistently with there not being any platonic mathematical 27 Enoch (unpublished). 225 objects, because mathematical discourse should be understood as committed to no such things. Analogously, we can distinguish three broad metanormative routes: First, there is Robust Realism. Then, there is some kind28 of metanormative error theory that agrees with Robust Realism about the commitment of normative discourse to irreducibly normative truths but denies the existence of such truths, and so concludes that normative discourse is systematically erroneous. And then there are many kinds of softer-interpretation theories, theories that try to save normative discourse by showing that it need not be committed to anything like irreducibly normative truths. The views to be discussed in sections 4.3 through 4.5 are all such softer-interpretation theories.29 This classificatory point is of some significance, as we are now in a position to draw the following conclusion: If Robust Realism is a plausible account of at least the commitments of normative discourse, then the only options from which to choose are Robust Realism and Error Theory30. And if the argument 28 There may of course be other kinds of metanormative error theories, focusing on other purported commitments of normative discourse. 29 Lewis’s (1989) dispositional theory of value is a relevantly interesting case, as regarding one purported commitment of value-discourse (that values are not contingent) he settles for a disjunction: Either value-discourse involves this commitment, in which case there are no values, or this commitment is not an essential part of value-discourse, in which case there are values (dispositionally understood) (ibid., 132-137). In my terms, Lewis is clear about the rejection of the strong realist option (about values), and – not deciding whether or not value-discourse involves the relevant commitment – settles for the disjunction of an error theory and a softer-interpretation theory. 30 It is this point, I think, that explains why error theories are often much more plausible – and seem more honest – than softer-interpretation theories: They at least acknowledge the commitments of the relevant discourse. I think Nagel has in mind softer-interpretation theories when he writes 226 above is sound then of these two options only Robust Realism remains stable. So what remains to be done in following sections is just to see whether any alternative understanding of normative discourse is more plausible as an account of the commitments of normative discourse, and in particular of normative discourse as applied in deliberation. If no softer-interpretation theory passes this test, Robust Realism is vindicated31. 4.3 Noncognitivism In section 4.3.1 I characterize Noncognitivism in more detail than in section 4.1 above. I then focus, in section 4.3.2, on a rather crude version of Noncognitivism – the now infamous Emotivism to be found, for instance, in Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic, showing why it cannot serve to block my argument for Robust Realism. However, no contemporary philosopher, as far as I know, is a crude emotivist, and so the point of section 4.3.2 is not so much to expose some inadequacies in that now-deserted view, but rather to facilitate discussion of its more sophisticated descendants. I discuss them – arguing that, as far as the problems I discuss here are concerned, they do no better than crude Emotivism – in section 4.3.3. In section 4.3.4 I briefly discuss Simon’s Blackburn’s QuasiRealism, which may seem to allow noncognitivists to accommodate the kind of (1986, 89): “One may be a skeptic about x no matter how sincerely one protests that one is not denying the existence of x but merely explaining what x really amounts to.” 31 I return to a discussion of softer-interpretation theories in general below, in section 4.7. 227 normative truths I argue are deliberatively indispensable. I argue that QuasiRealism – regardless of its other merits – cannot help noncognitivists in doing that. It is perhaps worth emphasizing again, that the discussion that follows is not – nor is it meant to be – a comprehensive discussion of Noncognitivism and its shortcomings. My aim in this section is merely to reject Noncognitivism as a way of blocking my argument for Robust Realism by showing that irreducibly normative truths and facts are not needed for deliberation after all, because deliberation can be had on noncognitivist grounding. Objections to Noncognitivism from the literature are discussed in what follows only when – and to the extent that – they are relevant for the limited scope of this project. 4.3.1 Noncognitivism, Nonfactualism, Expressivism Noncognitivism about a discourse is characterized as, roughly, the view that typical sentences in that discourse do not describe (accurately or inaccurately) facts or parts of reality, because there are no such facts for the discourse to answer to; that sentences in the relevant discourse do not (typically) express beliefs and other belief-like, cognitive, representational, attitudes, but rather conative, desirelike attitudes; that, as expressions (rather than reports) of such attitudes, these sentences are neither true nor false. In order to characterize Noncognitivism less 228 roughly, we need to distinguish between the semantic, psychological and metaphysical views implied by this rough characterization32. Take, for example, Metaethical Noncognitivism. The semantic thesis associated with Noncognitivism holds that typical moral sentences (like “Abortion is morally wrong” or “Abortion is morally permissible”) are neither true nor false, that – like question-sentences, or imperatives – they are, as is sometimes said, not in the business of being true or false, because they are not really descriptive sentences (their surface grammar notwithstanding)33. The semantic reading of Noncognitivism thus draws the distinction between discourses we should be cognitivists about and those we should be noncognitivists about in terms of truthaptness. The psychological view associated with Metaethical Noncognitivism is the thesis that moral sentences do not typically34 express beliefs or other cognitive attitudes, but rather conative attitudes. According to this reading of metaethical For the distinction between the semantic and psychological views I am indebted to O’LearyHawthorne and Price (1996, section 1); for discussions regarding the distinction between both and the metaphysical thesis, I am indebted to Josh Schechter, Mark Schroeder and Crispin Wright. 33 A more local absence of truth value – as may occur in sentences suffering from reference failure (according to at least one way of understanding such sentences) or in vague sentences in borderline cases (according to at least some ways of understanding vagueness) – does not, of course, suffice to justify a noncognitivist conclusion (of whatever sort) about the relevant discourse. 34 We can use any sentence in any way we choose. We can decide, for instance, to use a code so that I can say “Abortion is wrong” in order to let you know that – express my belief that – the police are coming. Of course, this trivial point cannot refute Metaethical Noncognitivism, nor can similar points utilizing more systematic relations between sentences and their less-than-standard uses. So Noncognitivism should not be understood as claiming that all utterances of moral sentences express conative states rather than beliefs. The point has to be that the meaning of moral sentences (or terms) is such as to allow them to express conative states (just like the meaning of the sentence “The police are coming” makes it suitable to express the belief that the police are coming). This way of putting things relegates to philosophers of meaning the task of distinguishing between standard and non-standard ways of using words and sentences. The “typically” in the text is meant to be a place-holder for whatever criterion will be delivered by the best theory of meaning. Rosen (1998, 402, footnote 3) notices that there is some unfinished business here for the noncognitivist. 32 229 Noncognitivism the line between a discourse best understood cognitivistically and one best understood noncognitivistically is a psychological one: that between (roughly) belief-like and desire-like states of mind. These two characterizations of Noncognitivism are clearly distinct. But given some plausible assumptions about the relation between truth-aptness and belief-aptness, the two characterizations seem to coincide: It seems plausible to assume that all and only truth-apt sentences typically express beliefs, and even if there are counterexamples to this generalization, there seem to be none that are relevant to my discussion here35. In what follows, I will assume the coincidence of the semantic and psychological characterizations of Noncognitivism. The metaphysical thesis often associated with Noncognitivism is Nonfactualism: the denial of facts the relevant discourse answers to 36. Metaethical Nonfactualism is, for instance, the denial of moral facts. Now, this metaphysical thesis is not unrelated to the semantic and psychological ones, but it is important not to conflate them. For one thing, one can be a psychological and semantic noncognitivist about a discourse without being a nonfactualist about it. Consider the following example37: It seems fairly plausible to be a noncognitivist (or to hold 35 For some relevant discussion, see Jackson, Oppy and Smith (1994). Further dialectical steps taken by contemporary noncognitivists – mostly, endorsing a minimalist conception of truth and facts and going quasi-realist – complicate matters here. But even if noncognitivists can come up with clever ways to allow them to talk of (e.g.) moral facts, still they typically deny moral facts more robustly understood, facts radically independent of us and our responses, or perhaps facts that carry their own weight in explanation. Nonfactualism is to be understood as denying the existence of facts robust in some such way that the relevant discourse answers to. 37 For which I am indebted to Crispin Wright. 36 230 a closely analogous view) about sentences like: “I promise that …” or “I promise to …”. It seems plausible, in other words, to view such sentences as not typically serving to express beliefs and describe a part of the world, but rather to do something very different (to make promises), and so as not strictly speaking truthapt. Such a view of first-person present-tense promising sentences, however, does not commit one to a related Nonfactualism: We think that there are facts to which promising discourse answers, that it is a fact, for instance, that George Bush promised not to raise taxes. True, these promising-facts are typically describable in non-first-personal or non-present-tense sentences, but they do depict facts of the kind that can make “I promise not to raise taxes” true, and it would seem a mistake to treat this sentence as just ambiguous between promise-making utterances and description-of-promise-making utterances38. Much more can be said here, of course, and noncognitivist-yet-factualist views face some obvious challenges (like characterizing the facts they don’t deny in ways other than using the very discourse they don’t think is primarily factstating39). But it should nevertheless be clear that views about the meaning and functions of bits of language do not as such entail – all by themselves – views about what there is, and so Noncognitivism does not entail Nonfactualism. The 38 If you are not convinced, consider the following conversation (for which I am indebted to Tom Nagel): A: “George promises not to raise taxes.” B: “George, is that true?” George: “Yes, it’s true.” George’s utterance seems both to be a promise-making, and also to affirm the truth of A’s thirdperson statement. 39 See Pettit (2001, 283, footnote 14). 231 distinction between Nonfactualism and Noncognitivism notwithstanding, it is no surprise that the two typically go hand in hand (at least in the metaethical context). For given the denial of moral facts, the only metaethical options left to choose from seem to be an error theory – according to which moral discourse is a failed attempt to describe or represent such facts – and a view that understands moral discourse in a completely different, noncognitivist, way. Assuming the denial of an error theory, then, Nonfactualism entails Noncognitivism. And, though Noncognitivism does not entail Nonfactualism, often Nonfactualism is the canonical way of motivating a noncognitivist understanding of the relevant discourse, and so often Noncognitivism without Nonfactualism remains an unmotivated (if consistent) view.40 For my purposes, then, it will not be necessary to distinguish Nonfactualism from Noncognitivism: I have already rejected Metanormative Error Theory as unable to block my argument for Robust Realism, so the nonfactualist option that remains has to be noncognitivist. And a noncognitivist view of normative discourse that is not also a nonfactualist one is not a relevant alternative to Robust Realism (and to other metanormative views), for it still owes us an account of these normative facts, and presumably it will be along either reductivist or robust realist lines. In what follows, then, I use the term “Noncognitivism” (the 40 It is perhaps interesting to mention here yet another characterization of (metaethical) Noncognitivism one sometimes comes across: It is the claim that there are no moral properties. I think this characterization can be either metaphysical or semantic, depending on one’s views about properties (and often such a characterization trades on both the metaphysical and the semantic claims and fails to distinguish between them). 232 more common term in the metaethical literature41) as referring to the view that there are no normative facts, and that normative discourse is not primarily in the fact-stating business, but rather serves to express non-cognitive attitudes. How, then, is Metanormative Noncognitivism supposed to block my argument for Robust Realism? The noncognitivist can happily concede that normative thoughts and commitments are deliberatively indispensable. So long as she can then defend a noncognitivist understanding of such thoughts and commitments, she can block the move from this indispensability to (justified) belief in normative truths, facts, properties and the like. Yes, the noncognitivist can argue, we cannot sincerely deliberate without taking some things to be better reasons than others (and so on); but such normative thoughts and commitments on our part do not commit us to there being reasons, or reason-facts, or normative properties, out there in the world, for normative discourse (of which these thoughts and commitments are part) does not attempt to describe the normative part of the world. Rather, it serves to express noncognitive attitudes. If my argument from deliberative indispensability to Robust Realism is to be successfully defended, then, I must show that deliberation cannot survive this way of thinking of the normative thoughts and commitments indispensable to it.42 The term “Expressivism” is also sometimes used in the literature to depict noncognitivist views. But I think the term is somewhat misleading, as sentences in perfectly factual discourses also serve to express attitudes – beliefs, usually. What distinguishes noncognitivist from cognitivist discourses is not their expressive function, nor the fact that what is being expressed are attitudes, but rather the kind of attitude expressed, and in particular whether or not it is belief-like. 42 Or, to repeat a point made in section 4.1, it will be sufficient to show that Noncognitivism fails for independent reasons. But I will not discuss such reasons here. 41 233 4.3.2 Why Emotivism Will Not Do the Job So consider first a crude version of Noncognitivism, the Emotivism of Ayer (1936, chapter 6). Now Ayer put forward a Metaethical Emotivism, but it seems clear from his arguments and positivistic motivation that he would happily generalize it to the metanormative theory more relevant here. According to Metanormative Emotivism, then, there are no normative facts, and normative sentences – their indicative mood notwithstanding – are not truth-apt at all, but are rather disguised exhortations, expressions of approval or disapproval (of a special kind, perhaps). Saying that you had reason to help her (as indeed you did) is, according to this Emotivism, somewhat like saying “You helped her – Good!” and saying that it is irrational to believe a contradiction is a bit like saying “Believing a contradiction – Boo!”43, and similarly for all other normative judgments. Now consider a situation in which you deliberate, asking yourself what it makes most sense for you to do. And remember that at this stage of the argument we already assume (what was established in chapter 3) that normative thoughts and commitments are indispensable for deliberation. So we can safely assume that when you try to decide what to do, you engage (though perhaps not explicitly) in normative thought. Now suppose Emotivism is true, and that you know as much. So you know that any normative judgment you are going to end up making is 43 Tom Nagel reminds me that booing can be a way of expressing a perfectly objective, factual belief (his example is “Boo!” shouted at an umpire in response to a decision of hers). The booing emotivists want for the analogy with ethics is, of course, not this kind of booing. 234 going to amount to a disguised exhortation, to a mere expression of an a-rational attitude of approval or disapproval. You are considering, to pick up the example from chapter 3, whether to go to graduate school in order to study philosophy or to join a law firm, and you know that when you are finally willing to commit yourself to something like “All things considered, joining a law firm really is the thing for me to do” this commitment of yours is going to be equivalent to something like “Joining a law firm – yeah!” or “Graduate school? Yuch!”. It seems clear, however, that these are exactly not the kind of things we look for when we deliberate. To see that consider the following point, emphasized in chapter 3. When deliberating, we look for the right answer, or at least one of the better answers, to the question what should we do. And, of course, such an endeavor is ruled out by viewing all answers as equally good, or by the (believed) absence of any relevant criteria of correctness. If whatever decision I am going to end up endorsing is going to be the right one simply in virtue of me endorsing it, for instance, I cannot sincerely deliberate (though I can still waste time and energy on an agonized picking). But assuming Emotivism, I know that my conclusion is going to be merely the expression of an a-rational attitude, one that I just happen to find myself with. Of course, this observation need do nothing to undermine the attitude, but it does undermine any deliberation. For according to Emotivism, there are – ex hypothesi – no criteria of correctness that apply to the attitudes expressed by 235 normative judgments44, and in the absence of such criteria no deliberation is possible. Some resemblance between the phenomenology of deliberation and that of interpersonal disagreement has already been discussed in previous chapters. It is worth mentioning, then, that the point made here about deliberation parallels a well-known objection to Emotivism based on interpersonal disagreement. For if all normative judgments are mere expressions of a-rational attitudes, then normative disagreement is either impossible45 (if understood as disagreement in belief, or even more broadly as disagreement regulated by some rational criteria), or – if it exists – is at least very different from how we typically think of it, being – in Stevenson’s (1937) terms – a disagreement in attitude. Such a view of disagreement – including of what is going on when we present arguments and try to convince our interlocutors (and they us) – does carnage to our view of normative disagreement. When we engage in a normative (e.g., moral) discussion with people with whom we differ, we typically look for exactly the kind of right answers Emotivism says are not out there to be found, we typically think our interlocutors are wrong, not just that they have different attitudes than we do and that we want them to come to have more similar ones46. 44 One of the advantages of contemporary Noncognitivism over Emotivism is that the former can deny this claim. I discuss this move in the next section. 45 This seems to have been Ayer’s original view: 1936, 107. 46 Blackburn (2001, 4) seems to make just this point when he writes “We do not just ‘prefer’ this or that.”, but he actually denies it, as can be seen from the sentence that immediately follows: “We prefer that our preferences are shared; we turn them into demands on each other.” 236 Perhaps we are wrong – perhaps there are no answers to the questions we ask ourselves in deliberation and each other in interpersonal disagreement. Perhaps, in other words, the argument in section 4.2 (and in previous chapters) fails and an error theory is after all in order. But surely Emotivism – presented as a purported descriptive account of normative discourse and its commitments, and thus as an alternative to a metanormative error theory – is unacceptable. 4.3.3 Why More Sophisticated Versions of Noncognitivism Will Do No Better As already mentioned, no one today (I think) is a crude emotivist. And modern descendants of this crude version of Emotivism – mostly Blackburn’s Projectivism and Quasi-Realism47 and Gibbard’s Norm-Expressivism48, and to an extent also Hare’s Universal Prescriptivism49 – do present significant improvements over it. I now want to argue, though, that the improvements – important though they may be in other contexts – will not help the noncognitivist accommodate what is indispensable for deliberation, and that Noncognitivism can therefore not be used to block my argument for Robust Realism. The only possible way of deserting Emotivism while staying within a noncognitivist framework is, it seems, to rely on a more subtle psychology. Noncognitivism requires that the state of mind or attitude expressed by normative 47 See, for instance, many of the papers collected in his Essays in Quasi-Realism (1993a). Systematically developed in his Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (1990). 49 See, for instance, his Moral Thinking (1981). 48 237 judgments be desire-like rather than belief-like, but it does not require that normative judgments express attitudes as simple as those expressed by utterances of “Boo!”. The relevant conative attitude can be fairly complex and even structured, available or unavailable to simple introspection, it can be a function of some sorts of other more basic attitudes interacting in different ways, different normative judgments may involve different conative attitudes, and so on. And this is indeed at least one central route contemporary noncognitivists have taken. So, to take a prominent example: According to Gibbard (1992), all normative judgments are reducible to judgments of rationality, and these are in turn understood noncognitivistically – to call something rational is to express acceptance of a system of norms that permits it (7). The state of mind of accepting a norm (from which acceptance of a system of norms is constructed) is a complex dispositional state (74-5), involving the disposition to be motivated in accordance with the relevant normative judgment (75), the disposition to avow one’s normative commitment in an open discussion (74), the disposition to accept higher-order norms that require acceptance of the relevant norm (that is, the disposition to be in the complex dispositional state – accepting a norm – also regarding this higherorder normative judgment) (101), and so on. Furthermore, the state of accepting a system of norms is highly structured, allowing Gibbard to speak of relations of implication and entailment among normative judgments (83-102). And, again 238 unlike “Boo!”-attitudes, the state of accepting a norm need not be easily accessible by introspection50: You may be surprised to find out what norms you really accept. Such psychological complexities and subtleties make Gibbard’s Noncognitivism immune to some of the obvious difficulties Emotivism seems unable to overcome. Gibbard’s Noncognitivism can accommodate – to an extent, at least – the phenomenon of someone sincerely uttering a normative judgment without having a clear, phenomenologically accessible, pro-attitude towards it; the structure of normative judgments and of the mental states of accepting them allows Gibbard to go a long way in addressing the Frege-Geach challenge, that of giving a unified account of the content of normative judgments in assertoric and nonassertoric contexts; and the availability of higher-order norms – norms that govern the acceptance of norms – allows Gibbard’s Noncognitivism to escape the charge that the attitudes expressed by normative judgments are completely a-rational, immune to normative criticism. It should be noted here, however, that these psychological complexities also make Noncognitivism vulnerable to two common objections I shall only mention here: The first is that the complex attitude expressed by normative judgments cannot be identified except in just this way – using normative vocabulary51. This was not a problem with Emotivism, where the relevant attitudes were supposed to be phenomenologically distinct and rather 50 I do not know of a place in Wise Choices where Gibbard says so explicitly, but that this is so clearly follows from the complex dispositional nature of the state of accepting a norm. 51 See, for instance, McDowell (1987, 219) and Rosen (1998, 389). 239 simple. But with complex theoretical constructs52 such as the state of mind of accepting a norm, a mental state that is not necessarily accessible upon introspection, the worry that no characterization of the attitude except in normative terms will be adequate is a serious one. The second objection sophisticated Noncognitivism – unlike Emotivism – is vulnerable to is that it may be so sophisticated, that it is no longer clear that it is not merely a terminological variant of some cognitivist views53. If accepting a norm is an attitude subject to rational criteria of consistency, if it is logically structured, and so on, why not just acknowledge that it is a belief (perhaps of a special sort), and cease to present one’s view as noncognitivist?54 The sophisticated noncognitivist may have available to her replies to these objections, and I do not pretend that they are obviously conclusive. Nor will I be able to discuss them further here. I mention them only in order to make the following point: The psychological subtlety modern noncognitivists bring to their metanormative theory has – despite its significant advantages – also some serious prima facie costs. What effect, though, do these psychological subtleties have on the possibility of Noncognitivism accommodating the kind of normative thought 52 See Gibbard (1992, 970-1). See Zangwill (1990), Hill (1992), and Dreier (1999). 54 Such suspicions are strengthened by Blackburn’s Quasi-Realism which I briefly discuss in the next section. One reason often given why a view such as Gibbard’s is still best seen as a version of Noncognitivism is that according to it acceptance of normative judgments can motivate, but beliefs cannot. But it is hard to see what – except for a choice of terminology – distinguishes such a noncognitivist view from a cognitivist view that denies the Humean claim and sees normative beliefs as motivationally efficacious. Blackburn himself (1993b, 367) makes what I think is a similar point, and in conversation so has Gibbard. For a suggestion that Noncognitivism should be understood simply as the claim that normative judgments can motivate, see Horwich, (1993 and 1994). 53 240 indispensable for deliberation? It may seem that there is in this respect all the difference in the world between Emotivism and modern-day Noncognitivism. The problem with Emotivism, remember, was that disguised exhortations and expressions of a-rational pro-attitudes are inadequate to settle deliberation, free as they are from any criteria of correctness. But Noncognitivism seems to avoid this problem, by employing a number of mechanisms unavailable to Emotivism. Perhaps the most useful of them is that of higher-order norms (Gibbard, 1990, 168-170)55. As mentioned above, the psychological complexity of Noncognitivism allows it to utilize the useful device of higher-order norms – norms about what norms ought to be accepted – the acceptance of which is itself the complex conative state purportedly expressed by normative judgments. With such a device at hand, it ceases to be true that the attitudes expressed by normative judgments are immune to criticism. Thus, if you accept a norm n, and I accept a second-order norm requiring that n not be accepted, I can say that you accept a norm you ought not to accept, and noncognitivists can present an understanding of such a claim. Importantly, it may even be the case that I accept n, but also the higher-order norm requiring that I not accept it. In this case I can say that I accept a norm I should not accept, and again noncognitivists can accommodate as much. Furthermore, given that norm-acceptance need not be introspectively transparent, there may be cases in which I sincerely wonder not just what to do, but also what norms I should (and 55 Though not as explicit about this, Blackburn too makes extensive use of this device. See, for instance, Blackburn (1982, 175). 241 do) accept. So the attitude expressed by normative judgments can no longer be seen to be a-rational in the way Ayer’s disguised exhortations were. They are themselves subject to normative criteria. Furthermore, given the possibility of mistake – that is, the possibility of accepting norms I ought not to accept 56 – the relevant criteria of correctness do not depend on my decision at the end of any particular instance of deliberation. So it seems that normative thought understood along such noncognitivist lines can yield what is needed for deliberation – better and worse answers, criteria of correctness that do not depend on the result of the very deliberation at hand. Let me concede a point here: Given sufficiently robust criteria of correctness (and I return to this robustness condition shortly) that apply to relevant noncognitive states and attitudes, I think Noncognitivism is entirely compatible with all that is needed for deliberation. Even if, for instance, moral judgments are (merely) expressions of conative attitudes, still their objectivity57 is not threatened so long as there are objective criteria of correctness as to which noncognitive attitudes are appropriate in the relevant circumstances58. But, remember, the noncognitivist view we are interested in here is Global Metanormative 56 There is a worry here, one that I hope to pursue elsewhere: For it seems that Noncognitivism here conflates mistake with absence of justification, or truth with justification. To the extent that we hold this distinction dear to our heart even with regard to normative beliefs (or judgments), this may be a serious flaw. For a hint at this objection, see Sturgeon (1986b, 129-132). 57 “Objectivity” is, of course, a dangerously ambiguous word. The sentence in the text is true, I think, in any sense of objectivity, so long as it is objectivity in the same sense of both moral judgments and the criteria of correctness. 58 So there is room in logical space for an often neglected view – an utterly objectivist version of Metaethical Noncognitivism. See Butler (1988, 21), and Scanlon (1998, 59), who says there is little difference between his (realist) view and Gibbard’s “as long as there are standards of correctness for attitudes of the relevant sort”. 242 Noncognitivism, the view that applies to all normative judgments. So in particular, it applies to the very purported criteria of correctness that in their turn apply to the relevant noncognitive attitudes. And this, I think, undermines their status as genuine criteria of correctness. A quick way to make this point is as follows: Either our first-order conative attitudes are sufficient to bring deliberation to its conclusion, or they are not. If they are, there is of course no (deliberative) need for higher-order norms and the criteria of correctness regarding lower-order norms they incorporate. If, however, first-order norms cannot bring deliberation to its conclusion because while deliberating we look for something more robust (or more robustly normative), then it is hard to see how higher-order norms are going to do any better.59 But more can be said. When deliberating, what we look for is the elimination of arbitrariness and contingency (or at least contingency on the wrong things). We look for reasons. As argued in section 3.4.2, even when acting on a desire having concluded our deliberation, we commit ourselves to the normative judgment that the desire does indeed give a reason for our acting in the relevant way. And, as also argued in chapter 3, our deliberation doesn’t stop at the base level. We also deliberate about which desires to cultivate, and indeed also about what norms – lower- as well as higher-order ones – to accept. But just as we 59 This objection parallels a famous one made by Watson (1975, section 3) against Frankfurt on higher-order desires. Zangwill (1990, 594) and Nagel (1997, 110) make similar points in this context. 243 cannot, while deliberating, settle for a mere desire we find ourselves with but rather we require a normative judgment (even if it is just that the desire gives a reason to act in the relevant way), so too we cannot, when deliberating about what norms to accept, settle for the norms (of whatever order) we merely find ourselves with. What we are looking for are norms the status of which does not depend in any way on arbitrary and contingent factors, like our conative makeup. So Metanormative Noncognitivism mischaracterizes the commitments of normative thought and discourse as applied in deliberation. And notice that the problem thus understood applies to any version of Noncognitivism60: So long as there are no norms the status of which is not rooted in our perfectly contingent and arbitrary affective attitudes – so long, in other words, as Noncognitivism is assumed to be true – there are going to be no criteria of correctness sufficiently robust to allow for deliberation61. Metanormative Noncognitivism precludes deliberation.62 It may be helpful here to cite from Blackburn (1988, 176) what may be treated as a noncognitivist reply to my argument: Does the lover escape his passion by thinking ‘Oh, it’s only my passion, forget it’? When the world affords occasion for grief, does it brighten when we realize that it is we who grieve? 60 And for quite a number of cognitivist yet subjectivist views. I return to those in section 4.4. McDowell (1987, 218) makes a similar point. 62 Metaethical Noncognitivism is often criticized for being entirely third-personal, fitting at most the point of view of the anthropologist studying human moral behavior, not that of an agent. See, for instance, Wiggins (1998). (See also Darwall (1995, 16) and Schneewind (1998, 361), though they discuss some of the antecedents of modern Noncognitivism – Hume and Hutcheson). The criticism in the text can be seen as an elaboration of this objection. 61 244 Blackburn here points at the fact that acknowledging the arbitrary and contingent source of a strong emotion need not in any way diminish its intensity or somehow undermine it. And this is surely true in the cases of love and grief. But the case of normative judgments – those needed in deliberation – is very different. We are struck by love and grief, and criteria of correctness seem completely irrelevant to such emotions63. Love and grief do not involve a search for reasons, for the elimination of arbitrariness. When trying to decide what it makes most sense for us to do, on the other hand, reasons are exactly what we look for. The cases of love and grief can therefore not be used by the noncognitivist to argue that normative thought noncognitivistically understood suffices for deliberation. Noncognitivism, then, cannot accommodate the normative truths and judgments indispensable for deliberation. But perhaps it should not be understood as trying to. Perhaps it should be understood as rejecting the view of deliberation presented in chapter 3, and in particular in section 3.4.2, arguing that desires (or more sophisticated desire-like attitudes) are after all sufficient to bring deliberation to its conclusion64. I shall not here rehearse my arguments against such a view. 4.3.4 Why Quasi-Realism Is beside the Point There is another, related, difference between Blackburn’s examples and the case of normative judgments. We typically think of normative judgments as interpersonally valid in a way love and grief are not. This is yet another place where there is an important analogy between deliberation and interpersonal disagreement. But I cannot discuss this point in detail here. 64 I suspect Blackburn tends more clearly than Gibbard in this direction, as can perhaps be seen from the passage on love and grief just quoted. 63 245 For many years now Simon Blackburn has been developing his quasi-realist project (about ethics as about other discourses), the essence of which is supplying with antirealist grounds that allow one to say just about everything the realist wants to say65. The idea is simple enough – start with an antirealism of the noncognitivist variety. Then ask what it is that we realists find troubling about such antirealism. Compile a list of all the things we realists want to be able to say about the relevant discourse, things we think we can only say if we are realists about it. These would presumably include (in the moral case) things like: Bullfighting is wrong; Bullfighting is really wrong; It’s true that bullfighting is wrong; It’s a fact that bullfighting is wrong; Bullfighting is objectively wrong; Bullfighting would have been wrong even had we thought it was permissible; Our thinking so doesn’t make bullfighting wrong; Bullfighting is wrong even in societies that accept bullfighting; We believe that bullfighting is wrong because it is, not the other way around; I believe bullfighting is wrong, but I may be wrong about this; and so on.66 The final, crucial, stage in the quasi-realist project is showing that these sentences, when properly understood, are perfectly available to the antirealist. Showing that is supposed, of course, to leave the realist rejection of antirealism unmotivated.67 Gibbard too seems now to endorse something very much like Blackburn’s Quasi-Realism. See, for instance, Gibbard (1999, 142, footnote 3). 66 For some of these examples, and a few others, see Blackburn (1993, 4). 67 For one of the clearer presentations of the quasi-realist project, see Blackburn (1988). 65 246 The details of the quasi-realist project – though of considerable independent interest – are not needed here. Nor are the many problems of detail this project still faces. What is important for my purpose here is that the project, if successful, can be thought to challenge the argument in section 4.3.3. For if Blackburn can entitle us – consistently with an antirealist, noncognitivist, grounding – to say all we realists want to say, and seeing that we want to be able to use normative judgments in deliberation, then Blackburn can entitle us – consistently with the rejection of realism (and certainly of Robust Realism) – to use normative judgments in deliberation68. And if that is so, then irreducibly normative truths are after all not indispensable for deliberation. Of course, Blackburn cannot let his quasi-realist project be too successful, for if it is – if there really is nothing the realist wants to say that the quasi-realist cannot say – then rather than arguing against realism Blackburn will have argued against the distinction between realism and antirealism69. But Blackburn repeatedly emphasizes70 that his Quasi-Realism is based on his antirealism. So we have to see what difference remains, according to Blackburn, between the realist and his quasi-realist. Here is Blackburn: “… realists always find it hard to say anything with which idealists cannot arrange to agree by giving it their own meaning.” (Nagel, 1986, 101) 69 For an especially clear presentation of this worry, see Rosen (1998, e.g. at 395). Johnston (1989, 141) seems to express a similar suspicion when he characterizes those who hold a view of colors analogous to Blackburn’s metaethical Quasi-Realism as “delayed-reaction colour realists”. 70 As when he characterizes his view as “expressivism with quasi-realist trimmings” (1999, 213). Nevertheless, at times he is not as clear about this, apparently willing to accept realism as commonly characterized – see Blackburn (1991b, 42). 68 247 But sure we do have a serviceable way of describing the [realist-antirealist] debate, at least as far as it concerns evaluation and morals. It is about explanation. The projectivist holds that our nature as moralists is well explained by regarding us as reacting to a reality which contains nothing in the way of values, duties, rights, and so forth; a realist thinks it is well explained only by seeing us as able to perceive, cognize, intuit, an independent moral reality. He holds that the moral features of things are the parents of our sentiments, whereas the Humean holds that they are their children.” (1981, 164-5; see also 185-6). So the difference seems to come to a difference in explanatory priority 71. One may, of course, question whether the explanatory claim Blackburn saddles the realist with is really essential to realism (Rosen (1998, 396) does, and to an extent so have I, in chapter 1). But let me grant Blackburn for the sake of argument this characterization of what is at issue. Notice, then, that this distinctive commitment of the quasi-realist to the explanatory priority of our normative emotions and reactions over the normative truths or facts is all that is needed in order to run against him the line of section 4.3.3 above. For such priority, together with the contingency and arbitrariness of our psychology, entails that the normative truths and facts (or quasi-truths and quasi-facts) are contingent and arbitrary in exactly the way their role in deliberation doesn’t allow. 71 See also Blackburn (1999, 216). For a similar point made by Gibbard, in the context of replying to the worry that his view is a mere terminological variant of some cognitivist view, see Gibbard (1992, 971). 248 Now, Blackburn likes to emphasize that – via a careful reading of counterfactuals and claims about dependence and contingency – his view actually rules out contingency just as much as a fairly robust realism does 72. But, regardless of the details here73, this just cannot be right74: If he succeeds in abolishing all contingency, he abolishes with it what is supposed to distinguish between his view and a fairly robust realism. And if, as seems more likely, at least one kind of contingency – the one depicted by the parent-and-child-metaphor – remains, then the point in the previous paragraph applies. Either way, then, Quasi-Realism is, as far as my argument for Robust Realism is concerned, beside the point. 4.4 Normative Naturalism Normative Naturalism is the metanormative analogue of the metaethical view (or family of views) knows as Ethical Naturalism – the view that, roughly, acknowledges normative (moral) facts, and holds that they are reducible to natural facts. In section 4.4.1 I characterize Normative Naturalism more carefully, then arguing – in section 4.4.2 – that no normative naturalist view can accommodate deliberation. In section 4.4.3 I reject an argument purportedly showing that the conjunction of (any kind of) metanormative realism with a very plausible claim about the modal status of basic normative truths entails Normative Naturalism. 72 See, e.g., Blackburn (1988, 173). For objections to his rather obviously tendentious discussion of counterfactuals, insisting on reading them only “internally”, see, for instance, Cassam (1986) and Ramussen (1995). 74 The point that follows resembles a point made by McDowell (1985, 124, footnote 4) and Sturgeon (1992, 114, footnote 2). 73 249 One preliminary point is in order here: I will only be discussing in this context naturalist reductions of the normative. In so restricting the scope of my discussion I may seem to be compromising the exhaustiveness of the taxonomy presented in section 4.1, because of the possibility of views attempting to reduce the normative to something other than the natural. The obvious examples of such views are versions of the (metanormative analogue of) Divine Command Theory. I will not discuss such views for three reasons. First, I do not view them as serious metanormative options, and nor does the literature (or the part of it I am interested in), perhaps partly because there is no God. Second, such views seem especially unmotivated as an alternative to Robust Realism. In particular, the metaphysical and epistemological qualms that make (some) people uncomfortable with Robust Realism seem to count at least as heavily against any purported supernaturalist reduction base for the normative. Third, and most importantly, as the reader will notice, the problems raised below for Normative Naturalism are easily applicable, mutatis mutandis, to Normative Supernaturalism, so that a separate discussion of such views can, I think, safely be avoided. 4.4.1 Normative Naturalism The defining thesis of Normative Naturalism is that normative facts (or propositions, or properties) are reducible to natural facts (or propositions, or properties). In order to understand Normative Naturalism better, then, we need to look into the ideas of the natural and of reduction. 250 Now, it seems like many problems regarding the understanding of the natural can be set aside as irrelevant here. What seems crucial is that, according to normative naturalists, normative facts are reducible to, or identical with, nonnormative ones – (normative) facts about what you have reason to do, for instance, are reducible to (non-normative) facts about what would satisfy your desires. But this way of putting things, however intuitive, cannot be right: The natural facts normative facts are purportedly reducible to are – in virtue of this very reduction – identical to normative facts, and so are normative facts. So what must be meant by the reducibility of the normative to the non-normative is the reducibility of the normative to the apparently non-normative, or to the not-clearly-normative. Similarly – if mental states are physicalistically reducible, then the relevant physical states are mental states, and so the reduction is not of the mental to the non-mental, but rather to the not-obviously-mental, or more simply, to the physical. Now, because of the unclarity and imprecision of locutions such as “notobviously-normative”, it would be better if we had an independent idea of the reduction base, something analogous to the idea we have of the physical75 when we come to formulate physicalist reductions of the mental. What are, then, the natural facts to which normative naturalists think the normative is reducible? These are, roughly speaking, the facts of the kind the 75 It is, of course, anything but clear that we have such an understanding of the physical, one that is independent of the (supposed) contrast between the physical and the mental. But for the purposes of the analogy in the text, we can assume this problem away. 251 natural sciences deal with76. These include the facts physics deals with, but not necessarily only them. The natural facts include also highly complex facts of the kind the special sciences deal with, whether or not they are reducible to the physical ones. Among these are, of course, the facts of biology, but also psychological facts, sociological ones, and so on. This way of putting things is vague, but it is not without content – we can easily come up with paradigmatically natural facts, such that if normative facts are reducible to them Normative Naturalism is clearly vindicated. These include facts about people’s desires, people’s pleasures, economic growth, survival and productivity, and so on. In what follows, this rough characterization of the natural will do: The major examples of normative naturalist views are attempts to reduce the normative to such paradigmatically natural facts, and I will argue against any view that endorses a reduction to anything not clearly normative. Things get trickier when we get to reduction, as many normative naturalists (in the sense I use this term) now explicitly deny the reducibility of the normative to the natural77. What they typically deny is, first, an analytic or a priori knowable reduction, one that asserts an equivalence of meaning (or a relation very close to that) between normative sentences (or predicates) and natural ones. They deny reduction thus understood either because of general Quinean worries about 76 See, for instance, Svavarsdóttir (2001, 181). Brink (1989) repeatedly characterizes his view a non-reductive realism. See also the characterization of such views as non-reductive in Darwall, Gibbard and Railton (1992, 26). A reminder: I freely generalize the views of other writers (these included), from the metaethical views they explicitly endorse or discuss to the metanormative views directly relevant for my discussion here. 77 252 analyticity or the a priori, or because of other general arguments (like Boyd’s cardinality argument), or because impressed with specific problems for analytically reducing the normative, perhaps most notably some version of the Open Question Argument (or because of any combination of these reasons).78 Another, related, claim typically denied by normative naturalists who nevertheless present themselves as rejecting reduction is that (what I call) the reduction base of, say, normative properties is as “friendly” as the reduced ones. Yes, they argue, normative facts are at bottom natural facts, but the relevant natural facts may be messy, highly disjunctive, and so on79. Others, who go for a metaethical analogue of functionalism in the philosophy of mind, may deny reduction meaning they deny any necessary type-type identity thesis between normative and at least firstorder natural properties80. Yet others deny even that normative facts are identical with natural facts, still clinging to Naturalism by arguing that normative facts are nevertheless constituted by natural ones81. I want to include all of these views (or rather their metanormative analogues, for they are typically presented as metaethical theories) under the heading of Normative Naturalism, and I want to consider a naturalist reduction its defining thesis. So I should present a broader understanding of reduction. The general Quinean worries are often left implicit. For a discussion of Boyd’s cardinality argument, see Sturgeon (1984, 59-60). For the relevance of the Open Question Argument, see, for instance, Railton (1989b, 157), Brink (2001). 79 Sturgeon (1984, 60-1). 80 See Jackson and Pettit (1995), but note that they acknowledge that their view presents a naturalist reduction of sorts. For a brief discussion of a related view – one supposedly analogous to Davidson’s anomalous monism in the philosophy of mind – see Scott (1980, 266). 81 See Brink (1989, chapter 6). 78 253 The intuitive idea behind reduction-claims can, I think, be put roughly as the following conjunction: A kind of fact F1 is reducible to a kind of fact F2 just in case F1-facts are nothing over and above F2-facts, and if there is something more basic about their description as F2-facts compared to their description as F1-facts82. The first conjunct is the intuitive ground for an identity thesis (except, given the denial of identity by certain normative naturalists, it may be better to settle for the intuitive formulation in terms of the nothing-over-and-above relation). The second is meant to capture the anti-symmetrical character of reduction – the idea that if F1facts are reducible to F2-facts, then really, at bottom, F2 facts do the work. An example might help, so think of chair-facts. It is very hard to come up with a reductive definition of chair-facts in, say, physical terms, and the task does not become much easier (though perhaps somewhat easier) if we allow psychological facts into the reduction base. Furthermore, any plausible reduction base is going to be highly complex and disjunctive. It seems likely that in any such reduction base functions are going to play a crucial role. And it may be argued that chairs are not identical with the matter that constitutes them (for, arguably, the very same chair could have been composed of slightly different material parts83). Nevertheless, it seems clear that chair-facts are reducible – in a perfectly understandable sense of this term – to facts that are not clearly chair-facts, to This characterization roughly follows Fine’s (2001). He proceeds to discuss worries about the intelligibility and nature of the notion of basicness here involved, and consequently of that of reduction (and of realism), but, as will become obvious, I do not need to address these worries here. 83 This is the criterion Brink uses to distinguish between identity and constitution. See Brink (1989, 157). 82 254 physical and perhaps psychological and functional facts. Chair-facts are not plausibly considered sui generis, and there are no (special) metaphysical mysteries, it seems, about chairs, because of the availability of such reduction. The characterization of reduction above captures, I think, the sense in which chair-facts are obviously reducible to physical (and psychological and functional) facts: Facts about chairs are nothing over and above these facts, and their non-chairdescription is more basic. Normative Naturalism, then, is the thesis that normative facts are reducible in this sense to natural ones, that, in other words, normative facts are nothing over and above the facts of the kind studied by the natural sciences, and that there is something more basic about their description as natural facts, that normative facts are at bottom natural facts and not the other way around.84 Of these two components of the view, I will focus on the first, arguing that any view according to which normative facts are nothing over and above natural facts cannot allow for sincere deliberation. The second component will remain in the background, but it will not be without significance: A view according to which, say, the reduction goes the other way – natural facts are reducible to normative ones – will not be ruled out by the argument that follows, because, whatever its other flaws, it does not rule out deliberation. 84 Sturgeon (1984, 59; 1986, 117), who denies reduction in more narrow senses, concedes that his view is reductivist in a broader sense, like the one in the text. 255 Normative naturalist views come in many forms. It may be helpful to give here a few examples of categories of views that are naturalist in the sense employed here (the examples are not necessarily mutually exclusive). One clear example is that of classically reductive views, views that take a major normative property and argue for its analytic (or at least a priori) identity with a natural property. Bentham’s identification of rightness with the property of maximizing the balance of pleasure over pain85 is a prominent example of this classically reductive line. Some contemporary writers endorse such an identity (or one similar to it), but argue that it is a posteriori, and certainly not analytic. Such views – sometimes referred to as instances of Cornell Realism, New-Wave Moral Realism, or Synthetic Naturalism – are also examples of Normative Naturalist views86. Similarly, functionalist views that think of (whatever they take to be) the central or most basic normative property as identical with the natural property – whatever it is – that plays a certain role (specifiable, of course, in naturalistically respectable terms) are normative naturalist views87. So are typical examples of dispositionalist views, according to which normative properties are to be understood as roughly analogous with secondary qualities (with those understood dispositionally), so that the property of being, say, a value is the property of being such as to elicit in us a certain reaction, perhaps under suitable conditions, with these conditions 85 Bentham (1789, 4 (Chapter 1, section 11)). See, for instance, Sturgeon (1984), Lycan (1986), Railton (1986a), Boyd (1988), Brink (1989). 87 See Jackson and Pettit (1995). I should say that it is not completely clear to me that there is a real difference – not, that is, merely a terminological one – between such Functionalism and Synthetic Naturalism of the sort just discussed, especially given the scientific methodology typically endorsed by holders of that latter view. See, for instance, Boyd (1988). 86 256 understood in a naturalistically respectable way (not in normative terms, that is, and in particular not in terms of a whatever-it-takes-to-get-things-right clause)88. Ideal Observer (or Advisor) Theories are also naturalist views because they hold that the relevant normative properties are identical with the natural property of being chosen (or liked, or approved of, or whatever) by an observer suitably placed (again, assuming the ideal conditions are specified in a naturalistically respectable way)89. Neo-Aristotelian views according to which normative facts are to be understood primarily as complex facts about the functions of things (or persons) and how they measure up to these functions are also typically thought of as naturalist views, as indeed they should be so long as the relevant functions and the measuring-up relation are understood in naturalistically respectable ways 90. All desire-based theories of reasons, according to which facts about what reasons one has are identical with facts about what desires or preferences one has (or would have under some counterfactual conditions specified in a naturalistically respectable way) are likewise instances of Normative Naturalism91, as are 88 See Lewis (1989); Brower (1993). Johnston (1989, 145) is especially clear regarding whatever-ittakes clauses. Because of Smith’s insistence that he does not offer a reduction of the normative (see, e.g. Smith, 1997, 98), it is not clear to me whether Smith’s Dispositionalism is another example relevant here. His analysis may remain entirely within the normative domain. Johnston’s view (1989), though dispositionalist to an extent, is certainly not an instance of Normative Naturalism, as he insists that the reduction base of anything normative must itself be normative (and so his analysis employs at least one normative notion). 89 See, for instance, Firth (1952), and Railton (1986a and 1986b). 90 See, for instance, Foot (2001). 91 See Darwall’s (1983, 81) formulation (but not endorsement) of such views. See also Williams (1980), where the relevant conditions are those of rational deliberation, with this rationality naturalistically understood. And see Hubin (1996) for an argument claiming that hypothetical motivation views should be discarded and replaced by actual motivations theories. 257 conventionalist or relativist views reducing normative facts to social ones 92. And, as will be explained in section 4.5, constructivist views may be considered naturalist too. As is clear, then, Normative Naturalism is a family of very many different views, and it would be impossible to do justice to them all here. In what follows I focus on what they all have in common – the identification of normative with some natural facts – and to a large extent ignore the differences among them. The discussion of section 4.4.2 is therefore not meant as a comprehensive discussion of naturalist metanormative views, but rather just as the minimum needed in order to see why it is that reductivist views cannot block my argument for Robust Realism. One last preliminary: Normative Naturalism should be clearly distinguished from the (obvious) claim that what is being evaluated by our normative thoughts are natural states of affairs, actions, persons, and so on. It is, of course, true that the things that are good are (typically, primarily, and perhaps even only) natural things, that we have reasons to perform perfectly natural actions, and so on. From this platitude Normative Naturalism – the identification of normative facts and properties with natural ones – does not follow. To use Parfit’s (forthcoming, chapter 2) terms, we must not conflate the property of being good (or right, or reasonable, or valuable) with the natural properties that make things 92 See, e.g. Harman (1977). 258 good (or right, or whatever)93. Perhaps Naturalism is after all true, but surely its truth cannot be established by relying on such confusion. So, for instance, one can believe that the only thing intrinsically good is pleasure without thinking that the property of goodness is identical with the property of being a pleasure, or that we only have reasons to satisfy our desires but that being a reason (for one) is not identical with anything about the satisfactions of one’s desires. (It may be thought that there nevertheless is a route from the platitude to Normative Naturalism. I argue against such a route in section 4.4.3.) 4.4.2 Why Normative Naturalism Will Not Do According to Normative Naturalism, there are normative facts, and so the normative questions we ask ourselves in deliberation have right and wrong, or at least better and worse, answers. So it seems that my argument from deliberative indispensability – even if successful as an argument for some kind of metanormative realism – cannot rule out Normative Naturalism. This would mean, of course, that as an argument for Robust Realism my argument fails – if naturalistically reducible normative truths or facts are all that is needed for deliberation, irreducibly normative truths are after all not deliberatively indispensable. This is why Normative Naturalism threatens to block my argument for Robust Realism. Though scholars differ regarding what Moore had in mind when talking of “The Naturalistic Fallacy”, it seems to me clear that it was exactly the conflation mentioned in the text. See Moore (1903, 62 (section 10)). 93 259 Now, as already mentioned, naturalist metanormative views come in different stripes, and one possible way of facing this threat is to argue against them piecemeal. Different naturalist views face different problems and challenges, and – as can be seen from the absence of consensus or anything resembling a consensus even among naturalists – none of these views is clearly successful in addressing them. So rejecting Normative Naturalism can be grounded in rejecting specific naturalist views, and perhaps also in a kind of induction: All reductions suggested so far have been found inadequate, and this may be taken to be at least some reason for pessimism regarding the prospects of future reductive attempts. I, however, will attempt a more ambitious strategy, arguing against all possible naturalistic reductions at just one go (or perhaps, as is about to be made clear, two goes). Another strategy I will not pursue here starts with the observation that naturalist views can be divided into two kinds, according to whether the reduction claim they affirm is analytic or synthetic, or perhaps whether it is knowable a priori or a posteriori. One can then argue that the naturalist faces insurmountable difficulties either way. It seems to me a plausible case against Normative Naturalism can indeed be made in this way – I very briefly mention how in a footnote94 – but I will not pursue it here. Rather, in accordance with the strategy 94 As against Analytic Naturalism, perhaps something can be saved from the now-notorious Open Question Argument. For one such attempt, see Gibbard (1990, 11-18), who emphasizes that there may be deep disagreements regarding, say, what is right, that it seems wrong to attribute to the erring party to such a disagreement a linguistic (as opposed to a normative) error, and that Analytic Naturalism is committed to such an attribution. As against Synthetic Naturalism, a number of 260 advertised in section 4.1 above, I want to focus on the inadequacy of Normative Naturalism from the point of view of the deliberating agent. In particular, I think that considering Normative Naturalism from this deliberative standpoint emphasizes a worry often raised with regard to attempts at reducing the normative to the natural. It is the worry that no naturalist reduction can keep the normative force of the reduced facts. Of course, it is not entirely clear what normative force is, and it is hard to suggest an account of it that will not – in our context – beg important questions against at least one party to the metanormative debate. So let me present my argument against a naturalist reduction in a different way, and let me just note here that I think of it as a way of making (reasonably) precise the intuition that no reduction can preserve normative force. From the standpoint of the deliberating agent, suggested reductions can be divided into objective and subjective ones, with these terms stipulatively defined as follows95: A reduction is subjective if the reduction base includes an ineliminable indexical referring to the deliberating agent or her environment; it is objective otherwise. So, the reduction offered by Lewis’s (1989) Dispositionalism related objections can be raised: that it entails the wrong modal status for the supervenience of the normative on the natural (see, for instance, Johnston (1989, 153), who thinks a similar objection threatens any psychologistic reduction of values); that it entails trans-world – and, given plausible anthropological assumptions, even intra-world – relativism (a charge made in a series of papers by Horgan and Timmons, e.g. Horgan and Timmons 1991 and 1992); that it relies on an analogy between normative and scientific theoretical terms, but that the analogy fails because we have very different referential intentions in the two cases (Gampel, 1996; see also Parfit, forthcoming, chapter 2). 95 These terms are not picked arbitrarily, of course: I believe the stipulation in the text captures at least one common meaning of the objective-subjective distinction. The resort to stipulation is meant just to avoid messy controversies about how this distinction is best understood. 261 – according to which something is of value if we are disposed to value it under ideal conditions – is paradigmatically subjective, as is witnessed by the (ineliminable) occurrence of the (plural96) first-person pronoun in it. Similarly, Williams’s (1980) view of reasons – according to which facts about your reasons are reducible to facts about your desires97 – is again offering a subjective reduction, as it is your desires that play a role in the reduction base. Socialrelativist reductions are likewise subjective. Bentham’s (1789, Chapter 1) reduction of the right to the pleasure-over-pain-balance-maximizing is, on the other hand, completely objective, as the specification of the suggested reduction base does not include any ineliminable reference to the deliberating agent 98. Ideal Observer (or Ideal Advisor) Theories are presented sometimes as offering subjective, sometimes objective reductions, depending of the details of the view99. It is clear, I think, that the objective-subjective dichotomy among reductions (as introduced above) is exhaustive, so that if I successfully argue against both these options, I will have argued against Normative Naturalism. Given Lewis’s concession that “we” in his analysis may mean “You and I, and I’m none too sure about you” (1989, 128), it might as well have been the singular first-person pronoun, as he also concedes. 97 Williams complicates matters – I’m not sure that helpfully – by speaking of your subjective motivational set and not just your desires. For my purposes in the text this complication can safely be ignored. 98 It is important not to be confused here by the fact that Bentham’s conception of the good is in terms of subjective states (pain and pleasure). Still, according to Bentham, what it is right for you to do does not depend on your desires or pleasures or pains, except insofar as these influence the general balance, and so there is no ineliminable reference to you in Bentham’s reduction. 99 For a locus classicus of an objective (or, as he refers to it, an absolutist) version of an Ideal Observer reduction, see Firth (1952). For criticisms arguing that Firth’s Ideal Observer Theory should be revised so as to allow for subjectivity (or, as Taliaferro puts it, attempts at relativizing the Ideal Observer Theory), see Brandt (1955), Firth (1955), and the discussion in Taliaferro (1988). 96 262 Take subjective reductions first. The problem about those should already be clear at this point of the argument (see sections 3.4.2 and 4.3.3 above). Any subjective (purported) reduction of the normative is asking the deliberating agent to take something about herself – something that is completely arbitrary and contingent100, like her desires – as given prior to deliberation, and indeed as the source of any answer to the questions she is, in deliberating, asking herself. But it is exactly such arbitrariness that deliberation is an attempt to eliminate. The mere psychological fact that I desire something cannot by itself bring my deliberation to its conclusion (without a normative commitment on my part to take my desire as a reason), and it is hard to see how some (naturalistically respectable) idealization of my desires can help101. So long as perfectly natural – physical, say, or psychological – facts about me play an ineliminable role in her suggested reduction base, the subjectivist is asking me to treat these facts as settling deliberation. But while deliberating I treat these facts – I cannot avoid treating them – as merely contingent, rationally arbitrary, facts about myself. And it is in 100 One may argue that all persons, or humans, or agents, necessarily have certain desires, and then the fact that I have the relevant desire is not contingent. This, I think, is Velleman’s view (developed in many of the papers in his 2000). But, even if such a move can eliminate contingency, it cannot eliminate arbitrariness. Here my criticism of Velleman (in section 2.A.3, in chapter 2) is relevant. 101 Of course, if we are allowed to rule some desires in and some out based on normative criteria – say, discarding all irrational desires (with irrationality understood substantively) – then idealization of that sort may help (though problems would still remain). But, of course, then we do not have at hand a suggested reduction of the normative to the natural. For a clear statement of the claim that one needs, in order to avoid obvious counterexamples, a normative criterion according to which desires are sorted into those that count and those that do not, see Hampton (1992). 263 this sense of arbitrariness that it is antagonistic to deliberation102. Perhaps no such non-arbitrary answers are to be had; perhaps, in other words, a metanormative error theory is after all in order, and our deliberation is doomed from the start to systematic failure. But regardless of whether or not deliberation can be successful, it seems clear that it does – or would – take more than subjective reductions for it to be successful. Any denial of this claim is just not loyal to the phenomenology of deliberation. Notice the contrast on this point between the kind of normative answers we look for in deliberation and discourses about which a subjective reduction seems more plausible. In the discussion of secondary qualities, one common example is that of the nauseating – a secondary quality most of us feel comfortable understanding dispositionally, and indeed subjectively. Now, it seems to me a commonplace regarding the phenomenology of the nauseating that we can appreciate fully the contingency and rational arbitrariness of our psychological and physical responses to which the nauseating is (arguably) reducible, without such awareness compromising in anyway the feeling that the thing in front of us is nauseating. This is so because there is nothing in the phenomenology of the nauseating that commits us to the necessity or rationality or reason-supported status of the nauseating. In the case of the nauseating, rather, we are perfectly 102 The subjective facts in the suggested reduction base may not be arbitrary in other sense of this word. There may, for instance, be good explanations for why we have them and not alternative possible attitudes or dispositions (or whatever). But such, purely explanatory, denial of arbitrariness will not do for deliberative purposes. I thank Tom Nagel for pressing me on a related point. 264 happy to settle for the responses with which we just find ourselves. Perhaps – though this is a complicated matter – color-phenomenology and the phenomenology of the beautiful are in this respect quite like that of the nauseating. But the phenomenology of deliberation is completely different on this point. Fully realizing that a suggested answer to the questions I ask myself in deliberation is contingent (on my conative makeup, say, or on our evaluative practices) and arbitrary does undermine its ability to bring my deliberation to its conclusion. Subjective reduction undermines deliberation.103 Now, necessity can be purchased for cheap, by toying with rigidification. In order to block the move from a subjective reduction to objectionable counterfactuals (had I desired to turn on any radio I come across, would I have had reason to do so?104), an actuality-operator may be introduced to the reductive analysis, one that rigidifies the reference to my actual (e.g.) desires105. Then normative claims gain some kind of modal robustness. But, as is often noted in the literature, such modal robustness is too cheap to be of value, and this rigidifying trick is not a way of addressing the genuine concern here but rather of making it harder to express (Lewis 1989, 132). As Darwall, Gibbard and Railton note (1992, 23), the rigidification trick perhaps guarantees (some kind of) necessity and rules out (some kind of) relativism, but it does so “without addressing underlying 103 In the metaethical literature people often emphasize the objective purport of moral discourse. The point made in the text here is really the metanormative analogue of this familiar point, considered from the standpoint of the deliberating agent. 104 The example is (roughly) Quinn’s (1993, 236). 105 See Wiggins (1990, 80; 1991, e.g. 240); Johnston (1989); Brower (1993, 242). 265 worries about the possible arbitrariness of our evaluative practices, since the feature seized upon to privilege our practices is simply that they are our practices.”106 So much, then, for subjective reductions. But notice that objective reductions are not vulnerable to the same objection, as they do not involve any reference to me and my rationally-arbitrary attitudes. Aren’t objective normative facts all that is needed for deliberation, regardless of whether or not they are naturalistically reducible? It is here that I have to rely on a brute intuition. When I ask myself what I should do, it seems that just answering “Oh – Φ-ing will maximize happiness.” is a complete non-starter, it completely fails to address the question. Of course, given some background commitments it can be a better answer. If, for instance, I am already a convinced utilitarian, willing to commit myself to something like “It always makes sense to perform the action that maximizes happiness”, then “Φ-ing will maximize happiness” seems like a reasonable answer to the question what should I do. But such background commitments are themselves paradigmatically 106 See also Wright (1992, 113-7) and Sosa (2001, 303-4). And here is Blackburn on a similar move: “… if a commitment is well seen as a culturally variable, brutely contingent expression of a disposition to put pressure on ourselves and others, everyone, not merely the freshman relativist, ought to feel uncomfortable at its also claiming a title to objective independent truth. It will not be enough to say that we have the practice of so dignifying it. This will only appear part of the error, or the confidence trick.” (1993b, 378) Ironically, I think Blackburn himself is guilty of a similar flaw when he insists on reading relevant counterfactuals (like “Had I had different conative states, different things would be of value”) only “internally” as themselves made within normative discourse. But I cannot pursue this point here. In a somewhat similar context Korsgaard nicely makes a similar point by analogy: “There’s an old joke about a child who’s glad he doesn’t like spinach, since then he’d eat it, and he hates the disgusting stuff.” (1996, 59). The child from the joke is, of course, toying with rigidification, and the reason the joke is (mildly) amusing is exactly that such a game is so obviously childish. 266 normative. Absent such background commitments, “Φ-ing will maximize happiness” seems just irrelevant to the question I ask myself, and so does any other answer put in purely natural terms. Rather than answering my question, such an answer simply changes the subject. The point I am trying to make is not that such background commitments have to be, as it were, present before your mind’s eye before you can see that that Φ-ing will maximize happiness is relevant to your deliberation. Indeed, very often one forms one’s general normative commitments as a result of noticing the normative relevance of more specific, particular considerations. The point is, rather, that by considering that Φ-ing will maximize happiness as relevant to the question you were asking yourself, you commit yourself to the background (normative) commitment mentioned above. Another way of pumping the same intuition is as follows107: One can know, it seems, all the relevant natural facts, without yet knowing what it makes most sense for one to do. (Or, relatedly, two can agree on all the relevant natural facts, but differ regarding what it makes most sense to do.) And from this it follows108 that the deliberatively-relevant normative fact is not just a natural one, 107 This way is inspired by the famous Knowledge Argument in the philosophy of mind. See Jackson, (1982). Let me state here – without further argument – that I do not see how the moves typically employed by physicalists to deal with the Knowledge Argument can be employed in the context of the normative. 108 Unless, of course, there are no normative facts (and similar arguments are indeed often used to motivate Error Theory or Noncognitivism). At this stage of the argument, however, we are free to ignore this possibility. 267 that it is just a mistake to say that it is nothing over and above the relevant natural one.109 Notice that this intuitive objection applies to subjective reductions as well, but it applies more clearly, I think, to objective ones. Subjective reductions can give answers that, though not normative, still address my concerns in some other way by relating to my motivations. Thus, a “So what?”110 response may sound odd to “Φ-ing is what you yourself would choose to do if you just thought about it carefully” in a way in which it does not sound odd to “Φ-ing will maximize happiness”. Objective reductions of the normative – while not introducing objectionable arbitrariness – divorce normative thought and discourse from their role in deliberation111. This is just a point repeatedly emphasized in chapter 3 looked at from the opposite direction. In chapter 3 I emphasized that, being essentially deliberative, you cannot avoid committing yourself to normative truths, because when letting a consideration bring your deliberation to its conclusion you commit yourself to the (obviously normative) claim that it is a reason. Noting that a naturalist reduction divorces normative thought from its role in deliberation is just a reiteration of that 109 In conversation, Tom Nagel suggested to me that this kind of knowledge argument is intuitively stronger in the case of the mental than in the case of the normative, because we cannot imagine someone who really knows all the natural facts about, say, the gratuitous infliction of suffering on an innocent person and still doesn’t know – doesn’t just see – that it is wrong. I – perhaps because less optimistic – do not share Nagel’s intuition. But even if he is right about the specific case, note that what would be needed in order to reject the argument in the text is that something like Nagel’s intuition would be true in all relevant cases, not just in the most extreme and obvious ones. And this, I think, is highly implausible, 110 For discussion of “the so called ‘So What?’ argument”, see Johnston (1989, 157). 111 It is a misunderstanding of this role – thinking of it as primarily motivating rather than normative – that explains, I think, much of the appeal of (some versions of) internalism. 268 point – deliberation requires normative commitment. And natural facts (and beliefs) just do not suffice for that. The intuition that no answer in terms of a naturalistic reduction succeeds in addressing the questions we ask ourselves in deliberation may be the intuition underlying Moore’s Open Question Argument, only highlighted from the perspective of the deliberating agent112. And so an immediate worry is that, like Moore’s argument, it applies (at most) to purportedly analytic reductions. But this, I think, is not the case. What precludes naturalistic facts from playing the role in deliberation for which normative facts are needed is not their description, but rather their very nature. I return, then, to the brute intuition: Normative facts of the kind needed for deliberation are too different from natural ones, too different to just be natural ones themselves113. 4.4.3 A Final Worry about Property Identity Normative properties are had by natural actions, character traits, objects and so on. And I emphasized the need to distinguish between this platitude and Normative Naturalism. But it may nevertheless be thought that there is in the vicinity an 112 Rosati (1995) also tries to save what can be saved from the Open Question Argument by highlighting it from the perspective of deliberating agents. 113 For expressions of similar intuitions, see Donagan (1981), Johnston (1989, 157), Dancy (1996, 180-2), McGinn (1997, e.g. 11 and 25), Scanlon (1998, 57-8), and Parfit (forthcoming, chapter 2). And perhaps Darwall, Gibbard and Railton have a similar intuition in mind when they say (1992, 30): “… despite their protestation, they [such reductive naturalists] might turn out to be error theorists after all.” For a similar intuition in another context (that of the normativity of meaning and suggested dispositional reductions) see Boghossian (1989, 532). 269 argument that shows that any metanormative realism is committed – given some further plausible assumptions – to Normative Naturalism. Assume a realist – a factualist, at least – view of the good, according to which all and only instances of pleasure are (intrinsically) good. Being a pleasure, according to such a view, may not be identical with being good, but is rather the only good-making property. Now assume that basic normative truths – the underived ones, those that are not merely the results of applying more general norms to specific circumstances – are (metaphysically) necessary. It then follows that, necessarily, all and only good things are pleasing. In other words, it follows that the property of being good and the property of being a pleasure are necessarily coextensive. But – and this is a further premise – necessarily coextensive properties are identical. So the property of being good is after all identical with the property of being a pleasure. A normative property is identical with a natural one. And clearly, a similar line of argument can be run for any other substantive view of the good, or of any other normative property.114 The premise about the necessity of basic norms is one I do not want to reject. It is, I think, highly implausible that, say, pleasure is good as a matter of sheer chance, and that there are counterfactual circumstances in which it ceases to be (pro tanto, or prima facie) good (assuming, that is, it actually is intrinsically of 114 Such an argument is implicitly to be found in Jackson and Pettit (1995, 22) and more explicitly in Jackson and Pettit (1996, 85), where they reply to a relevant worry by Van Roojen (1996) regarding their 1995. Instead of my premise regarding the necessity of basic norms, they use one regarding the modal status of a supervenience requirement. As far as I can see, the two can be regarded equivalent for present purposes. 270 value). Furthermore, in the context of my argument – one that insists on deliberation as the seeking of non-arbitrary, non-contingent answers to the normative questions we ask ourselves – it is not a premise I can reject. The way to go, then, is to reject the other premise, and argue that there can be distinct properties that are nevertheless necessarily coextensive. This, I think, is not an intuitively implausible view. But perhaps it is not even necessary to reject the argument above. For in characterizing Normative Naturalism, remember, I suggested to put things in the more intuitive terms of the nothing-over-and-above relation: The normative naturalist claims that normative facts are nothing over and above natural facts. Now, whatever your view regarding the identity of necessarily coextensive properties, it seems clear that necessary coextension does not entail a nothing-over-and-above judgment. Examples typically used to challenge the identity of necessarily coextensive properties are made even more intuitively compelling when put in this way: The property of being the number two is not nothing over and above the property of being an even prime, and it is not the case that the property of triangularity is nothing over and above the property of trilaterality115. Normative Naturalism is thus not entailed by realism and the modal status of basic normative truths.116 Van Roojen (1996) makes a similar point – except put in terms of identity – against Jackson and Pettit. They attempt a quick (and, I think, unsuccessful) reply at Jackson and Pettit (1996, 85). 116 I thank Cian Dorr and Josh Schechter for discussions regarding this section. 115 271 4.5 Constructivism About to begin our weekly tennis match, we wonder who should serve first. We decide to flip a coin, and you win. This settles our (short) deliberation, and you serve first. We both know, of course, and have known all along, that you do not have a prior entitlement – one that is independent of our coin-tossing procedure – to serve first. Indeed, as we also know, there was no independent reason to let you rather than me serve first. So there was, it seems, no normative truth applicable to the appropriate result of the deliberation at hand. And yet we were able to bring the deliberation to its conclusion in a reasonable way, and not, it seems, by merely picking. This little story may be thought of as a counterexample to my insistence that deliberation requires normative truths that are independent of the deliberation procedure itself. In section 4.5.1 I characterize Constructivism, the view that attempts to generalize the intuition underlying the coin-toss case. Then, in section 4.5.2, I restrict the scope of my discussion to what I call Interesting Constructivism, the kind of Constructivism that can serve as an alternative to (a more substantive) realism. It is only Interesting Constructivism that I need to rule out in order to defend my argument for Robust Realism, and I proceed to do that in section 4.5.3. As mentioned already in section 4.1, and as will become clearer below, it is not clear that (Interesting) Constructivism constitutes a genuine alternative to the metanormative views already rejected. Indeed, if the classification of views presented in 4.1 is exhaustive (as it seems to be), Constructivism cannot be a 272 genuine alternative to all. Why discuss it, then, as if it were? First, constructivists often write as if their view is a genuine alternative, and it may be interesting to see whether they are right. For that, we need a better understanding of Constructivism. Second, the most influential metanormative constructivist these days – Christine Korsgaard – develops her view in ways rather similar to (parts of) my argument for Robust Realism (the emphasis on us being essentially deliberative and on the role of deliberation in setting adequacy constraints on accounts of normativity are especially clear examples), and so I think it is of special interest here to see how Constructivism fails. A further, related, reason has to do with Kant’s role in inspiring constructivist metanormative theories as well as my argument for Robust Realism. I hope to discuss this Kantian inspiration in detail on another occasion. 4.5.1 Constructivism Constructivism (as I will be using this term117) is a thesis about the relations of correctness-priority between substantive results and the procedures of getting to them. In some cases – the you-cut-I-choose procedure of dividing a cake is a standard example118 – we know in advance what a correct, or justified, result would be (each of us getting roughly half of the cake), and a procedure is justified because of its likelihood of achieving the independently justified result (given 117 It is sometimes used differently, even in the metaethical context. See Brink (1989). Nevertheless, I think this is now the canonical way of understanding this term. See Darwall, Gibbard and Railton, (1992, 13), and the references there. 118 See Rawls (1980, 523; 1993, 72). 273 some plausible background assumptions, the you-cut-I-choose procedure is more likely than alternative procedures to yield the justified result). But, as can be seen from the coin-toss case, this is not the only possibility. Sometimes, no result is justified prior to the relevant procedure. It is not, prior to the coin toss, justified that I serve first, nor is it justified that you serve first. Obviously, then, in such cases the procedure is not justified because of its likelihood of generating the independently justified result (for there is no such result). Rather, the procedure itself is first justified, and when it terminates, the justified result is justified exactly in virtue of being the result of the independently justified procedure. Constructivism about a relevant discourse is the claim that there are no substantive correctness criteria that apply to (or in) that discourse, and that the only relevant correctness criteria are procedural in the way specified above. Thus, according to Metaethical Constructivism, there are no actions we ought to perform or to avoid performing independently of some (actual or hypothetical) procedure – say, that of reaching consensus in an open discussion about principles of conduct; rather, these procedures determine the moral status of actions. Metaethical constructivists all agree on the denial of moral correctness criteria that are independent of the relevant procedure; they differ in their characterization of the relevant procedure, the one I’ll call the constructivist procedure. And similarly, of course, for constructivists about other discourses. Importantly, Constructivism is not (primarily) an epistemological thesis. We can all agree – constructivists and non-constructivists alike – that we employ 274 epistemic procedures in trying to find out what, say, the moral facts are, and that these procedures (perhaps partly) determine what we are justified in believing. This commonplace does not entail Constructivism. According to Constructivism, the constructivist procedure is not considered as a way of tracking an independent fact, but rather as a way of creating, or constructing, it. The coin toss is not a way of finding out in a reasonably reliable way who is entitled to serve first, but is rather a way of creating such a fact, making it the case that one of us is so entitled. It is easy to miss this point, because often the very same procedure is thought of as a constructivist procedure by some, and an epistemological one by others. Consider, for instance, the procedure of attempting to get our moral judgments to be in reflective equilibrium. This is often thought of as a constructivist procedure, a procedure that serves to determine the relevantly correct (true, or reasonable) moral judgments. But it need not be so understood. It can be understood as an epistemic procedure, a (purportedly) reasonably reliable way of tracking independent moral facts. Constructivism is to be understood as a thesis about the truth in the relevant domain, not about the justification of our beliefs regarding it.119 119 Rawls is not always careful enough about this distinction. See Rawls (1980, 519). What helps to blur it is that in the case of Constructivism regarding morality, or justice, or indeed normativity, talk of justification is often conflated with talk of truth. In the coin-toss example, for instance, the relevant correctness criteria are exactly those of (probably moral) justification, and so Constructivism is a claim about the justificatory priority of the procedure over the result. But there too Constructivism is not merely a claim about the epistemic justification of our beliefs regarding who should serve first, but rather about what makes it the case that (say) you should serve first. The distinction is clearer in non-moral, and indeed non-normative, contexts. In the philosophy of mathematics, for instance, proof is considered an epistemic, tracking, procedure by realists, and a 275 Metanormative Constructivism is the view that there are no normative truths or facts that are independent in the relevant way of some procedures, and in particular of our procedures of getting at them. Rather, being the results of these procedures makes the relevant normative claims true. As an example of such a constructivist view, an example that will be important below, consider the view characterized – and tentatively attributed to Korsgaard120 – by Gibbard (1999, 148): “According to this logically constrained reflective subjectivism [Korsgaard’s version of Constructivism], reflectively deciding to do something makes it the thing to do, so long as your policies for action are logically consistent.” Suitably generalized to all normative discourse (and not just “the thing to do”) this view is a metanormative constructivist position, with consistent reflective endorsement as the constructivist procedure. And the reason such Metanormative Constructivism is a threat for my argument for Robust Realism is, as already noted, that Constructivism seems to supply the correctness criteria needed for deliberation without relying on (prior, independent) normative truths. It is a way, it may be thought, of acknowledging much of what I say about deliberation, and yet resisting the move to Robust Realism. Before proceeding to reject Metanormative Constructivism and this threat to my argument with it, I want briefly to comment on the relations between constructivist procedure by constructivists. These think of mathematical truth as constituted, or at least determined, by our proofs (those we possess or perhaps those we can possess). 120 For, as Gibbard (1999, 148-9) also notes, there are in Korsgaard’s text (1996) troubling inconsistencies, and evidence both for and against this reading. For Korsgaard’s characterization of her view as an instance of “procedural realism” – essentially, Constructivism – see Korsgaard (1996, 36-7). 276 constructivist views and the classification of metanormative views presented in section 4.1. The obvious suspicion is that Constructivism is a (perhaps especially sophisticated or appealing) version of a naturalist reduction121. Think of Constructivism regarding mathematics. If you think that, say, our actual proof procedures make mathematical statements true, you seem to have reduced mathematical truth to truths about our actual proof procedures. Or suppose you are a constructivist about social justice, thinking there are no true principles of justice independently of a certain (say) selection procedure, and that this selection procedure makes the principles chosen in it just. Then, it seems, you believe that the property of being just (as applied to principles) is reducible to that of being chosen in a certain (actual or hypothetical) situation by certain (actual or hypothetical) agents. So long as the canonical descriptions of the choice-situation and of the agents making the choosing are in naturalistically respectable terms, it seems you have committed yourself to a naturalist reduction of justice. But perhaps your favorite constructivist procedure is one that cannot be understood in non-normative terms. In that case, you may be presenting merely an intra-normative reduction, reducing some normative properties and facts to other – still clearly normative, and not natural – ones. Such a reduction may be of considerable significance and interest, but it is not a metanormative position of the kind I have to reject in order to defend Robust Realism and my argument for it. 121 Nagel (1996, 205) expresses this suspicion. 277 Indeed, it is the kind of Constructivism that can be happily endorsed by robust realists122. In classifying a constructivist position much depends, then, on the details of the constructivist procedure it employs. But there is also a suspicion that Constructivism can be understood as a rhetorical variant of very different views, and that – at least in Korsgaard’s version of it – is crucially ambiguous as between them. This allows Korsgaard, for instance, to deny any naturalist reduction (1996, 161), and yet also to come dangerously close to embracing it 123. And it allows Smith (1999) – a dispositionalist and a normative naturalist of sorts – to understand Korsgaard’s Constructivism as the view of a kindred naturalist spirit, and Gibbard (1999) – an expressivist – to understand her view as a fellowexpressivist one. Putting this suspicion to one side, it seems to me clear that Constructivism does not threaten the exhaustiveness of the classification in section 4.1. When all the details about the constructivist procedure are clearly in place, it seems, it will be clear which category the relevant instance of Constructivism falls under. Scanlon’s Metaethical Constructivism is an example of such a view, as it reduces moral wrongness to, roughly, being forbidden by reasonably non-rejectible principles, with “reasonably” normatively understood. And indeed, Scanlon’s metanormative view is, if not quite Robust Realism, something very close to it. See Scanlon (1998, chapter 1). Milo’s Contractarian Constructivism may be, like Scanlon’s, an intra-normative project, or – depending on his understanding of the reasons to which he reduces moral wrongness – it may a reductivist, naturalist position, and so one that is (in the terms introduced below) uninterestingly constructivist. See Milo (1995). 123 See footnote 130, below. 122 278 4.5.2 Interesting Constructivism I do not here need to discuss Constructivism in general, but only inasmuch as it seems to be able to block my argument from deliberative indispensability to Robust Realism. I will call views that satisfy this requirement versions of Interesting Constructivism. Needless to say, I do not mean to imply that other constructivist views are uninteresting124. It is just that they are not interesting in the specific context of my argument for Robust Realism. What would it take, then, for a constructivist position to be interesting in this sense? Clearly, it must be a genuine alternative to a more substantive realism; it cannot assume anything like it. Furthermore, it must be seen as distinct from a more substantive realism from the point of view of the deliberating agent. To see that, let me distinguish between Deliberative and Non-deliberative Constructivism, the former employing a deliberative constructivist procedure, the latter a nondeliberative one. A deliberative procedure is one that includes as a part of it (some kind of) deliberation of (some) agents. Coin-toss-procedures are, of course, nondeliberative ones, and so are (it seems) the kind of proof procedures relevant for Mathematical Constructivism. Rawls’s original-position-procedure, on the other hand, is a deliberative one, because it includes agents deliberating and making choices. 124 Those constructivist theories in which the constructivist rhetoric is completely redundant, and the constructivist procedure merely a heuristic device are, I suspect, less interesting, or at least less interestingly constructivist. I return to the possibility of viewing the constructivist procedure as merely a heuristic device below. 279 The crucial point I now want to make is that no instance of Nondeliberative Constructivism can be interesting. For remember that my argument for Robust Realism is grounded in the point of view of the deliberating agent. From this point of view, any non-deliberative constructivist procedure can be considered as merely a way of picking out the independently right answer. It makes no difference for me when deliberating whether you are entitled to serve first independently of any procedure, or whether you are entitled to serve first because you’ve already won a coin toss, or whether you are (going to be) entitled to serve first because you will have won a coin toss. In all these cases, I can only think of my deliberation as an epistemological, not a constructivist, procedure: There is still a fact as to who should serve first, a fact that is independent of me and my deliberation, one that I am trying to find out. In order to think of your deliberation in a way that blocks my argument for Robust Realism, then, you must think of it as a part of the relevant constructivist procedure. It thus follows that Non-deliberative Constructivism is uninteresting. In fact, the only kind of Constructivism that is not ruled out as uninteresting by this consideration is one where the constructivist procedure includes my own deliberation, and indeed this very deliberation of mine. This, then, is what it takes for a constructivist theory to be an instance of Interesting Constructivism.125 125 But is there not an argument against Robust Realism (or my argument for it) in the vicinity here? Aren’t uninterestingly constructivist theories proof that irreducibly normative truths are after all not deliberatively indispensable, because deliberation can settle for the truths constructed by non-deliberative procedures? 280 Here are two examples of interestingly constructivist theories. According to Legal Positivism126, there are some cases – so-called hard cases – where the court called upon to make a ruling creates the law. Prior to the court’s decision there are no legally right and legally wrong answers in such cases, because the law fails to determine what the right answer is. Rather, whatever ruling the court will make, it will be legally correct because it was the result of the legally appropriate procedure. So legal positivists are constructivists about the law in hard cases – they think that what makes the correct result correct is that it is the result of a correct procedure. Now, think of a judge who is a legal positivist 127, when having to make a ruling in a hard case brought in front of her. She knows there are no legally right (or wrong) answers to the questions she has to answer prior to her ruling, and she knows that the relevant constructivist procedure includes her very deliberation and decision. So she cannot think of herself and her deliberation as discovering (or attempting to discover) a legally right answer there anyway. Rather, she is knowingly creating the legally right answer. Legal Positivism (or this version of it), at least when believed by a judge deliberating about a hard case, is an Interesting Constructivism. The answer, of course, is “no”. For such uninterestingly constructivist theories are going to be really a paradigmatically reductivist position, and as such vulnerable to the objections in section 4.4, above. 126 In what follows I simplify slightly, and ignore the complexities and complications that serve to fuel much of the contemporary jurisprudential discussion. These simplifications do not, I think, prevent Legal Positivism from serving as an example of Interesting Constructivism. 127 It is sometimes noticed that typically judges are not positivists, at least if the opinions they draft are reliable evidence of their jurisprudential views. But even if this is so, surely a positivist judge is not an impossibility. 281 The second example has already been mentioned. It is Korsgaard’s Metanormative Constructivism, understood according to Gibbard’s (1999, 148) suggestion. This is, to repeat, the view according to which “reflectively deciding to do something makes it the thing to do, so long as your policies for action are logically consistent.” According to this view, then, there are no normative truths (about what the thing to do is, at least) that are independent of the deliberation process (that of consistent reflective endorsement). Rather, that process determines which considerations are normative; “The normative word ‘reason’ refers to a kind of reflective success.” (Korsgaard, 1996, 93) This is, of course, a constructivist view, and an interesting one, for the constructivist procedure it employs includes the agent’s deliberation. I want to mention here a particularly important type of view that is perhaps constructivist, but certainly not interestingly so. Dispositionalist views can be presented – and some of them sometimes are – as constructivist ones: Think, for instance, of a view according to which I have a (normative) reason to do something just in case I would be disposed to have a motivation to do it if I had all (relevant) facts vividly in front of my mind128. We can, if we want, think of the procedure of gathering more information and vividly presenting it to one’s mind as a constructivist procedure, arguing that the question what do I have reason to do is one that has no answer prior to that procedure, and that what makes it the case that This (sketch of a) view bears similarities to Lewis’s (1989) view of values and Williams’s (1980) view of reasons. 128 282 I have reason to help him, say, is that being motivated to help him would be the result of that procedure. But, even if this is enough for such views to qualify as constructivist ones, surely they are not interestingly constructivist: The constructivist procedure they employ is, at most, a heuristic device, a way of making a naturalist reduction more intuitively appealing129. When deliberating about what to do, I do not think of myself as making the answer I come up with right, but rather as discovering the independently right answer – discovering, that is, what I would be motivated to do when appropriately situated. Similar remarks apply to analogous (uninterestingly) constructivist views that are put in terms of, say, mere pickings.130 Such views may have their merits (though the objections to Normative Naturalism from section 4.4, if successful, apply to them), but they are certainly not interestingly constructivist. Note that this discussion applies to necessary dispositions or desires – should there be any – just as strongly as it does to contingent ones. So if there are things we – perhaps as agents – are necessarily disposed to do or motivations we are necessarily disposed to have, still a Constructivism that relies on them in the typical dispositionalist way cannot be an interesting one, and so cannot present a (non-reductive) alternative to Robust Realism. This is of significance, because at 129 Railton (1986b, 23-25) explicitly concedes this point regarding his own version of an Ideal Advisor Theory. Butler (1988, 21) and Krasnoff (1999, 398) also mention the possibility of superficially constructivist views where the constructivist procedure is really merely a heuristic device. 130 At times Korsgaard is clear about our practical identity – the source of all our reasons, according to Korsgaard – being utterly contingent, something we just find ourselves with (e.g. 1996, 239). To the extent this is her considered view, the point in the text applies also to her identityConstructivism. 283 times Korsgaard’s text lends itself to such a dispositionalist reading, with the dispositions involved being necessary.131 Let me return, then, to Interesting Constructivism. The constructivist procedure of such a Constructivism must be, I emphasized, a deliberative one. But what is the relevant result of the procedure? In the coin-toss example, you were entitled to serve first if a fair coin, properly tossed, landed (say) heads. The relevant result of the procedure is landing heads. Now, different constructivist procedures have different relevant results. Is there anything general that can be said about the results of deliberative procedures? I think there is. Assume an Interesting Constructivism about a discourse D. Then the relevant result of the deliberative constructivist procedure cannot, on pain of inconsistency or circularity, be the agent’s D-beliefs. Think of the example of Legal Positivism and the law in hard cases. In such cases, the legally right answer is the answer the court ends up giving, and it is the right answer exactly because the court ended up giving it. But positivist judges cannot, in deciding (knowably) hard cases, decide according to their beliefs about the legally right answer to the case in front of them. Ex hypothesi, there is no such answer, and they know as much. So positivists cannot argue that the legally right answer in hard cases is the 131 See Korsgaard (1996, 235). Korsgaard here seems to endorse a line rather similar to that developed in some detail by Velleman (1989) and discussed above in section 2.A.3 (in chapter 2). If this is indeed Korsgaard’s considered view, then – somewhat surprisingly, perhaps – she does not take our deliberative, reflective nature seriously enough after all. 284 answer, whatever it is, that the judges believe is legally right132. Instead, they must argue that the legally right answer is the one judges end up giving (without believing it is antecedently right), or the one that is consistent with their ruling, or perhaps the one they believe is morally appropriate, and so on. The relevant result of the deliberative procedure cannot be their beliefs about the law, and so must be either not a belief at all (like a ruling) or a belief about something else (like the morally right answer).133 Returning to Korsgaard’s Metanormative (Interesting) Constructivism, I want to note that her terms for the result of the constructivist procedure – “reflective endorsement”, or “valuing” – are dangerously ambiguous. They could, but need not, involve a belief that the considerations (or incentives, or desires, or whatever) being reflectively endorsed (or valued) are indeed reasons. Such reading would seem adequate given Korsgaard’s insistence on our reflective nature: “The reflective mind cannot settle for perception and desire, not just as such. It needs a reason. Otherwise, at least as long as it reflects, it cannot commit itself or go forward.” (Korsgaard, 1996, 93) On such a reading, though, her Constructivism would be unstable for the reason just mentioned – in the analysis of reasons our 132 Unless, of course, the judges do not themselves know that Legal Positivism is true. I return to this (and analogous) worries in discussing publicity, in section 4.6. 133 The point in the text is closely analogous to a point often made in the context of Ideal Observer Theories and dispositionalist ones: If you want to give an Ideal Observer account of the truth conditions of a judgment p, it cannot involve the Ideal Observer’s belief that p (See, for instance, Firth, 1952, 326). This is obviously so, unless – and this is an often neglected point – the Ideal Observer is ignorant of the analysis of the judgment that p or of her status as ideal. In the related context of dispositionalist theories of color, Boghossian and Velleman (1989) present especially clearly the circularity worry, and argue that it is a serious one. 285 belief that something is a reason appears in the analysans. So perhaps it is more charitable to understand her “endorsement” as not involving a normative belief, but rather as making a choice, or being disposed to make a choice, or performing an action, or having a desire, or a higher-order desire, or something of the sort. In short, it may be better to understand her endorsement as a conative rather than a cognitive state134. 4.5.3 The Constructivist Fallacy I have already restricted the scope of constructivist views I have to reject here to interestingly constructivist ones. Let me now restrict their scope even further. A constructivist view about a part of normative discourse – just morality, say, or political justice – is not one I need to reject, given the character of Robust Realism as an existential thesis. So the view I now want to argue against is Global Interesting Constructivism (about normativity). This still doesn’t make Korsgaard into a noncognitivist. For that we need to disambiguate another ambiguity in her text. When saying that some consideration is a reason, am I expressing my reflective endorsement, or am I reporting it, saying that I reflectively endorse it? From time to time Korsgaard says things like “The normative word ‘reason’ refers to a kind of reflective success.” (1996, 93) and even “‘Reason’ means reflective success.” (1996, 97), and this seems to imply that in saying that a consideration is a reason I’m saying that it is reflectively endorsed (by me, I guess), and so that I’m reporting reflective endorsement. If so, Korsgaard’s position is a cognitivist version of Subjectivism. Gibbard (1999) finds an expressivist reading, according to which one expresses one’s endorsement of the consideration one says is a reason, more in line with Korsgaard’s text. Perhaps this is the more charitable interpretation. Nowhere, as far as I know, is Korsgaard explicit about this further ambiguity. 134 286 Against this view I want quickly to present one worry, and then to pursue in more detail another135. Korsgaard repeatedly emphasizes the need to defeat – even convince136 – the skeptic, the person who sees no reason to behave morally, or perhaps who is not motivated to act morally, or perhaps not even motivated to act as she thinks she has reason to act137. And she emphasizes that no substantive starting point – a moral principle taken as self-evident, for instance – can satisfy this requirement. This is why she opts for a proceduralist, constructivist, approach. But the obvious questions to ask then are: “… whether procedures claim any advantage, as whystoppers, over substantive principles…” (Gibbard, 1999, 142), and “Is the right procedure, after all, just self-evident? What if I just don’t see that it is?” (Gibbard, 1999, 143). The problem here need not be put in terms of coping with the skeptic. Consider the coin-toss example again. True, the constructivist there can supply the 135 These are not, of course, the only possible problems for constructivist views. It is perhaps of special interest here to note that plausible versions of Metanormative Constructivism – ones that allow for at least some kind of objectivity – seem prima facie as vulnerable to some of the more serious epistemological worries as Robust Realism is (Rawls (2000, 243), for instance, seems to concede as much. See also Regan (2002, 272-3)). But I cannot pursue this point further here. 136 Korsgaard doesn’t distinguish between these two requirements, and her use of locutions such as “addressing the skeptic” (1996, 16) seems to get her involved in a dangerous equivocation. It seems like a reasonable requirement for a theory of normativity that it should defeat the skeptic, that is, that it should show him to be wrong. It is clearly not a reasonable requirement that the skeptic be necessarily converted (and, of course, Korsgaard’s own theory doesn’t pass this test either). By conflating the two – defeating and convincing the skeptic – she can employ, in criticizing realism, the stricter requirement with the perceived plausibility of the looser one. For her employment of the stricter requirement against realism, see Korsgaard (1996, 34). For relevant criticism, see Gibbard (1999, 146). 137 It is not clear which of these Korsgaard has in mind, as at different places in the text her main worry seems to shift between these (and possibly other) options. 287 relevant criteria of correctness, accounting for it being the case that you should serve first. But the mere availability of the coin-toss procedure does not suffice for that, for numerous other procedures – tossing a double-headed coin, for instance – are equally available. What is also needed is that the (fair) coin-toss is a justified or fair procedure in the circumstances. It seems, then, that unconstructed normative facts are after all involved in this Constructivism – namely, the fact that this procedure rather than that one is the relevantly adequate one. This, of course, is not a problem for locally constructivist positions. It is perfectly possible to be a constructivist about the right to serve first, but a robust realist (say) about the fairness of lottery procedures and the appropriateness of using them in different circumstances. But it is hard to see how Global Metanormative Constructivism can address this worry: At the bottom of any constructivist procedure, it seems, lies the justification of that procedure itself, and this justification – certainly a normative matter – is not constructed. Perhaps the global constructivist has a reply available to her. Presumably, it will be along coherentist lines (perhaps the normative fact that the procedure is justified is safe because vindicated by the procedure itself, and perhaps such a bootstrapping is consistent with Constructivism). Some Kantian constructivists have indeed been tempted to attempt such a way138, though it is – and remains after their work – very hard to see how anything like this line can be made to succeed. Be that as it may, I will not discuss this worry further. Let me proceed, 138 See, for instance, O’Neill (1992). 288 then, in accordance with the promise made in section 4.1, to discuss a problem for Constructivism that originates from deliberation and what it involves. Here, then, is a general adequacy constraint for constructivist theories. They – and their being publicly known – must not undermine the very procedure they use as their constructivist procedure. Constructivist theories that undermine their own constructivist procedure commit what I will call The Constructivist Fallacy. I now want to argue that Global Interesting Constructivism necessarily commits The Constructivist Fallacy.139 To see that, consider two examples, one where the fallacy is committed, the other where it is not. Consider first a constructivist view about the right to serve first in a tennis match, with the procedure being that of an umpire’s decision guided only by considerations regarding who should serve first. According to this view, what makes it the case that you get to serve first is that an umpire allowed to consider only who has a right to serve first so decides. This kind of Constructivism undermines the very constructivist procedure it employs, because the umpire – knowing, as he does, that whatever he decides will be the right decision simply in virtue of him so deciding – cannot sincerely deliberate about who should serve first. He can still just pick one, of course, but if the right-toserve-first-Constructivism allows for a mere picking in its constructivist 139 The argument as it appears in the text that follows is, as far as I know, original. But hints at the direction of this argument can be found in Cohen (1996, 188), Nagel (1996, 204), Gaut (1997, 163 and 178), Wiggins (1998), Cohon (2000, 69), Hill (2001, 326-8), Regan (2002), Gowans (2002), and Velleman (forthcoming). 289 procedure, then the procedure is no longer deliberative, and the Constructivism no longer interesting. For a benign Interesting Constructivism, one that avoids The Constructivist Fallacy, think again of Legal Positivism. The constructivist procedure it employs is that of judges’ deliberation about how to decide the hard case in front of them. But, given Legal Positivism, the relevant judge knows that there are no legal considerations that can guide her deliberation, that there are – perhaps among a class of legally acceptable decisions – no legally better or worse decisions, that the law has run out on her. This being so – and her knowing as much – need not undermine her deliberation, because there are many other considerations she can still weigh in her deliberation. She can ask herself which decision is the morally better one, which is right politically, which is the more efficient, which is more in line with God’s will, which fits better the ethos of the community of which she is a part, or whatever. Importantly, these are not considerations she is a constructivist about. At least, she is not committed to any such Constructivism in virtue of her jurisprudential views. So she can deliberate – she can ask herself which decision is the one she ought to make – because there are normative considerations she can consider which are not up to her, considerations that she discovers, not creates, and that therefore can guide her deliberation. True, legally she cannot go wrong, but she can make horrible moral mistakes, or make a terribly inefficient ruling, and so on. The questions she asks herself have answers (if not legal ones), and so she can 290 sincerely deliberate. Legal Positivism thus need not defeat its own constructivist procedure. Legal Positivism does not commit The Constructivist Fallacy. What allows Legal Positivism to avoid The Constructivist Fallacy is its restricted scope: It is because there are still sufficiently many other, non-legal, considerations that can guide the judges in their deliberation, considerations they are not constructivists about, that the deliberative procedure is not undermined by the very constructivist theory in question. But once this is noticed, it becomes clear that a Global Interesting Constructivism cannot succeed140. If, for instance, Korsgaard wants her theory to apply to all reasons (and often it seems she does141) then hers is a Global Metanormative Constructivism. Now, deliberating about whether to endorse a given consideration (or incentive, desire, urge, or even identity) thereby making it a reason, what reasons can guide my deliberation? None, of course, because there are no reasons prior to this very deliberation. It does not matter whether what is supposed to be endorsed at this stage are reasons directly, or first something like Korsgaard’s practical identity – still, nothing can be deliberatively, reflectively, chosen. And if this is so, I cannot sincerely deliberate, the constructivist procedure collapses, and with it the very 140 Velleman (forthcoming) notes that Global Constructivism faces a problem similar to The Constructivist Fallacy that more local constructivist positions – such as a Metaethical Constructivism – need not face. 141 Throughout her The Sources of Normativity (1996) it is clear she has in mind at least all practical reasons, and she expresses hope (1996, 20-1) for a unified account of normativity. At times (e.g. Korsgaard, 1997, 248) she seems to be drawn to a similar position regarding theoretical reasons as well. And whether or not she is drawn to such a generalization of her view, it seems clear her reasons purportedly supporting Constructivism apply to theoretical reasons just as they do to practical ones. 291 Constructivism it is supposed to ground142. Global Interesting Constructivism is – given the nature of deliberation and the plausibility of the publicity requirement143 – unstable.144 Notice that the point generalizes to any Global Interesting Constructivism. The unclarity noticed above regarding the nature of endorsement in Korsgaard’s theory, for instance, is not relevant here. So long as the procedure supposedly terminating in (reflective) endorsement is a deliberative one – and Korsgaard is clear about it being so – the argument above applies.145 In a recent paper, Regan (2002) criticizes Korsgaard’s Kantianism in a related way. He too notices that in a world devoid of “Moorean” values or reasons (that is, normative truths understood along robustly realist lines), an agent can only pick arbitrarily and not choose for reasons (though he does not notice the assumption of a publicity requirement), and he too takes this observation as a starting point for a criticism of Korsgaard’s views. But, being primarily interested in the normative question whether (only) our rational nature is of ultimate value rather than in metanormative questions, his criticism remains in the normative level: He argues (quite convincingly, I think, and perhaps echoing traditional worries regarding voluntarist theories of obligation) that there is nothing to value in the capacity to just pick arbitrarily (for a rather similar point, see Hill (2001, 326-7), and for the voluntarist connection see Skorupski (1998) and Cohon (2000)). My criticism, on the other hand, is not normative in this way. Rather, I emphasize that if Constructivism is to block my argument for Robust Realism it must employ a deliberative procedure, and that – given the nature of deliberation – Interesting Constructivism can thus not be global. 143 I have defended the assumptions regarding the nature of deliberation in chapter 3, and I tentatively defend the publicity requirement below, in section 4.8. But it is perhaps of special interest here that Korsgaard herself – and, it seems, other constructivists – are in a particularly uncomfortable position to avoid The Constructivist Fallacy by rejecting either my account of deliberation or the publicity requirement. Indeed, as noticed in chapter 3, my account of deliberation is strongly influenced by Korsgaard, and she herself endorses the publicity requirement (1996, e.g. at 17), as do Rawls (1980, 538) and Kant himself (see, for instance, Rawls 2000, 17). A Global Interesting Cosntructivism that does not seems entirely unmotivated. 144 There is much more in Korsgaard that merits discussion, including most importantly her arguments for her constructivist view. I hope to address these in more detail elsewhere. 145 I believe, though I cannot defend this claim here, that The Constructivist Fallacy is closely related to the well-known empty-formalism accusation against Kant (and Kantians). Briefly, metanormative constructivist views commit The Constructivist Fallacy because they do not supply the deliberating agent with reasons, considerations that can guide her deliberation. And this, it seems, is the crux of the empty-formalism objection as well: There is simply not enough in, say, the Categorical Imperative, to guide agents’ actions. Some of Velleman’s critical remarks regarding both Kant and Korsgaard can be seen as extremely close to the empty formalism objection on one 142 292 There are limits, then, as to how interesting and global a constructivist position can be. Rawls – whose Constructivism about political justice avoids The Constructivist Fallacy by allowing the parties in the original position to weigh considerations of self-interest, themselves not constructed146 – seems to have understood this well enough. Perhaps he had in mind something like The Constructivist Fallacy when writing147: “[N]ot everything, then, is constructed; we must have some material, as it were, from which to begin” (Rawls, 1993, 104). 4.6 Publicity Throughout the discussion of sections 4.1-4.5 I have been assuming that metanormative views, if true, are widely known to be true. In particular, what defeated deliberation in the different cases was not directly the (assumed) truth of the relevant metanormative theory, but rather the deliberating agent’s belief that it hand, and to my Constructivist Fallacy on the other. See Velleman (1996, 175-6; online; forthcoming). 146 It is not entirely clear to me whether Rawls’s Constructivism is interesting. In A Theory of Justice he himself concedes that the formulation of his view in terms of a hypothetical choice situation is dispensable and of merely expository value (Rawls, 1971, 18 and 21). It is possible, though, that he changes his mind regarding this point in later stages of his thinking (see, for instance, his comparison between Constructivism and Intuitionism in Rawls, 1980, 554-572). 147 Perhaps not. Perhaps what he has in mind is the problem briefly mentioned above, of the need to have some normative claims available to one in order to justify the constructivist procedure itself (or perhaps he thought of both problems). This understanding is suggested by the following comments on Kant: “Is the CI-procedure [the Categorical Imperative procedure, used in order to construct the totality of requirements of practical reason] itself constructed? No, it is not. Rather, it is simply laid out.” (Rawls, 2000, 238) “… the form and structure of the CI-procedure mirrors our free moral personality as both reasonable and rational[.] The idea here is that not everything can be constructed. Every construction has a basis, certain materials, as it were, from which it begins. While the CI-procedure is not, as noted above, constructed but laid out, it does have a basis: the conception of free and equal persons as reasonable and rational, a conception that is mirrored in the procedure… Thus we don’t say that the conceptions of person and society are constructed. It is unclear what that could mean.” (Rawls, 2000, 240). 293 is true. So, it may now be argued, I haven’t refuted the metanormative theories themselves. Perhaps they are true, and their truth allows for deliberation, at the price of the deliberating agent’s metanormative mistake (or ignorance). Suppose, for instance, that Noncognitivism is true, and that nevertheless the argument in section 4.3 above succeeds, so that a Noncognitivist, if consistent148, cannot genuinely deliberate. Still, Noncognitivism can be true. What is needed to defeat Noncognitivism in such a scenario is a further premise, one that embodies a publicity, or transparency, requirement, according to which it cannot be the case that a metanormative view can accommodate deliberation only by concealing itself from deliberating agents. Perhaps deliberation is possible only because the deliberating agents fail to appreciate the metanormative truth149. It is not clear to me whether publicity requirements should never – in moral philosophy in general – be compromised. Perhaps, for instance, they are especially powerful regarding first-order, normative principles. But a “government-house metaethics”150 may be less objectionable. There need be, for instance, nothing manipulative about such a metanormative theory that violates publicity. Perhaps, then, publicity is to be discarded, and my arguments in section 4.2-4.5 with it. Fortunately, I do not have to defend a general publicity requirement here. For remember, all I have to do in order to defend my argument for Robust Realism 148 See the discussion in section 3.4.8 above. But see also the discussion of illusion in section 3.4.5. 150 The term is Williams’ (1973, section 7), in his discussion of Utilitarianism and its (purported) violation of publicity. 149 294 is show that no alternative metanormative view can accommodate deliberation. So, once again, the relevant perspective is that of the deliberating agent and her commitments. But, as argued in section 3.4.11 (in chapter 3), from that perspective the distinction between the indispensability of the belief in normative truths and the indispensability of the normative truths themselves collapses. I cannot, while deliberating, say to myself “Sure, I cannot deliberate without believing in normative truths, but for all I care there may be no normative truths”. I cannot conceal the metanormative truth from myself while deliberating. In a manner perhaps reminiscient of Moore’s paradox, I cannot believe that there are normative truths without believing that there are normative truths. From the perspective of the deliberating agent – the only perspective relevant here – a publicity failure of the kind needed to reject the arguments in section 4.2-4.5 above is just not an option151. 4.7 Softer-Interpretation Theories: A Final Thought Experiment Imagine a world in which Robust Realism is true (surely, even if not actually true, Robust Realism is possibly true), but our normative discourse proceeds pretty much as it actually does. When deliberating about what to do, or when disagreeing among themselves on normative matters, isn’t it clear that the inhabitants of that David Velleman (1989, 62-4) believes we can have a belief – and a justified one – fully knowing that it is only that very believing of ours that makes the belief true. If he is right about that, perhaps there is a way to reject publicity from the first-personal perspective of the deliberating agent. But he is not. 151 295 world are trying to describe the normative facts existing – ex hypothesi – in their world? At least in their world, doesn’t the phenomenology of normative discourse – and in particular the phenomenology of deliberation – provide conclusive evidence against understanding (their) normative discourse in noncognitivist, reductivist, or constructivist terms? My strong intuition is that it does. But why should there be any difference between how we understand normative discourse in that world and in ours? The evidence – our relevant practices – is all the same. Of course, Error Theory is still an option – perhaps our counterparts are lucky in a way we are not, in that normative facts are a part of the fabric of their universe but not ours, and so their normative discourse sometimes succeeds where ours systematically fails152. But surely, the commitments of normative discourse on the two worlds seem indiscernible. If this is so, softer-interpretation theories must be rejected. The only options are Robust Realism and Error Theory153 (perhaps intuitively softened by revisionary suggestions). If so, the details of the softer-interpretation theories and the problems facing them are irrelevant, and the discussion in sections 4.3-4.5 redundant. If an Error Theory cannot accommodate sincere deliberation, then my argument for Robust Realism cannot be blocked. 152 You may wonder whether this is really possible, whether, in other words, it takes more than the relevant normative practice for some normative truths to be true. If so, you may be tempted by Internal Realism (briefly discussed in section 4.9 below), or by Quietism (briefly discussed in the Conclusion), or you may be wondering whether Robust Realism has any metaphysical commitments (again, a question briefly discussed in the Conclusion). I thank Hagit Benbaji for insisting that my little thought experiment brings out these worries. 153 See Sosa (2001, 289). 296 I do not want to overstate the power of this little thought experiment. There may be relevant problems here regarding how words in our and our counterparts’ normative discourse get their meaning and reference, and perhaps one can after all argue that there therefore are reasons to interpret the commitments of their discourse differently from ours.154 But I think the thought experiment does suggest that the stakes are higher than softer-interpretation theorists typically think they are: When push comes to shove, it’s either Robust Realism or Error Theory. Having read section 4.2, take your pick. 4.8 Hybrid Views The argument so far is, if successful, sufficient to show that alternative (nonrobust-realist) global metanormative views cannot accommodate deliberation and so cannot block my argument for Robust Realism. It shows, in other words, that, say, Noncognitivism about all parts of normative discourse, or Global Metanormative Error Theory cannot accommodate deliberation. But one may wonder whether hybrid views can do better. Suppose a view that is, let’s say, error theoretical about morality, naturalistically reductivist about epistemic norms and norms of instrumental rationality, and noncognitivist about “the thing to do” locutions. Has anything been said to rule out hybrid views? I suspect that even if, say, Putnam’s thoughts about the watery stuff on Twin-Earth and about Brains in Vats are roughly right, still analogous claims do not apply here, because of the differences between Twin Earth and Moral (or Normative) Twin Earth. See the discussion in Horgan and Timmons (1991). If this is right, the thought experiment in the text seems vindicated. 154 297 The problem seems especially pressing seeing that it is very plausible that normative discourse is not uniform. Even Ayer (1936, 103), for instance, conceded that some moral (or apparently moral) statements are naturalistically reducible (to statements about causes and effects) and so truth-apt after all. At the very least, no reason has been given here to expect to find in normative discourse the kind of uniformity hybrid views deny. Nevertheless, hybrid views do not here pose a further challenge. Let us divide hybrid views to those with a robustly realist component and those without such component. The former do not, of course, threaten my Robust Realism – an existential thesis, not a universal one – or my argument for it. The latter would, if successful, threaten my argument for Robust Realism. But then the arguments of previous sections apply to the relevant parts of normative discourse. Without a robust realist component, hybrid views cannot accommodate deliberation (for the reasons given in previous sections about what we now see as each component of the relevant hybrid view). With a robust realist component, hybrid views are not a threat. Either way, then, hybrid views do not constitute a further challenge. 4.9 Other Options? In this section I want briefly to discuss several other metanormative (or at least metaethical) views, showing that – appearances and rhetoric to the contrary notwithstanding – they escape neither the taxonomy in section 4.1 nor the objections in sections 4.2-4.5. The choice of views addressed below is 298 sociologically rather than philosophically grounded – I want to show that the most influential seemingly alternative views are not, in fact, independent options. Needless to say, what follows is not an attempt to do justice to these (often complex) views, but merely to show why a more serious consideration of them is not here called for. 4.9.1 Sensibility Theories McDowell (1981; 1985; 1987) and Wiggins (1991; 1998) develop metaethical Sensibility Theories (so dubbed by Darwall, Gibbard and Railton (1992, 19)) that may seem to escape the taxonomy of section 4.1155. According to their views, moral properties are best understood as analogous to (other) secondary qualities, with our relevant sensibilities playing a constitutive role in their identities. Nevertheless, the view is not reductivist: both writers explicitly say that their account is itself in normative terms – McDowell (1985, 119) speaks in terms of the responses that a situation or fact merits, and Wiggins (1991, 229) in terms of the appropriate sentiments – and both explicitly reject reductivist aspirations as illadvised (McDowell, 1988, 168 (footnote 6); Wiggins, 1991, 228-9). So the view, though subjectivist in an obvious sense, is not an instance of Ethical Naturalism. Furthermore, both writers endorse a “no-priority” view according to which it is neither the case that our sensibilities are prior to (and determine) the moral facts, Perhaps – though I am not sure – Johnston’s (1989) response-dependence theory is similar to McDowell’s and Wiggins’s in the ways relevant for the discussion that follows. 155 299 nor that those are prior to our sensibilities (so our sensibilities do not track an independent moral reality). Rather, the moral facts and our moral sensibilities are, as it were, made for each other; none can be understood without a grasp of the other (Wiggins, 1991, 232); “…the extra [moral] features are neither parents nor children of our sentiments, but – if we must find an apt metaphor from the field of kinship relations – siblings[.]” (McDowell, 1987, 219). Such metaethical views are not easily classifiable, partly because their presentation is anything but clear: One wonders how significant and distinct a metaethical view will emerge after the metaphors are replaced by clearer statements of the view. Nevertheless, I do want to show that these sensibility theories are not, for my purposes here, genuine alternative to the views already rejected. To see that notice, first, that it is not clear in what sense such theories are metanormative theories. Given the normative character of the analysans, perhaps their theories are best seen as entirely intra-normative projects. As such, they are not competitors of Robust Realism, and so I need not reject them here156. Indeed, they seem to accept irreducibly normative truths, and so – if it were not for their subjectivism – would be entitled themselves to be called robust realists157. 156 I can still, of course, reject their views for intra-normative reasons, for instance by coming up with counterexamples where a situation merits a certain response but the relevant moral judgment is nevertheless false. 157 See Johnston (1989, 148). 300 Second, regardless of their views on reductive aspirations, McDowell’s and Wiggins’s theories are subjectivist in a sense exactly analogous to the sense characterized in section 4.4.2 above, and so are vulnerable to the objection in that section158. It might help to think of the points made in this and the last paragraph as a dilemma. Whatever the details of the relevant sensibility theory and regardless of its explicit denial of reduction, either contingent facts about me play an ineliminable role in the analysis or they do not. If they do, the discussion in section 4.4.2 applies unproblematically. If they do not (say, because of talk of what merits a response, and not of what my response is), then the view is clearly intranormative and so not a threat to Robust Realism. Third – and this is a point that applies only to McDowell – he is happy to adopt a similarly subjectivist understanding of non-normative facts as well159. Now, this does not show, of course, that his theory – the metaethical or the more general one – is to be rejected. But it does show that he is not a particularly interesting antagonist in the context of my discussion. The more interesting adversaries are those who think that there is an interesting distinction between normative and non-normative facts, and that there is an important sense in which the latter are more respectable than the former160 (analogously – the interesting Perhaps Johnston (1989, 172-3) notices a similar point when joining Euthyphro’s (rather than Socrates’) side regarding the Euthypro contrast. And perhaps his awareness of the counterintuitiveness of this move is partly why he prefers thinking of his view as Revisionary (rather than Descriptive) Protogoreanism. See Johnston (1993). 159 See, for instance, McDowell (1987, 222) and throughout McDowell (1981). 160 I do not mean to argue that McDowell cannot allow any distinction between normative and nonnormative facts, or between primary and secondary qualities, within his largely antirealist 158 301 adversaries of a mathematical platonist putting forward an indispensability argument are not empiricists or instrumentalists who deny even the existence of electrons, but rather those scientific realists who distinguish between numbers and electrons, arguing that we have reason to believe in the existence of the latter but not the former). So McDowell’s and Wiggins’s theories – regardless of their other advantages and disadvantages – are not genuine competitors I need here to discuss in more detail. 4.9.2 Practical Reasoning There is – or has been for a while – a hope among metaethicists of avoiding metaphysical (and perhaps also epistemological) worries while nevertheless supplying something very much like the objectivity Robust Realism supplies by focusing on the relations between morality and the demands of practical reason. Darwall, Gibbard and Railton (1992, 9-12) divide such views into two traditions – broadly Hobbesian and broadly Kantian ones, with Baier and Gauthier among the Hobbesians and Nagel, Korsgaard, Donagan, Darwall and Gewirth among the Kantians. Now practical reasoning metaethical views may have significant advantages. But they are not genuine alternatives to Robust Realism and the philosophy. It’s just that whatever distinction he can accommodate is not of the kind that would make him an interesting adversary in this context. I thank Hagit Benbaji for many relevant discussions. 302 metanormative views already rejected. The reason is simple – an understanding of morality in terms of demands of practical rationality is still entirely within the normative domain. It is not entirely within the moral domain, and so it may supply important metaethical insights. But they supply no metanormative insight, as talk of the demands of practical rationality is itself normative through and through. Often, the metanormative views of practical reason theorists are revealed in their accounts – not of morality in terms of practical reason – but of practical reason and its demands. Some of them – typically, the Hobbesians – present a naturalist reduction of the demands of practical reasons (in terms, say, of desire satisfaction), others – like Nagel (in some moods, at least161) – are robust realists of sorts about them, yet others are constructivists. That practical reasoning approaches can be endorsed together with such different metanormative views is further evidence that they are not really metanormative theories at all. And so they do not present alternative views I have to reject here in order to defend my argument for Robust Realism. 4.9.3 Internal Realism Developed in some of the later texts of Putnam, Internal Realism is an attempt – if I understand it correctly – to give a realist (or almost realist) understanding of a relevant discourse, while at the same time acknowledging that its criteria of correctness are ultimately constituted by our relevant practice, because truth (as 161 For in others he sounds more like a quietist, a point I return to in the Conclusion. 303 applied to that discourse, at least) is best understood epistemically. According to one statement of the main idea – in the metaethical context – “we make ways of dealing with problematic situations, and we discover which ones are better and which worse.” (Putnam, 1995, 8). I should say that the details of Internal Realism are not entirely clear to me. It is, for one thing, not at all clear to me that Putnam can – as he clearly wants to – have it both ways regarding dependence of moral (and normative) facts on our relevant practices162. But, putting such worries to one side, I want briefly to argue that Internal Realism is not a further problem I need to address in order to defend my argument for Robust Realism. Perhaps the practice-dependence aspect of Internal Realism makes it – Putnam’s protests notwithstanding – a subjectivist view in the sense rejected in section 4.4.2 above. If so, the argument there applies. At times, though, Putnam sounds as if he thinks further – external – questions about our practices, questions not themselves asked from within our practices, are unintelligible, or somehow impossible. Internal Realism can then be seen as realist about the only real issues, with the “Internal” serving merely as a reminder that external issues are really pseudo-issues. If that is Putnam’s considered view, then he is a quietist in the For an attempt to improve on Putnam’s views while preserving what can be preserved by going dispositionalist, see Johnston (1993). 162 304 sense to be discussed in the Conclusion. Either way, then, my defense of Robust Realism does not require here a separate discussion of Internal Realism.163 4.10 Scorekeeping This completes, then, my argument for Metanormative Robust Realism. If the arguments of previous chapters are sound, then the only way to avoid Robust Realism is to present alternative metanormative accounts that can still accommodate deliberation. And if the arguments in this long chapter are sound, this cannot be done. But this does not complete the project of defending Robust Realism. In order to complete that project, I need to address directly certain traditional objections to robust realist views. These include metaphysical worries (about “queerness”, for instance), worries about epistemic and semantic access, worries regarding the supervenience of the normative and how it is to be explained, concerns regarding the relations between normativity and motivation and what follows from them regarding the nature of normativity, and a family of problems and arguments associated with the phenomenon of normative disagreement. Of course, what has already been said will be relevant in addressing these objections to Robust Realism, but if my defense of Robust Realism is to be complete, they must be addressed head on. The need to discuss these worries regarding Robust I addition, the point made about McDowell above – that he is not a particularly interesting adversary in this context – applies to Putnam’s Internal Realism as well. 163 305 Realism – my argument’s conclusion – is especially pressing, given the less-thanobviously-conclusive nature of my argument, and the need to decide among competing metanormative theories on basis of overall plausibility. I hope to address them satisfactorily on another occasion. It may now be asked, though, whether Robust Realism is really all that robust. Which of the traditional features of genuinely realist theories does Robust Realism – as supported by the argument in this essay – possess? I discuss this question in the Conclusion. 306 Conclusion How Robust is Robust Realism? As can be seen, then, from a study of the phenomenology of deliberation (chapter 3), normative truths or something very close to them are deliberatively indispensable, and no alternative, non-robust-realist, account of normative thought and discourse can accommodate deliberation (chapter 4). But seeing that deliberative indispensability – much like explanatory indispensability (chapter 1) – justifies ontological and other commitment (chapter 2), this gives us reason to believe that (general doubts about facts aside) there are irreducibly normative facts. Furthermore, given the arbitrariness involved in any subjectivist view of normativity, whether reductionist or not, and given that arbitrariness is exactly what deliberation is an attempt to eliminate, normative facts of the kind indispensable to deliberation are objective, they are not relativized to speakers and their community (chpater 4, section 4.4.2). Robust Realism is established. Or so, at least, I have argued. As emphasized in the concluding section of chapter 4, work remains to be done: It remains to defend Robust Realism against traditional objections to it. I hope to that elsewhere. In this Conclusion, however, I want briefly to discuss two 307 related families of worries regarding Robust Realism that are not best seen, I think, as objections to the argument itself. Rather, they are worries regarding the intelligibility of the debate in which Robust Realism is one of the possible ways to go and about the robustness of my Robust Realism. 1. Robustness Recently there has been much literature not just within, but also about the realistantirealist debate. The worry is being expressed that there is after all nothing (or at least nothing of any consequence) in genuine dispute between realists and antirealists regarding a discourse or a subject matter. (I return to this worry in addressing quietism, below.) In response to this worry different people focus on different supposed commitments of realism and of its denial, arguing that they are what is really in dispute. Crispin Wright (1992) has suggested a pluralistic approach, arguing that for realism to be earned the relevant discourse or subject matter must at least show some typical characteristics of realist discourses, each alone perhaps not necessary for realism1. The following worry now threatens: Regardless of how exactly I officially characterize my Robust Realism, and in particular whether this official characterization satisfies the general requirements for a position to qualify as realist (let alone robustly realist), perhaps my argument cannot support a result as strong as that. Perhaps my argument supports only some rather minimal realism 1 Though he seems to think of his Cognitive Command as necessary. See Wright (1992, 222). 308 about normativity – say, minimal-truth-aptness and the denial of an extreme and global error theory – but nothing more than that? Indeed, if that is all my argument supports, then a more radical thought is available. If all that is needed for deliberation are normative truths rather thinly understood, perhaps I have shown not that some robust version of metanormative realism is in order, but rather that it just does not matter whether Robust Realism or its denial (consistent with some fairly minimalist realism) is true.2 In reply to this worry, I want briefly to go through several (not necessarily unrelated) purported characteristics of more than minimalist realism, and to see which of these can be had on the basis of my argument. I will thus endorse Wright’s pluralism, though I will not confine myself to the characteristics he thinks relevant, nor do I want to commit myself to the claim that these are the only characteristics relevant for the classification of a view as realist. My adoption of Wright’s pluralism is methodological: It will allow me to further elaborate on the strength of my argument from deliberative indispensability. Though I think that using the name “Robust Realism” for the view supported by my argument does in no way constitute false advertising (at least in the metanormative or metaethical context, a point I return to below), at the end of the day I of course do not care about the name, but rather about the view and the argument supporting it. 2 Crispin Wright raised this worry in conversation. 309 Sometimes it is thought that what is at issue between realists and antirealists are questions of truth and factuality. And indeed, I have characterized my Robust Realism as a claim about normative truths or normative facts arguing that nothing weaker than normative facts or truths suffices for deliberation. But this way of putting things does not really help: Given the availability of rather minimal (purely or almost purely disquotational) understanding of both truth and factuality it seems that what realists want and antirealists deny is a more robust notion of truth or of fact. Unfortunately, it is not clear what this more robust sense could come to, and – even more relevant here – putting the realist-antirealist controversy in terms of (say) robust facts seems to take us back to square one, for an account of robust truth seems just to be an understanding of realism. Indeed, many of the marks-of-realism that I proceed to discuss are often presented as criteria for a robust truth or factuality. Putting things in terms of (robust) truth and factuality is thus – even if not a mistake – unhelpful. A similar point applies to an understanding of the realism debate in terms of objectivity. I think it is fairly clear that the two issues – that of realism and of objectivity – are closely connected. Indeed, perhaps (unreconstructed) philosophical discourse does not consistently distinguish between them. But precisely for this reason, and because of the unclarity as to what objectivity could consist in, putting things in terms of objectivity does not help. Now, at one point (in section 4.4.2) I do use an objective-subjective distinction, but there I stipulatively define the distinction I am using. I think the distinction there 310 introduced does capture at least one genuine concern we sometimes express by talk of objectivity, and with objectivity understood as addressing this intuitive concern – that of idiosyncrasy and arbitrariness – I think deliberation does require objective normative truths. But perhaps there is more to objectivity, and it in anyway seems unhelpful to explain the philosophical dispute about realism in terms of another dispute – itself not better understood – regarding objectivity. It is sometimes, though certainly not always3, thought that the debate over realism is ontological or metaphysical in nature, that what is in dispute is whether, say, duties or values or reasons are a part of the fabric of the universe. This too, however, is a less than completely clear way of putting things. Is my Robust Realism ontologically committed? It is committed to some things being reasons, some things counting in favor of actions or beliefs, and so on – these are, roughly, the things deliberatively indispensable; therefore, it seems, it is committed to the existence of reasons or of the property of being a reason, and to the relation of counting-in-favor-of. So I am committed at least to the existence of normative properties and relations, if not objects. Does this qualify as an ontological commitment? The issue is complex, and I hope to address it more adequately elsewhere. I want to express here the suspicion that what is at issue is really what has been at issue all along – an understanding of the realism debate, or something dangerously close to it – and so putting things in ontological terms does not 3 Many paradigmatic metaethical realists deny any ontological or metaphysical commitments. See Nagel (1986, e.g. at 139), Scanlon (1998, e.g. at 62), Parfit (forthcoming, chapter 6). These denials are rarely supported by argument showing how metaphysical commitment is to be avoided. 311 promote our discussion. For instance, it is sometimes assumed that a commitment to a certain kind of property is not (or not really) ontological if these properties are not part of the causal order. I think this is a tendentious understanding of what is involved in ontology, for we do not want to assume in advance that everything that exists is a part of the causal order, nor do we want to restrict ontology so as not to cover things that (for all we know) exist. Without this qualification, I have no objection to seeing Robust Realism – and my argument for it – as ontologically committed. If, however, causal or explanatory role is necessary for a commitment to properties to be ontological, then the question whether Robust Realism is ontologically committed is reduced to questions about causality and explanation. I return to these below. Irreducibility is sometimes thought of as a mark of the real (or the really, ultimately real). I have argued in chapter 4 (in section 4.4) against the reducibility of the normative to the natural. My argument does support, then, the irreducibility of the normative. Sometimes associated with an epistemic understanding of truth (of which more shortly), and following Dummett’s work on realism, bivalence is often thought of as a mark of the real4. Does deliberation require that all normative judgments be bivalent, either true or false? The answer, I think, is “no”, for two reasons. First, as repeatedly emphasized in this essay, deliberation does not require a dichotomy of true and false, or correct and incorrect answers to the questions we 4 For a critical examination of bivalence as a mark of realism, see Fine (2001, 5). 312 ask ourselves. It is sufficient for deliberation that these questions have better and worse answers. And this, it seems, is consistent with the failure of bivalence. Second, as was emphasized in chapter 3 (for instance, in section 3.4.7), deliberation does not require full determinacy, or full comparability. For similar reasons, it need not require global bivalence. What is necessary for deliberation is that the deliberative project is not doomed from the start to systematic failure, and what this requires is, it seems, that a sufficiently substantial part of normative discourse satisfies bivalence. Robust Realism as supported by my argument from deliberative indispensability does not, then, entail global bivalence. Consider now the four issues Wright himself associates with debates over realism. One has already been discussed, if somewhat provisionally, in chapter 3 (in section 3.4.14). It is the one regarding the possible evidence transcendence of truth in the relevant domain. As I argue there, I think evidence transcendence is, though not immediately necessary for deliberation, nevertheless a plausible result of my argument, as its failure would call for explanation, and no plausible explanation in terms compatible with my Robust Realism seems in the offing. As I also explain there, and perhaps contrary to appearances, my argument certainly does not commit me to the denial of evidence transcendence. Another one of Wright’s realism-related-issues was discussed at length in chapter 1. His criterion of Wide Cosmological Role – Wright’s (improved) version of an explanatory criterion for realism, which is satisfied only by views that attribute to facts of the relevant subject matter an appropriate role in the best 313 explanation of respectable explananda – is very close to Harman’s Challenge discussed in chapter 1. There I argue against an explanatory requirement understood as a necessary condition for justified belief in a (purported) realm of facts. In chapter 1 I also argue that our reason for believing in normative truths is not explanatory, remaining neutral regarding whether they play any explanatory role. The context now is, though related, different: We are now interested not in what justifies belief in, say, normative facts, but rather in what would constitute a (more than minimally) realist position about it. Nevertheless, my discussion in chapter 1 applies: I am not committed to something like a Wide Cosmological Role for the normative, nor am I committed to denying such a role. And I think that such an explanatory criterion, as an attempt to capture something like what is intuitively at issue between realists and antirealists, is, for the reasons discussed in chapter 1, entirely unmotivated. Wright also speaks of the Euthyphro contrast: Given an extensional equivalence between the truths of the relevant discourse and the best opinion, judgment, or (other) response relevant to that discourse, there still remains an issue highlighted by Socrates’ challenge to Euthyphro: Are certain acts loved by the gods because pious, or are they pious because loved by the gods? This directionof-because issue seems to capture at least one concern relevant to the realism debate: For it seems that realists are bound to think of the facts as independent of 314 the relevant responses, whereas antirealists are likely to deny that.5 Do I think, then, that certain normative judgments are true because so judged, or that they are held to be true because true? It is clear, I think, that the argument for Robust Realism commits me to the rejection of the (purportedly) anti-realist way of taking the Euthyphro contrast. A view according to which normative judgments are true because of our beliefs or other attitudes is subjectivist in exactly the sense characterized and rejected in section 4.4.2 (in chapter 4). So am I committed to thinking that our best responses are best because of the truth of the normative judgments, that, say, under ideal conditions we love (or desire, or desire to desire) an action because it is good? I think I can avoid this commitment. If I can remain neutral on the question of the explanatory role of normative truths, it follows that I can remain neutral on this because-statements as well. Even if it is not the case that (say) we believe that there is always reason to alleviate pain because there is always reason to alleviate pain, still this does not rob us of our reason for adopting Robust Realism6. Of course, it is hard to reach clear conclusions about these matters without a better understanding of the “because” that does the work in the Actually, Euthyphro’s case is a problematic example here. Divine Command Theorists – sometimes thought of as the Judeo-Christian heirs of Euthyphro in their metaethical views – would typically be classified, I think, as realists of a fairly robust kind, even if, perhaps with Euthyphro, they think that certain acts are wrong because forbidden by God (and not the other way around). That such a view can still count as realist is probably due to the fact that the relevant response is God’s, whereas the relevant realism is, as it were, from our human, less-than-divine, point of view. 6 It may raise other worries, though, like an epistemological worry about whether our normative beliefs track the truth, and if they do not whether we ever have normative knowledge. I hope to address this worry – and other related epistemological worries about Robust Realism – elsewhere. 5 315 Euthyphro contrast7. So let me tentatively conclude that while my argument for Robust Realism does support rejection of the antirealist direction of the Euthyphro contrast, it allows me to remain neutral regarding the purportedly realist one. Trying to precisify intuitions about the relation between objectivity and disagreement, Wright distinguishes between discourses that do and those that do not exert Cognitive Command: “A discourse exerts Cognitive Command if and only if: It is a priori that differences of opinion formulated within the discourse … will involve something which may properly be regarded as a cognitive shortcoming.” (1992, 144)8 I think I can safely avoid discussion of the details of Wright’s Cognitive Command requirement. In our context, these may have to be revised because Wright’s formulation is motivated by analogies with fax machines and platitudes about representation and correspondence (1992, 91-94), and it is not clear that these motivations apply as strongly in the case of the normative as elsewhere. Nevertheless, it is clear that the intuitive point Wright tries to capture by his Cognitive Command is one my Robust Realism is committed to. At one point (1992, 146), Wright characterizes this intuitive point as follows: “the opinions which we form [in objective matters] are in no sense optional or variable as a function of permissible idiosyncrasy, but are commanded of us…”. And that this is Wright (1992, 139) thinks we still lack a good understanding of this contrast: “We should expect a multiplicity of distinction cluster around the Euthyphro contrast. Most of the work of exploring them and rendering them serviceable for use in debates about realism and objectivity is still to be done.” 8 The text omitted from the quote includes a few qualifications that are not relevant here. 7 316 true of normative judgments does indeed follow from my argument for Robust Realism. What we look for in deliberation are exactly answers that are not optional. Optional answers cannot bring deliberation to its conclusion, because we still have to choose among them, and because we are not, when deliberating, willing to take our psychological idiosyncrasies as merely given. Suitably generalized, then, Cognitive Command is a requirement satisfied by my Robust Realism and supported by my argument for it.9 To conclude: My argument supports a metanormative realism that is probably committed to the truth-aptness, factuality and objectivity of the normative (though it is not clear what these come to), that is probably ontologically committed (though this too is not clearly understood), that is committed to the irreducibility of the normative, that denies the anti-realist way to go in the Euthyphro contrast, and that asserts something about the non-optionality of (at least some) normative opinions. My argument does not support directly – but perhaps it does indirectly – a commitment to normative truth being evidencetranscendent. And it does not support a commitment to the bivalence of the normative, or to the normative having a Wide Cosmological Role. 9 As Crispin Wright himself noted in conversation, his characterization of Cognitive Command in Truth and Objectivity is too strict. One can weaken the requirement so that it is possible to have some permissible difference of opinion. So long as it is impossible to have too much permissible disagreement, or disagreement about the most important things (say, some core normative issues), the intuitive objectivity requirement Cognitive Command is meant to capture is satisfied. So, just as Robust Realism and my argument for it can allow for some (though not global) indeterminacy, and some (though not global) incomparability, so too it can allow for some (though not global) failure of Cognitive Command. 317 Is this enough robustness to justify the name “Robust Realism”? This is where the question becomes largely terminological, and so uninteresting. The answer may differ with context. In the metanormative or metaethical context, I think this is a rather robust kind of realism. I, in fact, do not know of a contemporary writer endorsing a more robust realism. Be that as it may, this is the kind of realism my argument, if successful, supports. 2. Quietism A number of closely related worries – not so much about realism of whatever kind, as about the debate in which it is one of the competing views – are sometimes grouped together under the heading “quietism”. These worries, applied to the discussion of the normative, include doubts about the intelligibility of metanormative discussion; claims that significant metanormative discussion is impossible; assertions that metanormative debates – if at all intelligible – can only be decided by engaging in first-order, normative discourse itself; claims that apparently metanormative debate just is normative debate in disguise; the thought that the practice of engaging in normative discourse (perhaps like other practices) needs no justification that is external to it, and that it is anyway impossible to supply one; and so on. If these statements of quietist worries are less than fully clear, this is no mere flaw of exposition on my part. Quietist worries – in the metanormative or metaethical context as elsewhere – are rarely put clearly, and even more rarely 318 argued for10. Such worries – sometimes motivated by readings of the later Wittgenstein – are expressed by thinkers from very different traditions, and with very different other philosophical commitments, as different as Dworkin and Blackburn, Nagel and Cavell, McDowell and Putnam, the Positivists and Rorty. These philosophers differ not only in what motivates their quietist inclinations, but also in what they think follows from quietism (Dworkin (1996), for instance, thinks that quietist observations serve to vindicate our confidence in our own normative beliefs and in some fairly robust version of realism; Blackburn (e.g. 1993b) thinks his quietist observations serve to strengthen the case for his Projectivism; McDowell (1985) thinks similar points allow for a comfortable middle ground in the realism debate, a metaphysically uncommitted, objectivist yet non-platonist, laid-back kind of realism.). It is unclear to me whether the fact that such a variety of philosophers – disagreeing on just about everything else – nevertheless seem to express the very same quietist worries should count as evidence for the seriousness of the worries, or as reason for suspicions regarding their intelligibility or determinacy. I cannot, of course, discuss all these related worries in detail here, much less can I do justice to the relevant work of all these philosophers. Let me briefly address here, then, just quietist worries that threaten – or may seem to threaten – Robust Realism or my argument for it. 10 See Wright (1992, 205). 319 Let me start, then, with the “no-vantage-point” intuition. So long as the relevant practice – call the one relevant here “the normative practice” – is itself acknowledged to be contingent, or at least – even if necessary in some way – rationally arbitrary, then I reject the thesis that it needs no justification external to it. Indeed, a view according to which our normative practice determines the only criteria of correctness there are is subjectivist in exactly the sense rejected in section 4.4.2 above11. Let me remind you that the argument there was not presented as a complete defense of objectivism. It was designed to show that a subjectivist understanding of normative discourse is actually a misunderstanding, that it misrepresents the commitments of normative discourse. This point is compatible with an error theoretical rejection of objectivism. Perhaps, in other words, we cannot get what we want. But this should not confuse us as to the understanding of what it is that we do want12. Perhaps, then, the stronger worry is that, though our normative practice does require “external” justification or grounding, none is forthcoming. Perhaps, in other words, we are trapped in our point of view, or form of life, or whatever it is that is constituted by our practice, and perhaps this epistemic handicap of ours For a related criticism of Dworkin’s quietism, see Raz (2001, 126). “Philosophy cannot take refuge in reduced ambitions. It is after eternal and nonlocal truth, even though we know that is not what we are going to get.” (Nagel, 1986, 10) Nagel himself at times sounds like a quietist of sorts. I suspect there is a genuine tension in Nagel’s thought about these matters. See also notes 17 and 21 below. As already mentioned, quietist worries are often associated with Wittgenstein’s Investigations, and in particular with the rule-following considerations (see the discussion in Wright 1992, chapter 6). So it may be interesting to put the point in the text in terms more clearly relevant to that discussion. If the ideas of following a rule, of a rule requiring one thing rather than another, can at best be vindicated by something like Kripke’s (1982) “skeptical solution”, then error theory, not naturalist reduction, has been achieved, for our rule-discourse clearly requires more than that. 11 12 320 precludes us from getting the kind of justification that is nevertheless, in some sense, required. This, it seems to me, is not so much a quietist worry as a general skeptical one. And I do not pretend to have addressed it in this essay. To an extent, it is the most general skeptical worry, one that is not peculiar to the normative, and so one that I can be excused from discussing here. Quietist worries are supposed to be distinct from epistemological skeptical ones. Perhaps the point is not that external justification is impossible, not even that it is unnecessary, but that this way of putting things is unintelligible. By asking for such practice-independent justification, we are already trying, confused as we are, to step outside ourselves, look at the universe from nowhere, view everything from no point of view. And, as the last formulation perhaps makes clear, this very attempt is deeply confused, perhaps even incoherent. The idea of practiceindependent justification – or any other practice-independent discussion – is inherently confused. Applied to our context, this line of thought suggests that meaningful metanormative discussion is unintelligible. Rather, it is a confused attempt to discuss the normative practice from without, from no normative point of view. And this is just as confused here as it is elsewhere. I want to make three points in response to this line of thought. First, to the extent that I understand the considerations that tempt philosophers in this direction, I find them unconvincing. But I cannot hope to discuss this point 321 seriously here13. Let me just note that there is nothing obvious about such claims, that they need to be established, and that I am not sure this can be done (much less am I sure it has already been done). Second, whatever force this quietist intuition has, it has it only in its most global version. Surely, we can step outside local, specific practices, and still judge them from within our most general point of view. So local practices can be challenged externally without falling into unintelligibility. And normative practice may be local in this way; at least, it remains to be shown that it is not. So perhaps the metanormative debate can be saved consistently with this most general quietism14. Third, I suspect Fine is right when he writes: “the fact that a notion appears to make sense is strong prima facie evidence that it does make sense.” (Fine, 2001, 13)15: Consider, for instance, the issues associated with the realism-antirealism debate that are discussed in section 1 of this Conclusion, and indeed the arguments scattered throughout this essay. Are they all confused pseudo-issues? Surely, they seem to make sense. And this is strong evidence, I think, that they do make sense. At the very least – and here I return to the first point above – some strong argument is needed if we are to be convinced otherwise. Nevertheless, a point I cannot resist making: Suppose it’s true that practices neither need nor have external justifications. Doesn’t this point apply, then, to the metaphysical or philosophical practice itself, and in particular to the practice metaethicists engage in? Wouldn’t it be an instance of philosophical discrimination to subject the practice of metaphysicians to the very kind of criticism one denies is either possible or, even if possible, legitimate elsewhere? For a related objection to (general) quietism, put in terms of self-defeat, see Cassam (1986, 455). 14 Leiter (2001c, 70-71) makes this point as against Dworkin. 15 For a similar point, see Zangwill (1992, 160). 13 322 Perhaps quietism is best understood, then, not as a claim about the unintelligibility of apparently intelligible debates, but rather about the impossibility of deciding them16. If this is a point about the impossibility of conclusive proof, perhaps it is well-taken (though this too remains to be shown). But in the normative case as elsewhere we have learned to settle for less. And it seems highly implausible that these matters – now admitted to be intelligible – do not admit even of good arguments, arguments that give at least some reason to believe, say, Robust Realism or its denial. Again consider some of the arguments in this essay, and some of the arguments against Robust Realism discussion of which I postponed for another occasion, such as worries about supervenience, reliability of normative beliefs, and normative disagreement: Do all of these arguments fail completely, in that they do not provide even the faintest support for their conclusion? This seems to me highly implausible, and very strong argument is needed in order to convince us that this is indeed so.17 (Needless to say, such argument is going to have to be much stronger than any supposed metanormative one, or else the latter’s impotence is going to convict the former as well.) This is what Fine (2001, 13) calls methodological quietism. And I believe Pritchard’s (1912) worry about moral philosophy is rather similar. Perhaps this is why he is sometimes thought of as a quietist. 17 Here is how Nagel expresses doubts about claims regarding the unintelligibility of apparently intelligible questions: “… if a demonstration that some question is unreal leaves us still wanting to ask it, then something is wrong with the argument, and more works needs to be done.” (Nagel, 1979, x). On the other hand, arguments like those in the text may not convince unintelligibilitythinkers, for, as David Lewis (1986, 203, footnote 5) once put it, “any competent philosopher who does not understand something will take care not to understand anything else whereby it might be explained.” 16 323 So maybe quietism is best understood not so much as the denial of the intelligibility of metanormative debates or as the claim that no metanormative argument carries any force, but rather as a claim about the nature of such arguments. Perhaps what is crucial here is that apparently metanormative arguments are really normative themselves18. What is apparently a detached, normatively neutral meta-discourse is thus folded back into the normative discourse itself. And such claims are supported mostly, I think, by examples of supposedly metanormative issues that can be shown to be normative, or at least to have normative implications19. It would not suffice for this kind of quietism that some apparently metanormative arguments and issues turn out to be normative ones. Rather, it is necessary that all so turn out. So think again of my argument from deliberative indispensability. Is it plausibly considered a first-order normative argument? Or think of challenges to realism, such as the claim that if our normative beliefs are to be justified we must be able to explain their reliability, and that no explanation is possible on realist assumptions. Is this clearly a piece normative reasoning? Are all apparently metanormative arguments plausibly considered normative ones? Clearly, the answer depends on how liberal one is willing to be with one’s 18 This, I think, is the intuition most strongly influencing Dworkin and Nagel (when in a quietist mood). 19 I believe Dworkin’s (1996) discussion systematically conflates these two: He repeatedly shows (or attempts to show) that a metaethical issue or controversy has ethical implications, and he then takes himself to have shown that metaethics just is a part of first-order moral discourse. But this, of course, is a mistake: Where I come from (and not only there), religious discourse has political implications, but this doesn’t show that religion and politics are one. 324 understanding of “normative”. But merely labeling apparently metanormative issues as themselves normative is of little interest20. Nothing in the arguments themselves – either for or against realism, robust or otherwise – seems to depend on us using the word “metanormative” rather than “normative” to describe them. And yet, quietists of this type take themselves to have established something of importance when they (take themselves to) have shown that apparently metanormative discourse is itself normative. Why? I can think of three ways in which it might be thought to matter if apparently metanormative arguments are really themselves normative, and I want to briefly review them here. First, such an observation may be thought to support doubts about the intelligibility or possibility of genuinely metanormative discourse. If what seems to be metanormative discussion really is just normative discussion, then, this thought goes, genuine metanormative discussion, one that is not really normative, is not possible. This may be so, but it is important to note that this point does not take us beyond the merely terminological debate: For the soundness of (apparently) metanormative arguments does not depend on their classification as normative or as (now genuinely) metanormative. Perhaps, in other words, no genuinely metanormative discussion is possible (if you choose to use these words in this way), but still there are interesting arguments for and against realism (now considered a normative, not a genuinely metanormative, position), and indeed 20 See Leiter (2001c, 72-3). 325 these are the very same arguments we thought of all along when doing metaethics or metanormativity. But quietists surely mean to do more than recommend a cleaner terminology. So something else – not just support for intelligibility worries – must be thought to be at stake. A second way in which it may seem to matter if apparently metanormative discussion is really just part of normative reasoning is that this being so undermines, it might be thought, certain skeptical or antirealist worries. For if what seems to be a metanormative challenge is really itself normative, then the skeptic herself makes normative assumptions, and is thus guilty of inconsistency. If apparently metanormative thought is really normative thought then normative thought is unavoidable in a way that seems to undermine any radical challenges to it by rendering them unstable. This line of thought is mistaken, however, for a reason discussed above in section 2.A.1 (in chapter 2). To repeat, then: radical skeptical challenges are best thought of as analogous to reductio arguments, employing weapons we must concede are powerful against us. The radical skeptic is thus entitled to engage in the very discourse she wants to attack so long as it is a discourse we want to defend. By so doing she will have shown, if successful, that normative discourse undermines or defeats itself. The observation that her doubts are themselves normative, then, does nothing to defend normative discourse. If her arguments cannot be shown to fail for reasons independent of the quietist observation, the 326 quietist observation, far from dealing a devastating blow to the skeptic, marks her unqualified victory. The third reason why the quietist observation – that apparently metanormative discourse is itself normative – may seem to be significant is that if it is true, there can be no objection, it seems, to the use of first-order arguments and intuitions in order to fight off skeptical or nihilist attacks. Suppose some metaphysical or epistemological – apparently metaethical – considerations seem to undermine morality altogether, supporting either a nihilist or a skeptical conclusion. Then, it seems, all it takes to refute them is the strength of our convictions that wanton cruelty is wrong, and that we know as much21. If metanormative considerations were of a very different type from normative ones, perhaps such a move would be objectionable, because of its conflation of two distinct, perhaps even independent22, levels of discourse. But given the quietist observations, this worry can be set aside. I agree that metanormative discourse may have implications on normative discourse23. And I think there can be no general objection to the use of first-order “The situation here [in ethics] is like that in any other basic domain. First-order thoughts about its content – thoughts expressed in the object language – rise up again as the decisive response to all second-order thoughts about their psychological character. … That is why we can defend moral reason only by abandoning metatheory for substantive ethics. Only the intrinsic weight of firstorder moral thinking can counter the doubts of subjectivism.” Nagel (1997, 125). For similar points, see Dworkin (throughout his 1996 and forthcoming), and Scanlon (1998, 63-4). 22 Perhaps this is the line of thought Mackie has in mind when writing: “These first and second order views are not merely distinct but completely independent.” (1977, 16). It is, however, unclear whether Mackie consistently accepts this point throughout his Ethics (1977). 23 Sturgeon (1986b, 125) is careful about this point, arguing that even if metaethical theses do not entail – all by themselves – moral consequences, they may, together with relevantly uncontroversial moral premises, entail such consequences. 21 327 arguments and intuitions in metanormative contexts. If these are metanoramtively irrelevant, this must be shown case by case. But nothing like the quietist observation follows. Even if normative arguments are metanormatively relevant, this does in on way show that they are the only metanormatively relevant arguments, or that once the normative discussion has been conducted nothing further remains to be said. Perhaps there is after all some significance to the classification of apparently metanormative arguments as normative, though I cannot think of one. Or perhaps something else can be saved from the general (and vague) quietist intuitions, something that survives the discussion above while still constituting a general challenge to my Robust Realism or to the metanormative debate in which it is one of the competing views. But the suspicion now arises that quietist worries are first and foremost expressions of impatience. In the normative context, they are expressions of impatience with metaphysical and epistemological discussions that are perceived as merely hindering the real, practically important, first-order discussion. There may even be good historical reasons for such impatience24. In the first two thirds of the twentieth century there was little philosophical interest in substantive moral questions, because (no doubt among other explanations) moral philosophers were busy doing metaethics, which was perceived as prior to – and 24 For a related point in the context of the pretensions for the general power of philosophy, see Fine (2001, 2-3). 328 independent of25 – morality. Morality was perceived as either lacking intellectual respectability, or at least as needing metaethical defense. An overreaction to such thoughts may be what is fueling quietist intuitions in the metaethical context, at least the quietist intuitions expressed by the friends of morality. But this is indeed an overreaction. One need not deny the intelligibility or distinctness of metanormativity (or metaethics) in order to acknowledge the legitimacy and intellectual respectability – already here and now, before the metanormative discussion has reached conclusions that enjoy unanimous support – of first-order normative (or moral) discussion. Be that as it may, I conclude that neither Robust Realism nor my argument for it is threatened by (what I can make of) quietist intuitions. 25 Thus, there is a significant volume of literature on the question of the ethical neutrality of metaethics. For a characteristic discussion, and for references to many others, see Sumner (1967). Sumner repeatedly considers the possibility that such a neutrality thesis is analytically true of metaethics, so that by showing that any purportedly metaethical theory has normative implications one will have shown that metaethics is impossible. Perhaps this too is an intuition fueling some quietists’ worries. But it should not. As the word “metaethics” is used today, nothing like the neutrality thesis is plausibly considered analytically true, and probably not even as merely true. 329 References Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics (Ross, D. (trans.), revised by Ackrill and Urmson) (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press; 1980). Audi, R. (1997) Moral Knowledge and Ethical Character (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Ayer, J. A. (1936), Language, Truth and Logic (London: Victor Gollancz), 2nd ed. 1946. Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H. (eds.) (1983) Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings (2nd ed.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Bentham, J. (1789), The Principles of Morals and Legislation (1988: New York: Prometheus Books). Blackburn, S. (1981), “Reply: Rule-Following and Moral Realism”, in Holtzman and Leich (1981), 163-187. Blackburn, S. (1985) “Errors and the Phenomenology of Value”, in Honderich (1985), 1-22. Blackburn, S. (1988) “How to be an Ethical Antirealist”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1988), 361-375; reprinted in Blackburn (1993a), 166-181. Blackburn, S. (1991a) “Just Causes”, Philosophical Studies 61, 3-17. Blackburn, S. (1991b) “Reply to Sturgeon”, Philosophical Studies 61, 39-42. Blackburn, S. (1993a), Essays in Quasi-Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Blackburn, S. (1993b) “Realism, Quasi, or Queasy?”, in Haldane and Wright (1993), 365-383. Blackburn, S. (1998) “Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 195-198. Blackburn, S. (1999), “Is Objective Moral Justification Possible on a Quasi-realist Foundation?”, Inquiry 42, 213-227. 330 Blackburn, S. (2001), Being Good (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press). Boghossian, P. A. (1989) “The Rule Following Considerations”, Mind 98, 507549. Boghossian, P. (2000) "Knowledge of Logic", in Boghossian and Peacocke (2000), pp. 229-254. Boghossian, P. (unpublished) “Reasoning and Mental Content”. Boghossian, P. A. and Velleman, J. D. (1989), “Colour as a Secondary Quality”, Mind 98, 81-103. Boghossian, P. and Peacocke, C. (eds.) (2000) New Essays on the Apriori (Oxford: Clarendon Press). Bond, E. J. (1983) Reason and Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Boyd, R. N. (1988), “How to Be a Moral Realist”, in Sayre-McCord (1988b), 181228. Brandt, R. B. (1955), “The Definition of an ‘Ideal Observer’ Theory in Ethics”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15, 407-413. Brandt, R. B. (1979), A Theory of the Good and the Right (New York: Prometheus Books). Bransen, J. and Cuypers, S. E. (eds.) (1998) Human Action, Deliberation and Causation (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers). Brink, D. O. (1989) Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press). Brink, D. O. (1997), “Kantian Rationalism: Inescapability, Authority, and Supremacy”, in Cullity and Gaut (1997), 255-291. Brink, D. O. (2001) “Realism, Naturalism, and Moral Semantics”, Social Philosophy and Policy 18(2), 154-176. Brower, B. W. (1993), “Dispositional Ethical Realism”, Ethics 103, 221-249. 331 Burgess, J. A. (1998), “Error Theories and Values”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76, 534-552. Butler, D. (1988), “Meaning and Metaphysics in the Moral Realism Debate”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 26, 9-27. Carnap, R. (1956) "Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology", in his Meaning and Necessity (2nd ed.) (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press), pp. 205-221; reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam (1983), pp. 241-257. Cassam, Q. (1986) “Necessity and Externality”, Mind 95, 446-464. Chang, R. (1997) “Introduction”, in Chang, R. (ed.) Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason (Cambridge: Harvard University Press), 1-34. Churchland, P. M. (1984), Matter and Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). Churchland, P. M. (1985), “The Ontological Status of Observables: In Praise of the Superempirical Virtues”, in Churchland and Hooker (1985), 35-47. Churchland, P. M. and Hooker, C. A. (eds.) (1985) Images of Science (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press). Cohen, G. A. (1996), “Reason, Humanity, and the Moral Law”, in Korsgaard (1996), 167-188. Cohon, R. (2000), “The Roots of Reasons”, The Philosophical Review (109), 6385. Colyvan, M. (2001) The Indispensability of Mathematics (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Copp, D. (1990) “Explanation and Justification in Ethics”, Ethics 100, 237-258. Copp, D. and Zimmerman, D. (eds.) (1984) Morality, Reason and Truth – New Essays on the Foundations of Ethics (Totowa: Rowman & Allanheld). Cullity, G. and Gaut, B. (eds.) (1997) Ethics and Practical Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press). 332 Dancy, J. (1995) “Why There Is Really No Such Thing as the Theory of Motivation”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95, 1-18. Dancy, J. (1996), “Real Values in a Humean Context”, Ratio 9, 171-183. Dancy, J. (2000) Practical Reality (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Darwall, S. (1992), “Internalism and Agency”, in Tomberlin (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 6 (Ethics), 1992, 155-174. J. E. Darwall, S. L. (1995), The British Moralists and the Internal ‘Ought’ (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Darwall, S. L. (1998), Philosophical Ethics (Oxford: Westview Press). Darwall, S. L. (1983) Impartial Reason (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press). Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., and Railton, P. (1992), “Toward Fin de Siecle Ethics: Some Trends”, The Philosophical Review 101, 115-189; reprinted in Darwall, Gibbard and Railton (1997), 3-47. Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., and Railton, P. (eds.) (1997), Moral Discourse and Practice (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press). Davidson, D. (1970), “How Is Weakness of the Will Possible?”, in Davidson, D. (1980) Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon Press), 21-42. De Sousa, R.B. (1974) “The Good and the True”, Mind 83, 534-551. Donagan, A. (1981), “W. A. Frankena and G. E. Moore’s Metaethics”, Monist 64, 293-304. Dreier, J. (1999), “Transforming Expressivism”, Nous 33, 558-572. Dretske, F. (2000) "Entitlement: Epistemic Rights without Epistemic Duties?", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60, pp. 591-606. Dummett, M. (1978) Truth and Other Enigmas (Cambridge: Harvard University Press). Dworkin, R. (1996) “Objectivity and Truth: You’d Better Believe It”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, 87-139. 333 Dworkin, R. (Forthcoming), “Internal Realism”. Enoch, D. (unpublished), “Epistemicism and Nihilism about Vagueness: What is the Difference?”. Enoch, D. and Schechter, J. (unpublished), “How Are Basic Belief-Forming Methods Justified?”. Enoch, D. and Schechter, J. (unpublished), “Meaning and Justification: The Case of Modus Ponens”. Feigl, H. (1952) "Validation and Vindication: An Analysis of the Nature and Limits of Ethical Argument", in Sellars, W. and Hospers, J. (eds.) Readings in Ethical Theory (New York: Appleton-Centur-Crofts), pp. 667-680. Feigl, H. (1954) "Scientific Method without Metaphysical Presuppositions", Philosophical Studies 5, pp. 17-29. Feigl, H. (1963) "De Principiis Non Disputandum…? On the Meaning and the Limits of Justification", in Black, M. (ed.) Philosophical Analysis, A Collection of Essays (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall), pp. 113-147. Field, H. (1980) Science Without Numbers: A Defence of Nominalism (Oxford: Blackwell). Field, H. (1989) Realism, Mathematics, and Modality (New York: Basil Blackwell). Field, H. (1991) “Metalogic and Modality”, Philosophical Studies 62, 1-22. Field, H. (2000) "Apriority as an Evaluative Notion", in Boghossian and Peacocke (2000), 117-149; reprinted with an appendix in his (2001) Truth and the Absence of Fact (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 361-392. Fine, K. (2001), “The Question of Realism”, Philosophers’ Imprint 1, 1-30. Firth, R. (1952), “Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12, 317-345. Firth, R. (1955), “Reply to Professor Brandt”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15, 414-421. 334 Foot, P. (2001), Natural Goodness (Oxford: The Clarendon Press). Frankfurt, H. G. (1971) “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person”, Journal of Philosophy 68, 5-20; reprinted in Frankfurt, H. G. (1988) The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Fumerton, R. (1992), “Inference to the Best Explanation”, entry in Dancy, J. and Sosa E. (eds.) A Companion to Epistemology (Oxford: Blackwell), 207-209. Gampel, E. H. (1996), “A Defense of the Autonomy of Ethics: Why Value Is Not Like Water”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26, 191-209. Gaut, B. (1997), “The Structure of Practical Reason”, in Cullity and Gaut (1997), 161-188. Gewirth, A. (1993) “The Constitutive Metaphysics of Ethics”, Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale 4, 489-504. Gibbard, A. (1990), Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Gibbard, A. (1992), “Reply to Blackburn, Carson, Hill and Railton”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, 969-980. Gibbard, A. (1999), “Morality as Consistency in Living: Korsgaard’s Kantian Lectures”, Ethics 110, 140-164. Gowans, C. (2002), “Practical Identities and Autonomy: Korsgaard’s Reformation of Kant’s Moral Philosophy”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64, 546-570. Grice, P. (1975) “Method in Philosophical Psychology (From the Banal to the Bizarre)”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 48, 23-53. Haldane, J. and Wright, C. (eds.) (1993a) Reality, Representation and Projection (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press). Haldane, J. and Wright, C. (1993b) “Introduction”, in Haldane and Wright (1993a), 3-12. 335 Hampton, J (1992) "Hobbes and Ethical Naturalism", in Tomberlin J. E. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 6, Ethics, 1992, 333-353. Hare, R. M. (1981), Moral Thinking (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press). Harman, G. (1965), “The Inference to the Best Explanation”, The Philosophical Review, 74, 88-95. Harman, G. (1970) “Knowledge, Reasons and Causes” Journal of Philosophy 67, 841-855. Harman, G. (1977) The Nature of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Harman, G. (1984) “Is There a Single True Morality?”, in Copp and Zimmerman (1984), 27-48. Harman, G. (1986) “Moral Explanations of Natural Facts – Can Moral Claims Be Tested Against Moral Reality?”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (supp.), 57-68. Harman, G. (1998) “Responses to Critics”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 207-213. Harman, G. and Thomson, J. J. (1996) Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity (Oxford: Blackwell). Hill. T. E. (1992), “Gibbard on Morality and Sentiment”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, 957-960. Hill, T. E. (2001) “Hypothetical Consent in Kantian Constructivism”, Social Philosophy and Policy 18(2), 300-329. Holtzman, S. H. and Leich, C. M. (eds.) (1981), Wittgenstein: to Follow a Rule (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Honderich T. (ed.) (1985) Morality and Objectivity (Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul). Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (1991), “New Wave Moral Realism Meets Moral Twin Earth”, Journal of Philosophical Research 16, 447-465. 336 Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (1992), “Troubles on Moral Twin Earth: Moral Queerness Revived”, Synthese 92, 221-260. Horwich, P. (1993), “Gibbard’s Theory of Norms”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 22, 67-78. Horwich, P. (1994), “The Essence of Expressivism”, Analysis 54, 19-20. Hubin, D. C. (1996), “Hypothetical Motivation”, Nous 30, 31-54. Hurley, S. L. (1989) Natural Reasons (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press). Jackson, F. (1982), “Epiphenomenal Qualia”, Philosophical Quarterly 32, 127126. Jackson, F., Oppy, G. and Smith, M. (1994), “Minimalism and Truth Aptness”, Mind 103, 287-302. Jackson, F. and Pettit, P. (1995), “Moral Functionalism and Moral Motivation”, The Philosophical Quarterly 45, 20-40. Jackson, F. and Pettit, P. (1996), “Moral Funcitonalism, Supervenience and Reductionism”, The Philosophical Quarterly 46, 82-86. Jacobs, J. (1989) “Deliberation, Self-Conceptions, and Self-Enjoyment”, Idealistic Studies 19, 1-15. Johnson, R. N. (1998), “Minding One’s Manenrs: Revisiting Moral Explanations”, Philosophical Studies 90, 181-203. Johnston, M. (1989), “Dispositional Theories of Value”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supp.), 139-174. Johnston, M. (1993), Objectivity Refigured: Pragmatism without Verificationism”, in Haldane and Wright (1993), 85-130. Kant, I. (1783) Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (Carus, P. (trans.), revised by J. W. Ellington) (Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett; 1977). Kant, I. (1785) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Gregor, M. (trans.)) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1997). 337 Kant, I. (1788) Critique of Practical Reason (Gregor, M. (trans.)) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1997). Kim, J. (1998) “Reasons and the First Person”, in Bransen and Cuypers (1998), 67-87. Kitcher, P. (1989) “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World”, in Kitcher and Salmon (1989), 410-505. Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. C. (1989) Scientific Explanations, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science vol. VIII (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press). Kolnai, A. (1962) “Deliberation is of Ends”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 62, 195-218. Korsgaard, C. M. (1983), “Two Distinctions in Goodness”, The Philosophical Review 92, 169-195. Korsgaard, C. (1996) The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), (edited by Onora O’Neill). Korsgaard, C. M. (1997), “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason”, in Cullity and Gaut (1997), 215-254. Krasnoff, L. (1999), “How Kantian is Constructivism”, Kant Studien 90, 385-409. Kripke. S. A. (1982), Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Oxford: Basil Blackwell). Leibniz, G. W. (1686), Discourse on Metaphysics (translated by Martin and Brown), (New York and Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1988). Leiter, B. (2001a) “Moral Facts and Best Explanations”, Social Philosophy and Policy 18(2), 79-101. Leiter, B. (ed.) (2001b) Objectivity in Law and Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Leiter, B. (2001c), “Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication”, in Leiter (2001b), 66-98. 338 Levin, M. (1987), “Reflections on Noncognitivism”, in I. L. Horowitz and H. S. Thayer (eds.) Ethics, Science, and Democracy – The Philosophy of Abraham Edel (New Brunswick: Transactions Books) (1987), 167-187. Lewis, D. (1986), On The Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers). Lewis, D. (1989), “Dispositional Theories of Value”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. Vol. 63, 113-137. Lipton, P. (1991), Inference to the Best Explanation (London and New York; Routledge). Locke, J. (1689) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (Woozley A. D., ed.) (New York: Penguin; 1964). Lycan, W. G. (1985), “Epistemic Value”, Synthese 64, 137-164. Lycan, W. G. (1986) “Moral Facts and Moral Knowledge”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, Supp., 79-94. Mackie, J. L. (1977), Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books). McDowell, J. (1981), “Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following”, in Holtzman and Leich (1981), 141-162. McDowell, J. (1985) “Values and Secondary Qualities”, in Honderich (1985), 110129. McDowell, J. (1987), “Projection and Truth in Ethics”, The Lindley Lecture, The University of Kansas; in Darwall, Gibbard and Railton (1997), 215-225. McGinn, C. (1997), Ethics, Evil, and Fiction (Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press). Milo, R. (1995), “Contractarian Constructivism”, Journal of Philosophy 92, 181204. Moore, G. E. (1903), Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press); revised edition (edited by T. Baldwin), 1993. Moore, M. S. (1992) “Moral Reality Revisited”, Michigan Law Review 90, 24252533. 339 Nagel, T. (1979), Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Nagel, T. (1986) The View From Nowhere (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press). Nagel, T. (1996), “Universality and the Reflective Self”, in Korsgaard (1996), 200-209. Nagel, T. (1997) The Last Word (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Nietzsche, F. (1887) The Gay Science (translated by W. Kaufmann) (New York: Vintage Books (1974)). Nietzsche, F. (1967) The Will to Power (translated by W. Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale; edited by W. Kaufmann) (New York: Vintage Books). Niiniluoto, I. (1999), “Defending Abduction”, Philosophy of Science 66 (Proceedings), S436-S451. O’Leary-Hawthorne, J. and Price, H. (1996), “How to Stand Up for NonCognitivists”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 275-292. O’Neill, O. (1992), “Vindicating Reason”, in P. Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge University Press, 1992), 280-308. Parfit, D. (forthcoming) Rediscovering Reasons. Peacocke, C. (unpublished) “Moral Rationalism”. Pettit, P. (2001) “Embracing Objectivity in Ethics”, in Leiter (2001), 234-286. Pettit, P. and Smith, M. (1990) “Backgrounding Desire”, The Philosophical Review 99, 565-592. Pettit, P. and Smith, M. (1993) “Practical Unreason”, Mind 102, 53-79. Pettit, P. and Smith, M. (1998) “Freedom in Belief and Desire”, in Bransen and Cuypers (1998), 89-112. Platts, M. (ed.) (1980a) Reference, Truth and Reality – Essays on the Philosophy of Language (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). 340 Platts, M. (1980b) “Moral Reality and the End of Desire”, in Platts (1980a), 69-82. Prichard H. A. (1912), “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake”, Mind 21, 2137. Putnam, H. (1971) Philosophy of Logic, reprinted in Putnam (1979), 323-357. Putnam, H. (1979) Mathematics Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers Vol. I, second edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Putnam, H. (1995) “Are Moral and Legal Values Made or Discovered?”, Legal Theory 1, 5-19. Quinn, W. (1993), “Putting Rationality in Its Place”, in Quinn, W., Morality and Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 228-255. Quinn, W. S. (1986) “Truth and Explanation in Ethics”, Ethics 96, 524-544. Railton, P. (1986a) “Moral Realism”, The Philosophical Review 95, 163-207. Railton, P. (1986b), “Facts and Values”, Philosophical Topics 14, 5-31. Railton, P. (1989a) “Explanation and Metaphysical Controversy”, in Kitcher and Salmon (1989), 220-252. Railton, P. (1989b), “Naturalism and Prescriptivity”, Social Philosophy and Policy 7, 151-174. Railton, P. (1992), “Some Questions about the Justification of Morality”, in Tomberlin, J. E. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 6 (Ethics), 1992, 27-53. Railton, P. (1993) “Reply to David Wiggins”, in Haldane and Wright (1993), 315328. Railton, P. (1997) “On the Hypothetical and Non-Hypothetical in Reasoning about Belief and Action”, in Cullity and Gaut (1997), 53-79. Railton, P. (1998) “Moral Explanation and Moral Objectivity”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 175-182. Ramussen, S. A. (1995), “Quasi-Realism and Mind-Dependence”, Philosophical Quarterly 35, 185-190. 341 Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press). Rawls, J. (1980), “Kantian Construcitvism in Moral Theory”, The Journal of Philosophy 77, 515-572. Rawls, J. (1993), Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press). Rawls, J. (2000) Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy (B. Herman ed.) (Cambridge: Harvard University Press). Raz, J. (1975) Practical Reason and Norms (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Raz, J. (2001) “Notes on Value and Objectivity”, in Leiter, (2001), 194-233; reprinted in Raz, J. (1999) Engaging Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 118-160. Regan, D. H. (2002), “The Value of Rational Nature”, Ethics 112, 267-291. Reichenbach, H. (1938) Experience and Prediction (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). Reichenbach, H. (1949) The Theory of Probability (2nd ed.) (trans. by E. H. Hutten and M. Reichenbach) (Berkeley: University of California Press). Resnik, M. D. (1995) “Scientific vs. Mathematical Realism: The Indispensability Argument”, Philosophia Mathematica 3, 166-174. Resnik, M. D. (1997) Mathematics as a Science of Patterns (Oxford: Clarendon Press). Richardson, H. S. (1994) Practical Reasoning about Final Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Rosati, C. S. (1995) “Naturalism, Normativity, and the Open Question Argument”, Nous 29, 46-70. Rosen, G. (1994) “Objectivity and Modern Idealism: What is the Question?” in M. Michael and J. O’Leary-Hawthorne (eds.), Philosophy in Mind (Kluwer Academic Publishers), 277-314. Rosen, G. (1998), “Blackburn’s Essays in Quasi-Realism”, Nous 32, 386-405. 342 Sayre-McCord, G. (1988a) “Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence”, Midwest Studies 12 (1988), 433-457; reprinted in Sayre-McCord (1988b), 256-281. Sayre-McCord, G. (1988b) Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press). Sayre-McCord, G. (1988c), “Introduction: The Many Moral Realisms”, in SayreMcCord (1988b), 1-23. Sayre-McCord, G. (1992) “Normative Explanations”, Philosophical Perspectives 6 (Ethics), 55-71. Sayre-McCord, G. (1997) “ ‘Good’ on Twin Earth”, in Villanueva, E. (ed.) (1997) Philosophical Issues 8 (Truth) (Atascadero, Ca: Ridgeview Publishing). Sayre-McCord, G. (2001) “Mill’s “Proof” of the Principle of Utility: A More Than Half-Hearted Defense”, Social Philosophy and Policy 18(2), 330-360. Scanlon, T. M. (1998), What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press). Schiffer, S. (2002), “Moral Realism and Indeterminacy,” Philosophical Issues 12, 286-304. Schilpp, P. A. (1942) (ed.) The Philosophy of G. E. Moore (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court). Schneewind, J. B. (1998), The Invention of Autonomy – a History of Modern Moral Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Scott, R. B. Jr. (1980), “Five Types of Ethical Naturalism”, American Philosophical Quarterly 17, 261-270. Sencerz, S. (1995), “Moral Facts and the Problem of Justification in Ethics”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73, 368-388. Sidgwick, H. (1906), The Methods of Ethics (7th ed.) (Indianapolis: Hacket Publishing). Simon, C. J. (1990) “The Intuitionist Argument”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 28, 91-114. 343 Skidmore, J. (2002), “Skepticism about Practical Reason: Transcendental Arguments and Their Limits”, Philosophical Studies 109, 121-140. Skorupski. J. (1998), “Rescuing Moral Obligation”, European Journal of Philosophy 6, 335-355. Slors, M. V. P. (1998) “Two Claims that Can Save a Nonreductive Account of Mental Causation”, in Bransen and Cuypers (1998), 224-248. Smith, M. (1994), The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers). Smith, M. (1999), “Search for the Source”, The Philosophical Quarterly 49, 384394. Sosa, D. (2001), “Pathetic Ethics”, in Leiter (2001), 287-329. Stevenson, C. L. (1937), “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms”, Mind 46, 1431. Sturgeon, N. L. (1982), “Brandt’s Moral Empiricism”, The Philosophical Review 91, 389-422. Sturgeon, N. L. (1984) “Moral Explanations” in Copp and Zimmerman (1984), 4978. Sturgeon, N. L. (1986a) “Harman on Moral Explanations of Natural Facts”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (supp.), 69-78. Sturgeon, N. L. (1986b), “What Difference Does It Make whether Moral Realism is True?”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (Supp.), 115-141. Sturgeon, N. L. (1991) “Content and Causes: A Reply to Blackburn”, Philosophical Studies 61, 19-37. Sturgeon, N. L. (1992), “Nonmoral Explanations”, in Tomberlin J. E. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 6 (Ethics), 1992, 97-117. Sturgeon, N. L. (1998) “Thomson against Moral Explanations”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 199-206. Sumner, L. W. (1967), “Normative Ethics and Metaethics”, Ethics 77, 95-106. 344 Svavarsdóttir, S. (2001), “Objective Values: Does Metaethics Rest on a Mistake?”, in Leiter (2001), 144-193. Svavarsdóttir, S. (2001), “Objective Values: Does Metaethics Rest on a Mistake?”, in Leiter (2001), 144-193. Taliaferro, C. (1988), “Relativizing the Ideal Observer Theory”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49, 123-138. Taylor, R. (1966) Action and Purpose (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall) Thagard, P. R. (1978), “The Best Explanation: Criteria for Theory Choice”, The Journal of Philosophy 75, 76-92. Ullmann-Margalit, E. and Morgenbesser, S. (1977) “Picking and Choosing”, Social Research 44, 757-785. Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980), The Scientific Image (Oxford; Clarendon Press). Van Fraassen, B. C. (1989), Laws and Symmetry (Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press). Van Roojen, M. (1996), “Moral Functionalism and Moral Reductionism”, The Philosophical Quarterly 46, 77-81. Velleman, J. D. (1989), Practical Reflection (Princeton: Princeton University Press). Velleman, J. D. (1992) “The Guise of the Good”, Nous 26, 3-26, reprinted in Velleman (2000a), 99-122. Velleman, J. D. (1996) “The Possibility of Practical Reason”, Ethics 106, 694-726, reprinted in Velleman (2000a), 170-199. Velleman, J. D. (2000a) The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press). Velleman, J. D. (2000b) “Introduction”, in Velleman (2000a), 1-31. Velleman, J. D. (forthcoming) “Willing the Law”, to appear in Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays, (Monika Betzler and Peter Baumann eds.) (Cambridge University Press); available at: http://www-personal.umich.edu/~velleman/Work/Willing.html 345 Velleman, J. D. (online), “A Brief Introduction to Kantian Ethics”, available at http://www-personal.umich.edu/~velleman/KANT.html Watson, G. (1975), “Free Agency”, Journal of Philosophy 72, 205-220. Wiggins, D. (1990), “Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 91, 61-86. Wiggins, D. (1991), “A Sensible Subjectivism?”, in his Needs, Values, Truth (3rd. ed.) (Oxford and New York: Clarendon), 185-214; reprinted in Darwall, Gibbard and Railton (1997), 227-244. Wiggins, D. (1998) “Truth, Invention, and the Meaning of Life”, in his Needs, Values, Truth (3rd. ed.) (Oxford and New York: Clarendon), 87-137. Williams, B. (1973), “A Critique of Utilitarianism”, in Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, B. (1973), Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 77-150. Williams, B. (1980), “Internal and External Reasons”, in Williams (1981), 101113. Williams, B. (1981) Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations (Anscombe, G. E. (trans.)) (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers). Wright, C. (1992) Truth and Objectivity, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press). Wright, C. (1993) “Realism: The Contemporary Debate – W(h)ither Now?”, in Haldane and Wright (1993), 63-84. Yasenchuk, K. (1994) “Sturgeon and Brink on Moral Explanations”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 32, 483-502. Zangwill, N. (1990), “Quasi-Quasi-Realism”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50, 583-594. Zangwill, N. (1992), “Quietism”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 17, 160-176. Zimmerman, D. (1984) “Moral Realism and Explanatory Necessity”, in Copp and Zimmerman (1984), 79-103. 346