The Art of Argumentation Course Notes Meeting 4. The limits of logic. Formal logic has a number of weaknesses. The basic principle of deductive argument is that there can never be a situation where the premises are true and the conclusion false. This leads, however, to many problems. Tom is crazy, Tom is not crazy; therefore he can't be trusted. or worse: Tom is crazy, Tom is not crazy; therefore my car won't start. Obviously, A & ¬A is always false, therefore we can say A & ¬A⊢ B since the premise will never be true. My car will start; therefore, Tom is crazy or Tom is not crazy. My car will start, your car is green, bats can fly; therefore an apple is an apple. Here, since the conclusion can never be false, because it is a logical truth, any set of premises will lead to it. Even though the premises are clearly irrelevant. The basic principle can be changed to: the conclusion will always be true if the premises are, which eliminates the first problem. Another issue: Suppose By simplification By addition By simplification Disjunctive syllogism A & ¬A A AvB ¬A B Tommy is a cat and tommy is not a cat. Tommy is a cat Tommy is a cat or a dog Tommy is not a cat Tommy is a dog Does A v B really mean ¬A→B? These problems are caused by the relationship of formal logic to natural language which can be an awkward one. 'Therefore' in natural language suggests that the premise is somehow responsible for the conclusion, not just that the conclusion is true. Similarly, 'or' suggests a lack of knowledge over which is correct and cannot be used when we know one to be correct. What works logically does not always work linguistically - and we are studying language! The other big problem is that deductive reasoning does not cover all, or perhaps even many, cases of real world decision making. Informal logic: inductive, abductive and presumptive reasoning. Informal logic is the study of real-world argumentation. The types of argument which should be allowed are controversial. For example, John Locke wrote: Appeals that are valid because epistemologically superior: Appeal to Evidence (Induction), Appeal to Reason (Deduction) Appeals that are invalid because epistemologically inferior: Appeal to the Speaker’s Authority, Appeal to the Audience’s Ignorance But in his own arguments: Appeals that are dialectically superior because they do not interrupt the rational and dialogic search for truth : Appeal to an Opponent’s Premises and Conclusions (Argument-from Commitment and Personal-Attack Varieties), Appeal to Evidence (Induction), Appeal to Reason (Deduction) Appeals that are dialectically inferior because they do interrupt the rational and dialogic search for truth: Appeal to Guilt-by-Association, Appeal to the Speaker’s Authority, Appeal to the Audience’s Ignorance (Longaker 2014) Some definitions 'In a deductively valid inference, it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. In an inductively strong inference, it is improbable (to some degree) that the conclusion is false given that the premises are true. In an abductively weighty inference, it is implausible that the premises are true and the conclusion is false. The abductive type of inference tends to be the weakest of the three kinds. A conclusion drawn by abductive inference is an intelligent guess. But it is still a guess, because it is tied to an incomplete body of evidence. As new evidence comes in, the guess could be shown to be wrong.' (Walton, 2001) Deductive Reasoning: Suppose a bag contains only red marbles, and you take one out. You may infer by deductive reasoning that the marble is red. Inductive Reasoning: Suppose you do not know the color of the marbles in the bag, and you take one out and it is red. You may infer by inductive reasoning that all the marbles in the bag are red. Abductive Reasoning: Suppose you find a red marble in the vicinity of a bag of red marbles. You may infer by abductive reasoning that the marble is from the bag. (Preyer and Mans, 1999) Another example: Fossils are found; say, remains like those of fishes, but far in the interior of the country. To explain the phenomenon, we suppose the sea once washed over this land. This is an hypothesis. (Pierce 1965) Presumptive reasoning: A presumption then is something you move ahead with, for practical purposes, even though it is not known to be true at the present time. It is a kind of useful assumption that can be justified on practical grounds, in order to take action, for example, even though the evidence to support it may be insufficient or inconclusive (Walton 2001). How can we keep control of informal argumentation? How can we know if an informal - not logically necessary - argument is a good one or not? Aren't non-deductive arguments fallacious? Argument schemes: There are many different kinds of arguments that are best evaluated by standards that are neither deductive nor inductive. These types of argumentation are often equated with traditional informal fallacies. However, in many cases of their use, they are not fallacious. In such cases, if seen as presumptive arguments, they do have some weight as rational arguments that could be used to support a claim. Some of the best known examples are argument from analogy, ad hominem argument [attacking the man], argument from ignorance [we have no evidence otherwise], argument from sign [one thing indicates another], argument from consequences [the truth will have desireable consequences], appeal to popular opinion, appeal to pity, and appeal to expert opinion. Each of these types of argument does appear to have a recognizable form. But that form is not, at least in the vast range of cases, either a deductively valid form of argument or an inductively strong form of argument. In fact, they all seem to fall into the third category of arguments having some presumptive (or perhaps abductive) weight of plausibility. (Walton 2001) Walton & Reed 2002 Argument from Position to Know Major Premise: Source a is in a position to know about things in a certain subject domain S containing proposition A. Minor Premise: a asserts that A (in Domain S) is true (false). Conclusion: A is true (false). Because this is not a deductive argument we should ask critical questions: CQ1: Is a in a position to know whether A is true (false)? CQ2: Is a an honest (trustworthy, reliable) source? CQ3: Did a assert that A is true (false)? Appeal to Expert Opinion Major Premise: Source E is an expert in subject domain S containing proposition A. Minor Premise: E asserts that proposition A (in domain S) is true (false). Conclusion: A may plausibly be taken to be true (false). 1. Expertise Question: How credible is E as an expert source? 2. Field Question: Is E an expert in the field that A is in? 3. Opinion Question: What did E assert that implies A? 4. Trustworthiness Question: Is E personally reliable as a source? 5. Consistency Question: Is A consistent with what other experts assert? 6. Backup Evidence Question: Is A’s assertion based on evidence? Appeal to modus ponens Appeal to Popular Opinion If a large majority (everyone, nearly everyone, etc.) accept A as true, then there exists a (defeasible) presumption in favour of A. A large majority accept A as true. Therefore, there exists a presumption in favour of A. Modus Ponens Premises: As a rule, if P then Q P Conclusion: Q Modus Non Excipiens Premises: As a rule, if P then Q P It is not the case that there is an exception to the rule that if P then Q Conclusion: Q If he has a good lawyer then he will be acquitted. He has a good lawyer. Therefore he will be acquitted When is such an argument complete? How many critical questions can there be? Abductive Argumentation Scheme F is a finding or given set of facts. E is a satisfactory explanation of F. No alternative explanation E' given so far is as satisfactory as E. Therefore, E is plausible, as a hypothesis.