RMPS Language, Religion and Philosophy August 1998 HIGHER STILL RMPS Language, Religion and Philosophy Support Materials LANGUAGE, PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION Sense and nonsense about God by John Hull Introduction While there are a significant number of book and other resources on this topic which will be useful to both teachers and students, this book is being recommended as a basic text book for the unit. It covers most of the content of the unit and provides some useful questions and suggested answers which will be a very worthwhile resource for those who are teaching and studying it. The following is a brief outline of its content in relation to the sequence of the unit and the learning outcomes. OUTCOME 1 Demonstrate a detailed understanding of some of the main issues in the use of religious language. The main purpose of this outcome is to highlight two basic features: i) The exploration of the variety of language use in general ii) The demonstration of the variety of uses in the following way: Chapter 6 (The Uses of Language) This provides a useful introduction to the unit in that it concentrates on the variety of language use and how language must be contextualised before it can be properly understood. The social significance of language is covered as well as the way people use language and the various meanings it has (following the later Wittgenstein). The symbolic and transferable use of language to a different context e.g. solid used of a building and the character of an individual. Chapter 7 (On the meaning and use of religious language) This is a natural development from chapter 6 and looks at what religious words mean, and the symbolic nature of such language is emphasised. The meaningfulness of religious statements/language is also considered. The introductory chapter on Nonsense (Chapter 1) could also be used at this stage as a general introduction to the oddities of language use. Chapter 2 (On the meaning of language) In this chapter an emphasis is placed on contextualising language rather than seeing it in isolation. The chapter raises the issue of verification of language and is a natural link with Outcome 2 which considers issues of the meaningfulness of religious language in relation to the parables of The Road, The Gardener and The Stranger. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 1 OUTCOME 2 Analyse different views on the meaningfulness of religious language and evaluate these (with reference to one/two parables). Chapter 3 (God) considers the way in which religious beliefs and statements might be verified or shown to be meaningful. It considers the significance of the statement “God exists” and looks at the difference between analytic and synthetic statements (see below) and whether the phrase “God exists” actually means anything at all which could be verified. Reference is made to the parable of The Gardener (and this could be related to other support materials on this issue). Chapter 5 (On criticisms of the Verification Principle) is more difficult, but could be used by teachers with more able pupils if desired. The basic approach of this chapter is to show how language has a number of valid uses which go well beyond the limitations of what the verification principle was suggesting. This brings the more recent work on the meaning of religious language into profile (for example the later Wittgenstein). Chapter 4 (Some Replies by Theists) then looks at the issue of the meaningfulness of religious statements (rather than whether they are true or false in an empirical way). This has implications for recent developments in the use and meaning of religious language and how religious language has taken on a significantly non-factual interpretation. (This could be linked up with Outcome 3 where various interpretations of religious language are considered in a more detailed manner). This chapter concentrates on reinterpreting religious language into more existential terms in order to make it more relevant to the modern world. OUTCOME 3 Analyse different interpretations of religious language and evaluate their contemporary relevance and significance. In the support notes for this outcome, the five interpretations of religious language are outlined and developed. However, in Chapter 4 some useful material in relation to more existential and secular approaches as developed by theologians such as RG Smith, John Robinson and Paul Van Buren and picked up by those such as Tillich, Bultmann and Cupitt are included. This can therefore provide a useful backcloth to the various interpretations to be dealt with in Outcome 3. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 2 SENIOR STUDY SERIES Sense and Nonsense about God John Hull SCM Press LTD RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 3 The Senior Study Series consists of short booklets intended for use with students in sixth forms, colleges of education, universities and adult church and local education groups. Each booklet is written by an experienced teacher and provides an outline of the questions raised by its subject and skeleton material to form the basis for constructive discussion. The verse on page 9 is quoted by the kind permission of JM Dent and Sons Ltd and the trustees for the copyright of the late Dylan Thomas. 334 01490 5 First published 1974 by SCM Press Ltd, 56 Bloomsbury Street, London in conjunction with the Christian Education Movement © Christian Education Movement 1970 RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 4 Contents Note for the teacher or lecturer 1. Nonsense 2. Meaning 3. ‘God’ 4. Some replies by Theists 5. Criticisms of the Verification Principle 6. The Uses of Language 7. ‘God’ Again For further reading For the teacher or lecturer: Notes on the discussion questions RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 5 NOTE FOR THE TEACHER OR LECTURER In many discussion about religion, the main question is ‘Does God exist?’ But in recent years the central problem has been not so much the existence of God but the possible meaning of the very phrase – ‘God exists’. But how, one might ask, could there be any doubt about what is meant? Are the words not plain enough? This study outline, written by Dr John Hull who lectures in Religious Education at the School of Education, Birmingham University, provides a simple introduction to the problems of the meaning of religious language. It does not discuss the grounds for believing but aims to show the conditions under which statements about God can be meaningful. Sections and paragraphs are numbered for the convenience of cross referencing. Each student should be provided with a copy of the outline before the classes or meetings begin. Those who refer to the books mentioned at the end and those already familiar with them will quickly notice that the studies are entirely dependent upon them, both in general and in many points of detail. When books are mentioned in the text, copies should be available to the groups for reference to be made to them during discussion. Thanks are expressed to Professor Ninian Smart, who kindly looked through the manuscript, and made a number of helpful suggestions. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 6 1 NONSENSE 1.1 The curtain goes up, the orchestra play, and on come the Diddy People. They open their diddy mouths and out comes their diddy song, ‘Nick nocky nick nack nicky nocky noo.’ People laugh and clap. But nobody turns to his neighbour and says, ‘Do you agree?’ or ‘I’m not going to clap that! It just isn’t true.’ 1.2 The diddy song cannot be true of false because it does not say anything capable of truth or falsehood. It makes not assertion. Its function is not to convey information, but to act as a slogan, a comedian’s catch phrase, an entertaining song. So here we have the first way to recognise nonsense. Nonsense is incapable of being true or false because it does not say anything which could be true or false. 1.3 Nonsense, however, need not take the form of nonsensical words like ‘nocky’. Normal words, the meaning of which everybody knows, may be arranged in ungrammatical form so as to produce nonsense. ‘Sat cat mat the on the’ is an example. Once again, if I said to you, ‘Do you agree that sat cat mat the on the?’ you would not be able to agree or disagree. You would perhaps enquire as to whether you had heard me correctly. But if you replied, ‘No, on the contrary, I think that mat the on the sat cat,’ you would not have contradicted me. Nonsensical statements are incapable of contradiction. They cannot conflict with anything since they asset nothing. 1.4 Can normal English words be used in a grammatically correct way and still produce nonsense? Suppose I asked you ‘Don’t you thing this coffee tastes too red?’, you could answer neither yes nor no. You could only ask me what on earth I meant. You would seek clarification, because although the words of my question were arranged in a normal manner, with the verbs and adjectives and nouns in the normal places (unlike the cat example), I would be using one of these words in a very unusual way. I was asking for a judgement about the flavour of the coffee in terms of a word which could only refer to the colour. Ordinary words used in the wrong sense or in the wrong context may produce nonsense. 1.5 There are many examples of this last kind of nonsense in the writings of Lewis Carroll. In Alice through the Looking Glass, the messenger is asked whom he passed on the road. He replies, ‘Nobody.’ ‘Quite right,’ said the King. ‘This young lady saw him too. So of course Nobody walks slower than you.’ The indignant messenger protests, ‘Nobody walks faster than I do.’ ‘He can’t do that,’ says the King, ‘or he’d have been here first.’ Here the word nobody is being used by the King as if it was in the category of proper names. The work can mean persons in general; their presence being denied (Nobody at all) or it can mean a proper name (Mr Nobody). The confusion over the two senses leads to amusing nonsense. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 7 1.6 You can talk a lot of grammatically correct nonsense by combining words with contradictory meanings. If the maths master asks you to draw a four-sided triangle you will not even be able to start the task. This is not because you find the task too difficult, or because your knowledge and experience are inadequate (as might be the case if he asked you to draw a plan of the workings of an atomic power station) but because you will not know what he means. No conceivable reality, however odd and complex, could fit the description ‘Four-sided triangle’, because the description consists of two words which are by definition incompatible. Summing up We have found three kinds of nonsense. 1. Nonsense which depends upon the use of words which have no recognisable meaning. Nicky nocky (paragraphs 1.1 and 1.2). 2. Nonsense which depends upon words which have a recognisable meaning but are used in ungrammatical contexts. Lamb Mary had little a (paragraph 1.3). 3. Nonsense which uses words with recognisable meanings in grammatically correct contexts, but in such a manner that the normal meaning of the word seems not to apply. ‘Does gravity run faster than virtue?’ Sometimes the meanings of the words will actually conflict. ‘Draw me a straight curved line’ (paragraph 1.4–1.6) In every case, the test is not, ‘Does it sound funny?’ (it might contain unfamiliar vocabulary, or be in Japanese) but ‘Is it capable of being true or false?’ If it is not even capable of falsehood, it cannot be a wrong statement, but merely nonsense. Discuss 1. ‘Once it was the colour of saying Soaked my table the uglier side of a hill With a capsized field where a school sat still And a black and white patch of girls grew playing’ (Dylan Thomas, Collected Poems 1934–52, J. M. Dent 1952, p89.) Is this nonsense? Plato distrusted poets because he thought that the power of charming words led to the belief that something profound was being said, whereas in fact nothing was being said at all. Was his suspicion justified? 2. ‘Before I had studied Zen for thirty years, I saw mountains as mountains and waters as waters. When I arrived at a more intimate knowledge, I came to the point where I was that mountains are not mountains and waters are not waters. But now that I have got its very substance I am at rest. For its just that I see mountains once again as mountains and waters once again as waters.’ (Alan Watts, the Way of Zen, Penguin Books 1957, p.146.) Is this nonsense/How do you tell the difference (if any) between nonsense and paradox? Are there some things you can only say with paradox? RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 8 NOTES ON THE DISCUSSION QUESTIONS Chapter 1 1. Words can be used in non-literal ways and retain their meaning or even, as with vivid figures of speech, add to their meaning. So when the poet says 'a school sat still' we are not puzzled, as we would be if it was complete nonsense. He clearly means to contrast the solid immobile block of the building with the moving mass of uniformed (black and white) girls playing around it. There is no need to insist that schools cannot sit. But what about 'the colour of saying'? This looks very much like the sort of case discussed in paragraph 1.4. However, we do speak of a saying as being colourful, and we have expressions such as 'blue jokes'. So perhaps the phrase means 'the quality of the conversations we used to have around the table'. Note that even if nothing is being asserted or claimed, a feeling or mood may be evoked. The poet may be throwing a few snatches of memory together to try and re-create the fragmentary nature of our childhood memories. If his poem creates a mood, then it cannot be true or false. The mood may be sincerely expressed or it may be a pretence, but it cannot be logically true or false, any more than a piece of music can be true or false. Only assertions can be true or false (see chapter 2). In so far as pieces of music, or perhaps poems of this nature, contain no actual assertions, they have no actual sense and are in fact types of nonsense. But because something is nonsense it does not mean it is useless! Nonsensical statements can be strangely moving to the emotions, nonsense can be relaxing, wildly funny, even exhilarating. Even those who think religious statements are nonsense (see chapter 3) are agreed that it is an impressive and even useful kind of nonsense. 2. This is not nonsense but a terse and paradoxical statement of three stages of opinion or attitude towards the world which the Zen believer has passed through. First, as a unreflective man, he takes everything at its face value. Next, he sees through the externals of life to its deeper reality and its underlying significance – mountains are now not mountains. Finally, he comes to see that it is the ordinary things of life which are, after all, of true meaning of life. He returns to the point from which he set out, but with a deeper understanding – mountains are now mountains again. Compare this with Donovan's hit song, 'Once there was a mountain and there was no mountain, then there was.' The difference between nonsense and paradox is often hard to tell. In general, paradox tries to assert something very precisely, so exactly that the ordinary words are not exact enough. For example, if asked to say whether the Mona Lisa is a beautiful woman, you might reply, 'Well, in a way she is and in a way she is not.' Although it sounds like a straight contradiction, this reply is really saying that the word 'beautiful' is not sufficiently exact to describe the enigmatic appearance of the lady. Paradox can be a way of calling attention to two contrasting aspects of a situation, e.g. 'the poor little rich girl' indicates that the girl is emotionally impoverished in spite of her great wealth. The expression 'Parting is such sweet sorrow' similarly points out that there are some aspects of separating which are sad and others, such as the sudden realization of unexpected tenderness, which are joyful. See on this paragraph 5.14. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 9 No, there is no meaningful sentence which can be said only in paradox. If the paradox has a genuine meaning, it will be possible to unravel the meaning and so express it in a non- paradoxical way. The result will of course, as you see from the cases above, be less succinct than the paradox, and much less striking and less thought-provoking. Genuine nonsense resists the attempt to unravel it. Expressions such as 'round squares' hide no profound meaning and examination shows that this is because the ideas are mutually exclusive. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 10 2 MEANING 2.1 Nonsense is the absence of meaning. Let us now look at the positive side of the problem. Where do we find meaning? Individual words, in strict isolation, have little or no meaning. Even a very concrete noun, such as ‘dog’ has little meaning out of context and in isolation. If I came up to you in the street and muttered in your ear ‘Dog’, you would wonder what I meant. Was I trying to say, ‘Look out for the dog!’ or. ‘There is a dog.’ or ‘I want a dog.’ or what? You would assume that there was some kind of link in my mind between the sound I had uttered and the particular class of creatures called dogs, so what I had said would give you some information about my mind at that moment. But this would be psychological information about me; what I had said could not take on a logical significance (as distinct from psychological) until I used the word to assert something, e.g. ‘Look!’ or ‘Hooray!’, but usually the word has to be place in a sentence before it asserts anything, e.g. ‘There is a dog’; ‘I want you to look.’ 2.2 Meaning depends upon assertions. Meaning is usually located not so much in isolated words as in sentences telling how the words are being used. If this is true of nouns like ‘dog’, ‘man’ and ‘planet; it is even more true of words like ‘but’, ‘or’ and ‘however’; for such words derive all their significance from the sentence they are in. The same applies to abstract words such as home, relationship and contradictory. 2.3 We have already seen, however, in paragraphs 1.4-1.6 that not all apparent assertions are meaningful. Is there a further test by which we may know that ‘He is a teenage werewolf’ is a meaning assertion, but ‘He is ruppiltybloop’ is not? For both sentences have the grammatical form of assertions. But in the case of the former assertion, one can think of a variety of tests which could be carried out on the unfortunate subject. One could look at his birth certificate, to see if he is indeed a teenage. One could call in medical and zoological experts to determine any lupine characteristics. But how could one carry out tests for the ruppiltybloop assertion? Not knowing what could characterise such a creature, there would be no way of telling what would count for the assertion and what would count against it. It would therefore be revealed as a meaningless assertion. This brings us to a most important principle: The meaning of any statement is determined by the steps by which one could verify it. This is sometimes called ‘The Verification Principle’. Statements which can be verified, in fact or in theory, are meaningful. Statements which cannot be verified, because you would not even know what to look for are meaningless. 2.4 It is sufficient to guarantee the meaning of a statement if the steps by which it could be verified are determinable in principle, even though it may be impossible to carry them out in practice. For example, the statement ‘There is life on Mars’ cannot be verified in practice at the time of writing, but it is easy to think of many ways in which it could be verified. The problem is technical, not logical. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 11 2.5 Note also that the statement ‘The moon is made of cheese’ is not nonsense in the logical sense in which we are using the word. For although you might reply ‘That’s nonsense!’ if someone asserted that the moon was cheese, you would mean that the evidence against the proposition is so overwhelmingly strong that only a fool could continue to hold it. And yet, the very fact that it is possible to accumulate evidence against the proposition shows that it is not logically nonsense. You will recall that the distinguishing characteristic of the nonsense examples in the first part of this study in paragraphs 1.1 and 1.3 was that it was impossible to provide evidence either for or against them. But in the case of the moon being made of cheese, we can say very exactly what we would consider evidence for and against the hypothesis. So it may be silly , or against common sense to say the earth is flat, but it is not logical nonsense. We know what would count for or against it. 2.6 Let us suppose someone says to you ‘There is an elephant under the desk’. However unlikely this may seem, we can think of various factors which would count for and against it, and it is not therefore nonsensical. You might say, ‘An elephant wouldn’t fit under the desk’, and the answer might be that it was a special type of little elephant. But suppose you then stooped down and had a look and you were then told, ‘Oh, you won’t see it! The breeding process which produces these elephants also makes them invisible.’ You might gingerly stretch out your hand and feel nothing and your friend might then say, ‘And I don’t think you will feel him - these elephants have the quality of yielding like air to any attempt to touch them.’ In exasperation you would enquire by what steps the existence of the elephant could be decided one way or the other. If your friend replied that it could not be proved, there was nothing which could count one way or the other, even in principle, but that it was a matter of faith, you would be quite correct if you then dismissed his claim as mere nonsense. For if the meaning of a statement is to be found in the steps by which it might be verified and if the statement about the elephant will allow no such steps to be even imaginable, the statement has not meaning. One might just as well say that there was a ruppiltybloop under the desk or that there was a ruppiltybloop mider the bigrust. Summing up The meaning (logical significance) of a sentence is the method of its verification. Discuss Which of the following statements are meaningful and why? 1. The universe is expanding. 2. The angel Gabriel appeared to Mary. 3. Unicorns are found in Central America. 4. The battle of Hastings was a crisis in English history. 5. The sum of the angles of a triangle is 180 degrees. 6. The Clarinet Quintet by Brahms is one of his most lovely works. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 12 NOTES ON THE DISCUSSION QUESTIONS Chapter 2 1. Could anything count against this statement? No immediate observation made with the unaided senses could do so. If you went outside at night and watched the stars and reported that there was no apparent expansion, a scientist would not accept your finding as counting against his theory. However, the scientist would be able to name certain phenomena which would count against his theory, and this would be true no matter how abstract and generalized his theory was. It would be enough for him to name the type of phenomenon even if no scientific instrument existed which was precise enough to measure the effect he had in mind. If a scientist held a theory and refused to admit that anything could possibly make any difference to it, then we would be correct in regarding his theory as logical nonsense. 2. If we believe literally in angels and we want that belief to be a meaningful one, we must be ready to state what will count for and against the belief. If one saw a being like a man but with wings and shining white, that would count in favour of the theory. So would reliable reports of trustworthy people who had seen, or thought they had seen such creatures. What would count against angels? If no angels. were seen for centuries one might simply say that angels were getting shy, or that men were too sinful to be honoured by a visit. If one person claimed to be seeing an angel but photography and radar subsequently revealed nothing, that would count against angels (to say that angels are photograph-proof and that their voices have the peculiar quality of being not recorded by tape recorders is to start on the slippery slope towards nonsense, as we saw in the case of the little invisible elephant). It seems then that belief in literal angels is meaningful. Whether it is also true that in fact there are angels is another problem. It is meaningful (although as far as we know, false in fact) to assert the existence of unicorns. If we do not take angels literally the other alternative open to us is to say that this is the record of a certain experience couched in terms appropriate to the age. It might be a poetic way of saying that Mary had reached an important stage in her life. Statements of this sort could be verified in principle by examining the rest of Mary's life and seeing if this particular incident was significant in her later history. So in theory the verifying could be carried out, even though the necessary historical materials are not available in this case. We would then conclude that the sentence is meaningful but its truth or falsity cannot in fact, like the question of life on Mars, be determined. 3. Meaningful and false. We know exactly what to look for – horses with horns on their heads. All expeditions. to Central America have so far failed to find any. It remains meaningful however, since we know what sort of evidence would make us change our minds. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 13 4. A tricky one because it contains two problems. First, did this battle take place? That is easy, for we know what would count for and against an event being described as a battle. We would look for men hitting each other with weapons. If they were found to be sitting quietly playing cards this would count against the proposition. So in theory it is verifiable. In fact there is quite a lot of evidence in favour of this particular battle – the Bayeux tapestry etc.. The second part is more difficult. We have to decide if this battle was a crisis in English history. We would have to decide what would count for. and against a battle being a crisis. We might gather historians together and ask them to draw up lists of characteristics of critical battles. If this could be done then the idea of critical battles would be meaningful. We would then have to establish whether. the battle of Hastings meets, these conditions or not. So each part of this sentence – the fact statement about the battle, and the value judgment about its importance – has to be subject to (a) the principle of verification to establish meaning-fulness and (b) the facts of the case to establish truth or falsehood. 5. This can be verified by looking up a dictionary to see what the words in the sentence mean. The sentence is in fact a definition of a triangle, and its truth follows inevitably from the rules of geometry and, in a way, books of geometry are books of rather elaborate definitions. Statements such as these are called analytic statements and the principle of verification does not apply to them since, given the correct use of the words they deal with, they cannot logically be false. They do not assert anything about the world at large, only about the rules of language or maths or what have you. See paragraphs 3.3 and 3.4. 6. Procedure is similar to that for statement 4. You would ascertain the meaningfulness of the description 'lovely' by getting musical experts to draw up a list of qualities which would count for and against the description being applied to a piece of music. Then, assuming you could get agreement on the first stage, you would see if this bit of music had those qualities. Of course, it might be the case that assertions in the field of aesthetics were not in fact meaningful assertions. In that case, this, sentence would have psychological significance but not logical significance. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 14 3 GOD 3.1 Bearing in mind what has been said about the verification principle, let us consider what kinds of proposition can be tested or verified. The first type of proposition consists of statements about simple matters of particular fact, i.e. empirical statements (which means ones which can be tested by reference to the experience of the senses). If it is claimed that rain is falling, I test the meaning (as well as the truth) of the statement by sticking my head outside. The statement, ‘It is raining’ can thus be translated into the expression, ‘I get wet’. Statement 4 in the discussion material of chapter 2 about the unicorn is of this type. 3.2 The second kind of testable sentence is one dealing with statements of general fact such as scientific theories. These may often be highly abstract and may not be testable by direct sense experience, This would be the case if a theory postulated some new sub-atomic particle which could not itself be seen, touched, heard, etc. However, no matter how abstract and general it may be, the scientist will be able to state some conditions which support his proposition and will name others which if they occurred would count against his theory. Statement 1 in the discussion material of chapter 2, about the expanding universe, is of this type. 3.3 The third kind of statement consists of the statements of basic principles of maths and logic which are true by definition and may be tested simply by looking up a dictionary to see what the words mean. This kind of statement is called analytic because it consists of an analysis or re-definition of a word. Sentences such as ‘All bachelors are unmarried males’ as well as ‘The sum of two and two is four’ are telling us something about the way we use words such as ‘bachelor’ and ‘four’. You will notice that these statements do not tell us anything new about states of affairs. The convey no actual information. They only tell us what words mean. Contrast them with statements of the first two types and you will see the difference. For the sentence ‘Mr Jones is a bachelor’ tells me something new about the world around me and does not merely define a language symbol. I may, for example, know that all bachelors are unmarried males but not know whether in fact there are any bachelors about or not. Even if there were no bachelors, it would still be true to say that the word bachelor means a single man. 3.4 Analytic propositions have another interesting feature. Just as they tell us nothing about the actual world of experience, so they cannot be refuted by anything which might occur in the world of experience. If I came to you and said, ‘What do you think! I’ve just been talking to Mr Jones, who turns out to be married and yet is certainly a single male. He must be an exception to the rule,’ you would understand that I did not know the correct use of the words ‘married’ and ‘single’. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 15 These terms are mutually exclusive, so that the expression ‘a married single man’ is nonsense, like ‘a round square’. No, the truth that bachelors are single males is not derived from examination of actual single males but from a definition. It is impossible therefore that any actual fact can count against an analytic statement. They are immune from danger of falsification. But they win their immunity at the high price of saying nothing about anything apart from themselves. 3.5 Into which of these three classes does the proposition ‘God exists’ fall? If we say it is an analytic statement, that is, God exists by definition, then we are merely saying something about the use of the word ‘God’. We might in the same way say ‘God is love’ is true by definition, since (we might argue the word God means the same as the word love. But we must remember that analytic statements do not tell us about the world beyond themselves, and yet when a religious person says he believes that there is a God, or that God is love, he surely intends to be saying something about his view of reality. He thinks he is talking about a state of affairs outside himself, and not merely acting as a sort of religious word-book. 3.6 If such propositions are not analytic, then they must fall into the other classes which were discussed at the beginning of this chapter, paragraphs 3.1 and 3.2. These are called synthetic statements, because they synthesize or put together two or more different aspects of reality so as to yield new information, e.g. the apple is ripe. The relationship between the two terms is not a necessary one, as it is with analytic statements, but an observed one. And we have seen that although synthetic statements have the obvious advantage of telling us something meaningful about the world, they have to face the risk of being wrong. The apple may, after all, not be ripe. Now if the believer claims that his statements about God are synthetic statements, he falls into a number of difficulties. 3.7 The first one is that religious believers usually claim to know with absolute certainty. A true believer does not say that on the whole he is inclined to think that there is a God, nor that it is firmly held opinion that there is a God. He rejects the word ‘opinion’ altogether as being unsatisfactory, and speaks of ‘knowing’.* *We should distinguish between factual knowledge of the external world (certainty) and an inner feeling of confidence (certitude). Which does the believer mean when he says he knows God? All synthetic statements, because they are in principle open to falsification, must fall below the level of absolute certainty. Certain philosophers, however, such as the Cambridge moral philosopher G.E. Moore, claim that statements such as ‘keeping promises is part of our duty’ are synthetic. That is, they give us real information about external reality and yet because they spring from a sort of moral instinct or intuition they are incapable of being proved false. We just KNOW they are true. See pp. 54f. for some comments on this. Could the believer claim that belief in God was a kind of intuition or a self-evident truth? RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 16 Some truths are so highly probable that we rarely if ever doubt them - satisfied by a probability however high? Perhaps the believer could reply that what he claims is not certainty but certitude. The difference is that the former is objective, and the latter subjective. The believer claims to experience complete inner security or a feeling of absolute certitude. Is he compelled to claim also that his inner must correspond to a state of affairs outside himself, e.g. the reality of God? In other words can he be content with certitude and admit he has no absolute objective certainty? 3.8 There are other more serious difficulties. Is saying, ‘I believe that man is my father’? Religious people sometimes say that their belief is a simple matter of fact confirmed by experience as immediate as that which leads us to believe in the reality of our parents. But what the religious person usually means is that he has had certain kinds of inner emotional, mystical, perhaps moral experiences and that from these he concludes that there is a God. (a) If he agues that he had experienced God directly, then ‘God’ becomes a word he uses to describe a certain human experience. But most Christians think there is more to God than that. If God is just a part of human experience then in what sense can he be called Creator? If he is what we experience, he can have no existence apart from our experience. (b) On the other hand, if he is using his experiences as a proof of the existence of God he runs into other problems. For his claim becomes rather like a scientific theory.. He claims that a supernatural being is causing certain sensations in him. By what mean could this claim be verified? If we ask the believer how his experience would have to change before he would abandon his belief, he will probably reply that even the great saints have known the dark night of the soul and that he would continue to trust God even if his experience failed to be so vivid. Would not the sceptic ultimately have to conclude that there is little to choose between saying that the experiences are caused y God and that they are caused by X or by Oberon, King of the Fairies? 3.9 When the believer speaks of God in broader terms, his statements sound much more like scientific theories of the more abstract type, e.g. ‘God is the Creator of Heaven and Earth’, or ‘god is Universal Love’. But when we ask the believer what changes would have to appear in the universe before he would abandon his belief, there seems to be no answer. If he is taxed with the latest cosmological theory, he will say that his belief is that God created everything and he is willing to leave the manner of it to scientist. If the suffering of the world is pointed out to him, he replies by saying that it is all for a mysterious purpose. Nothing is incompatible with a statement, that statement cannot in fact be about states of affairs at all. It seems at this stage of our discussion that religious statements do not fall into any of the classes of meaningful propositions which we outlined at the beginning of this section. This consideration has led a number of important and influential philosophers to the conclusion that religious statements are literally meaningless. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 17 Talk about God, they claim, is in the class of logical nonsense since talk is incapable of verification. The fact that the word is revered and charged with emotion should not prevent us, they say, from seeing that it has no meaning. One might, they say, as well speak of Gid or Gad as of God. Summing up Certain philosophers claim that there are only three classes of meaningful statements: a) Particular matters of fact (synthetic statements) b) General matters of fact c) Truths of definition (analytic statements) Statements about God do not seem to fall into any of these classes. Whatever emotional comfort people may draw from reciting them, they appear to have no logical significance. Incapable of verification, they seem therefore incapable of bearing meaning. Neither true nor false, they would be mere nonsense. (See chapter 4 for what the believers say in reply and paragraph 5.12 for other classes of sentences.) Discuss 1. Professor Antony Flew reproduces a famous parable by John Wisdom about two explorers who find a clearing in a jungle which looks as if someone may be looking after it. But no gardener is ever heard or seen. The believing explorer is not convinced even when an electrified fence is set up and patrolled with dogs. There are no shrieks, the dogs never give cry. ‘But there is a gardener who comes secretly to look after the garden he loves.’ The sceptical explorer despairs. ‘But what remains of your original assertion? Just how does what you call an invisible intangible, eternally elusive gardener differ from an imaginary gardener or even from no gardener at all? See New Essays in Philosophical Theology, ed. Antony Flew and Alisdair MacIntyre, SCM press 1956, ch. VI p. 96. What reply does the religious believer have to the point made in this story? 2. ‘Suppose I were to tell a story about a square circle. There clearly can be no such entity, but I might go on to say who invented this curious object, what his early struggles were like and so forth, I might say how the square circle was lost at one time and what crusades and pilgrimage’s were undertaken to recover it, what battles were lost and won, what fortunes made and forfeited. This story might be told with more liveliness by some than by others, some would give it more colour and romance, some would tell it with much more eloquence and passion to it, some would tell it with much more intelligence and consistency than others and with a profounder understanding of human nature. But at the heart of it all there would be utter nonsense, for we cannot even conceive of anything being square and round in the same respect. So we have in religion inspired poets, gifted hymn writers, thinkers who far excel others in shrewdness and consistency, men of great RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 18 psychological insight and so forth. But at the heart of all this is irredeemable nonsense and the time has now come to expose it and rescue what we can of the trimmings if we like.’ (H. D. Lewis, Teach Yourself Philosophy of Religion, EUP 1965, p.71. By the way, Professor Lewis does not himself think that this is a correct description of belief in God.) is this the plight of the believers? 3. ‘... a branding of religious assertions as “nonsense” need not be anti-religious. It can be interpreted as an attack on those who in the name of religion are perverting religion. It can be interpreted as a return to the truth about religion ... what is essential about religion is its non-rational side, the part that cannot be ... put into words.’ (T. McPherson, ‘Religion as the Inexpressible’ in New Essays in Philosophical Theology, p.133.) Is this true, or partly true? What are the non-rational or inexpressible aspects of religion and why are they important ‘I know God exists because I talked with him this morning’ (Billy Graham). Discuss NOTES ON THE DISCUSSION QUESTIONS Chapter 3 1. The believer could admit the force of the parable and agree that his belief in God is logically without meaning. Damaging although this admission seems, it is a course which a number of thoughtful Christians have taken (see chapter 4). Paul Tillich, the important American theologian who died in 1965, believed that God was not an entity, a being, or a god, since that would be to put him in a class with others, i.e. a class of entities, of beings, of gods. God is not a spiritual 'individual' and the protest of the atheist is justified. Indeed, it is just as atheistic to assert the existence of such a god as to deny it. In fact, God is the ground of being, the power of being, or being- itself. God is therefore not manifest in the clearing any more than in the jungle. He is the depth of all that is. To what extent do you think this view helps the Christian retain a meaningful faith? Other Christians might reply that the parable treats God like a scientific hypothesis which explains how the world works. God, they believe, can only be known through God, i.e. only as he reveals himself, not as we force him to disclose himself by a process of laboratory tests. He reveals himself not in particular scientific phenomena but in history and in the moral and spiritual experience of men. and particularly in Christ without whom nothing Christian can be said of God at all. The leading Christian thinker in this school, and indeed the modern creator of this type of theology was the great Swiss theologian, Karl Barth. David Jenkins, in Guide to the Debate about God (Lutterworth Press 1966), deals. with many of the modern Christian reactions to the kind of situation the parable of the jungle outlines and his book will repay careful reading and discussion. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 19 2. This is the same kind of situation as in the first question, with the added suggestion that the Christian idea of God contains conceptions which are as mutually exclusive as the ideas of roundness and squareness. Clearly, if the idea of God is self-contradictory, the idea could only be retained at the price of a complete sacrifice of the reason. One might, for example, maintain that the proposition 'God is perfectly loving and perfectly powerful' does contain a contradiction in view of the evident suffering of God's world. On a much more crude level, one might maintain that God could not be three and one simultaneously. Christians must therefore try to expose the misunderstandings (if that is what they are! ) of their idea of God which have lead to accusations of this sort. Don't be sidetracked on to the question of whether in fact there is a God (see paragraphs 4.1 and 4.2). All we are concerned with here is whether it is meaningful to make an assertion about the existence of God. It cannot be meaningful in any logical sense if it is selfcontradictory. Of course, even if the Christian can show that the idea of God is. not self- contradictory, it is still open to the atheist to maintain that although he now understands what the Christian means, he does not in fact think there is such a being. The situation would then be like the case of the missing unicorn. 3. Most Christians would agree that it was at least partly true. Most would probably not agree, however, that it was wholly true. By 'non-rational' McPherson probably means 'that which is not particularly relevant or available to the enquiry of reason'. He does not mean that which is actually irrational, i.e. contradicted by reason. Non-rational elements of religion might be the feelings of benevolence to mankind which the religious man cultivates, or other feelings, such as humility, and gratitude towards life, or reverence towards life. Worship is in a sense non-rational since it is the expression of an attitude rather than the making of propositions. Mystical experience comes in here as well. Many might feel that these aspects of religion are indeed the most important ones, and that without them religion would be a barren set of statements not affecting the personal life. The real issue here, however, is whether these attitudes and experiences can still persist without the propositions about God, Christ, eternal life and so on. McPherson evidently thinks they can and must (see paragraphs 4.5, 4.6 and 4.7). 4. The important problem this raises is to what extent talking to a human being is like talking to God. A human experience of communication is here being used to describe religious experience. This is obviously an analogy or illustration and must not be taken too literally. For example, human talking is genuine communication, but 'talking' to God is not genuine communication since 'your heavenly Father knoweth what things ye have need of before ye ask him'. God is not informed by what we tell him! Consider how often this is got around in prayers, not only by actually telling God, but by reminding him (!) that he knows – 'Thou knowest, O Lord...' To what extent does the experience of talking to someone provide proof of his existence? Surely what proves your existence is not that I talk to you, but that I see you, watch your response, hear your voice coming back and so on. Talking to God is not like hearing a heavenly telephone since it is private and the 'voice' cannot be identified or verified by anyone else. It is subjective. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 20 The speaker is then asserting that he has a feeling of certainty which grows out of his religious experiences. We should describe this as creating certitude not certainty. For a feeling of reality in speaking to someone, however vivid, can be based on unreality. Consider the experience of talking to a friend only to find he was asleep all the time, or shouting out to him in the next room, only to find, when you had told him a long story, that he had quietly slipped out of the back door. You have a way of checking up to see if your feeling of communication corresponds to a real communication, but in talking with God, there appears to be no way of checking up on whether our feelings correspond to reality. Hence the New Testament saying, 'We walk by faith, not by sight.' Billy Graham's statement would therefore appear. to be a moving indication of deep religious faith and vivid religious experience but not to convey a proof or to suggest a method of verifying 'God' statements. The unbeliever could maintain correctly that it is psychologically interesting, but little more. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 21 4 SOME REPLIES BY THEISTS 4.1. The kind of objection to belief in God which we have been thinking about is much more subtle and damaging than the objections which used to be produced by the atheists of the nineteenth century. For the debate between believers and unbelievers a century ago, or even fifty years ago, was about evidence. The unbeliever denied that the believer had adequate reasons for his belief and the believer countered by trying to show that his reasons for faith were sufficient. But both sides were agreed on what they were arguing about. There was a broad agreement about the meaning of terms such as ‘infinite Being’ and ‘Almighty God’. 4.2. The debate during the last thirty years or so has moved at the deeper level of the nature of the very language in which the debate about God was being carried on. The philosophers whose views were outlined in the last chapters (they were often called logical positivists) maintained that once the rules governing meaningful assertions were understood, it would be seen that the arguments both for God’s existence and against them were equally vain, since the basic vocabulary itself was nonsensical. These modern philosophers do not deny the existence of God, they maintain simply that they cannot see any possible meaning in the claim that God exists. 4.3. The modern debate about God centres less, therefore, on the truth of claims about God and more on their meaning. Christians have been trying to show not so much that their claims are true, but that the things they say do at least have a distinct meaning, whatever the final judgement about the truth or falsehood of their claims may be. It is rather like the situation when you are making up your mind about the justice or injustice of a certain Act of Parliament. You read the wording of the Act and find that your first task is to try to understand the particular legal jargon which is used. There might be certain legal expressions used in rather a special way and you would have to grasp the nature of this legal language before any sensible discussion of the fairness of the Act could start. So it is with religious language. 4.4. Those who have defended belief in God from these charges against religious language are broadly correct. Various suggestions are then offered as to how Christianity may manage, or even prosper, without any need to speak of supernatural realities such as God, the soul, and eternal life. The second group rejects the charges themselves, claiming that the attitude towards language is too simple or that there are various errors of logic in the approach of the philosophers concerned. In the rest of this section we will look at some of the suggestions made by the first group. Suggestions made by the second group are dealt with in chapter five. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 22 4.5. Some Christian thinkers believe that the most important feature of Christianity is the quality of life, the inner experience, the personal attitudes which the Christian adopts. They are therefore not unhappy in discarding language about supernatural subjects and concentrating on the experiences of religion which seem more important to them. A number of such theologians have proposed to ‘translate’ talk about supernatural subjects into talk about human (Christian) attitudes. So, for example: ‘some experiences called meeting God will probably be experiences of meeting a person who loves you.’ God created the world’ is really saying: ‘Everything which we call material can be used in such a way that it contributes to the well-being of men.’ Others suggest that to believe that God created the world is to express your own personal sense of dependence upon God. It means that you acknowledge him as your creator, not that you hold any particular view about the origin of our material universe. 4.6. Here are one or two other examples of interpreting Christian doctrines as if they describe Christian experiences and nothing but experiences. ‘The resurrection is a way of affirming the forgiving purpose of God’ (R. G. Smith, Secular Christianity, Collins 1966, p. 13), that is, it is the belief that new invigorating life comes to us when by faith we accept that God in Christ truly loves us. It is not a belief about something which happened to Jesus’ body. ‘... to say that God is personal is to say ... that in personal relationships we touch the final meaning of existence as nowhere else’ (J. A. T. Robinson, Honest to God, SCM Press 1963, p. 49). So to talk of God is really to talk of human beings in a very serious frame of mind. 4.7. Another group of Christians see the mainspring of their faith not in the attitudes and experiences of the religious life, but inethics. For them, a Christian is a person who has decided to live a good life - not indeed any sort of good life, a goodness of which is illustrated in the New Testament and particularly in the life of Jesus. The various doctrines of Christianity are then really ways of expressing in vivid and often metaphorical terms this basic commitment to a good way of life. So, for example, when a Christian declares that ‘God is love’ he is announcing his intention to live a loving life - the sort of loving life which Jesus lived (e.g. Braithwaite - see ‘For further reading’ on page 49 of this booklet). He puts his assertion in terms of ‘God’ and so on because this kind of symbol, hallowed by use in devotion and sacred literature, is likely to inspire him most really to do what he says he is going to do, namely, live a life of love. But if he thought about it he would realise that he is not really talking about a supreme being ‘beyond space and time’ - he cannot be, for these expressions are contradictory and therefore meaningless. 4.8. In the last six or seven years a small group of theologians have appeared in America who describe themselves as Christian Atheists and take as their slogan ‘God is Dead’. Some of them, e.g. Paul van Buren, have come to this position as a result of the criticisms of religious language which we have been considering, and others for a variety of other reasons. But they all share a conviction that Christianity must concern itself exclusively with the present world and abandon all attempts to speak of transcendent, supernatural, or other - worldly objects. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 23 Summing up Some Christian welcome the criticisms of the linguistic philosophers and regard their writings not only as a valuable aid to clear thinking and as a way of helping Christians to see what they should be really concerned about, but also as being correct in dismissing any possible meaning in the claim that God exists. Discuss 1. ‘We shall summarise our interpretation of the language of the Easter event. Jesus of Nazareth was a free man in his own life, who attracted followers and created enemies according to the dynamics of personality and in a manner comparable to the effect of other liberated persons in history upon people about them. He died as a result of the threat that such a free man poses for insecure and bound men. His disciples were left no less insecure and frightened. Two days later, Peter, and the other disciples, had an experience of which Jesus was the sense-content. They experienced a discernment situation in which Jesus, the free man whom world, were seen in a new way. From that moment, the disciples began to possess something of the freedom of Jesus. His freedom began to be “contagious”. Foe the disciples therefore, the story of Jesus could not be told simply as the story of a free man who had died. Because of the new way in which the disciples saw him and because of what had happened to them, the story had to include the event of Easter. In telling the story of Jesus of Nazareth, therefore, they told it as the story which they proclaimed as the Gospel for all men.’ (Paul van Buren, The Secular Meaning of the Gospel, SCM Press 1963, p. 134.) Do you think this is a satisfactory description of the Christian statement ‘He rose from the dead’? 2. Is it true that living a good life is the true purpose and inner meaning of the Christian religion? If so, why does the Apostles’ Creed say nothing about this side of the Christian life? 3. If it were possible to have religious experiences - e.g. through drugs - without the intellectual embarrassment of being committed to beliefs in supernatural realities, would anything be lost in the process? RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 24 NOTES ON THE DISCUSSION QUESTIONS Chapter 4 1. The resurrection is here regarded as a projection into the literal world of bodies, graves, locked doors and meals, of what was originally a spiritual experience, a new way of looking at Jesus. The story of the empty tomb is thus seen as a sort of parable of Jesus' freedom, just as the Ascension is now regarded by many not as a literal event but as a symbol of Christ's lordship over heaven and earth. In deciding if this is 'satisfactory' we need to ask 'satisfactory to whom and to what? Is it satisfactory to the New Testament evidence? Note that the early church, as witnessed to in the Acts and Epistles, did not make the empty tomb story explicit and this may indicate that their original experience of resurrection was a spiritual experience and not an objective discovery of certain facts, e.g. that the body was missing. 2. Consider this in the light of the saying 'Religion is grace; ethics is gratitude.' The ethical part of the Christian life cannot stand alone but is a response to the truths stated in the creed. Note that the creed refers to 'the forgiveness of sins' so indicating the attitude of gracious acceptance by God of the one who in faith enters into the relationship of which the creed is the symbol. 3. Yes, a lot would be lost. The experience of the one who is under the influence of drugs does not correspond to the reality around him. He feels exhilaration or sees visions but his reactions are not prompted by the reality facing him. The Christian believes that his experience is reflective of reality outside himself. He believes that the truth about life has found him, and that he is not stewing in his own spiritual juice. So, for example, the Christian not only feels loving, but believes that love corresponds to the real truth about life itself He can go on having faith in love even when he does not feel loving. See paragraph 5.1 for notes on this. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 25 5 1 CRITICISMS OF THE VERIFICATION PRINCIPLE 5.1. Many Christians are dissatisfied with the replies to the challenge of the philosophers of language* given so far. They point out that if this sort of reply is all that can be made, then really Christians must stop talking of religion as truth. Christians may speak of religious experiences and religious attitudes, but if they admit that their claims do not refer to any reality beyond themselves, there can be no question of an objective religious truth. Many Christians maintain hat statements such as ‘God created the world’ and ‘Jesus Christ is Lord of all’ are in some sense stating facts. Unusual facts no doubt, but there is some element of fact in them. The factual aspect does not exhaust the meaning of these beliefs - no doubt we are to believe in them, to worship and pray by means of them, and to live a good life appropriate to them, but all these other aspects depend upon some element of fact, or objective truth, described by the actual statements. 5.2. Attention has also been given by philosophers themselves to certain weaknesses in the principle of verification. The main criticisms are as follows: First criticism: How can we tell if the principle of verification is itself meaningful? You will remember that the famous principle states that the meaning of any statement is determined by the methods by which it could be verified. Now we must ask whether this statement itself will fit into any of the classes of meaningful, i.e verifiable, statements. Is it analytic or is it synthetic? If it is analytic, then it is merely a definition of terms, e.g. that meaning equals method of verification. It would not tell us anything about actual sentences, for, you recall, analytic propositions define words and do not impart actual information about states of affairs. There would, therefore, seem to be no particular words. The linguistic philosopher may reply that the verification principle is just a handy and convenient rule of thumb for the use of language. And the religious believer may quite logically reply that it is not handy and convenient to him and he will not use it but will adopt some other definition of meaning! 5.3. One the other hand, the principle of verification may be synthetic. In this case, it would be an observation drawn from sense experience, and we would have to ask what kind of sense experience we would use to verify it. But here we notice that the verification principle rests upon a logical distinction, a distinction between analytical and synthetic statements. This is a logical observation about the nature of things, not a generalisation drawn from examining a lot of different actual sentences. Because it is a logical distinction, no sense experience could possibly upset it (see paragraph 1.6). You could not ‘come upon’ a sentence which to everyone’s amazement did not fit into either category and which made * In paragraph 4.2 this philosophical school was described as ‘logical positivist’. They are also known as ‘linguistic philosophers’ or ‘philosophers of language’ since they are dealing with the use of words. See paragraph 5.10. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 26 philosophers create a third category into which the new discovery could be fitted! No, nothing like this is possible. Logical distinctions are not established by sense experience and cannot be overthrown by sense experience. If the principle of verification is synthetic it must on its own terms be a bit of nonsense, since it is impossible to verify it by reference to experience. 5.4. Second criticism: The school of philosophers which has made most use of the principle of verification has been in the great tradition of English empirical philosophy, a tradition which includes such famous names as Locke, Berkeley and Hume. This tradition of philosophy believes that all true knowledge comes to us through our physical senses. The empirical background of modern linguistic philosophy may be seen in the insistence that synthetic statements should be verified by reference to sense experience. 5.5. From this it follows that one way of attacking the linguistic philosophers is to question their theory about how we obtain knowledge and to ask whether in fact it is true that all our knowledge comes to us through the senses. 5.6. (i) The law of contradiction, i.e. the belief that it is absurd to contradict oneself. Where do we get this basic conviction from? What makes us feel that it is absurd to contradict ourselves? Although our experiences of being found to look stupid when we do contradict ourselves no doubt impress the truth deeply on us, ‘the validation of it does not depend directly on experience. But this principle is basic to all our thinking, and there seems thus to be something nonempirical at the centre of all thought and experience'’(Lewis, p. 132). 5.7. (ii) Truths of mathematics. Although it is often said that these are mere definitions and do not therefore give us any new knowledge about anything, H. D. Lewis suggests that this is true only of the elementary forms of maths. ‘We know what 245 and 367 mean without having any notion what they will yield when multiplied. That would take time to discover, any the solutions to some problems require exceptional gift and in some cases genius. Surly we learn something new in the process (ibid., p. 133). 5.8. (iii) Value judgement in morals and art. Many thinkers, of course, regard ethical judgements as derived from our experience, the pressures of society and so on. Others regard them as merely expressing emotional attitudes of approval or disapproval. But there remain important ethical judgements (e.g. that it is wrong to cause pain and right to promote happiness) are insights which come to us from a source other than our own sense experience. The same is said to be true of theories of beauty. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 27 5.9. All these points are hotly debated. But it is worth mentioning them if only to point out that the empirical philosophers have not got the thing sewn up completely. There are important areas of human experience within which there is at least room for manoeuvre on the part of the religious believer. If he can show that some knowledge is not derived from the senses he can go on to claim that his knowledge of God is, in a similar way, not from the senses. 5.10. Third criticism: The philosophical school we are considering is not only rooted in empiricism (see paragraph 5.4). Its other source of inspiration is the study of language. This is why these thinkers are often called ‘linguistic philosophers’. Just as a moment ago we questioned whether their attitude to human knowledge and experience was sound, we may also ask whether their treatment of language is sound. Here are some examples of ways in which their view of the role of language may be criticised. 5.11. (i) These philosophers believe that language has only two functions - language either aids clarity of expression and thought by defining words (analytic propositions), or it informs us of new facts about the world (synthetic propositions). It is because language can be used only in these two ways that all meaningful propositions are reduced to the types which were outlined in chapter 3 (3.1-3.5). 5.12. But it may be claimed that this is a serious over simplification of how in fact we do use language. We do indeed say things such as ‘Tom is tall’ (synthetic) and ‘People of six feet or more are tall’ (analytic). But don’t we also say things like ‘Is he tall!’ Suppose I said ‘Tome is leaving the room.’ That would be a meaningful statement because it could be verified empirically, e.g. by sticking a length of cotton over the doorway and seeing if it were broken after Tom had seemed to pass through and so on. But suppose I said, “Tom! Leave the room immediately!’ How could that sentence be verified? After all, nothing might happen and Tom might refuse to move. Does that mean the command is without meaning? Surely not. Let us take another example. Sometimes language does not so much impart information as actually do something in its own right. Examples are ‘Arise, Sir Francis’ and ‘I name this ship Venus’. Here language is actually doing something, but it would seem difficult to show how one would prove or disprove by appeal to the senses that it is really doing anything when the words are spoken. 5.13. These uses of language may be termed the imperative use, the interrogatory use, the performatory use and so on. They are all perfectly normal and in the ordinary commonsense understanding of the expression, meaningful. Yet none of them will easily respond to the demand for verification. This suggests that there may be something wrong with the principle itself as a test of meaning. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 28 5.14. (ii) Another example of the rigid attitude of the older type of linguistic philosophy may be seen in its attitude to paradox. When describing a woman with a Mona Lisa type of beauty, I might at first say, ‘well, she’s beautiful, and yet again she’s not beautiful.’ In strict logical terms this sentence contains a flat contradition and must therefore be meaningless. But we would all understand that such a sentence was seeking to draw attention to an enigmatic quality of the lady’s expression. Such a sentence is saying that the word ‘beautiful’ is not quite sharply defined enough to convey this elusive quality and the paradoxical way of putting it is an invitation to sharpen up the adjectives, or to suggest others of greater precision. So we see that paradox can be a way of pointing to a deeper insight. Paradox can also be a way of trying to hide the fact that one is talking nonsense. The point is that the principles of the logical positivists did not seem to have any resource by which the legitimate and the illegitimate uses of paradox could be distinguished. Summing up The ideas of the logical positivists, expressed particularly in the demand that statements should submit to verification by sense experience, may be challenged in several ways. 1. The principle of verification itself is not free from logical oddity. 2. There may be other ways of knowing apart from the senses. 3. Language itself is more varied and subtle than the verification principle admits. Discuss 1. ‘When we run over our libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume, of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask - does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.’ David Hume 2. Do you agree with Hume that this would be a good way to purge our libraries? 3. Does the study of pure maths create fresh knowledge? Or does it only lead to more and more exact definitions? (a) WAITER WANTED: EXPERIENCE NECESSARY BUT NOT ESSENTIAL. Sign outside Chinese restaurant. (b) ... whose service is perfect freedom. Book of Common Prayer Which of the paradoxes above are genuinely illuminating? How do you tell which is in which class? RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 29 NOTES ON THE DISCUSSION QUESTIONS Chapter 5 1. Note that Hume's first class (abstract reasoning) is like the analytical class of statements, and his second class (experimental reasoning) is like the class of synthetic statements. What about novels? Under the heading of 'divinity' wouldn't some books pass even Hume's test? Biblical commentaries and histories of the church, for example? What about editions of stage plays? Or could we say that these, like poetry, contain matters of psychological fact? In that case, surely text books on psychology would express these facts rather better? 2. I must submit this one to those members of the discussion group who are mathematicians! 3. The question is whether the sentences contain words which are really mutually exclusive in their meaning or if the crucial words are only contrasted, or mutually exclusive in only part of their meaning. So 'necessary' and 'not essential' are mutually exclusive by definition. The Chinese manager did not know the meanings of the English words. But the words 'service' and 'perfect freedom' are not necessarily mutually exclusive. If, for example, freedom is the opportunity to be truly yourself by being faithful to your highest ideals, it is possible that the service of God could provide that opportunity. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 30 6 THE USES OF LANGUAGE 6.1 In the last section it was pointed out that the attitude of the older type of linguistic philosophy towards language was rather narrow. It must not be thought that the objections raised are merely an attempt by Christians to avoid the force of the arguments of the linguistic philosophers, for in fact it is the leaders of that philosophical school who, after further reflection on the nature of language, have again led the way in pointing out many additional uses. 6.2 Here the philosopher Wittgenstein, who was himself one of the pioneers of logical positivism, lists some of the uses to which language is put: Giving orders and obeying them. Describing the appearance of an object, or giving its measurements. Constructing an object from a description (a drawing). Reporting an event. Forming and testing a hypothesis. Presenting the results of an experiment in tables and diagrams. Making up a story and reading it. Play-acting. Singing catches. Making a joke; telling it. Solving a problem in practical arithmetic. Translating from one language into another. Asking, thanking, cursing, greeting, praying. He goes on: ‘It is interesting to compare the multiplicity of kinds of word and sentence, with what logicians have said about the structure of language’ (Philosophical Investigations, Blackwell 1953, pp. 11e-12e). 6.3 It became clear that the strict division into only two types of statement and the demand that to be meaningful a statement should submit to the demand for empirical verification was a good deal more tidy than the actual structure and use of language itself warranted. The earlier linguistic philosophers, although their valuable work had, in its time, marked an important advance, now seem to have been guilty of forcing language into their own preconceived notions of what it should be like. 6.4 ‘The image one gets of verification analysis is too much that of a sausage grinder, receiving a great variety of a cuts of meat but turning out a neat row of uniform wurst (Ferre, Language, Logic and God, Eyre and Spottiswoode 1962, p. 55). How then are we to tell when a sentence is meaningful? For the problems about nonsense and meaning outlined in chapters 1 and 2 are still just as pressing. We have seen enough to know that just as pressing. We have seen enough to know RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 31 that just because a sentence cannot be subject to empirical testing, it does not mean it is without any sense and meaning. As Professor Ferre puts it, ‘To say of a given sentence that it can be verified is not t say anything about the meaningfulness of the sentence, but to characterise it as being a sentence of a particular type, namely, an empirical sentence’ (ibid., p. 63). 6.5 We must state a new principle of meaningfulness as follows: The meaning of language is found in its use. This approach is often called functional analysis because it seeks to discover meaning in the role or function of a sentence. How does functional analysis because it seeks to discover the meaning of a sentence by this method are as follows: 6.6 (I) Examination of the typical case. You must find an example of the word being used in a normal everyday manner, and take its use there as a control for any odd or unusual uses you may have come across. For example, the Zen riddle asks, ‘What becomes of my fist when I open my hand?’ To solve the puzzle of the meaning of the question, let us take some typical cases of the use of the word ‘fist’; ‘He hammered on the table with his fist’; ‘He shook his fist at me’. Now you will quickly see that in all these cases, ‘fist’ refers to the hand being in a particular position - the clenched position. You don’t hammer with the palm of your hand - you slap! And you don’t threaten a man by holding up your hand but by pretending to punch him, i.e. by clenching your fist. The expressions ‘fist’ and ‘open hand’ are therefore mutually exclusive like ‘straight’ and ‘curved’. The answer to the riddle is simply that when one position takes over, the first naturally and by necessity, ceases. The key to the word (describing word (describing the position or shape) not a straightforward noun. 6.7 (ii) The use of a significant comparison. If the meaning of a statements is unclear, we may ask ourselves in what other words could the same thing have been said, or by what other means could the same effect have been achieved. If when travelling in Israel, I observe that people say ‘Shalom’ to one another, the meaning of this word will become clear to me when I notice that shaking hands seems to be a parallel or even substitutionary activity. ‘Shalom’ will be a greeting symbol, like shaking hands. This will be a significant (illuminating) comparison between two similar symbols - a word and a deed. 6.8 (iii) The one who uses the language must be allowed to explain its use. This does not mean that an individual can make up his own use for a word. That is clearly impossible, since words are socially agreed conventions of communication. No one person can therefore actually change the meaning of a word just by whim, although words may be enriched by personal action, as when we say ‘I never knew the meaning of courage until I saw him in action!’ 6.9 All language is social. But society is complex and contains many sub-societies. These may have their own sub-language, and sociologists may and do write special works on the language of the San Francisco beatniks, or the London Chinese restaurant proprietors. These groups may use expressions which would RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 32 be literally meaningless to the outsider, and nonsensical when analysed by the strict and old-fashioned rules of language. What, for example, would we make of the language of tennis, where the score of a player rises from thirty to forty although he only wins one point! This seems mathematically improbable. Do all the points in tennis have the same value? The first is called 'fifteen', the second 'thirty' and the last of the numerical series 'forty'. From this, one could deduce that the first winning action was worth more (15) than the third (only ten). In actual fact the reverse is the case, since the player who gets to 'forty' first has a more critical advantage and one could therefore claim that his latest point was worth more to him, not less! The language of tennis is a private language, agreed amongst the players. It is not without meaning, but the meaning can only be discovered by asking the players what they are trying to convey. 6.10 The language of religion is the language of a sub- culture. There is a group of people who speak like this. They have their traditions, their rituals, their literature. It is within the circle of the group, and not in abstract theory, that we must conclude our search for the meaning of the word 'God'. Summing up The more recent work of linguistic philosophy stresses the variety of language and this leads to new ways of discovering the meaning of language. If the meaning is to be found in the actual use of the language, we must discover what the people who speak the sentences themselves understand by them. Discuss 1. Sometimes students of physics find themselves wondering if anything is really solid. For, they ponder, even things we usually think are solid are in fact whirling masses of electrons. Can this confusion be removed by applying the methods of functional analysis – i.e. can you look for a typical case of the word 'solid' and so on? 2. In 1.5 we looked at the example from Lewis Carroll about the King and Nobody. How would you clarify this problem for the King? 3. Can you think of examples taken from the various disciplines which members of your discussion group study (geography, music etc.) of use of language which might strike the outsider as being odd or misleading? How would you explain the correct use of these expressions to such an interested but ignorant observer? RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 33 NOTES ON THE DISCUSSION QUESTIONS Chapter 6 1. Typical cases of the word 'solid' might be 'I was back on solid earth again'. 'I struck him a solid blow to the body.' 'The Australian eleven have now built up a pretty solid score.' 'You can trust him – he's as solid as a rock.' In these cases we see that the word 'solid' is used when one wants to express that aspect of matter which resists penetration by the human body. or which meets the human body with firm resistance. From this comes the metaphorical use, when 'solid' means reliable, trustworthy, that which will support and maintain. There are other ways of regarding matter. One can look upon it not as something resisting the body, but as that which is composed of electric particles and so on. The word 'solid' will not apply to matter when it is thought of in this way. But is it solid? For it is obvious that there are substances which resist the pressure of the human body and things which do this are really solid – that is what the word 'solid' means – just that. 2. Child's play at this stage. Read paragraph 1.5 again! 3. Note that good examples of this sort of language can often be found in current fashions, e.g. the words associated with the flower power movement of 1967 and with the student protest movements of 1968 – 'sit-in', 'rigid power structure', etc. Many words. were used by drug takers, e.g. turn-on, drop-out, high. One needs to distinguish between technical words which have no meaning outside their technical use, and words which are in everyday use like 'high') but are given a special use by a sub- group. The latter are the interesting ones. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 34 7 'GOD' AGAIN 7.1 If we want to find out what religious words mean, we must ask how religious people use these words. It is clear that religious language is used by believers for many different purposes. Think of a big evangelistic meeting, and everybody singing 'Rock of ages, cleft for me'. Or think of the words 'Our Father, which art in heaven, hallowed be thy name.' Think of the believer, who in a time of difficulty repeats to himself the words of the Bible, 'The Lord is my Shepherd, I shall not want.' And again, there is the theological lecturer in a university, who says, 'Today we come to the doctrine of the work and person of Jesus Christ.' Religious language is bewildering in the richness and variety of its use – for worship and praise, for prayer and devotion, for study and systematization. The following pointers to its use may be useful. 7.2 (a) If we want to get at the typical use of a religious expression, we must, in this case of the Christian religion, look up the word in the Bible, the creeds and confessions, and the way it is used in the worship of the church. All too often sceptical critics take a word in a sense which does less than justice to its normal religious use, and then proceed to criticize it. 'Sacrifice' is sometimes thought a bloody, barbaric and brutal conception because this is what the word conjures up in the mind of the normal educated person of today; but to find out what Christians mean when they describe Christ's death as a sacrifice, one must study not only the use of the expression in the New Testament, but also in the Hebrew religion, where it has special overtones which are of great importance for the correct understanding of the idea. We are all familiar with the sceptic who objects to the word 'God' and whose argument reveals that his own idea of the meaning of the word is by no means the same as that of Christians. 7.3 (b) It is also important to see that when religious people use certain phrases the importance they attach to them is often not at the literal level. When for example Christians speak of Christ's Ascension to heaven, they are not (or ought not to be !) upset by the observation that since direction is relative the notion of 'ascending' can have no absolute significance. The expression 'He ascended into heaven' is not a special indication of the whereabouts of Christ, or of heaven. It is a way of expressing the supreme place given to Christ in the life and devotion of the church, and also of his right to a more universal acclaim in the world as a whole. It is, in other words, a value-judgment about Christ. It can be seen then that the Christians discussed in chapter 4 who claimed that religious statements were expressive of religious feelings and attitudes were correct, although their view does not exhaust the meaning of these religious expressions. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 35 7.4 The sceptic may, however, readily admit that religious language has the uses so far mentioned, but he may argue that the language of religion is nevertheless without any objective meaning. He may claim that words such as 'God' and 'The Holy Spirit' do not refer to anything other than the emotions of believers. He may say that we are still like the people who told one another the story of the square circle, but although he may now feel rather more sympathy for the people who talk like this and may be ready to con-cede that the symbol of the square circle does fulfil some quite legitimate roles in religious life, he will think that it is still a concept which simply cannot be imagined or conceived of by the mind and is therefore void of genuine significance. 7.5 Now the person who believes in God will have to agree that the logic of the way he uses the word 'God' is unusual. The word certainly does obey very odd rules. In some ways it acts like somebody's name – like 'David'. For Christians, when they pray, say, 'O God...'. But when you talk about 'knowing David' or 'meeting David' you mean that you have done certain things – you have spoken to David, been in the same room with him, shaken hands with him and so on. Christians do speak of 'knowing God' but they do not refer to the same sort of things when they are asked what they mean. They refer to an 'awareness of God's presence', an 'inner certainty', a 'consciousness of being loved and forgiven'. In some ways, meeting David is like meeting God, but in other ways it is not. So the word 'God' does not follow exactly the same rules as the word 'David'. 7.6 Again, in some ways the word 'God' acts like a generalization such as 'the average man'. For Christians say that God, like the average man, is not to be found in any particular place or at any special moment of time; he is, like the average man, universal. The average man is abstract – God is as least not concrete! On the other hand, the average man is only an abstraction; there is no such being; but the Christian maintains that the word 'God' does correspond to real being. 7.7 The word 'God' does indeed obey conflicting laws. It is not the only word in the English language which has this characteristic. Consider the word 'point'. According to the geometers, a point is 'somewhere' and yet, a palpable contradiction, it has no actual size – it occupies no space. Here again, however, there is a difference between 'point' and 'God'. For geometers agree that the point does not exist; it is a convenient symbol for an abstraction. But Christians maintain that God does exist. 7.8 Let us for a moment suppose that there is indeed a being corresponding to the word 'God'. This would be a unique being, for God is held to be beyond space and time, infinite in power and knowledge and love, experienced by men and women yet not reducible to a human experience. If there were such a being, he would be a very odd, a very mysterious and strange being. And of course Christians claim just that – that God is fully mysterious. But clearly, if he were to exist, and if we were to try to talk about him, the effort of describing such a being would inevitably put the ordinary laws RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 36 of language under great strain. For these rules of language have been evolved to describe 'David' and 'the average man' and 'point'. We would expect a word referring to a supreme being of this sort to obey unusual and even contradictory rules. 7.9 So here we have rather a nice balance. The believer, impelled by certain experiences he has had, feels he must speak of such a being and accepts the strange word 'God' as a natural consequence. The sceptic, not having any particular reason to speak of such a being, maintains that he can give no meaning at all to such an odd word. 7.10 It is important to remember that the critic we are considering here is not saying that he does not think there is enough evidence for the existence of God. He is not asking for proof that there is a God. He is saying that he cannot give the word 'God' any meaning; it seems to be such an odd, contradictory conception that he finds himself incapable of imagining it at all. Can we find some ways then of explaining to such a person what the word means? Is it possible to fix the meaning of the word in some way so that at least it becomes possible to see that the word describes something? 7.11 As human beings we have the experience of being partly 'in time' and partly 'not in time'. For we speak of moments when 'time stood still' and we know that people's consciousness of time can be artificially disturbed – by drugs, by longdistance air flights and so on. By imagination we can live in the past and in the future. This is, as far as we know, a quality of human life alone; other animals do not appear to share these experiences. In the same way. we are 'in space' and yet 'not in space'. We say 'as swift as a thought' indicating our ability to transcend the limits of distance in some sense. Many people speak of a soul, or a mind, or some aspect of human personality not located in space, and (whether this is the best description of personality or not) this also indicates some such experience of being 'not in space'. Now it makes no difference to the argument if these experiences are illusory. The point is that, having had them, it is possible for us to imagine what a being might be like who possessed these qualities, or had (or thought he had) these experiences much more radically than we do. We could then even imagine, although it would begin to become just too mysterious to have the idea very clearly, what a being would be like who transcended space and time completely. This, however, is not an argument for the existence of God. There may, of course, be no such being, but what the argument does show is that the idea of such a being is at least possible, it has some meaning. It does not matter if the idea is vague – Christians agree that their knowledge of God is limited and, in many important respects, vague. 7.12 What about the other aspects of the idea of God? Is it possible to gain some indications of what is meant by saying the idea includes notions such as 'infinite', 'omni- potent', 'necessary' and so on? Many people have a feeling of wonder about the universe and they express this wonder by asking such questions as 'What's it all about?' or 'Where does it all lead to? ' or 'What lies behind it all?' This feeling is that the world is somehow dependent, that it RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 37 derives from some source other than itself. This again is not an argument for the existence of God. The feeling we describe may be some kind of superstitious hangover from the remote past. But the argument does show that if we can have this feeling about the world, we can, by a further stretch of the imagination, imagine a being, an entity, a world, which would not be dependent, but utterly self-contained and independent. This would give us a 'fix' on the meaning of 'infinite God', for he is regarded as one who is not derived but exists in his own right. 7.13 (d) One final use of religious language must be mentioned. Religious statements are linked with one another so as to form systems. In the international religions of today, Islam, Buddhism, Christianity etc.., these form an all-embracing network of attitudes and beliefs. Sometimes these systems are called 'metaphysical' systems, because they assume the reality of a sphere other than the material. This system as a whole provides a way of interpreting a11 the experiences of life. 7.14 There is a sense in which such a religious system functions rather like a great scientific hypothesis, in that many facets of experience and life are included and brought together, but on the other hand, religious systems do not provide us with literal descriptions of what reality is like – as if heaven really were 'up there'. A system like this may not describe literal reality, but it may nevertheless correspond to some experienced reality. For, after all, if (as Christians claim) their view of things does in fact illuminate our experience of morals, our experience of human relationships, even our sense experience, we would have to ask why this should be so. Why should the Christian faith prove to be so truly illuminating as an interpretation of life unless it does in fact correspond to some reality about life? Members of other faiths would be right to ask themselves, and us, the same question. 7.15 Like other systems, the Christian system can and must be assessed and judged. The sceptical philosopher asks the Christian, as we have seen. what difference there would have to be in the world for his view of things to be made false. The answer could be that many things might count against the validity of the Christian system. The evil and suffering in the world do count against it strongly, although not decisively. If the model around which the whole system is built, the life of Jesus Christ, were to be found intolerably unhistorical that would make a difference. 'Intolerably' – for Christians vary about the degree of historical reliability which can be tolerated within the Christian system. But all or almost all agree that if, for example, it could be shown that Christ had never even lived, that would count strongly against the Christian system. But all these possibilities enhance the Christian claim to be saying something at least full of meaning. Unlike the case of the elephant in paragraph 2.6, we can say what would count against the Christian faith. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 38 7.16 (e) Finally, the Christian system can be compared with the systems of other religions by asking the following questions: (i) Which is the more consistent system? A system which contradicts itself will be at a disadvantage. (ii) Which is the more coherent system. That is, in which system are the various 'parts' most closely linked together? (iii) Which system is most all-embracing? A system which illuminated all the experiences of life would correspond to the full reality of life more perfectly than one which threw light upon only some aspects of experience. It is not intended to suggest that Christianity would always come off best in any such comparison. For example, on point (i) Islam might be better than Christianity, since it has no Trinity. Point (iii) also assumes a prior religious outlook, for what a Christian finds 'illuminating' may not be so illuminating to a Buddhist. What is illuminating depends on your prior convictions. So perhaps these ways of comparison are too vague. Perhaps your group will be able to suggest better ways of comparing religions? (I am grateful to Professor Smart for these particular observations.) The point of comparing Christianity with other religions is not, at this stage, to establish whether or not one of them is the most convincing – that is a task for another study. The point is simply that since Christianity can be intelligently assessed and compared, it cannot therefore be entirely meaningless. Summing up Religious language has many uses and therefore many meanings. Although profoundly mysterious, its basic ideas are not inexplicably contradictory, nor completely unimaginable. As a system the Christian faith is capable of both logical and experimental analysis and comparison with other faiths. Religious statements may therefore fairly claim to be meaningful. Discuss 1. Is it possible for all religions to be equally true? 2. Is it possible to believe things you don't understand? For it has been said that blind belief is the same as blind unbelief. 3. What are the underlying motives for belief and unbelief? Why, for example, do believers find it difficult to give up their faith in God even when they lose arguments? Why do unbelievers refuse to have faith in God even when sometimes they lose arguments? 4. What is meant by the mystery of God? Is it like the mystery of a detective novel or of a crossword puzzle? Or is it like the mystery of light or of the origin of the sun? Or is it like the mystery of love, the mystery of life itself. Does the word 'mystery' mean different things in these different expressions? * ** ! means that the book is about the same standard of difficulty as these studies, or at least not very much more difficult. means it is a difficult book. means it is a very difficult book. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 39 NOTES ON THE DISCUSSION QUESTIONS Chapter 7 1. If by 'true' one means 'corresponding to actual objective fact' then the answer must be no. If the statement 'There is only one God' does have meaning as a proposition, then it must be possible to contradict it. The statement 'There are many gods' does in fact contradict it. Both statements may be wrong. But both statements cannot be correct. If, however, religious statements merely describe one's own feelings, then they do not and cannot contradict each other. If I say I feel hot and you say you feel cold we are not contradicting each other. If I say 'I think there is only one God' and you say you think there are several gods, we are not contradicting each other. We are simply comparing each other's mental states. This series of studies has tried to show that religious statements are more than reports of feelings and may correspond to objective truth. They at least claim to be true, and are entitled to be at last investigated. Notice that when people say 'It may not be true for you but it's true for. me', what they seem to mean is 'It may not be significant or important for you but it is: for me.' If something is true, i.e. corresponds to the facts, it must be true for everyone. A lot of confusion would be avoided if we reserved the word 'truth' for this objective sense, and used words like 'significant' or. 'important' to describe our own psychological reactions. 2. You cannot give intelligent assent to something unless you have at least some understanding of to what it is you are giving assent. You cannot really put your trust in a person who is utterly unknown to you- such trust would not be intelligent committal but irresponsible blindness. Blind belief and blind unbelief are similar in that both are entered into without consideration of the factors involved. But the fact that some understanding is required for intelligent faith does not mean that complete understanding is necessary. Without some knowledge, faith would be superstition. With full knowledge there would be no need for faith at all. Faith is reason exploring, it is reason become courageous, it goes beyond the evidence but it is not actually denied by the evidence. 3. It may be helpful to distinguish between causes and reasons. I may have a belief for a variety of causes. I may have been crossed in love, or have an inferiority complex, or I may have had too much to drink. All of these factors can be causes of my having certain beliefs. The reasons for the truth or falsity of the belief are quite different. America may be the greatest nation in the world for the following reasons: it may be the richest and the most powerful militarily. I may believe this because I am American and emotionally roused by the idea of America. Even if you exposed the causes of my belief, the question of whether there were reasons for believing it would still have to be faced. I may be a Christian (or an atheist) because my parents were. The reasons for believing either Christianity or atheism to be true would be unchanged in either case. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 40 4. Some kinds of mysteries may be unravelled. At the end of the detective story, there is no mystery left. Other kinds of mystery actually become more mysterious the more one goes into them. The mystery of why one's beloved loves one remains a kind of delightful mystery even after years of loving. The mystery of God is surely in the latter class. When God reveals himself, as Christianity and other faiths claim he does, his mystery is not dispelled, but deepened. RMPS Support Materials: Language, Philosophy and Religion 41