533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 I. Theories of Criminal Punishment A. Utilitarianism - forward looking, focuses on preventing harm; 1. Deterrence a. general - punishing this ∆ deters others b. specific - punishing this ∆ to deter this ∆. 2. Incapacitation - protect society by separating the criminal either by incarceration or stigmatization. 3. Rehabilitation - “cure” the ∆ to prevent future crimes. B. Retributivism 1. retribution - punish ∆ because he “deserves” it. a. assaultive (lex talionis) - “eye for an eye” b. protective - respect the ∆’s free will and punish him to pay his “debt to society” so that he can be reinstated to society’s protection and benefits. 2. denunciation - punishment expresses society’s disapproval. C. Principle of Legality 1. no crime without law; law must exist before the conduct occurs. a. criminal statute should be understandable to provide fair warning 1) rule of lenity - ambiguities go in ∆’s favor 2) encourages legislature to write statutes more clearly preventing too powerful state. b. some jurisdictions follow legislative intent/purpose to broaden statute beyond explicit language if needed. D. Doctrine of Proportionality - punishment should fit the crime. II. Actus Reus (Voluntary Act that results in a Social Harm) Requirement A. The following are not voluntary acts: 1. reflex or convulsion a. counter-ex: in Decina, the actus reus was defined as driving the car while knowing that an epileptic fit was likely, not the epileptic fit itself. (time-framing) 2. bodily movement during unconsciousness or sleep, a. sleepwalking is involuntary b. automatism - the person is acting automatically without any consciousness of his actions (different from mens rea). 1) ex: Newton - black man lost conscious control of his body and shot police officer reflexively. c. hypnotism and multiple personality disorder are probably not relevant because they are too hard to understand and too easy to claim. 3. movement not the product of the effort or determination of the actor. a. ex: being “bumped” by someone else. Roger W. Martin 1 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 b. ex: police dragging a drunk man from his home and then citing him for public drunkenness. B. Omissions are only criminal if: 1. the actor was under a legal duty (not just moral duty) to act either by: a. express statute; 1) ex: driver involved in accident required to stop at the scene. b. contract 1) ex: Pestinakis - oral contract to provide medical care to elderly man was breached, causing elderly man to die of starvation and exposure. c. special relationship 1) ex: mother who allows children to remain with abusive father. d. creation of the risk which led to the harm or materially increased it. e. volunteer and take away other options for help (also Pestinakis). 2. the person was physically able to perform the required act. C. “Possession” as the actus reus requires that the actor have been aware of his control of the object for a sufficient time to have been able to terminate his possession. D. The voluntary act must result in a “social harm” 1. Social harm is the “negation, endangering, or destruction of an individual, group or state interest which was deemed socially valuable.” 2. Sub-elements of the social harm: a. “conduct” crimes - no harmful result is required 1) ex: driving under the influence of alcohol b. “result” crimes - defined in terms of the prohibited result 1) ex: the killing of another human being (murder) c. attendant circumstances - must be present for crime to occur 1) ex: gun used for murder must be loaded - not part of the crime. 2) ex: burglary must occur at night - night is part of the crime definition. III. Mens Rea (mental state) A. Model Penal Code § 2.02 mental states: 1. Purposely a. result or conduct crimes - “conscious object” to engage in the conduct or cause the result. 1) ex: ∆ explodes a bomb in an airplane to kill his wife. ∆ purposely killed his wife. Roger W. Martin 2 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 b. attendant circumstances - “aware of the existence of such circumstances or believes or hopes they exist.” 1) ex: ∆ breaks and enters a house he is aware is a dwelling house at night when he can see it is dark outside. ∆ purposely acted with respect to the attendant circumstance of dwelling house and nighttime. 2. Knowingly a. result crimes - “aware or practically certain” that his conduct will cause the result. 1) ex: ∆ explodes a bomb in an airplane to kill his wife, and other passengers die as well ∆ knowingly killed the other passengers. b. attendant circumstances and conduct crimes - “aware that his conduct is of that nature or that such attendant circumstances exist.” 1) ex: ∆ fires a loaded gun in V’s direction, aware that V was in the target area. ∆ knowingly endangered the life of V. 2) ex: ∆ is given property which he is aware is stolen. ∆ knowingly received stolen property. a). “willful blindness” is avoided by expanding definition of knowingly to include “aware of a high probability” of the existence of an attendant circumstance, “unless he actually believes that it does not exist.” - ex: Jewell smuggling drugs but not looking in compartment. 3. Recklessly a. “conscious disregard of a substantial and unjustifiable risk” of a social harm. 1) “law-abiding person” standard 2) ex: ∆ bombs a car to kill a passenger, and knows that pedestrians walking by might also get killed, but doesn’t care. ∆ recklessly killed the pedestrians. 4. Negligently a. actor “should be aware of a substantial or unjustifiable risk” of a social harm. 1) reasonable person standard 2) ex: ∆ bombs plane to kill wife, plane crashes and kills people on the ground, even though ∆ was unaware that the plane would kill others on the ground when it crashed. ∆ negligently killed the people on the ground. b. only criminal when expressly provided for in the statute. B. If the statute does not specify which sub-elements require culpability, then all material elements require culpability. Roger W. Martin 3 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 1. ex: to be guilty of “causing an injury to a police officer,” a person would have to be culpable with respect to causing the injury, as well as knowing that the victim was a police officer. 2. material elements are those which go to the criminality or wrongfulness of the conduct, not the mere procedural elements. C. If the statute does not specify a mental state, then any mental state (purposely, knowingly, recklessly) except negligence will suffice. IV. Strict Liability Crimes (no mens rea requirement) A. Five factors may overcome the presumption against strict liability: 1. the statutory crime is not derived from common law crimes a. ex: speeding on the highway b. ex: Morrisette was not convicted of stealing government property because he lacked the mens rea for common-law larceny. 2. clear legislative policy would be undermined by a mens rea requirement for the crime a. ex: many people litter accidentally, but accidental littering is as ugly as intentional littering. b. ex: public welfare offense such as dumping sewage is so serious that the damage done by a single incident requires ignoring the mens rea - Weitzenhoff. 3. the standard imposed would properly be expected of reasonable person 4. the penalty is small a. ex: fine of $50 for expired parking meter. b. counter-ex: selling alcohol to a minor can result in a long prison sentence. 5. the conviction does not carry a large stigma a. ex: many people get speeding tickets. b. counter-ex: statutory rape carries a large stigma. B. Lady Wooten’s Proposal - dispense with the mens rea for all crimes, and only take culpability into account at sentencing. 1. Pro: utilitarian motive to deter all crimes, not just those that are where the actor is morally culpable. 2. Con: too much intrusion into our lives by police, waste of resources. V. Causation (part of the actus reus in a result crime). A. Actual cause - determines candidates for responsibility 1. “but for” test - “but for D’s voluntary act (or omission) would the social harm have occurred when it did?” If not, D is an actual cause. a. ex: D1 takes aim at V. Before he shoots, D2 shoots V, killing V instantly. D2 is an actual cause of V’s death, but D1 is not an actual cause of V’s death because V’s death would have occurred when it did anyway. Roger W. Martin 4 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 2. multiple actual causes a. accelerating a result - normal application of “but for” time frame (“when it did”) 1) ex: both D1 and D2 shoot V simultaneously in the stomach. Either shot would have killed V in 1 hour, but the combination causes V to die in 5 minutes. Both D1 and D2 are actual causes because V would not have died when he did but for both shots. b. concurrent sufficient causes - modified “but for” to include “as it did.” 1) ex: D1 and D2 simultaneously shoot V in the head, killing him instantly. Either shot would have been sufficient to kill him instantly. Both D1 and D2 are actual causes because V would not have died as he did (from 2 shots to the head) but for both shots. c. obstructed cause - normal application of “but for” time frame (“when it did”) 1) ex: D1 shoots V in the stomach (which would kill him in 1 hour). A second later, V is struck in the head by a bullet shot by D2, which kills him instantly. D1 is not an actual cause of V’s death because D2’s shot would have killed him instantly regardless of D1’s shot. B. Proximate Cause - public policy determination of liability from among actual causes. 1. Direct cause - no event of causal significance intervened between D’s conduct and the social harm. a. a direct cause is always a proximate cause. 2. Intervening causes - an independent force that operates in producing the social harm after D’s voluntary act must be foreseeable. a. responsive (dependent) intervening cause - occurs in reaction or response to ∆’s prior wrongful conduct - ∆ is liable unless response was “highly abnormal or bizarre” because responsive intervening causes are foreseeable by nature. 1) ex: D lethally wounds V. At the hospital, V receives negligent medical care, and then dies. D is still a proximate cause because negligent medical care is not “highly abnormal or bizarre.” b. coincidental (independent) intervening cause - does not occur in reaction or response to ∆’s prior wrongful conduct - ∆ is liable if the coincidence was foreseeable. 1) ex: In Kibbe, it was foreseeable that the drunk robbery victim would be hit by a car if left on the highway, even Roger W. Martin 5 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 though the driver of the car was acting independently of the robbers. 3. Special Factors - justify a different conclusion than the normal intervening cause doctrine. a. must not be de minimis 1) ex: D non-lethally wounds V who is struck by lightning and killed on the way to the hospital. D is an actual cause, but not a proximate cause due to his de minimis contribution to the death. b. intended consequences doctrine - allows many intervening causes if the intended result of the wrongdoer actually happens in an unforeseeable way. 1) ex: mother wishing to poison baby leaves poisoned “medicine” bottle with nursemaid who puts in on the shelf, thinking the “medicine” unnecessary. Later, another child finds it and feeds it to the baby. Mother is proximate cause of the intended poisoning of the baby. c. apparent safety doctrine - ∆’s force came to rest with victim in position of apparent safety. 1) ex: husband beats wife who runs to parents house and freezes to death on the porch because of embarrassment. Husband is not proximate cause. d. voluntary human intervention - a willful act by another human intervenes and causes the harm 1) ex: at the end of the drag race, one of the participants, of his own volition, decides to keep going and eventually crashes. Other drag racer is not proximate cause. e. omissions - rarely serves as a superseding intervening cause. 1) ex: D drunk drives a car in which P is a passenger, resulting in a crash which kills P. Even though P failed to wear his seatbelt, D is proximate cause. VI. Concurrence (Actus reus and mens rea must concur) A. Temporal concurrence 1. the social harm can occur after the mens rea, but the actus reus must occur at the time of the mens rea. a. ex: D shoots V, but later regrets it before V dies several weeks later from the wounds. D is still liable for murder. B. Motivational concurrence 1. the social harm can occur at the same time as the mens rea, but the mens rea has to be the motivation for the actus reus. a. ex: D intends to kill V by shooting him. On his way to V’s house, V steps in front of D’s car and is accidentally killed. D is not guilty Roger W. Martin 6 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 of murder because the mens rea was not the motivation for the actus reus (failure to stop in time). VII. Murder (criminal homicide) A. Murder and Manslaughter definitions 1. The Common-law definition of murder is “the killing of a human being ...with malice aforethought.” a. intent to kill another human being (express or implied) 1). The natural and probable consequences rule: intent-to-kill can be implied by a showing that the death was the natural and probable consequence of the ∆s action. 2). The deadly weapon rule: the intentional use of a deadly weapon allows a jury to properly infer that intent to kill was present. b. intent to inflict grievous bodily harm 1) normally results in second-degree murder. c. extremely recklessness plus extreme disregard for human life (depraved heart murder) 1) ex: playing Russian poker in Malone. 2) ex: firing a gun in a crowded bar in Register, even if the ∆ was drunk. 3) ex: consciously disregarding the known danger of killing others when driving drunk in Whitfield. d. intent to commit a felony during which a death results (felony murder rule). 1) common-law version substitutes for malice, but is narrowly construed to “inherently dangerous” felonies “high probability that a death will result.” 2) degree-fixing version substitutes for premeditation (to elevate to first degree) during “enumerated felonies” but not malice which is still required for murder. See Aaron. 3) felony may “merge” with the homicide if it is an “integral part,” preventing FMR from substituting for malice, otherwise all manslaughters would be murder because manslaughter is a felony. See Smith (felony child abuse as “integral part” of homicide precludes implied malice from felony). 4) does not apply in agency state when the a third party who is not a co-felon kills one of the co-felons. ex: shopowner kills co-felon in Canola. Exception - human shield. 5) gun-fight exception: does apply in proximate cause state when one of the victims shoots one of the other victims in a Roger W. Martin 7 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 gun fight. See Dowden (police officer kills police captain during heated gun battle, thinking it to be the felon). 2. Manslaughter is without malice aforethought. a. Voluntary manslaughter can be 1) adequate provocation - failure of proof defense which negates intent to kill a) ∆ acted in “heat of passion” - “violent, intense emotion.” b) ∆’s heat of passion was the result of adequate provocation - causation and adequacy are questions of fact for the jury c) ∆ did not “cool off” d) reasonable person would not have “cooled off.” slightly subjective standard taking into account some of the killer’s characteristics. e) ex: finding a spouse immediately before, during or after the act of adultery. 2) imperfect self-defense 3) diminished capacity b. Involuntary manslaughter can be 1) an unintentional killing that is the result of gross (criminal) negligence/recklessness (not “extreme” recklessness for depraved heart murder). A “gross deviation from the standard of care that reasonable people would exercise in the same situation.” a) objective reasonable person standard: Ex: failure to provide adequate fire safety in a public dance hall in Welansky; failure to take extremely ill baby to doctor in Williams. b. difference between gross recklessness and depraved heart murder is that depraved heart murderer consciously disregarded the risk. 2) Misdemeanor manslaughter is a killing that occurs during the commission or attempted commission of an unlawful act which is not a dangerous felony. a) limited to “inherently dangerous” misdemeanors b) risk of death must be foreseeable c) proximate cause of death must be the violation d) crime must be mala in se (not strict liability) e) Counter-ex: petty theft victim has heart attack as a result of chasing thief in Todd. B. Degrees of murder 1. First degree murder is: Roger W. Martin 8 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 a. by poison or lying in wait b. by willful and deliberate premeditation 1) Willful means “a specific intent to kill.” 2) Deliberate means “to measure and evaluate the major facets of a choice or problem.” 3) Premeditated means “to think about beforehand.” In most jurisdictions, this requires “some appreciable time,” so that the ∆ could give the matter “at least a second thought.” See Ollens (multiple stab wounds from behind show premeditation); But see Bingham (time alone is not evidence of premeditation) c. during the commission or attempted commission of an “enumerated felony.” 2. second-degree murder is all other murders that do not fall into one of the three categories above. a. a first degree murder is not mitigated to second degree solely because of motive. See Gilbert (first degree premeditated murder is not mitigated because motive was “love for dying spouse.”) VIII. Defenses A. Defenses Generally 1. Failure of Proof defenses - ∆ introduces evidence at his trial that demonstrates that the prosecution has failed to prove an essential element of the offense charged. ∆ did not commit the crime. a. Ex: ∆ thought that he fired his gun at a tree stump, not a human (mistake of fact-lacked mens rea). b. Ex: ∆ was unconscious (automatism-lacked actus reus). c. Prosecution retains the burden of proof (production and persuasion) to disprove the ∆’s failure of proof defense. 1. “True” defenses - if proved, results in the acquittal of the ∆, even though the prosecution has proved every element of the offense. ∆ committed the crime, but should be acquitted. a. Justification defenses - ∆ acted the “right” way, even though he committed a crime. 1). focuses on the act not the actor. 2). Ex: self-defense homicide. b. Excuse defenses - although the ∆ committed the crime, he should not be punished because he was not morally culpable. 1). focuses on the actor, not the act. 2). Ex: insanity B. Duress and Coercion 1. Five elements must be satisfied: Roger W. Martin 9 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 a. another person threatened to kill or grievously injure the ∆ or a close relative; 1). ex: a burglary to avoid a lightning storm or a rabid dog would not qualify for “duress”, but may qualify for “necessity.” 2). must be a threat of deadly force, not just property damage or economic coercion. b. the ∆ reasonably believed that the threat was genuine; c. the threat was “present, imminent, and impending” at the time of the criminal act; 1). “present” means that the ∆ be aware of the threat in his own mind at the time. 2). “imminent” usually requires that the threat be able to harm the ∆ at the very time that he is committing the act, not after if there is time to escape. d. there was no reasonable escape from the threat except through compliance; and e. the ∆ was not at fault in exposing himself to the threat. 2. Duress is normally treated as an excuse, not a justification. a. Utilitarian rationale for the excuse is that deterrence is ineffective when a person is truly under duress. b. Retributivist rationale is that the ∆ does not deserve to be punished. 3. Duress is not a defense to murder, although some states allow it as a defense to the felony murder rule. a. ex: In Hunter, hitchhiker who was threatened into accompanying felons was not held liable under FMR for a murder by one of the felons. 4. Duress differs from necessity in two ways: a. necessity justifies the ∆’s crime by stating it was the lesser of two evils; duress excuses the ∆’s crime even though it may have been a greater evil. b. in necessity, no social harm has occurred, so no person can be prosecuted; in duress, a social harm has occurred, and the coercer is liable for the harm. C. Necessity 1. As a result of some force or condition, the ∆ must choose between violating a relatively minor offense or suffering (or allowing others to suffer) substantial harm to person or property. 2. Requirements a. The actor must be faced with a “clear and imminent danger.” b. ∆ must reasonably expect that his action will be effective in abating the danger that he seeks to avoid. Roger W. Martin 10 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 c. there must be no effective legal alternative available. d. the harm caused must be foreseeably less than the harm avoided. e. legislature must not have anticipated the dilemma and previously resolved it against the choice made by ∆. f. ∆ must not be at fault in wrongfully placing himself in the position where he was forced to engage in criminal conduct. 3. Three limitations may apply: a. some states limit the necessity defense to emergencies created by natural (not human) forces. b. may not apply in homicide cases (Dudley & Stephens lifeboat case) 1). homicide is a case of equal harms, ∆’s life or an innocent life. 2). might be overcome if the harm was sufficiently imminent and the harm avoided was the death of both the ∆ and the innocent. c. the ∆ may not act to protect his reputation or economic interests, only persons or property. 4. Civil Disobedience - necessity can never be a defense. D. Self-Defense 1. At common-law a person who is not an aggressor is justified in using force upon another if he actually (subjectively) and reasonably (objectively) believes that such force is necessary to protect himself from imminent use of unlawful force by the other person. a. “necessity” requires that the force should not be used against another person unless, and only to the extent that it is necessary. b. “proportionality” requires that the person is not justified in using force that is excessive in relation to the harm threatened. c. some courts use a “subjectivized objective” standard taking into account subjective traits of person in determining reasonableness. 1) Ex: In Wanrow, elderly woman shot large man suspected of molesting her child when he came toward her. Jury allowed to consider size, age, and sex of ∆ to determine reasonableness. 2) Counter-ex: In Simon, elderly man shot Asian man thinking he was martial art expert. Jury not allowed to consider racism of ∆ in reasonableness finding - “normative” standard not “popular” standard. d. “imminent” can have two meanings: 1) “immediate” - temporally strict, narrow. 2) “imminent” - forthcoming in view of past events 2. Aggressor/Non-aggressor limitations Roger W. Martin 11 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 a. An “Aggressor” is a person whose “affirmative unlawful act is reasonably calculated to produce an affray foreboding injurious or fatal consequences.” 1). ex: if D unlawfully brandishes a knife and threatens to kill V, D cannot claim self-defense if V responds with violence. 2). a person is an aggressor even if he merely starts a non-deadly conflict. 3). a person is not an aggressor if his conduct is lawful. b. A deadly aggressor is a person whose actions are reasonably calculated to produce fatal results. 1). a deadly aggressor may only claim self-defense if he has withdrawn and successfully communicated to the victim that he is no longer a threat. 2). a non-deadly aggressor usually can assert self-defense if the response to his non-deadly aggression is deadly force, but some jurisdictions require even a non-deadly aggressor to retreat before regaining a right of self-defense. 3. Retreat a. most jurisdictions allow a non-aggressor to stand his ground and assert self-defense even if there are alternatives available to retreat to complete safety. 1). policy is that it would unduly put victims at the mercy of assailants because there could be few real self-defense cases. b. Some jurisdictions require the victim to retreat if there is a place of complete safety, unless he is in his own home (“castle” exception). a. policy is to place the value of human life over the “manly” right to stand up to aggression. b. issue is whether the ∆ was aware of escape to complete safety given the excitement of the situation. 4. Battered Woman’s syndrome a. history of abuse evidence is relevant to determining whether woman had actual (subjective) belief that the threat was imminent. b. however, states are split as to whether evidence of battered woman’s syndrome is relevant to the determination of the reasonableness (objective) of her belief. 1) ex: In Stewart, wife killed abusive husband while asleep, court said escape was available, so belief of imminent harm was unreasonable. c. battered child syndrome has not gained recognition yet. Roger W. Martin 12 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 1) ex: In Jahnke, abused son ambushed father. Held: evidence of battered-child syndrome not admissible if danger was not imminent. 5. “Imperfect self-defense” - if belief was actual but not reasonable, then murder is mitigated to manslaughter because ∆ did not have actual malice. E. Crime Prevention/Law Enforcement 1. Non-Deadly Force - may be used to prevent crime or make arrest if the ∆ reasonably believes: a. a felony or breach of the peace has been committed; and b. the force used is necessary. 2. Deadly Force -never permissible to prevent a misdemeanor, or arrest a misdemeanor suspect. a. Police officer must reasonably believe: 1) felony has been committed; and 2) deadly force is necessary 3) Tennessee v. Garner requires probable cause that the suspect poses a significant threat of death or serious bodily injury to the officer or others, and requires a warning shot if feasible. b. Private Citizen must be actually correct that: 1) a forcible felony has in fact been committed; 2) deadly force is necessary; 3) a warning is given. 4) Although Tenn. v. Garner applies to gov’t only, some courts make it applicable to citizens who “step into the shoes” of the police. Ex: Couch ∆ shot unarmed car stereo thief as he fled. F. Consent 1. Only a defense in sporting events, not aggravated battery. 2. ex: Samuels - sadistic ∆ filming a whipping of a “consenting” masochist. G. Property defenses 1. Deadly force is never permitted in the protection of property. a. spring guns are illegal because they are indiscriminate 1) ex: in Ceballos, ∆ liable for spring gun to protect garage full of property from unarmed teenage thieves. 2) exception - if ∆ would have been justified in using deadly force had he been present (self-defense in dwelling place). 2. Courts are split as to whether threats of deadly force are permissible. 3. Non-Deadly force is permissible if ∆ reasonably believes: a. force is necessary to prevent an imminent and unlawful dispossession; and b. ∆ first requests that attacker desist (mandamus) if possible. Roger W. Martin 13 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 c. recapture of property only if promptly after dispossession. H. Defense of Habitation 1. Three approaches: ∆ is justified in using deadly force in defense of habitation if he reasonably believes: a. V intends to imminently and unlawfully enter; AND b. commit a forcible felony or kill or seriously injure an occupant (narrowest approach); OR c. commit a felony or cause injury to an occupant (middle approach); OR d. V simply intends to enter (broadest approach); AND e. deadly force is necessary to prevent the intrusion. I. Intoxication 1. Voluntary intoxication is generally no defense for criminal conduct, with two narrow exceptions: a. ∆ did not harbor the specific-intent mens rea required, or b. ∆ suffered from long-term, intoxication-induced, “fixed” insanity. 2. Mens Rea a. General-Intent offenses 1). voluntary intoxication is not a defense to general intent crimes. 2). self-induced intoxication typically constitutes reckless conduct (i.e. ∆ should know that he is jeopardizing others by becoming drunk.) 3) although alcohol lowers inhibitions, it does not affect simple goal-directed behavior. b. Specific Intent offenses - (murder, assault with intent to rape, burglary.) 1). voluntary intoxication is a defense. 2). since the state has included a particular state of mind as a material element of the crime, intoxication is relevant to determining whether the ∆ had the specific state of mind at the time he committed the crime. 3) ex: In Hood, evidence of intoxication was allowable to defeat specific intent crime of murder. c. The distinction between general and specific intent crimes creates the anomaly that a ∆ can use intoxication as a defense if he is thwarted just prior to completing the specific intent crime, but not if he has already completed it. 3. “fixed” insanity caused by long-term alcohol abuse is a defense, but not “temporary” insanity caused by a single episode of drinking. Roger W. Martin 14 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 1) ex: alcoholic can not claim act was involuntary because the process of becoming an alcoholic was voluntary - habits are volitional. 4. Involuntary intoxication a. coerced intoxication - ex: drink or we’ll kill you. 1) probably must be a threat of physical harm. b. intoxication by innocent mistake - ex: eat this (cocaine), it’s a “breath freshener” 1) ex: accidentally drinking spiked punch at a party without reasonable notice 2) counter-ex: PCP intoxication from unwittingly smoking a PCP-laced marijuana cigarette is not innocent mistake because street drugs have no warranty. c. unexpected intoxication from a prescribed medication 1) as long as you didn’t overdose; and 2) you didn’t know of your susceptibility d. “pathological intoxication” - temporary biological reaction in a person who has an unknown predisposing mental condition such as epilepsy. e. does not always lead to automatic acquittal 1) an involuntary intoxicated person can claim all of the defenses that the voluntary intoxicated person can (i.e. negate specific intent, claim fixed insanity) plus he can also claim temporary insanity. 2) not a defense to a strict liability crime because there is no mens rea. J. Mistakes of Fact 1. Not a “true defense”, only a “failure of proof defense.” 2. Mistake is a defense to a specific intent crime because it negates the particular element of mens rea in the crime (elemental approach). a. it does not matter if the mistake was reasonable or unreasonable as long as it was actual; and b. the act was not morally wrong (moral wrong doctrine) or legally wrong (legal wrong doctrine) had the facts been as the ∆ believed them to be. 3. Mistake is only a defense to general intent crime under circumstances that negate his moral culpability (culpability approach). a. mistake must have been reasonable; and b. the act was not morally wrong (moral wrong doctrine) or legally wrong (legal wrong doctrine) had the facts been as the ∆ believed them to be. 4. Mistake is not a defense in strict liability offenses. Roger W. Martin 15 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 a. ex: In Garnett, retarded man was guilty of statutory rape even if his mistake was reasonable. K. Mistake of Law 1. In general, “ignorance of the law is not an excuse,” meaning that it does not generally negate the mens rea of the offense, because ordinarily, knowledge that the crime exists is not an element of the crime itself. a. utilitarian policy: prevents bogus defenses and subjective arguments as to the meaning of the law to each individual defendant - sacrifice the individual for the common good. b. however, to punish under honest mistake of law is contrary to the retributivist notion of moral blameworthiness. 2. Three general exceptions: a. reasonable-reliance doctrine 1). “personal interpretation” is not an excuse, even if it was reasonable. 2). however, “official interpretation”, i.e. the reliance on an official statement of the law, which later turns out to be erroneous, is a defense a) statutes declared to be invalid; b) overturned judicial decisions by highest court in the jurisdiction; or c) erroneous interpretations by authorized public officials, but not informal interpretations by lesser officials or poor advice of counsel. b. Fair notice: the Lambert principle - may be a due process excuse if: 1). the crime punishes an omission (ex: failure to register); 2). the duty to act was based on status rather than activity (ex: presence in Los Angeles); and 3). the act was malum prohibitum c. Negation of Mens Rea (“different law” mistake) - ∆ claims that she lacked the requisite mens rea for the violation charged because she mistakenly believed that a different law (or lack thereof) made her actions legal. 1). Specific Intent Crimes - valid defense (for the same reasons as mistake of fact - failure of proof) even if belief was unreasonable. a) ex: man “repossesses” his car from a mechanic not knowing about the lien law. 2). General Intent Crimes - apparently no defense (in contrast to mistake of fact). a) ex: woman charged with possession of a firearm by a convicted felon claims that she did not know she Roger W. Martin 16 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 was a convicted felon (mistaken about nature of prior conviction) - no defense. 3). Strict Liability Offenses - no defense. a) ex: man charged with bigamy claims that he thought his first wife’s divorce was legal when he married second wife. -no defense. K. Insanity- affirmative defense, does not negate mens rea, it provides an excuse. 1. Rationale for the defense: a. Utilitarian rationale 1). no specific deterrence of insane person because they can not see cause and effect relationship between their actions and the punishment. 2). insanity results in civil commitment, separating ∆ from society, so there is no need to stigmatize them to achieve the separation. 3). rehabilitation of insane ∆ is not possible in a prison. b. Retributivist rationale 1). insane person lacks “free will” capacity to make correct choices. 2). without “free will” there can be no moral blame. 2. Competency to stand trial -question of law a. a person may not be tried or sentenced if, during the criminal proceedings, she: 1). lacks the capacity to consult with her attorney “with a reasonable degree of rational understanding”; or 2). lacks a “rational as well as factual understanding of the proceedings” against her. b. a finding of incompetency results in the commitment to a mental facility for “a reasonable period of time necessary to determine whether there is a substantial probability that she will attain capacity [to stand trial] in the near future.” 3. Four possible verdicts: a. not guilty b. not guilty by reason of insanity 1). automatic commitment - no hearing to determine if ∆ is still mentally ill and dangerous - conviction; 2). discretionary commitment - judge has authority to order mental evaluation to determine illness and dangerousness. c. guilty d. (optional) guilty but mentally ill. a. ∆ receives normal sentence, but psychiatric care is made available in the prison setting or a mental institution. 4. Bifurcated trials separate the trial into two phases: Roger W. Martin 17 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 a. all aspects of the case except the ∆’s insanity are litigated; and b. then the sole issue of ∆’s insanity is litigated. c. saves time, confusion, decreases compromise, self-incrimination. 5. Burden of Proof a. burden of initial production of evidence is on ∆ (affirmative defense); b. burden of persuasion usually on ∆ a. some states require preponderance of evidence; b. other states require clear and convincing evidence. 6. Five tests for determining legal insanity: a. The M’Naghten test - focuses exclusively on cognitive disability (not volitional disability); very narrow. ∆ is NGBRI if, at the time of the act, due to defect of reason from disease of mind: 1). actor did not “know” the “nature and quality” of the act (∆ thought she was squeezing a lemon, not a person’s neck); OR 2). actor did not “know” that what she was doing was “wrong” (∆ didn’t know squeezing necks is wrong). 3). the word “know” is ambiguous a) some courts require only “formal” knowledge that the ∆ could describe what she was doing and knew that it was forbidden. -ex: In Freeman, drug wacko insisted drug sale occur in restroom. b) other courts require “affective” knowledge requiring that the ∆ could evaluate the impact of her actions. 4). “wrong” could mean legal or moral wrong a) Ex: if ∆ thought God told her to kill, and ∆ knew that murder was illegal, she would be sane if “wrong” meant “legal wrong,” but insane if “wrong” meant “moral wrong.” b) Exception in legal wrong states is “deific decree” insane even if you knew it was illegal. ex: In Serravo, man thought God wanted him to stab his wife. c) “moral” wrong is alternatively defined by a “subjective” standard (∆ did not think it was wrong) or an “objective” societal standard (∆ did not think that society thought it was wrong). b. “Irresistible Impulse” Test - arose due to lack of volitional prong of M’Naghten. 1). ∆ “acted from an irresistible and uncontrollable impulse”; 2). ∆ “lost the power to choose between right and wrong”; Roger W. Martin 18 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 3). ∆’s “free will has been destroyed” so that her actions are beyond her control. 4). Both “irresistible” and “impulse” may be narrow in that they do not account for degrees of insanity. c. ALI (Model Penal Code) Test 1). ∆ “lacked substantial capacity” to “appreciate the criminality (or wrongfulness) of her conduct; or 2). was “unable to conform her conduct to the requirements of the law.” 3). A revised version of the M’Naghten test, substituting “know” with “appreciate,” and irresistible impulse test, avoiding the word “impulse.” d. The Product (Durham) Test 1). person is excused if her unlawful act was “the product of a mental disease or defect.” 2). requires a determination of: a) whether the ∆ was suffering from a mental disease; and b) whether the crime would have occurred “but for” the mental disease. 3). provides no definition of “mental disease.” e. Federal Test 1). Statutory definition of legal insanity - ∆ must prove by clear and convincing evidence that as a result of a “severe” mental disease or defect she was unable to “appreciate”: a) the nature and quality of her conduct; or b) the wrongfulness of her conduct. I. Diminished Capacity A. Two categories: 1. “mens rea” form - negates the mens rea. An abnormal mental condition not amounting to insanity. a. failure of proof defense, not a true defense. b. may result in acquittal if the state allows it as a defense 1) model penal code allows evidence that the ∆ suffered from a mental disease to be admissible in any type of case where it is relevant. 2) some states limit its applicability to murder only. 3) some states allow it only as a defense to specific intent crimes. 4) some states refuse it as a defense altogether. c. arguments against: 1) it is not needed because insanity is easier to prove than the failure to form a simple intent. Roger W. Martin 19 533560746 Printed: 2/16/2016 2) it is too imprecise because it is really “partially insane” defense. 3) could result in acquittal, putting a dangerous person on the street. 2. “partial responsibility” - California approach. a. by making a strict definition of the mens rea, the court can state that the person was guilty only of a lesser offense, but it really is saying that the person was less culpable although not legally insane. b. abandoned by modern courts. Roger W. Martin 20