Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 Religion and Mental Health: an exploration of the relationship between the ineffable and the indefinable PETER CONNOLLY ABSTRACT This article suggests that the relationship between religion and mental health is both important and complex. It reviews some studies of the relationship and suggests that religion can be good or bad for one's mental health, depending on the content of the religious message. It also presents a model of mental health and suggests that this or some similar scheme can be employed to assess the extent to which one's religious or value system promotes mental health. The terms `religion' and `mental health'; both conjure up a variety of images, associations and emotions in people who think about them. The same is true among the scholars who write about them. People in general, and students of religion in particular, differ about the nature of and characteristics associated with the phenomenon of religion. That is, they disagree about the meaning of the word. They also disagree about the benefits and detriments which accrue from the adoption of religious beliefs and engagement in religious behaviours. A similar situation pertains in the field of mental health. Mental health is measured in many different ways, and each measurement strategy is based on an implicit definition. One recent study identified 21 different measures, and this figure is by no means comprehensive (Schumaker, 1992). In short, the referents of the terms and the relationships between them are matters of contention, and thus a simple demonstrable answer to the question `Is being religious good for one's mental health?' cannot be provided at the present time. What is more, to date the increase in the number of studies addressing this issue is doing little to improve the situation. In 1982 Daniel Batson and Larry Ventis reviewed 57 different studies of religion and mental health and found positive or negative correlations between them for four of their seven definitions of mental health. In 1993 they repeated their review, this time drawing upon 91 different studies, and found more or less the same pattern as that which emerged from their 1982 survey. Did this result imbue them with increased confidence in their findings? It did not. They write: ... we must once again emphasise the methodological limitations of this research. The quantity of research is certainly great, and is increasing all the time; unfortunately, the quality is neither great nor increasing ... Although we have suggested the need for more data in several areas, quality is a far more important research virtue than is quantity. Therefore, we do not wish to call for more research on the religion–mental health relation-ship without calling even more loudly for better research. (Batson et al., 1993, pp. 288–289) Batson and Ventis bemoan the facts that virtually all the research they reviewed was correlational, assessments of mental health were almost always based on self-reports and some of the sample populations were far from being representative. To some extent they could have addressed these issues themselves. Studies based on unusual populations could have been excluded from their review. Studies based on self-report could have been categorised into those which employed lie scales or other similar devices for identifying biases in the responses and those which did not. Studies which reported high correlations, say r = 0.05 or above, could have been distinguished from those reporting low 1 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 ones. The studies based on relatively average or representative populations, which employed lie scales or similar devices and reported high correlations could then have been offered as examples of what `better' research might look like. One factor not commented on by Batson and Ventis, though one which is certainly significant in this field, is that of investigator bias. As a group, psychologists of religion differ markedly from other psychologists. Many psychologists of religion are both trained psychologists and members of religious organisations yet, ever since James Leuba published the results of his investigation into the religious beliefs of American scientists in 1916, psychologists have consistently shown themselves to be the least religious of all types of scientist (Wulff, 1991, pp. 34–36). It is reasonable to expect, therefore, that many psychologists of religion will be predisposed towards information which supports rather than undermines their religious commitments. Non religious psychologists, particularly in America—which is where most of the research on the psychology of religion takes place—can hardly ignore religion and the issue of its effects on human welfare. The fact that they are non religious suggests either that they do not regard it as offering sufficient personal benefits for them to take it seriously or that they regard it as detrimental to human well-being. The likelihood is then, that at least some members of this group, when they write on religion, will exhibit a negative bias towards it. The current state of affairs amongst psychologists on the issue of religion and mental health can thus be described as one of fundamental disagreement. For some psychologists religion promotes negative self-evaluations, emotional repression, anxiety, dependency, conformity and a whole host of other debilitations. For others, it provides people with a sense of power and focused identity, anxiety reduction, emotional well-being, social cohesion and a range of other benefits (Schumaker, 1992, pp. 3–4). Yet others, such as Batson and Ventis, John Schumaker and myself, try to take up some kind of middle ground, where religion can be seen to promote either mental health or mental ill-health depending on the content of what is being propagated. The moral here then, as in many other areas of social enquiry, is that the identification of the researcher can often be as important as the research. Another confounding factor, which pervades much of the American research in this area, is the idea that there are different ways of being religious or that there are different religious `orientations', some of which are more `healthy' than others. The most well known and well used of these distinctions is Gordon Allport's separation of religious people into the intrinsically religious and the extrinsically religious. The former are the truly religious—those who sincerely try to live according to the tenets of their faith (the sheep), whereas the latter are merely conventionally religious— those for whom involvement in the faith is superficial and often undertaken for purely social reasons (the goats). Other psychologists of religion have produced similar distinctions such as individualised–institutionalised and committed– consensual, though none of these have come close to exerting the same influence none of these have come close to exerting the same influence on research as Allport’s scheme (Brown, 19; Allen & Spilka, 1967). Despite its influence and popularity, researchers who have approached the evaluation of the intrinsic–extrinsic distinction with a reasonable amount of rigour have consistently concluded that it is fundamentally flawed. L.B. Brown and J.E. Dittes have both argued that the I and E orientations are more like pervasive personality characteristics than religious orientations, and this would certainly fit with the obvious conclusions to be drawn from Allport's original essay (Allport, 1959/60, Brown, 1964; Dittes, 1971). In 1971 Richard Hunt and Morton King reviewed all the major works in the I–E concept and concluded, amongst other things, that although the results preclude employing I and E as poles of a single axis, separating them and forming two independent scales (the orthogonal variation) did not produce 2 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 two clearly independent factors. Like Brown and Dittes they reckoned that the I–E material points to pervasive personality variables rather than some kind of irreducible religious dimensions of life. Their recommendation was that psychologists of religion should abandon the attempt to identify irreducible religious factors and focus their attention on the common centre of socio-psychological study, namely the effects people have on each other's beliefs and behaviour. Their call has, however, tended to go unheeded (Hunt & King, 1971). In 1990, L.A. Kirkpatrick and R.W. Hood Jr published an article on essentially the same lines as that of Hunt and King (Kirkpatrick & Hood, 1990). They pointed out the invalidity of the I and E scales and the conceptual confusion surrounding • them, and encouraged psychologists of religion `to move beyond a simplistic I–E framework to more theoretically and psychometrically sophisticated approaches' (Kirkpatrick & Hood, 1990, p. 442). This further call to abandon I–E research is likely to fall on the same deaf ears as Hunt and King’s recommendation some 20 years earlier. In the light of these observations it is clear that one of the primary weaknesses in Batson and Ventis's analysis is that they too accept the general principle of the distinction between sheep and goat orientations and then add another of their own devising: the quest orientation. This merely exacerbates the situation, however. These orientations are all about ways of being religious rather than religion, about ways of approaching religion rather than religion as a distinctive dimension of human life. This dimension can be delineated and such delineation can reveal what it is that these so-called orientations have in common, that is, what makes them religious orientations. For this, a robust definition of religion is required, a definition that will distinguish the religious from other aspects of human life and which, at the same time, can encompass the various phenomena that are generally recognised as falling within the category of religion by informed investigators. Such a definition can then be employed in the construction of questionnaires designed to determine whether people are religious or not, and these, in turn, can be combined with various measures of mental health in order to ascertain whether religious people exhibit higher or lower levels of mental health than nonreligious people. This, of course, is an outline for a major piece of research that has not yet been conducted. The comments which follow are offered as a kind of preamble to such a project. First, I shall offer what I believe to be a fairly robust definition of religion. Second, I shall summarise the findings of Batson and Ventis's review—but without differentiating the so-called religious orientations—in order to provide a rough sketch of the current state of play; then I shall offer a kind of multi-category definition of optimum mental health and suggest that if religious people want to argue that living a religious life really does offer a route to human fulfilment then the criteria for mental health by which such claims must be judged need to be closer to this kind of optimum characterisation than the kind of minimalist `absence of mental illness' definitions employed by many researchers (Batson & Ventis, 1982, pp. 222– 223; Batson et al., 1993, pp. 262–263). Finally, I shall comment on what seems to me to be an important characteristic of the mentally healthy, a characteristic which provides insights into the reasons why religion can have either a beneficial or a detrimental effect on people's mental health and why, in the final analysis, even the most beneficial religious approaches to life fall short of being optimal strategies for mental health promotion. First, then, a definition of religion. At the present time the student of religion is spoiled for choice on the issue of definitions. Virtually every scholar who writes on the subject formulates their own. As with the research on religion and mental health mentioned earlier, not all of them are of equal quality. In the early years of the present century scholars tried to encapsulate what they regarded as the essence of religion in pithy, one-line definitions. Examples would be Alfred North White-head's `what the individual does with his own solitariness' or E.B. Tylor's `belief in spiritual beings' (Sharpe, 1983, pp. 34, 38). A more recent offering from Ronald Cavanagh is: 3 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 ... `the varied, symbolic expression of, and appropriate response to, that which people deliberately affirm as being of unrestricted value for them. (Cavanagh, 1978, p. 20) The best of these is, I would suggest, Tylor's `belief in spiritual beings'. Despite its many limitations (it lacks reference to the realm of activity or behaviour and leaves little room for non-personalistic conceptions of `the spiritual', for example) it does contain reference to the element which, it seems to me, offers the only rigorous way of distinguishing religion from other areas of human experience and behaviour, namely a reference to `the spiritual' [ 1 ] . Other commonly used terms for this dimension are divine, holy, numinous, sacred and supernatural. They all refer to a trans-empirical realm which is believed to be accessible to human beings and deemed to be the primary source of fulfilment for them. The other definitions lack this element and thus cannot meaningfully separate the religious from other aspects of life. Whitehead's cannot exclude reading pulp novels from the realm of religious activity, and Cavanagh, perhaps anticipating former England team manager Terry Venables, would have to allow Association Football to be classified as a religion. In recent years, partly to avoid the kind of over-emphasis on one aspect—as found, for example, in Whitehead's definition which, we may note, contrasts sharply with Durkheim's claim that religion `is an eminently collective thing' (Sharpe, 1983, p. 37), scholars have come to favour multi-category definitions of religion. Thus, Frederick Streng describes religion in terms of its three primary dimensions: the personal, the cultural and the ultimate (Streng, 1976, pp. 1–9). Eric Sharpe prefers the language of modes to that of dimensions and distinguishes four: the existential, the intellectual, the institutional and the ethical (Sharpe, 1983, Ch. 7). Sociologists Charles Glock and Rodney Stark identify five distinct dimensions: the experiential, the ideological, the ritualistic, the intellectual and the consequential, (Holm, 1977, p. 18) whilst philosopher and phenomenologist of religion Ninian Smart has distinguished six, and later seven, dimensions: mythical or narrative, ritual, social, ethical, doctrinal, experiential and, most recently, material (Smart, 1968, pp. 15–19; 1969, pp. 15–25; 1989, pp. 10–21). Such attempts to map out the primary ways in which religion manifests in human life certainly offer fuller notions of what might be encompassed under the heading of `religion' but, equally, they can distract attention away from what it is that makes them dimensions or modes of religion. In his second formulation of his six-dimensional model Smart goes some way towards correcting this omission by pointing out that what prevents Marxism or Humanism from being religious is not that they lack the dimensions but that they deny the existence of the supernatural, of the invisible world. This, to me, is crucial for dimensionalisation alone cannot distinguish the religious from the non-religious—a point pertinently exemplified by the fact that elsewhere Smart employs his scheme to analyse secular ideologies (Smart, 1983, 1989). Indeed, I would suggest that any definition of religion which places more emphasis on its dimensions or modes or whatever than its rootedness in the sacred is not only inadequate but misleading. A robust definition of the term `religion' would thus be `any beliefs which involve the acceptance of a sacred, trans-empirical realm and any behaviours designed to affect a person's relationship with that realm'. The most convenient term to refer to such behaviours is, perhaps, `spirituality'. Religions can thus be communal or individual (see Corbett, 1996). They will usually exhibit some of the dimensions or manifestations already mentioned. Sometimes they will exhibit all of them. The only really crucial element, however, is the belief in the sacred, the transcendent or trans-empirical realm. When this is present we have religion; when it is absent we do not. As with religion, there are many definitions of mental health that a researcher can employ and, again, not all are equally valuable. Despite its limitations, some of which are acknowledged by the authors themselves, the review of research into the relationship between religion and mental health conducted by Batson and Ventis (Batson et al., 1993, p. 386) is one of the most useful available to date, not least because these 4 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 authors recognise the dangers of bias creeping into this kind of work and take some steps to minimise its effects. Their organisation of the reports under review in terms of the seven most frequently employed definitions of mental health also provides a useful springboard for further enquiry. The seven are: (1) absence of mental illness; (2) appropriate social behaviour; (3) freedom from worry and guilt; (4) personal competence and control; (5) self-acceptance/selfactualisation; (6) personality unification and organisation, and (7) open-mindedness and flexibility. These conceptions of mental health are those that Batson and Ventis found employed in the literature they reviewed and thus, despite Schumaker's warning about the dangers of collapsing `a large number of mental health variables into a limited number of definitional categories' (Schumaker, 1992, p. 16), they do offer a reasonable first attempt at rendering the results of diverse studies on religion and mental health intelligible. Batson and Ventis' categorisation, suggests that when mental health is defined in the first way, i.e. absence of mental illness, it is positively correlated with being religious except for clergy and nuns (especially the cloistered), who display a negative correlation. Commentators on these latter findings tend to suggest that they derive from the tendency of people with a propensity towards mental disorder to seek a religious vocation. If this is true it points to serious deficiencies in the screening procedures for such occupations. When mental health is defined in terms of (4), personal competence and control, (5), selfacceptance/self-actualisation, and (7), open-mindedness and flexibility, the correlation with religion is negative, religious people do not display high mental health. Definitions (2), (3) and (6), appropriate social behaviour, freedom from worry and guilt, personality unification and organisation, yield only ambiguous relationships between religion and mental health. Thus, being religious can shield people from the most obvious forms of mental disturbance, perhaps because involvement with a religious organisation or group often provides a strong sense of community and identity as well as offering a framework of explicit behavioural boundaries. On the other hand, indicators of what our culture tends to regard as high mental health: personal competence and control; self-acceptance; open-mindedness and flexibility, do not appear to be common among the religious. The implications of this are clear. Whilst it might be useful to employ a range of mental health measures when seeking to determine the relation-ship between religion and mental health—so as to specify the subcategory dynamics between them—on the ultimate issue of whether religion has a role to play in the creation of optimum mental health the evidence suggests a negative answer. There is, however, some evidence that it does have a role. The Timberlawn research on healthy families, as reported by Robin Skynner, found that: ... the most healthy families of all gain great emotional support from some kind of transcendent value system .... Many of these families were committed members of a church or held to one of the traditional religious beliefs. But it didn't have to be that. Sometimes the `transcendent' values were not so much religious as connected with some broader humanitarian cause. What seemed to matter was that their greatest source of value came from something much bigger than themselves, beyond even their family, something which provided a feeling of meaning and purpose which could survive loss and change of all kind. (Skynner & Cleese, 1993, p. 33. emphasis added). If this is the case then religion would seem to offer a way, though only one way, of generating a mental-health-promoting family or group-transcending value system. The fact that non-religious value systems can have similar beneficial results raises some new issues, however. It suggests that research should focus not so much on religion and mental health as value systems and mental health. The crucial issue would then be one of identifying the characteristics of those value systems which exhibited the strongest correlations with optimum mental health rather than whether a commitment to a value system based upon the postulation of a supernatural realm is beneficial or detrimental. The task of identifying and characterising optimum mental health thus moves onto centre stage. In her influential 5 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 study of this issue Marie Jahoda argued that it involves more than an absence of mental illness, more than normality and more than a sense of well-being (Jahoda, 1958, pp. 14, 18, 21). She also provided an account of the constituents of this ‘more’, an account which has received substantial support from subsequent researchers. A mentally healthy person exhibits: ... a positive view of the self, the ability to be happy or contented, the ability to care for and about others, the capacity for productive and creative work, and the ability to grow and achieve within the context of a challenging and sometimes threatening environment. (Taylor, 1989, p. 48) At the present time, however, it is estimated that only about 20% of the population in `developed' countries are mentally healthy in the `above normal' sense and, of these, only 25% exhibit optimum mental health (Skynner & Cleese, 1993, p. 39). That is, the number of optimally mentally healthy people in the developed world is around 5% of the total population. There is thus plenty of scope for improvement. For those involved in mental health promotion the operationalisation of these components has been a significant challenge. L.H. Connolly, a counsellor and teacher of personal development strategies, has responded to this with a formulation of the optimum mental health characteristics which enables her to teach her clients and students how to develop them (Connolly & Connolly, forthcoming). This formulation, I would suggest, offers a useful framework for checking whether a person's value system (including their religious beliefs, if any) is conducive to the cultivation of improvements to their mental health. Her formulation of optimal mental health has six components: (1) high self-esteem; (2) effective communication; (3) adaptability; (4) a sense of meaning and purpose in life; (5) enabling beliefs and thoughts; (6) bodymind awareness. The kernel of selfesteem is the acceptance of oneself as one is, recognising that one is a person of value who shares a common humanity with all other human beings. Being an effective communicator involves having the ability to communicate congruently with people, that is, being able to convey the same message through all channels: body language, voice quality and words, when it is appropriate to do so. It also involves being receptive to feedback from those with whom one is communicating and having the ability to adapt one's behaviour accordingly. Adaptability is coping effectively with expected and unexpected changes in life. In particular, it has to do with how well one copes when things run counter to one's expectations. Sometimes this involves being able to accept things; sometimes it involves `reframing'—attaching meaning to situations that are different from those originally employed to make sense of events. There are two primary facets to having purpose and meaning in life. The first is having goals to aim for, things that motivate one to act; being ‘future orientated’. The second is having a feeling of being part of something bigger than oneself, a community, a noble cause or a religion for example. Enabling thoughts and beliefs are ones which empower oneself and others, thoughts and beliefs which facilitate success—both in terms of creating positive mental and emotional states within oneself and in terms of being effective in the world. Bodymind awareness involves being responsive to messages from your body and recognising that you are your body and your body is you. It also involves knowing how to use your body to change your mental and emotional states. It is worth noting that there is no mention of an accurate perception or conception of reality in this model, nor in the summary of Jahoda's account mentioned earlier. Many psychotherapists, particularly those of psychoanalytic persuasion, have argued that this should be a primary aim of therapy and is a significant indicator of mental health. We may also note that seeing the world as it really is (yathabhutam) lies at the heart of the Buddha's enlightenment experience. Indeed, Jahoda did emphasise this component in her survey and, more recently, so too has Robin Skynner. This probably reflects the influence of his early training in psychodynamic psychotherapy, not least because in the same work where he states that the central idea he cannot repeat too often 6 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 is that `if we can stay in touch with reality, the truth will heal us' (Skynner & Cleese, 1993, p. 334), he offers Japanese social organisation as an example of one way of promoting mental health. Yet, by his own admission, `For the Japanese, reality is negotiable ... because they value cohesion above any other quality, the Japanese are not interested in finding an accurate view of reality; they want a formula that everyone can agree on' (Skynner & Cleese, 1993, p. 208). Reality distortion may, then, have beneficial effects. Recent research confirms this conclusion and points to the need to reject accurate reality testing as a central criterion for mental health. Indeed, the people who seem to have the most accurate understandings of themselves and their situation in the world are depressives (Taylor, 1989, p. 213). The most mentally healthy actually display a positive talent for self-deception, particularly in terms of flattering perceptions of the self, illusions about the extent of their control over their lives and an unrealistic optimism about the future. This is not to say that the healthy fail to perceive things accurately, for they are quite good at perceiving the nature of both physical and social situations. Rather, it is to note that such perceptions are far less salient for them than for depressives. In other words, the healthiest people seem to be able to operate accurate and illusory conceptions of the world in parallel. The reason why this ability helps to promote mental health is, according to John Schumaker, that the generally accurate perception of reality made available to us by our developed cognitive abilities (for example, the recognition of the inevitability of death) can be debilitating. Human beings require, therefore, something to counter-balance the sense of powerlessness, meaninglessness and futility that an accurate understanding of our existence can generate. This something, suggests Schumaker, is our capacity for reality distortion. Religion, in his view, is the traditional method employed by cultures to distort reality in a way that is deemed to be beneficial—by the promotion of meanings and values for example. It succeeds in this because of the brain's capacity for dissociation, the capacity to run different programmes at different times and even in parallel (Schumaker, 1990; 1995). Reality distortion is not, however, always beneficial. Individuals and cultures can create negative illusions almost as easily as they can create positive ones [2]. What is more, illusions seem to be more potent when they are given objective status, when they are taken to be realities. That, I would suggest, is exactly what we find when we examine human conceptions of value, meaning and the sacred. In contrast with the long-standing, dominant tradition of moral objectivism in western ethical philosophy the main thrust of meta-ethical enquiry in the twentieth century has been to establish that moral principles are invented rather than discovered (see Mackie, 1977). Likewise, recent psychological investigations into the attribution of meaning to situations and events suggest that it is constructive rather than perceptual (see Bandler & Grinder, 1982) and Schumaker's most recent work, The Corruption of Reality: a unified theory of religion, hypnosis and psychopathology (1995), presents a strong case for understanding conceptions of the sacred in the same way. From the pragmatic perspective of assessing their contribution to mental health value systems, meaning systems and religious systems would all seem to be on a par. They are often attributed with objective status though there are good reasons for thinking that they are all illusions, constructed by human minds with the aim of benefiting human lives. Whether they do so is a matter for well-constructed empirical enquiries to determine. To paraphrase one well-known religious teacher `By their fruits shall ye know them'. In advance of such enquiries being undertaken my personal strategy for `fruit testing' is to ask of any value, meaning or religious system whether it contributes to the development of the six characteristics of mental health outlined above. By way of conclusion I would like to draw attention to one characteristic of religious systems which makes me doubt their full compatibility with optimum mental health. The fact that the sacred, the transcendental focus or whatever is difficult to access means that 7 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 most people are dependent on religious authorities for their information about it. This means, because the sacred is always deemed to be more important than the profane, that people cannot really trust their own judgements, especially in areas directly affected by or regarded as deriving from the sacred (such as ethics or the social order). Not being able to trust one's own judgement and having to rely on and defer to religious authorities inevitably undermines one's confidence and self-esteem. Whether religions can get around this objection whilst remaining effective reality distorters is something that only the future can reveal. In the end it may be that some kind of benefit trade-off is the best that any of us can hope for. Notes [1] Anthropologist A.F.C. Wallace (1966, p. 52) calls this `the supernatural premise' and argues that it is `religion's defining characteristic'. [2] Taylor (1989, p. 44) argues that the tendency for people to generate positive illusions about themselves, the world and the future derives from the fact that `they are natural, intrinsic to the cognitive system'. If she is correct, the issue arises of how negative illusions get started in the first place. One potentially useful line of speculation might be that which regards them as attempted adaptations to misperceptions of reality. References ALLEN, R.O. & SPILKA, B. (1967) Committed and consensual religion: a specification of religion-prejudice relationships, Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 6, pp. 191–206. ALLPORT, G.W. (1959/60) Religion and prejudice, in: Religion and Social Encounter (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). BANDLER, R. & GRINDER, J. (1982) Reframing: neuro-linguistic programming and the transformation of meaning (Moab, UT, Real People Press). BATSON, C.D. & VENTIS, W.L. (1982) The Religious Experience: a social psychological perspective (New York, Oxford University Press). BATSON, C.D., SCHOENRADE, P. & VENTIS, W.L. (1993) Religion and the Individual: a social-psychological perspective (New York, Oxford University Press). BROWN, L.B. (1964) Classifications of religious orientation, journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 4, pp. 91–99. CAVANAGH, R.R. (1978) Religion as a field of study, in: T.W. HALL (Ed.) Introduction to the Study of Religion (New York, Harper and Row). CONNOLLY, L.H. & CONNOLLY, P. (forthcoming) Happiness and Mental Health (provisional title) (Chichester, Kingsham Press). CORBETT, L. (1996) The Religious Function of the Psyche (London, Routledge). DITTES, J.E. (1971) Typing the typologies: some parallels in the career of church–sect and intrinsic–extrinsic, Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 10, pp. 375–383. HOLM, J. (1977) The Study of Religions (London, Sheldon). HUNT, R.A. & KING, M.B. (1971) The intrinsic–extrinsic concept: a review and evaluation, journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 10, pp. 339–356. JAHODA, M. (1958) Current Concepts of Positive Mental Health (New York, Basic Books). 8 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 KIRKPATRICK, L.A. & HOOD, R.W. Jr. (1990) Intrinsic–extrinsic religious orientation: the boon or bane of contemporary psychology of religion?, Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 29, pp. 442–462. MACKIE, J.L. (1977) Ethics: inventing right and wrong (Harmondsworth, Penguin). SCHUMAKER, J.F. (1990) Wings of Illusion: the origin, nature and future of paranormal belief (Cambridge, Polity Press). SCHUMAKER, J.F. (Ed.) (1992) Religion and Mental Health (New York, Oxford University Press). SCHUMAKER, J.F. (1995) The Corruption of Reality: a unified theory of religion, hypnosis and psychopathology (Amherst, New York, Prometheus). SHARPE, E.J. (1983) Understanding Religion (London, Duckworth). SKYNNER, R. & CLEESE, J. (1993) Life and How to Survive It (London, Methuen). SMART, R.N. (1968) Secular Education and the Logic of Religion (London, Faber & Faber) SMART, R.N. (1969) The Religious Experience of Mankind (New York, Charles Schriber). SMART, R.N. (1983) Worldviews: cross cultural explorations of human beliefs (New York, Schriber). SMART, R.N. (1989) The World’s Religions (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). STRENG, F.J. (1976) Understanding Religious Life 2nd edn (Encino, CA, Dickenson). TAYLOR, S. (1989) Positive Illusions: creative self-deception and the healthy mind (New York, Basic Books). WALLACE, A.F.C. (1966) Religion: an anthropological view (New York, Random House). WULFF, D.M. (1991) Psychology of Religion: classic and contemporary views (New York, John Wiley). Addendum Since this article was published in 1998 my wife and I have formed a company, Turning Point Consulting, and developed our model of mental health into an eightfold scheme, each component of which is learnable and teachable: The Eight Limbs of Human Flourishing: 9 Journal of Beliefs & Values, Vol. 19, No. 2, 1998, pp. 177-187 The 8 Limbs of Human Flourishing 8. Body-Mind Integration 1. Mental & Behavioural Flexibility 2. Self-Belief/ Self-Esteem 7. Effective Intrapersonal Communication 6. Effective Interpersonal Communication 3. Enabling Beliefs/ Positive Thinking 5. Supportive Environment 4. Purpose/ Direction in Life 10