Running head: The seduction of easiness The seduction of easiness: How science depictions influence laypeople’s 5 reliance on their own evaluation of scientific information 1 Lisa Scharrera*, Rainer Brommea, M. Anne Brittb & Marc Stadtlera 10 a Department of Psychology, University of Muenster, Fliednerstrasse 21, 48149 Muenster, Germany, Email: lisa.scharrer@uni-muenster.de; bromme@uni-muenster.de; stadtlm@unimuenster.de b 15 Psychology Department, Northern Illinois University, 363 Psychology-Math Building, Dekalb, IL60115, USA, Email: britt@niu.edu * Corresponding author: Westfälische Wilhelms-University, Department of Psychology, Fliednerstrasse 21, 48149 Muenster, Germany. Email: lisa.scharrer@uni-muenster.de; Tel.: +49 251 8339379; Fax: +49 251 8339105 20 1 Part of this work has been published as a contribution to the 33rd annual meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 2011, Boston, USA. Acknowledgments This research was supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG), grant BR1126/6-1. 25 Abstract The present research investigated whether laypeople are inclined to rely on their own evaluations of the acceptability of scientific claims despite their knowledge limitations. 30 Specifically, we tested whether laypeople are more prone to discount their actual dependence on expert knowledge when they are presented with simplified science texts. In two experiments, participants read scientific arguments that varied in comprehensibility and type of argument support and therefore in apparent easiness. We assessed participants’ inclination to rely on their own evaluation rather than deferring to expert advice when judging argument 35 persuasiveness. The results showed that laypeople were more strongly persuaded by apparently easy arguments than by difficult ones. Furthermore, they were more confident in their own evaluation of the information and less inclined to turn to an expert for decisionmaking support after reading easy compared to difficult arguments. 40 Keywords: knowledge evaluation; expertise; argument comprehensibility; causal explanations; evidence 1. Introduction Laypeople frequently encounter situations where they must make decisions about science45 related issues. Whether making up one’s mind about undergoing a particular medical treatment or deciding whether certain behaviors are detrimental to the environment, laypeople must judge scientific claims and the arguments provided to support such claims. While the Internet has reduced problems of access to scientific information, a major challenge remains in the evaluation of this information, regarding its acceptability, usefulness and sufficiency 50 for solving a problem at hand (Blair & Johnson, 1987; Brand-Gruwel & Stadtler, 2011; Bromme, Kienhues & Porsch, 2010; Goldman, 2011; Kienhues, Stadtler & Bromme, 2011; Mason, Ariasi & Boldrin, 2011; Wiley et al., 2009). One reason why evaluation presents such a challenge lies in the specific nature of science knowledge. Advances in science and technology have led to enormous growth of scientific knowledge, accompanied by 55 specialization and differentiation. To manage this complexity, scientific knowledge is organized into different disciplines that are represented by specialized experts (Keil, Stein, Webb, Billings & Rozenblit, 2008), constituting a ‘division of cognitive labor’ (Keil et al., 2008, Putnam, 1975; Stehr, 1994). Due to such division of cognitive labor in modern societies, we remain laypeople throughout 60 our whole lifetime regarding most topics and domains of science. Laypeople generally lack the high level of background knowledge and specialized training required to come to a wellfounded decision about the veracity and thus the appropriate persuasiveness of scientific claims. This is what sets laypeople apart from ‘experts’, who are specifically trained and experienced in a domain, and from ‘novices’, who are not yet experts, but strive to become 65 experts through relevant training and will already have acquired basic domain knowledge and a certain discipline-based perspective (Bromme, Rambow & Nückles, 2001). Hence, when laypeople are in a situation which requires them to decide about a complex science-related issue, they are confronted with a paradox: On the one hand they need to come to a decision but on the other hand they lack the expert knowledge necessary for making well- 70 founded decisions. This problem has been discussed predominately in health and medical research focusing on patient decision-making. In this context, the ideal of ‘informed decisionmaking’ has been proposed, according to which individuals make their own judgment (for example about a certain treatment option) only if they have acquired sufficient knowledge and information about the issue at hand to do so (Bekker et al., 1999; Charles, Gafni & Whelan, 75 1997). Such information might be delivered by the expert (the doctor in charge) or the layperson might find it elsewhere, nowadays mostly on the Internet (Fox, 2005). Even if this ideal of ‘informed decision-making’ is realized, laypeople must judge if their understanding of the issue is sufficient, or if it is still necessary to defer to an expert. Judging which of these two strategies is the appropriate course of action logically requires that the individual can 80 correctly assess the sufficiency of their own knowledge for the decision task at hand. In other words, they have to successfully engage in metacognitive calibration by forming an accurate awareness of what they know and what they do not know (Glenberg & Epstein, 1985; Pieschl, 2009). Unfortunately, as Keil (Keil et al., 2010) and his group have shown, laypersons tend to 85 overestimate their understanding of complex science- and technology-based issues. If laypeople fail to recognize their own knowledge limitations they might falsely assume that their understanding of the gathered information related to a certain knowledge claim enables them to evaluate the persuasiveness of the claim. As a consequence, they might underestimate their actual need to defer to an expert to reach a truly informed decision. Conversely, only if 90 individuals feel they lack sufficient understanding of the matter should they refrain from relying on their own evaluations. Ascertaining the conditions under which laypeople become aware of their own epistemic limitations when they process science-based text information remains an open empirical question. In this investigation, we are interested in the characteristics of science texts that might affect the development of such awareness. 95 Judging scientific claims is no simple and straightforward act. Persuasiveness itself is a graded concept. Persuasiveness of arguments can be indicated by intensity of claim agreement and evaluation of argument strength, two measures that feature prominently in persuasion research (O’Keefe, 2002). Both can be expected to be closely related but are nevertheless not equivalent. While lay recipients may perceive the evaluation of argument 100 strength as a more abstract, comparably ‘safe’ task without any major consequences, expressing agreement with a claim must be approached more cautiously, since claim agreement might be regarded as closely connected to actual behavioral consequences. To summarize, laypeople’s reliance on their own evaluations should manifest itself in their inclination to be easily persuaded by provided information. In contrast, if recipients do not 105 feel competent to decide about information quality, they should be more hesitant in their judgments and refrain from indicating a strong opinion. Furthermore, an inclination to rely on their own evaluations should be reflected even more directly by laypersons’ confidence in their own decision about a claim. Strong confidence in a decision should manifest itself in high levels of trust in the own judgment and conversely in a weak desire to turn to an expert 110 for decision support. This pattern is consistent with the concept of informed decision-making (Bekker et al., 1999), which implies that only if recipients feel that they are sufficiently informed and competent to form an opinion about the subject matter should they let themselves be persuaded by a given argument. 115 1.1 Characteristics of science information It may be particularly difficult for laypeople to recognize that they should not rely on their own judgment when they encounter scientific information written in a way that makes the subject matter appear less complex and easier to evaluate than it actually is. Such is the case when laypeople read scientific information especially prepared for their consumption, i.e. 120 presented in a simplified way in order to make it superficially comprehensible for the lay public (Kajanne & Pirttilä-Backman, 1999; Wagner, Elejabarrieta & Lahnsteiner, 1995; Zimmerman, Bisanz, Bisanz, Klein & Klein, 2001). When laypeople encounter simplified texts, their sense of understanding may mislead them to consider the subject matter easy and uncomplicated and to judge their mental representations of the described phenomena as more 125 complete and accurate than they actually are (cf. Goldman & Bisanz, 2002). Such an impression may manifest itself in the conviction that their knowledge and skills do not differ meaningfully from that of an expert in the field. In this case, laypeople would fail to differentiate between the background knowledge required to comprehend presented information and the background knowledge required to evaluate the acceptability of the 130 information for justifying a given claim. Comprehending simplified information might thus lead laypeople to regard the described phenomena and mechanisms to be so transparent and self-evident that they themselves are able to evaluate the information (cf. Keehner & Fischer, 2011) and that deferring to an expert is an unnecessary waste of time and energy. Therefore, if presented with a simple account, laypeople should be inclined to rely on their own content 135 evaluation. If, however, the information is presented in a way that does not conceal the inherent difficulty of the subject matter, then laypeople should refrain from relying solely on their own judgement about information persuasiveness (cf. Reber & Schwarz, 1999; Schwartz, 2004). 140 1.2 Influences on perceived easiness of scientific contents The assumption, that easy information causes recipients to rely more strongly on their own evaluation of scientific claims, raises the question as to what characteristics make scientific information appear easy to laypeople. We presume that perceived easiness is influenced by at least two message characteristics: (1) comprehensibility of the depicted information and (2) 145 type of argument support which is presented to back a claim. Our assumption is based on theoretical considerations from previous literature and empirical findings which show both characteristics to have an impact on the persuasiveness of arguments (e.g. Brem & Rips, 2000; Eagly, 1974; Slusher & Anderson, 1996). 150 1.2.1 Information comprehensibility Previous findings have shown that people agree more strongly with claims presented as part of comprehensible arguments than with those that are difficult or impossible to comprehend (e.g. Bradley & Meeds, 2004; Murphy, Long, Hollerana & Esterly, 2003). However, research on this issue has mainly dealt with arguments supporting moral claims and arguments 155 advertising the usefulness of consumer products. Due to this focus on moral claims and advertisement, it remains unclear whether the observed comprehensibility effect also applies to scientific arguments. In fact, the question of whether it generalizes is not trivial. In the case of moral arguments or arguments intended to advertise everyday products, recipients may perceive their own values and personal experiences as a sufficient basis for argument 160 evaluation. However, in the case of scientific information laypeople might be aware that its evaluation is usually beyond their capabilities—regardless of whether they feel that they understand a piece of information. If this is the case, laypeople should not be inclined to agree more strongly with a scientific claim supported by comprehensible than by incomprehensible information. 165 Two studies did in fact investigate the persuasive effect of comprehensibility for scientific arguments. While Miller et al. (1976) detected no difference in persuasiveness between comprehensibility conditions, Eagly (1974) found incomprehensible arguments to cause weaker claim agreement than comprehensible arguments. However, neither study adequately answers the question of whether laypeople are more persuaded by arguments they perceive as 170 easy. In Miller et al.’s (1976) study, it remains unclear whether the manipulation of comprehensibility was indeed successful, as no manipulation check was conducted. Furthermore, Eagly’s (1974) study investigated a situation of expert–novice communication rather than of expert–layperson communication. Participants (psychology students) were required to evaluate contents from their own field of study and, due to their prior training, 175 may have perceived themselves as principally able to evaluate the given message. In sum, previous findings on moral issues and advertisement support the notion that comprehensibility has an influence on argument persuasiveness. However, it is not clear whether comprehensibility also affects the persuasiveness of scientific arguments and whether any persuasiveness effects of comprehensibility extend to laypeople’s confidence in their own 180 judgments of the provided information. 1.2.2 Type of argument support Previous research has differentiated between two types of argument support that can back a causal claim: causal support and empirical support. Causal support explains the mechanism 185 underlying the claimed causal connection (e.g. ‘Beta blockers decrease high blood pressure, because they inhibit the activity of hormones which cause blood pressure-raising stress reactions in the body.’). In contrast, empirical support backs the claim by referring to relevant statistical data (e.g. ‘Beta blockers decrease high blood pressure, because blood pressure was decreased by 20-28% among patients who regularly took beta blockers.’) (for comparable 190 distinctions see Brem & Rips, 2000; Koslowski, 1996; Sandoval & Cam, 2011; Slusher & Anderson, 1996). In other words, whereas causal support answers the question ‘Why are two concepts causally related?’, empirical support answers the question ‘How do we know that two concepts are related?’ (Glassner, Weinstock & Neuman, 2005). Kuhn (1991) considers only evidence (i.e. empirical support) as ‘genuine evidence’ while discounting explanations 195 (i.e. causal support) which are not complemented by additional data as ‘pseudoevidence’. According to Kuhn, explanations serve to establish the plausibility of a claim, which is neither necessary nor sufficient to supporting its believability. Rather, it is only evidence that provides direct support for the correctness of a causal claim. This notion is also prevalent in the empirical sciences, where the most highly regarded justification for claims is empirical 200 evidence. However, despite the prominent role that evidence plays in empirical science, previous literature regards explanations as a particularly persuasive form of argument support (Gopnik, 2000; Lombrozo, 2006; Trout, 2002) and suggests that laypeople prefer causal support as claim justifications, possibly because its evaluation is perceived as easier. According to Keil 205 (2006, 2010), individuals have a sophisticated sense for causal relations and structure and seek out explanations. These activities form the essence of individuals’ folk science. Thus, laypeople may consider causal support as easier to evaluate than empirical support, since causal support more closely reflects the kinds of claim justifications they consider in everyday life. This assumption is also in line with Brem and Rips’ (2000) reasoning that explanations 210 provide a method for vetting claims by allowing individuals to judge the described mechanisms for internal coherence and consistency with prior knowledge. Due to allowing this kind of vetting, laypeople may perceive explanations as adequate subjects for their own evaluation. Laypeople should therefore be more easily and confidently persuaded by arguments containing causal support than by arguments containing empirical support. 215 The persuasive effect of causal support compared to empirical support has been investigated in several studies. However, while findings by Slusher and Anderson (1996) indeed confirm that arguments containing causal support cause greater claim agreement than arguments containing empirical support, Brem and Rips (2000) conversely found recipients to prefer evidence over explanations. Similarly, in a study by Sandoval and Cam (2011), 8 to 10 year 220 old children were shown to slightly prefer empirical over causal support. Overall, findings on the persuasive impact of scientific causal and empirical support indicate that there is indeed a difference in persuasiveness between the two support types. Although theoretical considerations suggest a persuasive advantage of causal over empirical support from a layperson’s point of view, results are mixed as to the direction of the persuasive difference. A 225 possible explanation for the inconsistency of findings is that type of argument support and comprehensibility might have been confounded in at least some studies. In cases where empirical support had been more comprehensible than its causal counterpart, the perceived easiness of comprehensible support might have outweighed the easiness ascribed to causal support. Moreover, and similar to the state of affairs regarding comprehensibility, the effect of 230 support type on recipients’ confidence in their decision about information persuasiveness has not been investigated directly. Thus there is a need to assess whether and how support type influences laypeople’s readiness to rely on their own evaluations. 1.3 The present research 235 In two experiments we investigated how features of science depictions influence lay recipients’ inclination to rely on their own evaluations of scientific information. Therefore, we investigated how scientific argumentative texts with different levels of comprehensibility and argument support influence argument persuasiveness and laypeople’s confidence of their claim agreement decision. 240 We expect that if scientific information is presented in a way that makes it difficult for laypeople to process, they will be more likely to realize that as non-experts they are in fact unable to decide whether the information poses a sound argument to support a given claim. Specifically, we hypothesized that recipients would be more intensely persuaded by comprehensible than incomprehensible arguments. Therefore, reading comprehensible 245 arguments should lead to greater agreement with the claim than reading incomprehensible arguments (hypothesis 1a) and laypeople should evaluate comprehensible arguments as stronger (i.e. more supportive of the claim) than incomprehensible arguments (hypothesis 1b). Analogously, based on the assumption that causal support is perceived as easier by laypeople, arguments containing causal support should be more persuasive than arguments containing 250 empirical support. Therefore, we expect that reading causal support will lead to stronger claim agreement than empirical support (hypothesis 2a) and moreover, that laypeople will evaluate arguments containing causal support as stronger than those containing empirical support (hypothesis 2b). We also expect that laypeople would be more confident in their own decision about the 255 acceptability of provided scientific information when information processing is easy than when it is difficult. Therefore, comprehensible arguments should cause laypeople to have greater trust in their own decision about the claim (hypothesis 3a) and conversely a weaker desire to consult an expert for further decision-making support than they would have with incomprehensible arguments (hypothesis 3b). Similarly, receiving arguments with causal 260 support should lead lay recipients to trust more strongly in their own decision about the claim (hypothesis 4a) and to have a weaker desire to consult an expert than when they receive arguments with empirical support (hypothesis 4b). 2. 265 Experiment I To investigate our hypotheses, we conducted a first experiment in which participants read texts about scientific topics which provided support for a claim. The extent to which laypeople were persuaded by the provided information and their confidence in the claim agreement decision were assessed. 270 2.1 Method 2.1.1 Design and Participants The experiment was conducted with a 2x2 repeated measures design, the independent variables being argument comprehensibility (comprehensible vs. incomprehensible) and type of argument support (causal vs. empirical). Each participant was assigned to all four 275 experimental conditions. In each condition, participants were asked to read an argument about a medical topic. Thus, every recipient read four arguments in total: one comprehensible argument containing causal support, one comprehensible argument containing empirical support, one incomprehensible argument containing causal support and one incomprehensible argument containing empirical support. The order of exposure to experimental conditions was 280 counterbalanced among participants by using a Latin square design. Hence, across the sample, arguments from each condition were equally often presented in each position. Eighty-eight undergraduates (52 female, 36 male, mean age = 25.66 years, SD = 5.13) of various majors at a German university took part in the study and received 8 Euros for their participation. Thus, the sample consisted of adult participants who had undergone at least 285 some academic training and who should therefore have developed a generally sophisticated understanding of the nature of knowledge, making them principally able to appropriately handle scientific knowledge questions (e.g. King & Kitchener, 1994). To ensure participants’ lay status, students of medicine, biology or related subjects and students of empirical sciences (including psychology), who can be assumed to be particularly familiar with empirical 290 argument support, were excluded from participation. 2.1.2 Materials Expository texts about four medical issues were created (mean text length = 80.5 words, SD = 16.46). The texts contained concepts and relations that were derived from real-world concepts 295 but were by themselves imaginary. The use of imaginary contents was aimed to keep readers’ prior knowledge as low as possible. Furthermore, it should reduce the likelihood that participants had already formed a strong prior attitude about the specific issues, as prior attitude has been shown to have an influence on individuals’ agreement with an argument (Erb, Bohner, Rank & Einwiller, 2002). All texts were written by the first author of this paper, 300 with the help of authentic online texts of different types and from various sources that dealt with related medical issues, for example texts from scientific journals such as European Journal of Lipid Science and Technology, popularized science texts intended for lay audiences such as information from www.netdoctor.de (a German website offering information on various health topics), and websites offering a mixture of simplified contents 305 and more specialized in-depth information such as Wikipedia. Each text consisted of an argument that supported an issue-related causal claim (claim 1:’The intake of Eratomin leads to a decrease of the blood cholesterol level.’, claim 2: ‘The BurkittVirus causes the development of the Devic Syndrome in the body.’, claim 3: ‘A side-effect of Rethoxat is that it brings about asthma attacks.’, claim 4: ‘The intake of Lisinorase helps 310 against high blood pressure.’). The claim was always stated at the beginning of the argument, followed by information that acted as claim support. For every text, four variations were created, analogous to the experimental conditions: In the causal support conditions, the claim was supported by an explanation of the underlying mechanism and in the empirical support conditions by statistical data. For example, presented below is the English translation of the 315 following four argument versions that support the claim ‘The intake of Eratomin leads to a decrease of the blood cholesterol level’: (1) Comprehensible argument containing causal support: ‘The intake of Eratomin leads to a decrease of the blood cholesterol level. 320 This is because the body is provided with cholesterol through absorbing it from food. During the absorption process in the small intestine, specialized proteins split fats that are contained in the food into cholesterol. Eratomin binds these proteins and by this means, the proteins lose their ability to split fat molecules. As consequentially the amount of cholesterol that is absorbed from food is decreased, the amount of cholesterol in the body 325 is lowered.’ (2) Incomprehensible argument containing causal support: ‘The intake of Eratomin leads to a decrease of the blood cholesterol level. This is because cholesterol absorption in the intestinum tenue is controlled by PKA330 regulated lipases. In this process, triacylglycerol from food is split into mono- and diglycerid as well as cholesterol. Eratomin acts as ligand of carboxylesterase and thus as competitive inhibitor, because the carboxylesterase-ligand-complex has no hydrolytic effect. This leads to a reduction of the cholesterol absorption rate and consequentially to a decrease of the amount of high- and low-density lipoprotein in the sanguis.’ 335 (3) Comprehensible argument containing empirical support: ‘The intake of Eratomin leads to a decrease of the blood cholesterol level. This is because studies have shown that after a daily intake of 30mg Eratomin over a period of six months, blood cholesterol levels are decreased by 20-28%. In contrast, 340 among a comparison group of patients who in the same period of time did not take Eratomin, there was no lowering of cholesterol levels. This was attested by measurements of the amount of cholesterol in the blood of both patient groups at the beginning and at the end of the six months period. For this purpose, cholesterol particles were chemically separated from the other component parts of the blood. The amount of cholesterol in the 345 blood could by this means be determined at both times of measurement.’ (4) Incomprehensible argument containing empirical support: ‘The intake of Eratomin leads to a decrease of the blood cholesterol level. This is because studies among patients have shown a reduction of the amount of large350 bouyant and intermediate-dense as well as triglyceride-rich lipoproteins in the haima after daily application of 30mg Eratomin over a period of six months by 20-28%. In a verum free group there was c.p. no decrescence. This resulted from pre and post interventionally applied capillary electrophoresis on all patients’ sanguis during which the sample injection of CE (48 nl) was executed hydrodynamically.’ 355 Comprehensibility of both argument support types was manipulated in three ways. First, incomprehensible arguments contained unexplained technical terms, whereas in the comprehensible condition these terms were translated into more familiar words (Nagy, 1988) (e.g. ‘lipase’ in the incomprehensible condition was replaced by ‘specialized proteins’ in the 360 comprehensible condition). Second, incomprehensible support comprised unnecessary, distracting details, which were not required to support the argument claim (Trabasso, Secco & van den Broek, 1984) (e.g. the fact that lipase is PKA-regulated). Third, in comprehensible argument support, important information was repeated. According to Tyler (1994), repetition contributes to discourse comprehensibility by signaling recipients how to incorporate new 365 information into the progressing discourse, thus facilitating perceptions of text coherence (e.g. ‘This is because the body is provided with cholesterol through absorbing it from food. During the absorption process [...]’; NB repeated information was not underlined in the original material). However, comprehensibility manipulations were only applied to the argument support while the claim was stated in the same wording in all conditions. 370 Participants were provided with one argument from each experimental condition, whereby each argument addressed a different medical topic. Before reading each argument, participants were presented a framing story to provide a context for reading (Stadtler & Bromme, 2008). In this framing story, the participant was asked to imagine that a good friend who had a particular medical problem was unsure whether a certain problem-related claim 375 was true or false and asked the participant about their opinion. After reading the framing scenario, participants were asked to imagine that they had researched the Internet for information to find an answer to the friend’s question. Participants were then presented with an argument text which dealt with the medical topic described in the scenario, and which they had allegedly found during their search. 380 In each experimental condition, participants were presented with a separate framing scenario, fitting to the respective medical topic of the argument. In order to keep the social role ascribed to the online source from which the argument stemmed constant between conditions, each argument was described as being authored by a medical expert but without providing a name or any further information about the author. No indication was given to participants that the 385 texts they read in the different conditions were authored by the same source. Rather, participants should have been deterred from assuming the same author behind every text, since they were required to imagine themselves in completely different scenarios in every condition. 390 2.1.3 Dependent measures Manipulation check. To assess whether comprehensibility had been manipulated as intended between the argument versions, participants evaluated each argument for perceived comprehensibility on a scale from 1 (‘very incomprehensible’) to 7 (‘very comprehensible’). Since comprehensibility might be interpreted differently by different readers (Wiley, Griffin 395 & Thiede, 2005), participants were provided with a short definition of what the experimenters meant by comprehensibility to ensure that each participant judged the arguments by comparable standards. This definition was formulated as follows, by drawing on components of Jucks’ (2001) questionnaire to assess laypeople’s perspective on text comprehensibility (translated from German): ‘By comprehensible we mean that you perceive the text as vivid, 400 that you feel you can distinguish essential from rather unimportant information, that you think you can judge whether the single statements are consistent and not in conflict with one another, and that you feel you can clearly and comprehensively understand and connect the single statements made by the author.’ 405 Argument persuasiveness. The extent to which participants were persuaded by the information contained in the argument texts was measured by two variables: (1) Claim agreement. Participants’ agreement with each claim was assessed prior and subsequent to reading the claim-supporting argument. Participants were asked to indicate their agreement on a 1 (‘I don’t agree at all’) to 7 (‘I totally agree’) scale; the scale did not 410 comprise a separate ‘I don’t know’ option. The pre-measure of claim agreement was administered to ensure that laypeople’s prior opinion about the claims did not coincidentally differ between experimental conditions. (2) Argument strength. Participants were asked to evaluate the strength of each argument on a 1 to 7 scale, where 1 meant ‘the argument provides no support for the claim’ and 7 meant ‘the 415 argument provides strong support for the claim’. Confidence in the claim agreement decision. Participants’ confidence in their own capability to make a claim agreement decision was indicated by two measures: (1) Trust in one’s own judgment of the claim correctness. After reading each argument, 420 participants indicated on a 1 to 7 scale how strongly they agreed with the statement ‘I am confident in my own decision about whether it is true that [claim statement inserted]’ (1: ‘don’t agree’, 7: ‘strongly agree’). (2) Desire to consult an expert for additional decision support. After reading the argument , participants were asked how strongly they agreed with the statement ‘Before I decide about 425 whether it is true that [claim statement inserted], I would like to seek further advice from an expert’ on a 1 to 7 scale (1: ‘don’t agree’, 7: ‘strongly agree’). 2.1.4 Procedure Data collection took place in group sessions with a maximum of eight participants who 430 worked individually on a booklet containing the arguments and scales for collecting the dependent measures. The booklet first presented participants with a scenario in which the fictitious friend’s problem was described and therefore the frame story for the participants’ task to read the argument. The pre-measure of participants’ claim agreement was collected and then participants read the argument, which they had allegedly found while doing Internet 435 research to find information regarding their friend’s problem. Afterwards, they provided their post-measure of claim agreement as well as their trust in their own judgment and desire to consult an expert. This was repeated four times, so that each participant read four arguments, one of each experimental condition. After the described measures were collected for all four arguments, readers were presented again with each argument and were asked to evaluate its 440 strength and comprehensibility. Participants then completed a demographic questionnaire and were finally debriefed about the fictitious nature of the presented arguments. On average, the session lasted about 45 minutes. 2.2 Results 445 Means and standard deviations of the dependent measures as a function of comprehensibility and argument support type are shown in Table 1; in the text we will additionally refer to pooled data (estimated marginal means and standard errors) that was used for statistical analyses. To determine the statistical power achieved when analyzing the data with repeated measures F-Tests, a post hoc power analyses using G*Power (Faul, Erdfelder, Lang & 450 Buchner, 2007) was conducted. The analysis with alpha error probability set at .05 and correlations between levels of the repeated measures factors set at zero showed that the design and sample size of the experiment yielded a power of .91 for detecting medium sized effects (f = .25 according to Cohen, 1988). 455 --- Insert Table 1 about here --- 2.2.1 Test for order effects First, we tested whether order of argument presentation had any effects on the dependent measures. By this means we intended to rule out the possibility that the reading of earlier 460 presented arguments supported readers’ understanding of later presented arguments due to their structural similarity, which might have interfered with our manipulation of argument comprehensibility. For this purpose, we conducted repeated measures ANOVAs with argument order (position 1 to 4) as within-participant-factor on scores of comprehensibility, argument strength, pre- and post-measures of claim agreement, trust in own agreement 465 decision and desire to consult an expert. The results revealed no significant effects of argument order on any of the dependent variables (all F < 1.96, ns). 2.2.2 Manipulation check: Perceived argument comprehensibility A repeated measures ANOVA on comprehensibility ratings with the within-participant470 factors comprehensibility (comprehensible vs. incomprehensible) and type of argument support (causal vs. empirical) yielded a significant main effect of argument comprehensibility, F(1,87) = 744.053, p < .001, part. η2 = .895. An inspection of group means revealed that as intended, arguments designed as comprehensible were considered as more comprehensible (estimated marginal means (EMM) = 6.102, SE = .097) than arguments 475 designed to be incomprehensible (EMM = 2.028, SE = .112). Neither the main effect of support type nor the support type*comprehensibility interaction was significant (both F(1,87) < 1.9, ns). Thus, the manipulation check confirmed comprehensibility to vary orthogonally to type of argument support. 480 2.2.3. Argument persuasiveness We had expected laypeople to be more intensely persuaded after they had read comprehensible compared to incomprehensible arguments and after they had read causal argument support compared to empirical support. This should be indicated by greater claim agreement (hypothesis 1a) and higher ratings of argument strength (hypothesis 1b). Moreover, 485 we had hypothesized that causal argument support leads to greater claim agreement (hypothesis 2a) and higher ratings of argument strength (hypothesis 2b) compared to empirical support. (1) Claim agreement. Our hypotheses with regards to participants’ claim agreement were tested by subjecting pre-and post-measures of claim agreement to a repeated measures 490 ANOVA. Comprehensibility, argument support type and time of measurement (prior vs. subsequent to reading the argument) acted as within-participant-factors. Results showed a significant main effect of time of measurement, F(1,87) = 119.048, p < .001, part. η2 = .578, which was due to participants agreeing more to the claim after (EMM = 4.969, SE = .092) than prior to reading the argument (EMM = 3.989, SE = .075). With regards to the influence 495 of comprehensibility on claim agreement, no significant main effect of comprehensibility was found, F(1,87) = 1.338, ns, but a significant comprehensibility*time of measurement interaction, F(1,87) = 7.482, p < .01, part. η2 = .079. As a follow-up, separate repeated measures ANOVAs on the pre- and post-measures of claim agreement were conducted. Results showed that whereas claim agreement did not differ between comprehensibility conditions prior to 500 argument reception, F(1,87) =.269, ns, there was a significant difference between comprehensible and incomprehensible arguments after participants had read the argument, F(1,87) = 5.659, p < .05, part. η2 = .061. In line with our expectations (hypothesis 1a), group means revealed that agreement with the claim was higher after reading comprehensible (EMM = 5.08, SE = .101) compared to incomprehensible arguments (EMM = 4.858, SE = 505 .105). In contrast to our expectations regarding the influence of support type (hypotheses 2a), we found neither a significant main effect of support type, nor a significant interaction of support type and time of measurement, both F(1, 87) < 2.625, ns. The three-way interaction of comprehensibility, support type and time of measurement was also not significant, F(1, 87) = .795, ns. 510 (2) Perceived argument strength. To test our hypotheses regarding argument strength, we conducted a repeated measures ANOVA on argument strength ratings with comprehensibility and support type as within-participant-factors. Results revealed a significant main effect of comprehensibility, F(1,87) = 11.41, p < .001, part. η2 = .562. Descriptive statistics showed that as expected (hypothesis 1b), lay recipients judged comprehensible arguments as stronger 515 (EMM = 5.506, SE = .107) than incomprehensible arguments (EMM = 3.733, SE = .147). Furthermore, we found a main effect of support type, F(1,87) = 13.067, p < .001, part. η2 = .131, which confirmed hypothesis 2b: Arguments containing causal support were rated as stronger (EMM = 4.892, SE = .125) than arguments containing empirical support (EMM = 4.347, SE = .121). The interaction of comprehensibility and support type did not reach 520 significance, F(1,87) = 1.232, ns. 2.2.4 Confidence in the claim agreement decision We had furthermore hypothesized laypeople to be more confident in their own decision about the claim after they had read comprehensible compared to incomprehensible arguments, 525 indicated by a higher trust in their own decision (hypothesis 3a) and a weaker desire to consult an expert (hypothesis 3b). In addition, we expected causal argument support to lead to higher levels of trust in one’s own decision (hypothesis 4a) and to a weaker desire to consult an expert (hypothesis 4b) compared to empirical support. Pearson’s correlation of both confidence measures showed that trust in the own agreement 530 decision and desire to consult an expert were negatively associated in all experimental conditions (comprehensible causal: r = -.529, incomprehensible causal: r = -.406, comprehensible empirical: r = -.418 and incomprehensible empirical: r = -.421; all correlations were significant at a .01 level). (1) Trust in own agreement decision. To test our hypotheses about the influence of 535 comprehensibility and support type, we conducted a repeated measures ANOVA on trust scores with comprehensibility and support type as within-participant-factors. As to the influence of argument comprehensibility on trust scores, we found that after argument reception, trust was higher in the comprehensible (EMM = 4.125, SE = .162) than in the incomprehensible conditions (EMM = 3.483, SE = .177), F(1,87) = 19.424, p < .001, part. 540 η2 = .183, which supports hypothesis 3a. With regards to the influence of support type on trust in own decision, no significant main effect of support type was yielded, F(1,87) < 1.682, ns, which is in contrast to our expectations (hypothesis 4a). Finally, the interaction of comprehensibility, and support type was not significant, F(1, 87) = .127, ns. (2) Desire to consult an expert. Our hypotheses regarding the desire to consult an expert were 545 tested by conducting a repeated measures ANOVA on desire ratings with comprehensibility and support type as within-participant-factors. Concerning our expectations for argument comprehensibility, results showed that, in line with hypothesis 3b, desire to seek out expert advice was significantly higher after reading incomprehensible (EMM = 6.205, SE = .116) than comprehensible arguments (EMM = 5.858, SE = .141), F(1, 87) = 7.527, p < .01, part. η2 = 550 .080. However, results revealed no significant differences in desire scores between both support types, F(1,87) < 3.379, ns. Hypothesis 4b was therefore not confirmed. Finally, no significant interaction of comprehensibility and support type was found, F(1, 87) = .841, ns. 2.3 Discussion 555 The results obtained in Experiment I show that comprehensibility of scientific texts clearly influences laypeople’s reliance on their own evaluations of scientific claims. In line with hypotheses 1a/b, participants were more intensely persuaded by comprehensible than incomprehensible arguments, which was indicated by a greater inclination to agree with the argument claim and higher ratings of perceived argument strength. Moreover, as we had 560 expected, laypeople were more confident in their agreement decision after reading comprehensible arguments. In this case, they showed higher levels of trust in their own decision about the claim and conversely perceived themselves less in need of additional expert advice than after reading incomprehensible arguments, thus supporting hypotheses 3a/b. 565 Results obtained for type of argument support partly differ from the pattern observed for comprehensibility. Although in line with hypothesis 2a lay recipients evaluated arguments containing causal and empirical support differently regarding argument strength, with arguments containing causal support being slightly preferred, this did not translate to their actual agreement with the claim or to their confidence in their claim agreement decision. 570 Hypotheses 2b and 4a/b were therefore not supported. A possible explanation for type of argument support yielding only a small effect on evaluation of argument strength and no effect at all on claim agreement and confidence in the agreement decision might be that our participants had difficulties recognizing the difference between both support types and thus did not perceive one type as easier to evaluate than the other. 575 Previous research indicates that laypeople frequently fail to distinguish between explanations and evidence (Kuhn, 1991 but see also Brem & Rips, 2000). It therefore remains unclear whether the observed limited influence of support type is due to laypeople perceiving causal and empirical support as equally easy to judge or due to laypeople’s failure to recognize the difference between causal and empirical support. 580 It is important to note that the participants in Experiment I may have already had some experience in science. On average they were in their 7th semester (M = 7.71, SD = 4.91), corresponding to the later phase of undergraduate studies, and might have been more familiar with scientific research methods and empirical evidence than the ‘average layperson’. Consequently, participants may have had greater awareness of the controversial and tentative 585 nature of scientific findings and attributed a greater value to empirical argument support than laypersons would who had less or no science exposure. This might have made them generally resistant to strongly and confidently agreeing with a claim based on only one argument, regardless of support type and comprehensibility, and this may have reduced variability of responses between conditions (across conditions, the increase in claim agreement after 590 compared to before reading an argument was below one scale point on average, from M = 3.988 in the pre measure to M = 4.968 in the post measure, as was the decrease in participants’ desire to ask an expert, from M = 6.63 in the pre measure to M = 6.033 in the post measure). It remains an open question whether the detected effects might be more pronounced in a less experienced population. Finally, only medical topics were used as 595 argument contents. Thus we cannot conclude with certainty whether the yielded results only apply to medical arguments or can be generalized to other scientific domains as well. 3. Experiment II We conducted a second experiment which was aimed at replicating the findings of 600 Experiment I, and extended them in three respects. First, in order to clarify whether our participants are in fact able to recognize causal and empirical support as different support types, we asked readers to categorize the arguments accordingly. Second, we sought to investigate whether the effects yielded in Experiment I might be more pronounced in a population that is scientifically less experienced than the students included in the first sample. 605 Finally, to extend the applicability of our findings beyond a medical context, we included arguments from a second scientific field, climate research, in our set of materials. 3.1 Method 3.1.1 Design and Participants 610 The same 2x2 repeated measures design was used as in Experiment I, and again all participants were presented with all four experimental conditions. Each participant read two medical arguments and two arguments related to the topic of climate-change. The order of exposure to experimental conditions was counterbalanced between participants by using a Latin square design. Furthermore, the allocation of arguments to experimental conditions was 615 balanced so that across participants every condition was represented equally often by arguments of the medical and climate domain. Eighty-eight undergraduate students (66 female, 22 male, mean age = 21.36 years, SD = 2.84) participated and received 8 Euros to compensate for their time. Forty participants were firstyear students with various majors at a German university who had begun their studies no 620 longer than one to two months prior to the experiment. The remaining 48 participants were students of varying subjects at a University of Applied Sciences, an educational institution whose curricula focus primarily on practical education for a profession and less on preparation for research. By including university students who had only just begun their studies as well as students from an educational institution which is less research-focused than 625 general universities, participants should represent a population that is scientifically less experienced than participants in Experiment I. 3.1.2 Materials Similar to Experiment I, the materials were written arguments about four imaginary scientific 630 issues (mean text length = 95.88 words, SD = 23.22). Two arguments supported a causal claim on a medical topic (claim 1: ‘The intake of Periphenol leads to a decrease of the blood cholesterol level.’, claim 2: ‘The formation of kidney stones is caused by an overfunction of the adrenal medulla.’), and two arguments supported a causal claim on a topic related to climate-change (claim 3: ‘High amounts of Aeropine in the environment contribute to the 635 causation of thunderstorms.’, claim 4: ‘The utilization of Soymethanol as fuel contributes to global warming.’). As in Experiment I, four versions of each argument were created, varying in comprehensibility and support type. Again, all texts were written by the first author of this paper based on different types of online texts from various sources that dealt with related medical and climate issues. 640 Participants were provided with four arguments, one of each experimental condition, and every argument addressed a different medical or climate-related issue. Each argument text was again embedded in a framing story. The framing scenarios of climate arguments described a friend wondering about the environmental friendliness of certain behaviors (e.g. whether or not using fuel that contains Soymethanol contributes to global warming). After 645 reading the framing scenario, participants were presented with the argument which was allegedly found by the participant while doing Internet research to find an answer to the friend’s problem. As in Experiment I, the texts were described as being written by an expert without providing any further information about the author. Again, participants were given no indication that the arguments they read in the different experimental conditions originated 650 from the same source. 3.1.3 Dependent measures The same measures were collected as in Experiment I. Additionally, participants were asked to judge whether the argument contained (1) causal or (2) empirical support or whether (3) 655 they could not decide between both options. Arguments containing causal support were defined as describing ‘the processes and mechanisms that lead to the phenomenon mentioned in the claim’. Arguments containing empirical support were defined as presenting ‘measurement data which were obtained through scientific studies and which show that the phenomenon mentioned in the claim occurs.’ 660 3.1.4 Procedure The procedure followed that of Experiment I, with the addition that, at the end of the procedure, participants categorized each text they had read for the type of argument support it comprised. The session lasted about 45 minutes on average. 665 3.2 Results Means and standard deviations of the dependent measures as a function of comprehensibility and argument support type are presented in Table 2. To assess the statistical power of our data analysis, a post hoc power analyses using G*Power (Faul et al., 2007) was conducted with an 670 alpha error probability of .05 and correlations between levels of the repeated measures factors set at zero. Results showed that the design and sample size yielded a power of .91 for detecting medium sized effects (f = .25 according to Cohen, 1988) when calculating repeated measures F-tests. --- Insert Table 2 about here --- 675 3.2.1 Test for order effects To check for possible effects of argument presentation on the dependent measures, we conducted repeated measures ANOVAs with argument order (position 1 to 4) as withinparticipant-factor on scores of comprehensibility, argument strength, pre- and post-measures 680 of claim agreement, trust in own agreement decision and desire to consult an expert. Analogous to Experiment I, results showed no significant effects of argument order on the dependent variables (all F < 2.18, ns). 3.2.2 Manipulation check: Perceived argument comprehensibility 685 A repeated measures ANOVA on comprehensibility ratings with the two within-participantfactors comprehensibility (comprehensible vs. incomprehensible) and type of argument support (causal vs. empirical) revealed a significant main effect of argument comprehensibility, F(1,87) = 511.888, p < .001, part. η2 = .855. Group means indicate that arguments intended to be comprehensible were considered as more comprehensible (EMM = 690 5.71, SE = .105) than arguments written to be incomprehensible (EMM = 2.108, SE = .123). There was neither a significant main effect of support type, F(1,87) = 1.465, ns, nor a significant support type*comprehensibility interaction, F(1,87) = 1.517, ns, which confirmed comprehensibility to vary orthogonally to support type. 695 3.2.3 Judgment of argument support type Regarding the categorization of arguments as containing causal or empirical support, participants performed well above chance level in all four conditions. Comprehensible arguments containing causal support were correctly classified in 92.05% of the cases, incomprehensible arguments containing causal support in 73.86% of the cases, 700 comprehensible arguments containing empirical support in 76.14% of the cases and incomprehensible arguments containing empirical support in 72.72% of the cases. In the comprehensible causal and incomprehensible empirical conditions, most errors were due to readers picking the ‘undecided’ option (comprehensible causal: 4.5%, incomprehensible empirical: 15.9%). In contrast, in both other conditions, the majority of errors were due to 705 participants misclassifying the support as the wrong type (incomprehensible empirical: 18.2%, comprehensible causal: 19.3%). 3.2.4 Argument persuasiveness We had expected that laypeople would be more persuaded after reading comprehensible than 710 incomprehensible information, reflected by greater claim agreement (hypothesis 1a) and higher ratings of argument strength (hypothesis 1b). Similarly, we expected that after reading an argument containing causal support, laypeople would agree more with the claim (hypothesis 2a) and rate the arguments as stronger (hypothesis 2b) than after reading an argument containing empirical support. 715 (1) Claim agreement. Our hypotheses regarding participants’ claim agreement were tested using a repeated measures ANOVA on pre-and post-measures of participants’ claim agreement. Comprehensibility, support type and time of measurement (prior vs. subsequent to argument reception) acted as within-participant factors. A significant main effect of time of measurement was found, F(1,87) = 76.673, p < .001, part. η2 = .468, due to participants 720 agreeing more to the claim after having read the argument (EMM = 5.026, SE = .114) than before reading (EMM = 4.116, SE = .088). The analysis yielded no significant main effect of comprehensibility, F(1, 87) = .758, ns, but a significant comprehensibility*time of measurement interaction, F(1,87) = 14.926, p < .001, part. η2 = .146. Whereas claim agreement did not differ between comprehensibility conditions prior to argument reception, F(1,87) = 2.222, ns, there 725 was a significant difference between comprehensible and incomprehensible arguments after participants had read the argument, F(1,87) = 11.199, p < .001, part. η2 = .114. In line with hypothesis 1a, agreement with the claim was higher after reading comprehensible (EMM = 5.210, SE = .128) than incomprehensible arguments (EMM = 4.841, SE = .125). However, there was no significant main effect of support type and no significant interaction of support 730 type and time of measurement, both F(1, 87) < .496, ns. Hypothesis 2a was therefore not confirmed by our results. Furthermore, results yielded no significant three-way interaction of comprehensibility, support type and time of measurement, F(1, 87) = .154, ns. (2) Perceived argument strength. In order to test the hypotheses regarding argument strength, a repeated measures ANOVA on strength ratings with comprehensibility and support type as 735 within-participant factors was conducted. Results confirmed hypothesis 1b by revealing a significant main effect of comprehensibility, F(1,87) = 139.020, p < .001, part. η2 = .615: Across support types, comprehensible arguments were regarded as stronger (EMM = 5.574, SE = .095) than incomprehensible arguments (EMM = 3.614, SE = .162). As expected in hypothesis 2b, we also found a significant main effect of support type, F(1,87) = 13.505, p < 740 .001, part. η2 = .134, due to arguments with causal support being rated as stronger (EMM = 4.835, SE = .121) than those with empirical support (EMM = 4.352, SE = .125). The interaction of comprehensibility and support type was not significant, F(1,87) = .002, ns. 3.2.5 Confidence in the claim agreement decision 745 We had hypothesized that laypeople would be more confident in their own decision about the claim after reading comprehensible than incomprehensible arguments, which should lead to a higher trust in their own decision (hypothesis 3a) and a weaker desire for expert advice (hypothesis 3b). Moreover, we had hypothesized higher levels of trust in one’s own decision (hypothesis 4a) and a weaker desire to consult an expert (hypothesis 4b) after reading causal 750 compared to empirical support. As in Experiment I, Pearson’s correlation showed that trust in one’s own agreement decision and desire to consult an expert were negatively related in all conditions (comprehensible causal: r = -.383, incomprehensible causal: r = -.476, comprehensible empirical: r = -.420 and incomprehensible empirical: r = -.577; all correlations were significant at a .01 level). 755 (1) Trust in own agreement decision. To test our hypotheses regarding participants’ trust in their own decision, a repeated measures ANOVA on trust scores with comprehensibility and support type as within-participant factors was applied. Regarding the expected influence of argument comprehensibility, results showed that trust was higher in the comprehensible (EMM = 4.54, SE = .167) than in the incomprehensible conditions (EMM = 3.483, SE = 760 .165), F(1,87) = 41.465, p < .001, part. η2 = .323, providing support for hypothesis 3a. As to the influence of type of argument support, results revealed that reading causal and empirical support led to different levels of trust, F(1,87) = 9.204, p < .01, part. η2 = .096. In line with hypothesis 4a, participants’ trust in their own decision was higher after reading causal support (EMM = 4.21, SE = .157) than after reading empirical support (EMM = 3.813, SE = .159). 765 There was finally no significant interaction of comprehensibility and support type, F(1, 87) = 1.668, ns. (2) Desire to consult an expert. Our hypotheses regarding laypeople’s desire to seek out expert advice were tested using a repeated measures ANOVA with comprehensibility and support type as within-participant factors. As to the influence of argument comprehensibility, 770 the results were consistent with hypothesis 3b; laypeople’s desire to consult an expert was significantly higher after reading incomprehensible (EMM = 5.636, SE = .133) than comprehensible arguments (EMM = 5.114, SE = .162), F(1, 87) = 21.802, p < .001, part. η2 = .200. With regards to the hypothesized influence of support type, we found no significant main effect of support type, F(1, 87) < 1.807, ns. Hypothesis 4b was therefore not supported by 775 our data. Finally, the interaction of comprehensibility and support type did not reach significance, F(1, 87) = 1.375, ns. 3.3 Discussion The results of Experiment II demonstrate that participants were able to identify the type of 780 argument support presented. Readers were most successful in correctly classifying comprehensible arguments containing causal support but were also clearly above chance level in the three other conditions. Consistent with the results of Experiment I, Experiment II showed comprehensibility to be an important influence on the persuasiveness of provided information and confidence in the agreement decision. Comprehensible arguments led again 785 to more pronounced claim agreement and were rated as stronger than incomprehensible arguments (as expected in hypotheses 1a/b). Moreover, in accordance with hypotheses 3a/b, laypeople showed higher levels of trust in their own decision about the claim and a weaker desire for expert advice after reading comprehensible arguments than after reading incomprehensible ones. The results also revealed slight but inconsistent influences of support 790 type on persuasiveness of the provided information and confidence in the agreement decision. Although in line with hypothesis 2a laypeople evaluated arguments providing causal support as slightly stronger than those providing empirical support, this did not translate to their actual agreement with the claim, thus contradicting hypothesis 2b. Moreover, although participants’ trust in their own decision was higher after reading causal support than after reading empirical 795 support (as predicted in hypothesis 4a), this was not reflected in in a differential desire to consult an expert depending on what type of argument support they had read (hypothesis 4b). Despite the similarity between the findings of the two experiments, there are also several differences, particularly with regards to effect sizes. Compared to the first experiment, the second experiment yielded stronger effects of comprehensibility on claim agreement (Exp. I: 800 part. η2 = .061 vs. Exp. II: part. η2 = .114), trust in own decision about the claim (Exp. I: part. η2 = .183 vs. Exp. II: part. η2 =.323) and desire to consult an expert (Exp. I: part. η2 = .080, Exp. II: part. η2 = .200). Thus, the presumably less scientifically experienced participants in Experiment II agreed more strongly with the claim, showed greater trust in their own decisions and perceived themselves less in need of expert advice after reading a 805 comprehensible compared to an incomprehensible argument. Moreover, in contrast to the results of Experiment I, Experiment II showed that participants trusted more strongly in their own agreement decision after reading causal compared to empirical support. 4. 810 General Discussion By presenting participants with texts of varying easiness, the present experiments investigated whether laypeople are inclined to rely on their own evaluation of scientific claims. We had expected that laypeople would more clearly and confidently accept information they consider as easy compared to information that was difficult and complex. Thus, we predicted claim agreement to be greater and arguments rated stronger when recipients read comprehensible 815 compared to incomprehensible arguments (hypotheses 1a/b), and causally supported arguments compared to empirically supported ones (hypotheses 2a/b). Moreover we had expected higher levels of trust in laypeople’s own decisions and conversely a weaker desire to consult an expert after reading comprehensible compared to incomprehensible arguments (hypotheses 3a/b) and causal compared to empirical support (hypotheses 4a/b). 820 4.1 Summary of present findings Both experiments revealed that, as expected in hypotheses 1 a/b, laypeople were more persuaded by information about scientific contents when the information they had received was comprehensible than when it was incomprehensible. Moreover, in line with hypotheses 825 3a/b, after reading comprehensible arguments, laypeople showed higher levels of trust in their own agreement decision and a decreased desire to ask an expert for decision support. Findings with regards to type of argument support are less conclusive and only partly confirm our expectations. We found that recipients were indeed able to differentiate between argument support types, and they evaluated arguments containing causal support as stronger than 830 arguments containing empirical support (in line with hypothesis 2b). However, the influence of support type did not extend to recipients’ claim agreement or to their desire to consult an expert (contrary to hypotheses 2a and 4b). Finally, while our expectation that support type would influence laypeople’s trust in their own decision (hypothesis 4a) was not confirmed in Experiment I, it did receive support in Experiment II, where participants’ trust scores were 835 higher after reading causal than empirical support. The present finding of causal support being perceived as stronger than empirical support is consistent with previous research showing that laypersons do not evaluate arguments in the same way as experts, who prefer empirical evidence and consider explanations unsubstantiated by data as generally weak or unsupported (Kuhn, 1991; Slusher & Anderson, 1996). The results also corroborate Keil’s (2010) 840 proposition that reasoning in terms of causal explanation plays a central role in laypeople’s folk science. An additional contribution of the present work was to ensure that the observed preference for causal support is not due to a confounding with comprehensibility. A possible confounding with argument comprehensibility might explain the mixed results obtained in previous research where comprehensibility had not been controlled, with some studies 845 showing laypeople to favor causal support (e.g. Slusher & Anderson, 1996) and other research finding a preference for empirical support (e.g. Brem & Rips, 2000). By controlling for comprehensibility of both support types, the present findings show that laypeople have an actual preference for causal over empirical support. Furthermore, the results obtained regarding laypeople’s desire to ask an expert for support 850 suggest that laypeople are generally inclined to make use of the division of cognitive labor when having to come to decisions about science-related issues. Even when receiving easy texts, participants’ ratings of their desire to ask an expert did not average below 5 on a scale from 1 to 7 (with 7 indicating a strong desire). Nevertheless, the decreasing influence of information comprehensibility on the perceived need for expert advice suggests that an over- 855 simplification of scientific contents might mislead lay recipients to underestimate the importance of relying on experts. Overall, the results of both experiments show strong similarities, which indicates the robustness of the obtained findings and moreover demonstrates that the observed effects are not specific for the domain of medicine. However, compared to Experiment I, Experiment II 860 yielded stronger differences in laypeople’s decisions depending on the easiness of the received information. This is in line with our expectation that the influence of perceived easiness on laypeople’s reliance on their own content evaluations depends on their scientific experience. The participants of Experiment II, who we assume to have been less aware of the general complexity and tentativeness of scientific knowledge, appear to have more readily 865 formed the impression that being able to understand information qualified them to decide about the persuasiveness of knowledge claims. In sum, our results confirm the hypothesis that laypeople are more inclined to rely on their own evaluations of scientific contents when they perceive the topic at hand as easy than when they perceive the issue as beyond their own understanding. Moreover, it seems that though 870 comprehensibility has a strong influence on lay recipients’ impression of content easiness, the impact of support type is comparatively small. Support type might have a stronger effect on easiness perceptions among laypeople who are scientifically more naïve than the participants we included in our experiments. The less familiar laypeople are with empirical evidence, and thus with evidence that is not part of their naïve folk science, the more difficult they may 875 perceive its evaluation and the more inclined they might be to seek out the help of experts. 4.2 Limitations and future directions It needs to be borne in mind that the present experiments were conducted on a student sample. Thus, although our participants did not study subjects directly related to the knowledge claims 880 in question and had only just begun their higher education, their scientific experience was presumably more extensive than that of the ‘average layperson’. In fact, this renders our findings more remarkable, as it appears that even individuals who should to some degree be aware of the general complexity and tentativeness of scientific knowledge are prone to disregard their own epistemic limitations in light of perceived text easiness. 885 To ensure the lay status of our participants, we not only examined university students with non-empirical majors (Experiment I), but restricted our selection to students who had only just begun their higher education or were from a less research-oriented institution (Experiment II). However, it should be noted that we assumed the participants of each experiment to differ in their scientific experience due to their educational background. 890 Therefore, we cannot conclude with certainty that the differences in effect sizes between experiments are indeed due to both samples varying in relevant experience. Future research could further investigate the impact of scientific experience by assessing laypeople’s epistemological beliefs, which might become more sophisticated as a function of scientific training, and compare those individuals who have been confirmed to differ in their beliefs 895 about the nature of scientific knowledge (for information about the relationship between educational experience and epistemological beliefs see Weinstock & Zviling-Beiser, 2009). In this context, it would also be an interesting direction for future research to more generally examine the connection between epistemological beliefs as they are traditionally conceptualized in research (i.e. as beliefs regarding an individual’s own knowledge) and 900 individuals’ conceptions and utilization of the division of cognitive labor (which is related to individuals’ beliefs about other people’s knowledge). While a comprehensive theoretical elaboration of the relationship between epistemological beliefs in the traditional sense and beliefs about the division of cognitive labor is beyond the scope of this article, the interested reader is referred to Bromme et al. (2010). 905 Two further limitations concern the text materials applied in the present experiments. First, comprehensibility of the arguments was varied in three ways: through technical jargon, inclusion of unnecessary detail and repetition of important information. While this was done to ensure a strong manipulation of comprehensibility, we cannot conclude with certainty whether the observed effects are due to all three ways of comprehensibility manipulation or 910 whether they are attributable to only one or two of them. In future research, only one way of manipulating comprehensibility at a time could be applied in order to disentangle their respective contributions to the presently obtained effects. Second, the arguments used as stimulus materials were written by one of the experimenters, who is not a medical or climate expert. Although great care has been taken to write the texts in a style and wording 915 comparable to genuine medicine and climate-related science texts, it cannot be completely ruled out that participants perceived the texts as less valid representations of science texts than would have been the case had the texts been written by actual domain experts. It also needs to be noted that we manipulated comprehensibility and type of argument assuming that both factors influence perceived easiness of the provided information, but did 920 not explicitly assess laypeople’s impressions of content easiness. In order to more conclusively establish the assumed role of perceived easiness as a mediating variable of the observed effects, easiness perceptions should be measured directly in future experiments. With regards to the specificity of our findings, we would like to point out that although our experiments were only focused on laypeople, we do not propose that the observed effects are 925 unique to lay recipients. It is possible that experts or novices would show the same inclination to more strongly and confidently accept an argument when the information is easy as the laypeople in our samples. However, we suspect that laypeople may be especially prone to overestimate their epistemic capabilities as a consequence of receiving an easy text. Compared to laypeople, experts and novices should be more aware of the complexity of 930 scientific knowledge − especially about the topics they have studied laboriously in order to become an expert. As a result, they might be less likely to perceive a topic as simple and easy to evaluate only because a specific depiction of the topic is easy to understand. Whether this assumption is accurate, however, or whether experts and novices are in fact equally inclined to more readily accept easy information remains an open empirical question warranting 935 further research. 4.3 Educational implications Our results have implications for science education as well as for the communication of science knowledge to laypeople outside of the formal learning context. The finding of 940 laypeople tending to rely more strongly on their own evaluations of scientific contents if the subject matter is presented in an easy way suggests a limited awareness of the general complexity and tentativeness of scientific knowledge. Due to this limited awareness, laypeople appear to be susceptible to belief that their own epistemic capabilities are sufficient to evaluate the veracity of scientific claims, even though they actually possess little or no 945 relevant prior knowledge about the subject matter. This susceptibility may result from a lack of appreciation for the need to rely on the division of cognitive labor. Even research and literature on epistemological beliefs is guided by the idea that it is predominately epistemologically naïve individuals who accept knowledge from authority, whereas sophisticated individuals attempt to construct knowledge by themselves (but see Elby & 950 Hammer, 2001 for a criticism of this stance). This is reflected in the dimension ‘source of knowledge’ of epistemological beliefs theories (e.g. Schommer, 1990), which derives from the belief that knowledge originates from authority figures such as teachers or experts to the belief that knowledge is the outcome of inquiry and personal construction (and this pole is conceived as the most elaborated one). 955 The assumption that independence from external sources is a desirable developmental goal might on the one hand go back to Piagetian influences on research programs on epistemological beliefs. In the Piagetian tradition, cognitive development during childhood has been conceived as being driven predominately by children’s own experiences with their environment, whereas testimony offered by adults has been dismissed as “providing mere 960 'verbal' knowledge, rather than genuine understanding" (Harris, 2001, p. 495), denying any educative role of such second-hand information (see Harris, 2001 for a criticism of this view). On the other hand, the view of authority-independence as a desirable state might be influenced by the normative ideal of students becoming citizens who make up their own minds instead of deferring to authorities (Perry, 1979). Such a view implicitly suggests that 965 the optimal way for individuals to handle scientific issues is to overcome the division of cognitive labor by evaluating information and deciding for themselves, on par with an expert. This criticism does not apply to all epistemological beliefs researchers (see for example Chinn, Buckland & Samarapungavan, 2011). King and Kitchener (1994) do not argue for a rejection of reliance on expert knowledge either, but rather for a critical reflection about 970 experts’ knowledge claims. Nevertheless, even the developmental trajectory underlying their work emphasizes a development towards cognitive autonomy which implies an independence of one’s own ideas from external authorities and which might be not realistic. If this normative ideal, held even by several scientists, is shared by laypeople, it may explain their readiness to make decisions in situations when they should actually ask an expert for advice. 975 In order to prevent individuals from sharing this belief, it is important to increase awareness of the specific nature of scientific knowledge, the evaluation of which usually requires years of specialized training. In this context, laypeople should be sensitized to the central role of the division of cognitive labor in modern societies. In school, as well as in the course of higher education, students should learn that oftentimes it is not only acceptable but even desirable to 980 rely on other people rather than attempting to solve a problem on one’s own. Our findings furthermore suggest that caution should be taken whenever scientific contents are communicated to laypeople outside of the educational context. Popularized science reports, i.e. science depictions especially intended for public consumption, are usually characterized by simplification in order to facilitate the target audience’s content 985 understanding (Goldman & Bisanz, 2002; Zimmerman et al., 2001). However, the present findings indicate that such a simplification includes the risk of making scientific knowledge appear less complex and easier to evaluate than it actually is. Of course we do not intend to propose that laypeople should not be informed about scientific contents in a way that allows them to understand the central facts. However, we consider it important that popularized 990 science reports not only inform laypeople about scientific contents but also make recipients aware of the fact that the content information presented is usually not sufficient to allow confident evaluations of related knowledge claims that may influence their decision making. 5. 995 References Bekker, H., Thornton, J. G., Airey, C. M., Connelly, J. B., Hewison, J., Robinson, M. B., et al. (1999). Informed decision making: An annotated bibliography and systematic review. Health Technology Assessment, 3, 1-156. Blair, J.A. & Johnson R.H. (1987). Argumentation as dialectical. Argumentation 1, 41-56. doi:10.1007/BF00127118 1000 Bradley, S. D. & Meeds, R. (2004). The effects of sentence-level context, prior word knowledge, and need for cognition on information processing of technical language in print ads. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 14, 291-302. doi:10.1207/s15327663jcp1403_10 Brand-Gruwel, S. & Stadtler, M. (2011). Solving information-based problems: Evaluating 1005 sources and information. Learning and Instruction, 21, 175-179. doi:10.1016/j.learninstruc.2010.02.008 Brem, S. K. & Rips, L. J. (2000). Explanation and evidence in informal argument. Cognitive Science, 24, 573-604. doi:10.1016/S0364-0213(00)00033-1 Bromme, R., Kienhues, D. & Porsch, T. (2010). Who knows what and who can we believe? 1010 Epistemological beliefs are beliefs about knowledge (mostly) attained from others. In L. D. Bendixen & F. C. Feucht (eds.), Personal Epistemology in the Classroom: Theory, Research, and Implications for Practice, pp. 163-193, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511691904.006 Bromme, R., Rambow, R. & Nückles, M. (2001). Expertise and estimating what other people 1015 know: The influence of professional experience and type of knowledge. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 7, 317-330. doi:10.1037//1076-898X.7.4.317-330 Charles, G., Gafni, A. & Whelan, T. (1997). Shared decision-making in the medical encounter: What does it mean? Social Science and Medicine, 44, 681-692. doi:10.1016/S0277-9536(96)00221-3 1020 Chinn, C., Buckland, L. & Samarapungavan, A. (2011). Expanding the dimensions of Epistemic Cognition: Arguments from philosophy and psychology, Educational Psychologist, 46, 141-167. doi:org/10.1080/00461520.2011.587722 Cohen, J. (1988). Statistical power analysis for the behavioral sciences (2nd edition). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. 1025 Eagly, A.H. (1974). Comprehensibility of persuasive arguments as a determinant of opinion change. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 29, 758-773. doi:10.1037/h0036202 Elby, A. & Hammer, D. (2001). On the substance of a sophisticated epistemology. Science Education, 85, 554-567. doi:10.1002/sce.1023 1030 Erb, H.-P., Bohner, G., Rank, S. & Einwiller, S. (2002). Processing minority and majority communications: The role of conflict with prior attitudes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 1172-1182. doi:10.1177/01461672022812003 Faul, F., Erdfelder, E., Lang, A.-G. & Buchner, A. (2007). G*Power 3: A flexible statistical power analysis program for the social, behavioral, and biomedical sciences. Behavior 1035 Research Methods, 39, 175-191. doi:10.3758/BF03193146 Fox, S. (2005). Health information online. Washington, DC: Pew Internet & American Life Project. Glassner, A., Weinstock, M. & Neuman, Y. (2005). Pupils' evaluation and generation of evidence and explanation in argumentation. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 1040 75, 105-118. doi:10.1348/000709904X22278 Glenberg, A.M. & Epstein, W. (1985). Calibration of comprehension. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 11, 702-718. doi:10.1037//0278-7393.11.1-4.702 Goldman, S.R. (2011). Commentary: Choosing and using multiple information sources: Some 1045 new findings and emergent issues. Learning and Instruction, 21, 238-242. doi:10.1016/j.learninstruc.2010.02.006 Goldman, S.R. & Bisanz, G.L. (2002). Toward functional analysis of scientific genres: Implications for understanding and learning processes. In J. Otero, J.A. Leon, & A.C. Graesser (eds.), The psychology of science text comprehension, pp. 19-50, Mahwah NJ: 1050 Erlbaum. Gopnik A. (2000). Explanation as orgasm and the drive for causal knowledge: The function, evolution, and phenomenology of the theory formation system. In F. C. Keil & R. A. Wilson (eds.), Explanation and cognition, pp. 299-323, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Harris, P.L. (2001). Thinking about the unknown. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 494-498. 1055 doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01789-7 Jucks, R. (2001). Was verstehen Laien? Die Verständlichkeit von Fachtexten aus der Sicht von. Computer-Experten. Münster: Waxmann. Kajanne, A. & Pirttilä-Backman, A.-M. (1999). Laypeople's viewpoints about the reasons for expert controversy regarding food additives. Public Understanding of Science, 8, 303- 1060 315. doi:10.1088/0963-6625/8/4/303 Keehner, M. & Fischer, M.H. (2011). Naive realism in public perceptions of neuroimages. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 12, 118. doi:10.1038/nrn2773-c1 Keil, F.C. (2003). Categorisation, causation, and the limits of understanding. Language and Cognitive Processes, 18, 663-692. doi:10.1080/01690960344000062 1065 Keil, F. C. (2006). Explanation and understanding. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, 227254. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.57.102904.190100 Keil, F.C. (2008) Getting to the truth: Grounding incomplete knowledge. Brooklyn Law Review, 73(3), 1035-1052. Keil, F.C. (2010). The feasibility of folk science. Cognitive Science, 34, 826-862. 1070 doi:10.1111/j.1551-6709.2010.01108.x Keil, F.C., Stein, C., Webb, L., Billings, V. D. & Rozenblit, L. (2008). Discerning the division of cognitive labor: An emerging understanding of how knowledge is clustered in other minds. Cognitive Science, 32, 259–300. doi:10.1080/03640210701863339 Kienhues, D., Stadtler, M. & Bromme, R. (2011). Dealing with conflicting or consistent 1075 medical information on the Web: When expert information breeds laypersons’ doubts about experts. Learning and Instruction, 21, 193-204. doi:10.1016/j.learninstruc.2010.02.004 King, P.M. & Kitchener, K.S. (1994). Developing reflective judgment: Understanding and promoting intellectual growth and critical thinking in adolescents and adults. San 1080 Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Koslowski, B. (1996). Theory and evidence: The Development of Scientific Reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kuhn, D. (1991). The skills of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lombrozo, T. (2006). The structure and function of explanations. Trends in Cognitive 1085 Sciences, 10, 464-470. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2006.08.004 Mason, L., Ariasi, N., & Boldrin, A. (2011). Epistemic beliefs in action: Spontaneous reflections about knowledge and knowing during online information searching and their influence on learning. Learning and Instruction, 21, 137-151. doi:10.1016/j.learninstruc.2010.01.001 1090 Miller, N., Maruyama, G., Beaber, R.J. & Valone, K. (1976). Speed of speech and persuasion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 34, 615-624. doi:10.1037//00223514.34.4.615 Murphy, P.K., Long, J.F., Hollerana, T.A. & Esterly, E. (2003). Persuasion online or on paper: A new take on an old issue. Learning and Instruction, 13, 511-532. 1095 doi:10.1016/S0959-4752(02)00041-5 Nagy, W. (1988). Teaching vocabulary to improve reading comprehension. Newark: International Reading Association. O’Keefe, D. J. (2002). Persuasion: Theory and research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Perry, W.G. (1970). Forms of intellectual and ethical development in the college years: A 1100 scheme. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Pieschl, S. (2009). Metacognitive calibration - an extended conceptualization and potential applications. Metacognition and Learning, 4, 3-31. doi:10.1007/s11409-008-9030-4 Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In K. Gunderson (ed.) Language, Mind and Knowledge, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, VII, pp. 215-271, 1105 Cambridge: University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511625251.014 Reber, R. & Schwarz, N. (1999). Effects of perceptual fluency on judgments of truth. Consciousness and Cognition, 8, 338-342. doi:10.1006/ccog.1999.0386 Sandoval, W.A. & Çam, A. (2011). Elementary children's judgments of causal justifications. Science Education. 95, 383-408. doi:10.1002/sce.20426 1110 Schommer, M. (1990). Effects of beliefs about the nature of knowledge on comprehension. Journal of Educational Psychology, 82, 498-504. doi:10.1037//0022-0663.82.3.498 Schwarz, N. (2004). Meta-cognitive experiences in consumer judgment and decision making. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 14, 332-348. doi:10.1207/s15327663jcp1404_2 Slusher, M.P. & Anderson, C.A. (1996). Using causal persuasive arguments to change beliefs 1115 and teach new information: The mediating role of explanation availability and evaluation bias in the acceptance of knowledge. Journal of Educational Psychology, 88, 110-122. doi:10.1037//0022-0663.88.1.110 Stadtler, M. & Bromme, R. (2008). Effects of the metacognitive tool met.a.ware on the web search of laypersons. Computers in Human Behavior, 24, 716-737. 1120 doi:10.1016/j.chb.2007.01.023 Stehr, N. (1994). Knowledge Societies. London: Sage. Trabasso, T., Secco, T. & van den Broek, P.W. (1984). Causal cohesion and story coherence. In: H. Mandl, N. L. Stein & T. Trabasso (eds.), Learning and comprehension of text, pp. 83-111, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. 1125 Trout J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69(2), 212-233. doi:10.1086/341050 Tyler, A. (1994). The role of repetition in perceptions of discourse coherence. Journal of Pragmatics, 21, 671-688. doi:10.1016/0378-2166(94)90103-1 Wagner, W., Elejabarrieta, F. & Lahnsteiner, I. (1995). How the sperm dominates the ovum – 1130 Objectification by metaphor in the social representation of conception. European Journal of Social Psychology, 25, 671-688. doi:10.1002/ejsp.2420250606 Weinstock, M. & Zviling-Beiser, H. (2009). Separating academic and social experience as potential factors in epistemological development. Learning and Instruction, 19, 287-298. doi:10.1016/j.learninstruc.2008.05.004 1135 Wiley, J., Goldman, S.R., Graesser, A.C., Sanchez, C.A., Ash, I.K. & Hemmerich, J.A. (2009). Source evaluation, comprehension, and learning in Internet science inquiry tasks. American Educational Research Journal, 46, 1060-1106. doi:10.3102/0002831209333183 Wiley, J., Griffin, T.D. & Thiede, K.W. (2005). Putting the comprehension in 1140 metacomprehension. Journal of General Psychology, 132, 408-428. doi:10.3200/GENP.132.4.408-428 Zimmerman, C., Bisanz, G.L., Bisanz, J., Klein, J.S. & Klein, P. (2001). Science at the supermarket: A comparison of what appears in the popular press, experts’ advice to readers, and what students want to know. Public Understanding of Science, 10, 37-58. 1145 doi:10.1088/0963-6625/10/1/303 Table 1 Means and standard deviations (in brackets) for the dependent measures of Experiment I perceived comprehensibility, perceived argument strength, agreement with the claim prior 1150 and subsequent to reading the argument, trust in own agreement decision, and desire to consult an expert as a function of comprehensibility and type of argument support. All scales ranged from 1 to 7 (with 7 meaning higher scores on the dimension). Claim Trust in Desire for Argument Compre- Argument agreement own expert condition hensibility strength pre post decision advice Compr. 6.07 5.85 3.99 5.14 4.22 5.72 causal (1.10) (1.28) (1.08) (1.22) (1.87) (1.63) Incompr. 2.14 3.93 3.94 4.93 3.63 6.16 causal (1.36) (1.59) (1.01) (1.16) (2.03) (1.29) Compr. 6.14 5.16 3.94 5.02 4.03 6.00 empirical (1.14) (1.56) (0.99) (1.15) (1.85) (1.36) Incompr. 1.92 3.50 4.08 4.78 3.34 6.25 empirical (1.24) (1.67) (0.91) (1.26) (1.93) (1.25) 1155 Table 2 Means and standard deviations (in brackets) for the dependent measures of Experiment II perceived comprehensibility, perceived argument strength, agreement with the claim prior and subsequent to reading the argument, trust in own agreement decision, and desire to consult an expert as a function of comprehensibility and type of argument support. All scales 1160 ranged from 1 to 7 (with 7 meaning higher scores on the dimension). Claim Trust in Desire for Argument Compre- Argument agreement own expert condition hensibility strength pre post decision advice Compr. 5.86 5.82 4.11 5.38 4.58 5.11 causal (1.35) (1.14) (1.38) (1.36) (1.77) (1.79) Incompr. 2.10 3.85 4.16 4.80 3.84 5.45 causal (1.45) (1.74) (1.36) (1.46) (1.90) (1.79) Compr. 5.56 5.33 3.92 5.05 4.50 5.11 empirical (1.20) (1.30) (1.42) (1.55) (1.77) (1.76) Incompr. 2.11 3.38 4.27 4.89 3.13 5.82 empirical (1.43) (1.70) (1,40) (1.39) (1.84) (1.39)