DRAFT PAPER: 6TH JEAN MONNET SEMINAR, UNIVERSITY OF ZAGREB, 21 APRIL 2008 THE ROLE OF ENVIRONMENTAL PRINCIPLES IN COMMUNITY ARTICLE 28 JURISPRUDENCE DIGGING DEEPER INTO ENVIRONMENTAL EXCEPTIONALISM ELOISE SCOTFORD INTRODUCTION The Article 281 environmental case law of the European Court of Justice – those cases in which national ‘environmental’ legislation that prima facie infringes Article 28 is under review – is exceptional. As a body of jurisprudence it defies expectations of legally certain reasoning, particularly in relation to the Cassis de Dijon ‘rule of reason’.2 One way to conceive of this body of case law is this: it is exceptional because, in the balancing of free movement of goods and environmental protection under Article 28, environmental protection occupies a special BSc LLB (Hons) (Syd) BCL MPhil (Oxon), Career Development Fellow in Environmental Law, Corpus Christi College, Oxford, OX1 4JD. Many thanks to Dr Liz Fisher for her generous and timely help on drafts of this paper. All errors are and remain mine. 1 Article 28 EC. 2 Case 120/78 Rewe Zentral v Bundesmonopolverwaltung für Branntweinn (Cassis de Dijon) [1979] ECR 649. 1 place of prominence. In view of the environmental agenda of the Community and the prominence of environmental protection now in the EC Treaty,3 this form of ‘environmental exceptionalism’ has attractive explanatory force. In this light, the increasing role of ‘environmental principles’ (such as the principle of rectification at source and the integration principle) in Article 28 case law reflects the elevated Community view of and concern with environmental protection, translated into law. Some have argued that environmental principles can thus be used to instigate and design a new turn for Article 28 environmental jurisprudence. However, this view is too simplistic. Community environmental principles are complex creatures. They embody ambiguities of substance, of identity (being instruments of both policy and law), and of regulatory competence for environmental policy in the Community. As such they represent flashpoints for a number of challenging issues in Community environmental law, particularly in relation to Article 28. They are signals that bigger issues lurk beneath the surface in Article 28 environmental cases: issues of what is meant by ‘environmental protection’, and who should decide what that meaning is. These issues reflect a conception of Article 28 that sees Article 28 not simply as a legal site for trading off economic against social goals, but one at which the balance of institutional regulatory competence, and institutional choices about the nature of environmental protection, are implicated. Seen in this different light, current academic debates about Article 28 environmental case law, which focus on issues of legal certainty and the balance between free trade and environmental protection struck in the outcomes of the cases, are superficial. Environmental principles are a lever deeper into the case law. They are tools that can be used to see more difficult questions in the complicated and contested arena of multi-level governance in which Community environmental law operates. These questions warrant consideration. 3 Treaty of Rome, as amended (hereafter the ‘Treaty’). 2 This paper will primarily focus on three cases of the European Court of Justice concerning Article 28 infringements sought to be justified on environmental protection grounds: Walloon Waste,4 PreussenElektra,5 and Toolex.6 In each of these cases, ‘environmental principles’ are employed in the Court’s reasoning on justification. Part I explores the reasoning in these cases in order to demonstrate the nature of current academic debates in this area, and how the role of environmental principles is superficially understood in this discussion. Part II examines the complex and ambiguous nature of environmental principles and indicates how their role in the Article 28 case law might accordingly be complex. Part III presents a deeper picture of the Article 28 environmental case law, proposing an alternative conception of the role in environmental principles in the Article 28 case law. This deeper view explains why this case law appears so unsatisfactory (and is likely to remain so) and uncovers the questions that warrant debate in this area. Three caveats are made at this stage. Firstly, while Article 29 EC is intimately connected to Article 28, in that it is the complementary prohibition on quantitative and equivalent restrictions on exports to that on imports in Article 28, it is not considered in any depth in this paper. Where Article 29 cases are relevant to the discussion and arguments of this paper, they are mentioned in passing. Detailed analysis is reserved. Secondly, Article 28 cases that concern public health are also largely outside the scope of this paper. There is a considerable body of Article 28 jurisprudence that concerns national public health consumer protection regulation in which the ‘precautionary principle’ features strongly,7 applied explicitly by the Court as a relevant ‘environmental principle’ of the Treaty. These cases are 4 Case C-2/90 Commission v Belgium (Walloon Waste) [1992] ECR I-4431. Case C-379/98 PreussenElektra AG v Schhleswag [2001] ECR I-2099. 6 Case C-473/98 Kemikalienspektionen v Toolex Alpha AB [2000] ECR I-5681. 7 In particular, Case C-192/01 Commission v Denmark [2003] ECR I-9693 and the line of cases that follow its reasoning on the use of additives in food and feed. 5 3 not considered here. It is however noteworthy that there exists an overlap between ‘environmental’ and ‘public health’ cases,8 which reflects not simply the broad and unclear meaning of what is ‘environmental’, but raises interesting issues about patterns of contested regulatory competence in these areas of Community law along the lines suggested in this paper. This paper is a first step and detailed analysis of cases in which environmental principles are employed, beyond the three ‘environmental’ cases here focused on, is a matter for further and subsequent examination. Thirdly, and following on from this, this paper is part of a larger inquiry into the role of ‘environmental principles’ in Community law. The methodology underpinning this paper is one that posits that context is all important in ascertaining the roles of environmental principles, and that precise legal contexts must thus be explored to ascertain those roles.9 Hence the focus in this particular paper on Article 28 case law. To the extent that it leaves questions unanswered or avenues of exploration concerning the role of environmental principles in Community law untravelled, this is intentional. Next steps will follow. I THREE ARTICLE 28 ENVIRONMENTAL CASES AND THE CURRENT DEBATE The ‘environmental’ Article 28 cases with which this paper is concerned are those in which environmental protection grounds are adduced to justify infringements of Article 28. Article 28 infringements, which involve national regulatory measures that amount to quantitative restrictions or measures of equivalent effect between Member States,10 can be 8 Toolex demonstrates this nicely. This methodological approach, as well as being jurisdictionally precise, draws on literature that concerns ‘legal culture’: see further D Nelken, 'Using the Concept of Legal Culture' (2004) 29 Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 1; J Webber, 'Culture, Legal Culture and Legal Reasoning: A Comment on Nelken' (2004) 29 Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 27. 10 Broadly interpreted in Case 8/74 Procureur du Roi v Dassonville [1974] ECR 837. For examples of national ‘environmental’ measures that infringe Article 28, see JH Jans and HB Vedder, European Environmental Law (3rd edn, Europa Law Publishing, Groningen 2007) 235-7. 9 4 justified legally in two ways: under Article 30’s exculpatory ground of protecting ‘the health and life of humans, animals and plants’,11 or under the judicially derived ‘rule of reason’ which includes ‘environmental protection’ as one of its mandatory requirements.12 There are three main areas of confusion in the ECJ’s application of these two justifications in the Article 28 environmental case law. These areas of confusion and consequent academic debate are now be surveyed, using three cases as illustrative examples: PreussenElektra, Walloon Waste and Toolex Alpha. Article 30/Rule of Reason Overlap A division between the scope of Article 30, which allows infringing national measures to be justified on grounds of ‘protecting the life and health of humans, animals and plants’, and the Cassis mandatory requirement of ‘environmental protection’ exists.13 The primary reason that this division retains significance is the rule of reason’s restriction to national measures that are ‘applicable to domestic and imported products without distinction’, 14 which does not apply under Article 30. Once this restriction ceases to have importance however (see the second area of confusion below), so does the division between Article 30 and the rule of reason. This is particularly so because the distinction between protecting the health and life of humans, animals and plants (Article 30) and environmental protection (rule of reason) is difficult to 11 Article 30 EC. Cassis de Dijon; Case 302/86 Commission v Denmark (Danish Bottles) [1988] ECR 4607. In strict terms, the rule of reason does not set out a justification for the infringement of Article 28, rather it precludes its operation: A Ziegler, Trade and Environmental Law in the European Community (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1996) 50. However, this formal distinction makes little sense: J Wiers, Trade and Environment in the EC and the WTO: A Legal Analysis (Europa Law Publishing, Groningen 2002) 99-100. In practice, Article 30 and the rule of reason are treated as similar ‘justifications’ by the Court: see, for example, Case C-389/96 Aher-Waggon GmbH v Germany [1998] ECR I-4473 [19]. 13 A proposal to insert ‘environmental protection’ into Article 30 was rejected at the Intergovernmental Conference preparing the Amsterdam Treaty. 14 Danish Bottles [6]. 12 5 draw. The cases tell us that it lies somewhere between a case in which the survival of a species of bee was at stake (within Article 30 as protecting the life of animals)15 and ones in which a geographical area was at risk of overpollution from imported waste16 or the viability of a domestic recycling industry was at issue17 (concerned with ‘environmental protection’). Why such a distinction is drawn at all is, as a matter of common sense, unconvincing. Protecting ‘the health and life of humans, animals and plants’ is a phrase that seems very apt to capture a broad idea of environmental protection, as any anthropocentric view of environmentalism would attest. Commentators share this view.18 As the Court’s reasoning in PreussenElektra demonstrates, the distinction does not work and arguably it is no longer of any real relevance in the case law in this area. In PreussenElektra, the Court reviewed German ‘buy local’ provisions, which obliged German network operators to purchase renewable energy at a fixed minimum cost from German energy suppliers, for their compatibility with Article 28. The measures infringed Article 28 (electricity is a good) and were found to be justified. Whether they were justified by Article 30 or the mandatory requirement of environmental protection was not specified by the Court, which found that ‘the use of renewable energy sources [which the measure is designed to promote] is useful for protecting the environment in so far as it contributes to the reduction in emissions of greenhouse gases which are amongst the main causes of climate change’19 and that Community policy on climate change is ‘also designed to protect the health and life of humans, animals and plants’.20 Commentators have 15 Case C-67/97 Criminal Proceedings against Bluhme (Danish Bees) [1998] ECR I-8033. Walloon Waste [30]. 17 Case C-203/96 Dusseldorp [1998] ECR I-4075. 18 P Craig and G de Burca, EU Law: Text, Cases and Materials (4th edn, Oxford University Press, 2008) 706-7; cf L Krämer, EC Environmental law (6th edn, Sweet & Maxwell, London 2007) 104-5. 19 PreussenElektra [73]. 20 ibid [75]. 16 6 understood the Court in this case to be applying the rule of reason,21 but it does so in an unarticulated way that demonstrates the overlap of Article 30 and the rule of reason. The Role of Discrimination There is extensive debate about the role that discrimination has, or should have, in justifying infringements of Article 28 on environmental protection grounds.22 Whatever the merits of this debate, there is a significant line of case law indicating that discrimination now irrelevant in Article 28 environmental cases. Discrimination, as an issue, appears in two guises in the justification of Article 28 infringement. Firstly, it appears in the second sentence of Article 30, which provides that the justificatory grounds in Article 30 ‘shall not... constitute a means of arbitrary discrimination’. This proviso has been little discussed in the cases. This is not surprising – it does not introduce a test of discrimination; rather it qualifies the nature of the requirement in Article 30’s first sentence by highlighting that infringing national measures must genuinely protect the health and life of humans etc.23 Secondly, as mentioned above, a test of ‘indistinct applicability’ triggers the rule of reason. This form of discrimination is one that refers to discrimination on the basis of origin. Thus, under the rule of reason, the national measures under scrutiny must treat goods and traders alike, whatever their origin. Such discrimination is often equated with ‘formal discrimination’ or ‘discrimination in law’. Debate 21 F Jacobs, 'The Role of the European Court of Justice in the Protection of the Environment' (2006) 18 Journal of Environmental Law 185 191-2; S Poli, 'Case Comment: National Schemes Supporting the Use of Electricity Produced from Renewable Energy Sources and the Community Legal Framework' (2002) 14 (2) Journal of Environmental Law 209; Wiers 98-99. 22 Krämer 110-113; Jacobs 189-194; Jans and Vedder 247-9; N Notaro, 'The New Generation Case Law on Trade and Environment' (2000) 25 (5) European Law Review 467; H Temmink, 'From Danish Bottles to Danish Bees: The Dynamics of Free Movement of Goods and Environmental Protection - A Case Law Analysis' ([2001]) Yearbook of European Environmental Law 61, 90-92; Wiers 121-7. 23 Cf Wiers 121. 7 in this area is unhelpfully confused by loose terminology.24 The notion of discrimination might also refer to ‘discrimination in fact’ or ‘indirect discrimination’. Cases in which the goods or activities of traders of importing Member States are treated differently in effect by indistinctly applicable national measures fall within these conceptions.25 Indirect discrimination, however, is not of concern in Article 28 justificatory cases; it is an issue that is relevant to whether there is an infringement of Article 28 at all.26 The contentious ‘discrimination’ issues when it comes to justification under the rule of reason are whether the rule’s limitation to national measures that are indistinctly applicable to local and imported goods and traders is (1) sensible and (2) actually applied by the ECJ in environmental cases. The second issue can be resolved shortly: whether distinctly or indistinctly applicable national measures (as well as measures that are discriminatory in fact) are under scrutiny, the rule of reason, if it can still be recognised as that, is nonetheless applied by the ECJ in environmental cases.27 The first issue, whether the discrimination criterion is a sensible one, is not considered by the Court, which has shifted its ‘rule of reason’ jurisprudence in environmental cases without acknowledgement, but it is considered by commentators.28 Walloon Waste demonstrated the first step towards the open application of the rule of reason to both distinctly and indistinctly national measures, which are adopted on environmental grounds. In this much discussed case, the Wallonian Regional Executive in Belgium passed a decree preventing the storage, tipping or dumping of any non-Wallonian 24 C Hilson, 'Discrimination in Community Free Movement Law' (1999) 24 European Law Review 445; Wiers 119-120. 25 As under the recycling scheme under scrutiny in Danish Bottles. 26 Particularly in light of Joined Cases C-267/91 and C-268/91 Criminal Proceedings against Bernard Keck and Daniel Mithouard [1993] ECR I-6097. See also Opinion of AG Kokott, Case C-142/05 Aklagaren v Mickelsson and Roos, 14/12/2006. Cf the possible effect of Keck on justifications for Article 28 infringement: Wiers 122. 27 Danish Bottles; Walloon Waste; Dusseldorp; Aher-Waggon; PreussenElektra; Case C-320/03 Commission v Austria [2005] ECR I-9871. 28 Above, n22. 8 waste in Wallonia. The Commission brought an Article 226 enforcement action against Belgium for infringing Article 28 in preventing the import of waste from other Member States. The ECJ found that the Wallonian decree, while it infringed Article 28, was justified under the ‘imperative requirements relating to environmental protection’ (rule of reason). Rather than abandoning the distinction between distinctly and indistinctly applicable measures, the ECJ found that the Wallonian measure was not in fact ‘discriminatory’29 since waste from outside Wallonia had a different character from Wallonian waste (there then being no question of distinct applicability where the decree applies to different imported goods). In reasoning widely criticised as ‘unconvincing’,30 the Court uses the principle of rectification at source laid down in Article 174(2) of the Treaty (supported by the principles of proximity and selfsufficiency)31 to find that waste produced in different places is different, in light of the Community environment policy embodied in this principle that waste should be disposed of as close to its place of production as possible. The ECJ here undermines the relevance of the Cassis discrimination test by employing this awkward reasoning.32 In PreussenElektra, the Court confirms the unimportance of discrimination under the rule of reason, by abandoning any pretence of maintaining the distinction between distinctly and indistinctly applicable measures. In that case, the measures in question are distinctly Note the loose use of ‘discrimination’ by the Court but it is concerned with discrimination on basis of origin. Cf Jans and Vedder 248. 30 Jacobs 189. The counter argument posits that waste is waste, wherever it comes from, and that this is self-evident. 31 The Court draws on these principles from international environmental law (the Basel Convention of 22 March 1989 on the control of transboundary movements of hazardous wastes and their disposal) to which the Community is subject (as a signatory to the Convention). It could alternatively have drawn on the same principles from secondary Community law (Waste Directive, Article 5). The fact that it did not do so is interesting: it contributes to the discussion of the ECJ’s role in articulating substantive environmental policy, and where it is getting that policy from, as a matter of ‘law’. See Part III below. 32 For similar reasoning in a non-environmental Article 28 case, see Case 113/80 Commission v Ireland [1982] ECR 1625: MP Maduro, We the court : the European Court of Justice and the European Economic Constitution : a critical reading of Article 30 of the EC Treaty (Hart Publishing, Oxford 1998) 52. 29 9 applicable, in that they restrict free movement of electricity on the basis of its origin, yet the ECJ has no trouble justifying the measures on environmental protection grounds. The irrelevance of the distinction is then reinforced in Commission v Austria,33 in which case the ECJ applied the rule of reason with no examination of the distinct applicability of the national measure under review, despite the Commission’s insistent arguments that its discriminatory nature precluded justification on environmental protection grounds.34 In both these cases, the Court refers to the ‘integration principle’ in Article 6 of the Treaty35 to support its findings that the contested national measures fall within the scope of environmental protection justification. Again, the Court relies on an environmental principle to smooth over the creases in its reasoning under the rule of reason. In this way, the integration principle has explanatory force – as a principle that requires environmental protection requirements to be integrated into all Community policies and activities, it explains why these environmental protection cases are exceptional, and thus why their rule of reason reasoning is exceptional. Advocates General and commentators alike have drawn on this explanation to suggest that the integration principle not only marks a shift in the case law, but that it should do so.36 Advocate General Jacobs in PreussenElektra thus argues that the integration principle means that ‘special account must be taken of environmental concerns in interpreting the Treaty provisions on the free movement of goods’,37 and consequently that discriminatory national measures should be justifiable on grounds of environmental protection. In current debate, therefore, environmental principles are seen as informing and explaining current case law tests, and, in relation to discrimination under 33 Commission v Austria, above n27. ibid [38]–[39]. 35 Article 6 EC. 36 PreussenElektra, Opinion of AG Jacobs, Commission v Austria, Opinion of AG Geelhoed; M Humphreys, 'Case Comment: Disproportionate and Discriminating Environmental Protection' (2007) 9 (2) Environmental Law Review 137, 147; Poli 228. 37 Jacobs 192. 34 10 the rule of reason, as a reason for clarifying that environmental protection, as a justification for infringing Article 28, applies to distinctly as well as indistinctly applicable measures. Legal certainty in the case law is the goal of this call for clarification.38 A Question of Proportionality The principle of proportionality also causes considerable confusion in Article 28 environmental cases. In theory, proportionality is a limit generally applied by the Court in reviewing national measures that infringe Article 28 on environmental protection grounds, whether justified under Article 30 or the rule of reason. The case law however veers between cases in which there are detailed proportionality analyses,39 to those cases where the proportionality principle is not considered at all40 or very weakly applied.41 When proportionality is considered by the Court, there is confusion over its precise elements.42 This confusion is not helped by the shorthand used in these cases requiring infringing national measures to be ‘necessary and proportionate’ to be justified.43 Necessity is best seen as an element or description of proportionality.44 The elements or limbs that potentially comprise the proportionality test are: 1. the suitability of the national measure to the attainment of its ‘legitimate’ objective (in these cases, environmental protection);45 2. the necessity of the measure – that it is the means of attaining its objective that is least restrictive of the free movement of goods; 38 ibid 192. Danish Bottles, Aher-Waggon, Commission v Austria, Case C-309/02 Radleberger Getrankegesellschaft v Land Baden-Wuttemberg [2004] ECR I-11763; Case 463/01 Commission v Germany [2004] ECR I-11705. 40 Walloon Waste, PreussenElektra. 41 Danish Bees. 42 Notaro 486. 39 43 44 45 Wiers cf Kramer. Sometimes also unhelpfully referred to as ‘necessity’. 11 3. proportionality stricto sensu – that the restriction on free movement must not be disproportionate to the legitimate aim of environmental protection pursued. In most of the Article 28 environmental cases that consider proportionality, the Court assumes the first element and focuses on the second.46 Only in Danish Bottles does it apply the third element (albeit without clear elaboration) to find that the level of environmental protection set by Denmark in the provisions of its national container recycling scheme was too high.47 This case demonstrates why the inclusion of the third limb is so significant – it allows the ECJ to adjudicate what is the appropriate level of environmental protection that a Member State can pursue.48 This is a powerful limit on the regulatory discretion that Article 28 justifications leave to Member States in environmental protection matters. In the same way, the first limb of proportionality has the potential to restrict the discretion that Member States have to pursue environmental policies, to the extent that the Court assesses the ‘legitimacy’ of the objective pursued by infringing national measures, and how suitably it is achieved. In the cases, the Court has either accepted that the objective of environmental protection is pursued by the national measure under review49 or assessed its legitimacy and suitability favourably in accordance with Community law.50 In both ways, the Court is affording a broad discretion to Member States to regulate with respect to environmental protection; however the second route does demonstrate control over that discretion. 46 Thus, both the first and third limbs of See, for example, Aher-Waggon, Commission v Austria, Radleberger, Commission v Germany. Cf, for example, Commission v Austria, in which case the ECJ accepts the level of protection assumed by the Austrian measure, but focuses on whether a means less restrictive of free movement could have been adopted. 48 Wiers 107, Maduro 56. 49 Consider Aher-Waggon: the Court did not discuss the suitability limb expressly but appeared to assume its satisfaction in approving the German government’s concern with ensuring that its population is protected from excessive noise restrictions [19]. Similarly, in Commission v Austria, the ECJ finds that it is ‘undisputed that the contested regulation was adopted to ensure the quality of ambient air in the zone concerned and is therefore justified on environmental protection grounds’, before going on to assess whether it is the least restrictive means for attaining this air quality objective [71]. 50 See Part III. 47 12 proportionality have institutional implications; they give the ECJ the power, should it choose to exercise it, to decide how much discretion Member States should have in articulating what environmental protection is and at what level it should be set. As for the role of environmental principles in proportionality tests, Toolex Alpha is a case that demonstrates how the ECJ has used an ‘environmental principle’ to inform the proportionality inquiry. In Toolex, the infringing national measure was a Swedish regulation that prohibited the industrial use of trichloroethylene (TCE), but which provided exemptions for undertakings where alternatives for TCE are not yet available, conditional on the relevant undertaking continuing to investigate (and use) safer TCE substitutes. The regulation was found to infringe Article 28, but to be justified on public health and environmental grounds under Article 30.51 The proportionality principle was applied very perfunctorily in this case. There was no discussion of the various limbs of the proportionality test; rather the ‘substitution principle’ was invoked to demonstrate compliance with proportionality. The substitution principle is a principle of ‘environmental management’, which embodies the idea that dangerous substances should be systematically replaced by less dangerous ones, as soon as they become available.52 This idea is one that is reflected increasingly in secondary Community law, and, as a principle of Community environmental policy, it was sufficient to sanction the proportionality of the Swedish measure in this case.53 Heyvaert notes that Toolex might herald the demise of the proportionality principle, along with the rise of environmental principles, ‘which could augment the Member States’ freedom to choose the means they deem 51 Note the overlap between public health and environmental grounds, which does not affect reliance on Article 30. 52 V Heyvaert, 'Balancing Trade and Environment in the European Union: Proportionality Substituted?' (2001) 13 (3) Journal of Environmental Law 392, 404. 53 Toolex [47]. 13 appropriate to secure the desired level of health and environmental protection’.54 This is only true in so far as Member States’ policies marry with those at Community level, as Toolex demonstrates, thus leaving the Court with control to determine the scope of Member State discretion in the environmental domain by measuring its exercise against the ‘principles’ of Community environmental policy. In this way, the use of the substitution principle presents, in different form, similar institutional implications to those latent in the first and third limbs of proportionality, as discussed above. The substitution principle has not removed some of the more controversial elements of proportionality; rather it has recast them in different form. Such institutional implications are where things start to get interesting in the Article 28 environmental cases, as the following Parts of the paper will demonstrate. However, academic debate on proportionality in these Article 28 environmental cases has not been preoccupied with such concerns.55 Rather, it is often concerned with the outcomes in the cases where proportionality is discussed and ascertained, viewing proportionality analysis in terms of a balance between trade and environmental concerns, and outcomes as trade or environmentallyoriented in the balance.56 II ENVIRONMENTAL PRINCIPLES: AMBIGUOUS IN NATURE AND COMPLEX IN APPLICATION The Single European Act saw the beginning of a period in which ‘environmental principles’ have been introduced and increasingly prioritised in Community law, in line with the 54 Heyvaert 405. Cf Wiers and Maduro, above n48. 56 See, for example, Heyvaert; Jacobs; Notaro. 55 14 prioritising of environmental protection goals in the Treaty.57 The following Community environmental principles, at least, can now be identified: 1. the four principles of Community environmental policy in Article 174(2) of the Treaty: the precautionary principle, the preventive principle, the principle of rectification at source and the polluter pays principle; 2. the ‘integration principle’ of Article 6;58 and 3. those principles that find expression in, or ‘emerge’ from, secondary legislation (eg principles of proximity, self-sufficiency, and substitution).59 Already one of the complicating features of ‘environmental principles’ is apparent – they are an amorphous group of ideas that do not take the same form or have a common derivation. They are linked generally by a common theme of embodying ideas that support environmental protection. Also, they do not embody precise rules.60 57 Commentators like to talk of After successive Treaty revisions (Single European Act, Maastricht and Amsterdam Treaties in particular), environmental protection is prioritised in the Treaty as follows. The Community has as one of its basic tasks in Article 2 EC the promotion of ‘a high level of protection and improvement of the quality of the environment; also, in Article 2, the Community is to execute its task by establishing a common market and by implementing the policies and activities in Article 3 EC, which include an environmental policy (Article 3(l) EC). In addition, environmental protection now finds a place in Article 6 EC’s requirement that environmental protection requirements must be integrated into all Community policies and activities (the ‘integration principle’), as a reason for and a reason for derogating from harmonisation measures under Article 95 EC, and as a central plank of the head of Community competence and policy in Title XIX. Within Title XIX, Community environmental policy that aims at a high level of protection is to be based on four principles: the precautionary principle, the preventive principle, the principle of rectification at source and the polluter pays principle (Article 174(2) EC). No other area of Community policy in the Treaty is prescribed by principles in this way. For a survey of the history of these developments, see Jacobs, 185-7; Notaro, 467-8. 58 Note Article 6 is not referred to as the ‘integration principle’ in the Treaty, but is identified as such by the Court and commentators across the board. 59 Directive 2006/12/EC on waste [2006] OJ L114/9, Article 5 (principles of self-sufficiency and proximity); Directive 89/391/EEC on the introduction of measures to encourage improvements in the safety and health of workers at work [1989] OJ L 183/1, Directive 90/394/EEC on the protection of workers from the risks related to exposure to carcinogens at work (Sixth individual Directive within the meaning of Article 16(1) of Directive 89/391/EEC) [1990] OJ L196/1) (substitution principle). 60 Any lengthy discussion on the nature of principles and rules from a jurisprudential perspective is avoided, as it is liable to fall into an area of academic scholarship (founded on Dworkin’s theory of rules, principles and policies) that has been developed in a different legal context (in particular, judicially developed principles in common law litigation) and that prescribes the legal nature of ‘principles’. This 15 environmental principles as a group,61 which suggests that they are equivalent, or at least related, concepts. Such an assumption of equivalence between environmental principles is not here assumed; rather their contextual identity is explored in Article 28 jurisprudence. In this particular legal context, we can see that environmental principles are implicated and related in the ECJ’s reasoning in four ways. Firstly, as seen in Part I, the ECJ has increasingly relied on environmental principles to develop its reasoning in Article 28 environmental cases; at the same time such reasoning is faltering on orthodox lines of Article 28 justification. Secondly, environmental principles represent the basis of ‘Community’ policy on the environment.62 The meaning of this is ambiguous. Does Community environmental policy mean environmental policy determined by Community institutions, within their sphere of competence? Such a position is uncontroversial to the extent that the Community has competence to develop environmental policy.63 However, it has the potential to be controversial in that environmental policy is explicitly a shared competence – Member States have a reserved role in formulating environmental policy and regulation64 – and paper aims to investigate and not prescribe. On this alternative literature, see, by way of introduction, R Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (2nd edn, Duckworth, London 1978) Chs 3,4; M Doherty, 'Hard Cases and Environmental Principles: An Aid to Interpretation?'[2002] (3) Yearbook of European Environmental Law 57. 61 See, for example, N de Sadeleer, Environmental Principles : From Political Slogans to Legal Rules (OUP, Oxford 2002); A Epiney, 'Environmental Principles' in R Macrory (ed) Reflections on 30 Years of EU Environmental Law (Europa Law Publishing, Groningen 2006); S Bell and D McGillivray, Environmental law (6th edn, OUP, Oxford 2006) 59-78. 62 Article 174(2) states that ‘Community policy on the environment’ shall be based on the four principles there set out. Equally, in Article 6, the integration principle extends to all Community policies and activities. However, those principles derived from secondary Community legislation are different – they are expressly environmental policy determined by Community institutions. However to the extent that these legislative principles exist in framework Directives, like the Waste Directive, they leave Member States room to implement and interpret them as they choose, and so some ambiguity remains as to who is responsible for the formulation of policy based on these environmental principles. 63 Article 6, 95, 175 EC in particular. 64 Article 5 EC (which used to be solely located in the environmental title of the Treaty: ex-Article 130r(4)), Article 176 EC. Note that Member State competence is not limited to action that is best taken at Member State level (limit of subsidiarity), but that Member States enjoy a discretion to take more protective environmental action. What this additional margin of discretion allows is complicated by the fact that it must be exercised in accordance with the Treaty, but surely it cannot mean that it is limited by 16 so any articulation of ‘Community’ environmental policy by Community institutions (including the ECJ) must respect that division of power. Thus, and in line with Article 176 EC, this first interpretation of ‘Community environmental policy’ reserves discretion to Member States to articulate environmental policy, however they conceive it. Or does ‘Community’ environmental policy mean environmental policy for the entire Community, for Member States individually and the Community as a whole, whichever institutions (Community or Member State) are responsible for its articulation? Militating in favour of this second interpretation is the oft-recognised problem that environmental issues do not necessarily respect national boundaries. However, sometimes environmental problems are localised to Member States (eg pollution of groundwater, those that relate to local planning etc) – the very reason why subsidiarity is such an appropriate prescription in this area. This second interpretation opens up the possibility of Community institutions assuming control of the content of environmental policy throughout the Community, and is particularly pertinent in the ECJ’s review of Member State action in Article 28 cases, in which it relies on principles of ‘Community’ environmental policy, since in these cases it is concerned with Member States’ discretion to assert their own environmental policy. Thirdly, the principles all have ambiguous identities as instruments of law and policy. They are conceptions of environment policy, which are legally prescribed by different forms of Community law (Treaty, secondary law). This ambiguity is highlighted nicely in the wording of Article 174(2) EC: ‘Community policy on the environment shall be based [on the four environmental principles there set out]’.65 This split legal/policy identity suggests two things: (1) that the principles have legal roles of some sort (the nature of which this paper explores in a the Community institutions’ view of what ‘environmental protection’ is? See Part III below. Position post-Lisbon? 65 See further E Scotford, 'Mapping the Article 174(2) Case Law: A First Step to Analysing Community Environmental Law Principles' (2008) Yearbook of European Environmental Law (forthcoming). 17 particular legal context), and (2) that policy choices are implicated when the principles are relied on. This second suggestion augments the complexity of the issue just discussed in relation to competence. The issue of competence for formulating environmental policy involves not simply a balance between Community and Member State institutions in formulating environmental policy, but between types of institutions – both policy-making (legislature/administration) and law-deciding (courts). To the extent that principles are imbued with both policy and legal prescriptions, the use of principles by the ECJ has the potential to erode the (assumed) demarcation between political and legal institutional roles and to implicate the Court in policy choices relating to environmental protection. This possibility is very real in light of the fourth common feature of the environmental principles that are implicated in the ECJ’s Article 28 reasoning: these principles are undefined. It is possible to identify general ideas underlying the principles, but defining them with precision is no easy task. Let us take, by way of examples, the integration principle and the principle of rectification at source. The integration principle in Article 6 provides that ‘environmental protection requirements’ must be integrated into all Community policies and activities. However it is far from clear what constitute ‘environmental protection requirements’, how they might be integrated and what Community ‘activities’ are covered.66 Some ECJ case law has indicated that the mandatory requirement of ‘environmental protection’ should be informed by the four principles in Article 174(2);67 the ‘environmental protection requirements’ of the integration principle would likely be similarly construed. This leads to the second example of the principle of rectification 66 In particular, it is not clear whether this covers the activities of the Community courts, or how such incorporation by the courts might take place. In so far as this paper examines how the ECJ has relied on the integration principle in its reasoning, judicial developments go some way to filling in these gaps. 67 Walloon Waste above; Case C-209/98 Sydhavnens Sten & Grus ApS [2000] ECR I-3743 [48]. 18 at source, which is closely related to the principles of proximity and self-sufficiency.68 The general idea underlying this principle is that environmental damage should be rectified by targeting its original cause, by requiring preventive action at source rather than at any other point on the continuum of activity that results in environmental harm. Several commentators have pointed out that blunt ‘across-the-board, undifferentiated’ applications of this principle might lead to the compromising of environmental objectives.69 Thus, in relation to waste management, requiring that all waste be disposed of or treated as close to its generation as possible might prevent waste from being treated at more efficient, ‘environmentally friendly’ facilities further afield, or lead to the drawing of arbitrary geographical boundaries to restrict ‘rectification’ to the ‘source’ of an environmental problem. Such a requirement would conflict with the preventive principle (that, broadly speaking, environmental damage should be prevented rather than cured),70 thereby undermining ‘environmental protection’ and demonstrating that the principles interact with each other and can operate in tension.71 Such arguments, more than anything, demonstrate and reinforce the contested nature of ‘environmental protection’; this contest lies at the heart of these definitional complications in relation to environmental principles. What constitutes ‘environmental protection’ is, 68 Notaro finds that these two principles are subsumed under the principle of rectification at source. The principle of proximity concerns resolving environmental problems closely or proximately to their place of generation (assuming this can be identified), while the principle of self-sufficiency requires particular areas to be ‘self-sufficient’ in managing and remedying their actions that compromise the environment. For a consideration of these principles in relation to waste, see JH Jans, 'The Status of the SelfSufficiency and Proximity Principles with regard to the Disposal and Recovery of Waste' (1999) 11 Journal of Environmental Law 121. 69 Heyvaert, 405-6. See also Notaro 477-8; G Van Calster, 'Court Criticises Restrictions on Free Movement of Waste' (1999) 24 (2) European Law Review 181, 183. 70 For the layers of meaning trapped in the ‘preventive principle’, see E Scotford, 'Trash or Treasure: Policy Tensions in EC Waste Regulation' (2007) 19 (3) Journal of Environmental Law 367. 71 Note that these tensions are recognised in the proximity and self-sufficiency principles that find legislative expression in Article 5 of the Waste Directive, above. In Article 5, these principles are tempered by limits as to ‘appropriateness’ and ‘cost’. At the same time a considerable ambiguity is introduced in Article 5(1), in its prescription that both Member States individually and the Community as a whole become self-sufficient in waste disposal. Which is it? 19 scientifically and politically, often very difficult to articulate.72 These general ‘environmental principles’ do not resolve the difficulties, and their application thus tends to be a ‘precarious exercise’.73 In this way, EC environmental principles can viewed as ‘multi-meaning normative statements’,74 representing a stage of political agreement (between Member States about Community environmental policy in the case of the Treaty principles, and between Community institutions in the case of secondary Community law that gives rise to environmental ‘principles’), whereby ‘agreement is reached in the form of words when there is no agreement on what the words mean’.75 In the result, the undefined nature of EC environmental principles leaves room for manipulation of the ambiguities that they embody, in particular as to their substantive policy nature and relating to the sharing of environmental competence between Community and Member State institutions. These considerations are particularly pertinent in considering how the ECJ employs the principles, since the Court’s use of them implicates (often implicitly), at the minimum, a consideration of these difficult issues and, at most, choices as to their resolution. This in turn raises questions about the role of the ECJ in deciding on the nature of Community and Member State environmental policy. III A DEEPER PICTURE OF THE ARTICLE 28 ENVIRONMENTAL CASE LAW From the ambiguities in the environmental principles identified in Part II, two stand out as particularly relevant in understanding the implications of their employment by the ECJ in the Article 28 environmental case law: their reflection of the shared competence for environmental 72 See J Dryzek, The Politics of the Earth (2nd edn, Oxford University Press, 2005). Heyvaert 405. 74 Maduro 18. 75 T Hartley, 'Five Forms of Uncertainty in European Community Law' (1996) 55 Cambridge Law Journal , 273. 73 20 policy at the Community level and the uncertainty of their substantive meaning. When the ECJ uses environmental principles to inform and support its reasoning in justifying national measures that infringe Article 28, it is enlivening these two issues. Thus, the Court’s reasoning exposes two principal questions at stake in the Article 28 environmental case law: (1) what is the nature of environmental protection?; (2) who should be responsible for deciding this (or where does the institutional balance of environment regulatory competence lie)? We now take a deeper look into the Article 28 environmental case law to see how these questions are implicated, revisiting the three main cases discussed in Part I. Balancing Regulatory Competence Maduro, in his extensive and insightful treatise on Article 28, suggests that this Treaty provision involves ‘an allocation of competences between the EU and Member States and a balance between different economic, social and cultural values’.76 In this way, the Court’s interpretation of Article 28 and its justifications allows it to determine the extent to which a Member State is competent to maintain its own regulation in particular social domains, measured against the Community standard that Article 28 imposes for the free movement of goods.77 However, the Court’s balancing of regulatory competence under Article 28 is not the only word on the balancing of environmental regulatory competence at the EC level. As seen above, the Community and Member States share competence for environmental policy, under the principle of subsidiarity and the provisions of Title XIX in the Treaty. Thus the decision that Article 28 cases force with respect to environmental regulatory competence is a complex one – it concerns a coordination of economic and environmental goals in a governance 76 77 Maduro 21. The ‘rule of competences’ approach to Article 28: ibid 167-8. 21 framework in which it is unclear (or to be decided) where the competence for setting those environmental goals lies. This complexity of balancing regulatory competence reflects one aspect of the ambiguity of ‘Community’ environmental principles, as noted in Part II: either they are confined in their operation either to Community institutions operating within their sphere of environmental policy competence, or they set a broader prescription for Community and Member State institutions in setting environmental policy. A closer look at the use of environmental principles in the cases demonstrates that the Court has made a choice in favour of the latter interpretation. Thus, in Walloon Waste, the awkwardness of the ECJ’s reasoning can be explained by the Court’s prioritising of Member State environmental policy that accords with the prescription in Article 174(2) that ‘Community’ policy on the environment shall be based on the principle of rectification at source. Thus, in this case, the principle of rectification at source is operating at two levels. Formally and particularly, it informs the test of discrimination applied to trigger the rule of reason justification.78 However, viewed differently, the principle informs the rule of reason more generally. It informs the ‘imperative requirement’ of environment protection since the principle of rectification at source is prescribed in Article 174(2) as founding Community environmental policy, and this motivates the resolution of the discrimination question. In this way, Community environmental policy particularises the Member State policy that may be adopted to derogate from the Article 28 free movement guarantee in the name of environmental protection, thus qualifying the scope of regulatory competence accorded to the Member State under Article 28. Viewed in this second light, the uncomfortable application of the discrimination test is explained – the issue of discrimination is simply not that important to the Court in its reasoning. What is important is supporting a 78 Cf Doherty, 60-62; S Weatherill, 'Publication Review: "Free Movement of Goods in the European Community" (Peter Oliver)' (2003) 28 (5) European Law Review 756, 758. 22 Member State measure that is consistent with the principle of rectification at source – a central plank of Community environmental protection policy. In a similar way, in PreussenElektra, the ECJ defers to a Community conception of environmental protection to approve the infringing German provision under review. The Court spends some time assessing whether the aim of the German renewable energy measure is compatible with Community environmental objectives.79 Climate change is an area where the Community and Member States have assumed joint responsibility, since both are signatories of the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change. The Court uses this fact to assume that Member State and Community policy in this area are aligned (which is not an unreasonable assumption), and cites a host of Community legislation on renewable energy promotion to approve the aim of the national measure under review. Thus the Court here assumes a role in approving the substance of national environmental policy that limits the discretion of the German governmental to set its own regulatory agenda with respect to climate change. The Court’s use of the integration principle to support its reasoning confirms that its main concern in reviewing the German measure is its alignment with Community environmental policy.80 It does this without any analysis of the nature of the shared competence for environmental policy, which is particularly acute with respect to an issue like climate change. The cases in which the ECJ spends time assessing proportionality involve similar assumptions and choices as to the scope of national environmental regulatory discretion. As seen in Part I in the discussion of Toolex, the Court again defers to the ‘Community’ version of environmental protection in reviewing the proportionality of the Swedish measure prohibiting use of TCE, through its reliance on the substitution principle. As in the above cases, the ECJ 79 80 PreussenElektra [73]–[78]. ibid [76]. 23 here implicitly decides where the balance of regulatory competence for articulating environmental policy lies, and finds that balance lies in favour of the Community. In other cases where proportionality is considered, but environmental principles are not, the Court makes similar decisions on regulatory balance. To the extent that it restricts its analysis to the ‘necessity’ of the measure under review (that it is least restrictive of intra-Community trade), it reserves a relatively broad margin of discretion to Member States to regulate in those areas of social policy identified in Article 30 or as mandatory requirements. However, if the Court investigates the first or third limbs of proportionality in any depth, it erodes the regulatory competence of Member States preserved by the Article 28 justifications, as seen in Danish Bottles. By appreciating the balancing of regulatory competence that goes on in these Article 28 environmental cases, the institutional implications of these decisions become apparent. The Court, by prioritising Community understandings of environmental policy, is making implied choices about the nature of the shared competence for environmental policy in the Community, effectively choosing that it is not all that ‘shared’.81 To the extent that Community and Member State views on environmental policy align, this is not hugely problematic; however to assume complete equivalence is to negate Member State regulatory autonomy in this sphere and to undermine the nature of ‘shared competence’. The justifications to Article 28 are intended to create a space in which national competence for social policy is preserved; in the Article 28 environmental cases, this space is eroded, particularly through the use of environmental principles. This fits with Maduro’s idea of majoritarianism, that the Court’s Article 28 reasoning is simply concerned with whether the regulations under review ‘correspond to the European majority policy on the issue under review’: Maduro 58. 81 24 The Nature of Environmental Protection In eroding the scope of national regulatory competence for environmental policy through the use of environmental principles in Article 28 cases, the ECJ implicates another complex issue that is latent in environmental principles: the nature of environmental protection. In order to find that the national provisions under review comply with a Community understanding of environmental protection (or the protection of the life and health of humans, animals and plants), the Court must have a view of the nature of that understanding substantively. It does not discuss this view in any explicit depth however, relying often on a superficial appreciation of environmental principles to identify what constitutes ‘environmental protection’. As seen in Part II, such a superficial approach overlooks the ambiguities of substance embodied in the principles. Take Walloon Waste as an example. In finding that the Belgian measure conformed to the principle of rectification at source and principles of proximity and self-sufficiency, the Court did not acknowledge the substantive complexities involved in those principles. In particular, the principle of rectification at source can compromise environmental protection if applied too strictly, and without acknowledging its symbiosis with the preventive principle; also, the principle of self-sufficiency might be applied at a local, regional, national or Community-wide level.82 There is an argument that it would have been preferable for the Court, in Walloon Waste, to have articulated that the principle of self-sufficiency applied at a Community-wide level, which would have condemned the Belgian regulation.83 Such ambiguities in environmental principles show that there are debates of substance to be had about the nature of environmental protection, and that they are not resolved by 82 83 Note the ambiguity in Article 5 of the Waste Directive. Notaro 477-8; Van Calster 182-3. 25 asserting that a particular environmental principle applies.84 In assuming control for assessing whether national measures, which infringe Article 28, conform to Community environmental policy, the Court involves itself in articulating the substantive nature of that policy. From this involvement, two issues flow: firstly, the extent to which the Court should openly articulate its reasoning on the nature of environmental protection; secondly, whether it should be involved in deciding such issues at all. On the first issue, it is no doubt helpful to call for the Court to be more explicit in its reasoning. On the second issue, however, a more difficult question about the role of the Court in the institutional balance of the Community is raised. It is one thing to say that there should be more debate on the nature of environmental protection; it is another to say that the ECJ is the appropriate forum for resolving that debate. That the Court finds itself in a position where it is making choices about the nature of environmental protection is the product of a number of pieces in the architecture of Community law: the existence of ‘multimeaning normative statements’ (ie environmental principles) to found Community environmental policy (the meaning of which statements needs to be decided by someone or some institution), the shared competence for environmental policy between the Community and Member States (the precise nature of which sharing needs to be decided by someone or some institution), and the nature of Article 28, which casts a broad net in its supervision of national social regulation and provides a site for these undecided issues to be resolved. A problem in the Article 28 case law is the limited scope for its articulated tests to grapple with these bigger questions. As Maduro states, the ‘specific legal logic [of free movement rules has extended much beyond its natural area] to new fields without contextualisation..., without being adapted to its new functions.’85 The aim of this paper has 84 A similar debate can be had about the nature of the substitution principle, which its invocation in Toolex provokes: see Heyvaert 406-7. 85 Maduro 23. 26 been to contextualise Article 28 in relation to Community environmental law, and to identify some of its functions in that context. As a result of this identification, we are left with difficult questions of institutional conflict to confront. Environmental protection is an important but elusive goal, and Article 28’s jurisprudence demonstrates that there is a deep institutional tension over the responsibility for its achievement – between the Community and Member States, and between the ECJ and the non-judicial institutions of the Community. Identifying these difficult questions helps to explain the exceptional nature of the Article 28 environmental cases, although it does not provide an easy answer for their (judicial) resolution. It may well be that this case law is bound to be unsatisfactory, in terms of legal certainty, while these bigger issues loom. CONCLUSION In the literature, the debates in this area of ‘environmental’ Article 28 jurisprudence are often put in terms of a trade-off between free trade and environmental protection when the outcomes of the ECJ’s environmental cases are under scrutiny, or in terms of legal certainty (with a view to there being ‘certain’ jurisprudence that protects the environment) when the reasoning adopted in these cases is analysed. Looking closely at these Article 28 cases shows that the terms of these debates are too superficial. The real debates are (1) what constitutes environmental protection, and (2) who, in the Community context, has the responsibility for determining how it should be achieved – Community or Member State institutions, courts or legislatures. These issues are at play in all environmental Article 28 cases, but the introduced role of principles provides a lever for their articulation. Until these issues are confronted and debated (academically, institutionally, judicially), the reasoning in environmental Article 28 cases will remain incomprehensible and the outcomes unpredictable. In addition, the role of the Court is called into question to the extent that is making unilateral choices about what 27 constitute environmentally protective measures, in a manner that disguises debate about how environmental protection is best achieved and who is competent (and/or best placed) to make such choices. 28