Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics PHIL 250 – Epistemology & Metaphysics Introducing Metaphysics Let us begin our introduction to this portion of the course by considering two uses of the term ‘metaphysics’… 1 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Two understandings of ‘metaphysics’: Popular Metaphysics studies issues such as: Reincarnation/Past lives Out of body experiences Mysticism Magic Etc. This discipline is: Not particularly wedded to contemporary empirical sciences. Usually involves speculation. Almost equivalent to ‘spiritual’ or ‘supernatural’. 2 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Philosophical Metaphysics is different. Aims to construct theories or viewpoints based on logic, rigour, and reason. Tries not to contradict scientific results. From now on, ‘metaphysics’ will be taken to mean ‘philosophical metaphysics’. So, philosophical metaphysicians construct accounts or theories. What are these theories for/of/about? 3 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Metaphysical motives Metaphysics is driven by the following kind of question: What is the most basic set of categories under which existents fall? Which categories are necessary for an adequate understanding of reality? Which ones will suffice for such an understanding? In other words, we want to figure out the most fundamental features of the world. Note: we don’t try to do this all at once; rather, we break down our efforts. 4 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Metaphysical questions For example, we might want to ask about the causal structure of the world: Is causation a relation between events, objects, properties, or what? To answer this we need to know whether the world contains events as well as objects. I.e. is ‘event’ a basic category under which entities fall. Or, we might ask about the nature of persons: Are we just bodies, or are we bodies + minds? To answer this we need to know whether ‘mind’ is a basic category under which entities fall. I.e. are there minds as well as bodies? 5 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Metaphysical questions We expect that by determining which categories of entities exist, we shall also uncover enlightening perspectives on the nature of those entities. For instance, we don’t just ask whether there are events as well as objects. We also ask what the difference is between them, how the two categories are related, etc. We don’t just ask whether the universe contains minds as well as bodies We also ask: what is the difference between minds and bodies, how are they related, can one exist without the other, etc.? We might also ask about the nature of space and time, abstract entities, the foundations of physical theories, and much more. 6 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Investigating reality We can summarize metaphysics by stating that it asks the following two questions: What (in general) exists? What is the nature of that which exists? This understanding of metaphysics is often called ‘ontology’, which means the study of being (or existence). 7 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Generality One aspect of metaphysics that you have probably picked up on is its generality. Metaphysicians do not ask questions such as: How many polar bears are there in Canada? That is a question for wildlife managers. Metaphysicians don’t ask: How many species of bear exist? How many species of animal exist? These are questions for biologists. Metaphysicians don’t ask: What causes a cold? What causes black holes? That is a question for doctors/physicists. A metaphysician will ask: what is the nature of causation? 8 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics More on generality The generality of metaphysics is supposed to be fundamental, basic, ultimate. We might restrict ourselves to the metaphysics of causation, time, persons, objects, etc. These are fundamental aspects of reality. We don’t restrict ourselves to particular places, times, people, etc. Metaphysical theses are also meant to be taken literally. We often speak metaphorically, e.g. ‘the sun is rising’; ‘the car doesn’t want to start this morning’; etc. These must be reinterpreted before they can be part of a metaphysical theory. 9 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Ontology For this reason, metaphysics cannot be done by perusing an encyclopedia, which tells us a great deal about what exists. For example, you might find articles on the cause(s) of the Second World War. You will not find articles on the nature of causation in general (if you do, it’s likely a philosophical article). For that we turn to metaphysics. 10 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics The metaphysical and the empirical In short, metaphysics is not an empirical discipline. It is not the gathering of facts and information from various sources. That, however, leaves metaphysics with the appearance of mystery. After all, it supposedly tells us about the world—it uncovers the basic categories and nature of existing entities. Yet, it isn’t empirical—it doesn’t depend on experiments or scientific observation. How is such an enterprise possible? 11 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Against metaphysics You have probably encountered a philosophical movement known as ‘empiricism’. Empiricists argue that all knowledge must be derived from sensory observations. Anything that goes beyond the senses is illegitimate (nonsense). Hence, empiricists tend to conclude that metaphysics is impossible. In the 20th Century, logical positivists took up the empiricist position and argued that only what is verifiable empirically has meaning. Hence, metaphysics is to be replaced by science. Toward the end of this course, we shall examine such criticisms. In the meantime, let us examine another perspective on metaphysics. 12 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Rationalism Empiricism stands in contrast to rationalism, which argues that (at least some) knowledge rests on non-empirical grounds. Think, for example, of mathematics. Consider the following proposition: All even numbers are divisible by two. This seems as certain as anything; almost impossible to doubt. Yet, we haven’t confirmed it by checking every even number. That is impossible. Hence, the rationalist might argue, we can know certain propositions to be true without empirically verifying them. How could this be? 13 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics The tradition of philosophical ‘analysis’ In the lat 1800’s and early 1900’s, the discipline of formal logic was developed. It allowed us to study systems of inference or reasoning in great detail. This movement was driven by philosophers such as Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, Moore, Carnap and Quine. Russell in particular made an interesting observation: A great deal of common, uncontroversial and obviously valid reasoning can be explained if we assume that our language has an underlying logical structure. By appealing to this structure we can make sense of, and shed light on, the nature of reason. 14 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Language, logic and reason It was once thought that every meaningful proposition that we can express must have a subject—an entity—that it is about, and must attribute something (a predicate) to that subject. E.g.: If I say ‘Fred is happy’, then I express a proposition that is about Fred and attributes happiness to him. If I say, ‘dogs are mammals’, my proposition is about dogs. Etc. It was thought that if a sentence weren’t about a particular entity, it would be meaningless. Hence, in virtue of using language/thought meaningfully, we commit ourselves to the existence of entities that are the subjects of our expressions/thoughts. 15 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Definite descriptions But now consider the following sentence: ‘the present king of France is bald’. Russell argued that this is a meaningful sentence, but since France no longer has a king, it cannot be about a particular person. So, the subject-predicate theory is wrong. Hence, in using this phrase we must not be committing ourselves to any particular subject. Russell showed how the correct logical analysis of the proposition expressed by ‘the present king of France is bald’ makes this clear. Hence, Russell concluded that our language contains a logical structure that can be uncovered by analysis. 16 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Analytic philosophy This was a key part of the impetus behind what came to be known as ‘analytic philosophy’. The basic idea is as follows. We consider propositions that are too obvious to be doubted. E.g.: if John is happy, then someone is happy. We then reconstruct those propositions to highlight their logical structure. We know we’ve done this well when the logical analysis captures the original features (entailments) of the proposition. This analysis will tell us what we are ontologically committed to in virtue of the logical structure of our language. Since the original propositions are too obvious to be doubted, we must accept these commitments. 17 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Logic and ontology In short, we use a logical analysis of claims to uncover what we ontologically commit ourselves to in virtue of accepting those claims. We can, of course, deny those claims rather than accept the commitments. In many cases, however, such a denial is far less plausible than the commitments. Also, we try to do this in a way that does not conflict with well-established scientific results or theories. Since, however, such an analysis provides a very general form of commitment, there is hope that science and metaphysics can co-exist. For example, perhaps metaphysics provides the general categories; science provides the content for those categories. 18 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Disputes continue Despite the popularity of the analytical approach to philosophy, disputes in metaphysics were not settled once and for all. Let us look at an example of the method, and the disagreements that might follow… 19 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics A metaphysical problem: universals ‘Strawberries and raspberries have something in common; they are both red.’ This does not seem to be a startling or controversial claim. But if we mean it literally, then it seems we must believe that there is (exists) something that these two fruit share: redness. The usual term for something that unites particular objects is a property or a universal. So, our common speech commits us to the existence of properties, i.e. things that different objects can each have. Does this settle the matter? Hardly… 20 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Some responses Platonist: universals exist and are shared by objects. Nominalist: everything is concrete, all that different pieces of fruit share is our use of the word ‘red’. Since, however, our everyday speech seems to commit us to redness, the nominalist has some work to do. In particular, she will likely argue that we can paraphrase the original expression so that it doesn’t contain any commitment to universals. 21 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Metaphysics and paraphrase Imagine a materialist (Bob) who believes that only matter exists. Bob says: Jane has a strong will. Jill: A-ha, Bob! You believe that people have wills, but wills are not made up of matter, so you aren’t a materialist after all. Bob: I was just speaking loosely. All I meant to say was, ‘Jane will resist most suggestions you give her. If I say, “do this” she normally replies “no”. My use of “will” just summarizes this pattern. All that exists is atoms, including those that vibrate to make sound’. Paraphrase is a common metaphysical technique. I.e., we argue that we are only apparently committed to the existence of something. 22 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Ontological commitments If you deny that there exist any X’s, but you can’t paraphrase commitment to X’s out of your language, then it seems that your resistance to X’s is ungrounded (unless you are willing to change other beliefs you hold). If, however, you can paraphrase away commitment to X’s, there is still ground for dispute: Should we accept the paraphrase? If so, why? How are we to decide such issues? What is the evidence we use? Getting a grip on questions such as these is a big part of what metaphysics is about. 23 Joshua Mozersky, Queen’s University Introducing Metaphysics Why study metaphysics? In sum, metaphysics is the study of the most general features of reality. It is the attempt to use reason to uncover the fundamental structure of the world. It is general enough that scientific results can be accommodated. Since a great deal of the humanistic enterprise is to understand our place in the universe, metaphysics is a central component of the humanities. Still metaphysics remains controversial, so I hope you will agree that it is a topic well worth studying. 24