Animal Dignity by Craig Duncan A longstanding tradition in moral philosophy, associated most closely with Immanuel Kant but having precursors in the ancient Stoics,1 accounts for moral rightness and wrongness in terms of a moral duty to respect the dignity of humans, a dignity that stems ultimately from our powers of rational agency. And yet, broad-minded though this idea was in the ancient world and in the eighteenth century, it has come now to be viewed by many philosophers as parochial. This is so because it appears to exclude non-human animals from the circle of moral concern. In a recent discussion of the Stoic account of dignity, for instance, Martha Nussbaum writes Reason, language, moral capacity—all these things are seen as worthy of respect and awe at least in part because the beasts, so called, don't have them, because they make us better than others. This view has its moral problems, clearly. It has long been used to deny that we have any obligations of justice toward nonhuman forms of life.2 One can imagine that in ancient times this would hardly have been judged a problem. But with the recent growth in moral consciousness regarding the treatment of nonhuman animals, any view that fails to ground some duties to nonhuman animals risks obsolescence. The same defect has been attributed to Kant’s moral philosophy. Christina Hoff, for instance, speaks of a “seamier side” to Kant’s ethical humanism. His “invidious humanism,” she claims, leads him to deny any direct moral duties toward animals, and in denying this he For discussion of the connections between the ancient Stoics and Kant’s moral philosophy, see Martha C. Nussbaum, “Kant and Stoic Cosmopolitanism,” Journal of Political Philosophy 5:1-25 (1997). 2 Martha Nussbaum, Daedalus 132(1) (Winter 2003), 18. 1 “altogether excludes animals from the moral domain.”3 Indeed, the alleged failure of dignitybased approaches (Stoic, Kantian, or otherwise) to show due moral concern for non-human animals is the subject of an entire book, namely, James Rachels’s Created from Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism.4 Let us call this alleged defect of dignity-based moral approaches “the problem of animal dignity.” It is my aim in this essay to solve this problem. 1. Animal Dignity and Purposive Agency. The problem of animal dignity is indeed a challenging one. The challenge, I think, lies not in believing that some nonhuman animals possess a dignity; I for one find that rather easy to believe. Instead the challenge lies in articulating precisely the nature of animal dignity. By way of tackling this challenge, let me recount a story that one of my colleagues relates about once taking his young son to a circus in town, and discovering there a lone protestor outside the tent silently holding aloft a sign that read "REMEMBER THE DIGNITY OF ELEPHANTS." The sign hit him like a lightning bolt, my colleague said. The protester's point is surely an intelligible one, though we could debate about whether it is genuinely reason enough to avoid all types of circuses. As a second example, think about an eagle whose wings have been clipped to keep it in a zoo's cage; it is not unreasonable to look upon such a creature and feel a keen sense of its loss—even something of a tragic sense of its loss. The key to explaining these reactions, I believe, is the sense that elephants and eagles have some significant powers of agency of their own. It is true that such animals lack the powers Christina Hoff, “Kant’s Invidious Humanism,” Environmental Ethics5 (Spring 1983): 63, 70. Cited in Gerald Gaus, “Respect for Persons and Environmental Values,” pp. 239-264 in Jane Kneller and Sidney Axinn, eds., Autonomy and Community: Readings in Contemporary Kantian Social Philosophy (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998). 4 Oxford University Press, 1990. 3 2 of rational agency that humans possess, for I presume they cannot consciously formulate judgments as to which actions they have reason to perform and which actions they have reason to avoid. However, many nonhuman animals surely are able to have conscious experiences (they feel pain, have felt needs and wants, etc.)5 and are able to act in a purposive manner (e.g. as when an animal goes to a river bank to drink), even though they admittedly do not have conscious thoughts along the lines "I am now doing such-and-such in order to achieve this-andthat." Referring to these abilities as the "powers of purposive agency," my suggestion is that creatures with these powers possess a type of dignity, even when these powers fall short of truly rational agency. My claim, then, shall be that where one finds purposive agency one also finds dignity. I regard this as a normative claim rather than a meta-ethical claim, that is, in saying this I do not purport to be defining the concept of dignity. Hence, before turning to a defense of the normative claim just mentioned, a few words are in order about the definition of concept of dignity itself. One possible definition is due to Stephen Darwall, who defines dignity as “[a] moral status or standing that is the appropriate object of (recognition) respect.”6 This is a suggestive definition, but I have two worries about it. First, if indeed Darwall intends this to be a strict definition of dignity, then it has a disappointing implication: since a reference to respect is built right into the definition, it turns out that the claim “One ought to show respect for another person’s dignity” is merely an analytic truth, rather than a substantive moral truth. Second, I 5 For a state-of-the-art look at the issue of animal consciousness see Colin Allen, "Animal Pain," Noûs 38:617-43 (2004). 6 Stephen Darwall, Philosophical Ethics (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1998), p. 234; this definition for “dignity” comes from the glossary section at the end of the book. Note that this same glossary defines “recognition respect” as “The attitude of recognizing someone’s dignity.” Hence the definitions as written are circular. For a more 3 worry the definition is overbroad. For example, Andy Warhol’s famous soup can paintings probably merit respectful treatment—one shouldn’t burn them as campfire fuel, for instance— but do they really possess a dignity? Should one really explain one’s moral unwillingness to burn them as a case of showing respect for the dignity of the paintings? I doubt this.7 Hence I want to propose a distinct definition of dignity: the concept of dignity is just the concept of a special sort of value, namely, what we might call “self-originating value.” (We might also, following Kant, describe an object that self-originates its value to be an “end in itself,” though I won’t employ this phrase in what follows.) Warhol’s paintings lack this; though they are valuable in their own right (that is, they are not just instrumentally valuable), their value was created by the artist: Warhol created the value that now inheres, so to speak, in the paintings. The paintings did not create their own value; they are the creation rather than the creator. By contrast—to temporarily advert back to the standard case of persons—persons, while of course created by their parents, are not solely the creation of their parents, for in virtue of their significant powers of rational agency, persons have significant (albeit still limited) powers of self-creation. (Note that here I purport to be elucidating the concept of dignity rather than vindicating it. It may be that our ideas of self-creation, and free will generally, are illusory, and detailed account of recognition respect that might remove this circularity, see Darwall’s “Two Kinds of Respect,” Ethics 88:1 (1977), pp. 36-49. 7 Perhaps one might try to rebut this objection by arguing that paintings are not fitting objects of recognition respect. Darwall, however, apparently does not want his notion of recognition respect to be so limited. In his article introducing the notion of recognition respect, he defines it thusly: “There is a kind of respect which can have any of a number of different sort of things as its object an which consists, most generally, in a disposition to weigh appropriately in one’s deliberations some feature of the thing in question and act accordingly” (ibid., p. 38). As examples of possible objects of recognition respect, Darwall lists “someone’s feelings, the law, for the judge (in a legal proceeding), for nature, and so on” (p. 39). It is true that Darwall goes on (p.40) to define a narrower sense of recognition respect, namely, moral recognition respect. Some fact or feature is an object of moral recognition respect “if inappropriate consideration or weighing of that fact or feature would result in behavior that is morally wrong.” I don’t think a switch to this narrower notion would solve the problem, however. For burning a Warhol painting probably is morally wrong. What is more, defining dignity as “a moral status or standing that is the appropriate object of moral recognition respect” does not avoid the first problem for the definition noted above, namely, that it results in it being merely analytically true that it is morally wrong not to show respect for another person’s dignity. 4 must fall prey to a purely mechanistic picture of the natural world. This would entail that dignity is likewise an illusion. There is a real question of the compatibility of our ideas regarding dignity and mechanistic ideas of nature. I cannot hope to answer this question here.) Suppose I am right to identify the concept of dignity with the concept of self-originating value. Where does this leave my earlier claim that wherever one finds purposive agency, there one finds dignity? Is this simply a contingent regularity, much like the claim that wherever one finds a creature with a heart, there one finds a creature with a kidney? I do not think so. Instead, I believe that my earlier claim exhibits the same sort of necessity as does the claim “wherever one finds water, there one finds H2O.” In this regard, some terminology developed by Allan Gibbard is instructive. The concept of water, says Gibbard, is just that which must be known by competent users of the term “water.” This is distinct from the concept of H2O; young school children, for instance, have some concept of water even though they may never have heard of hydrogen or oxygen, and the same goes for adults who lived before Lavoisier’s discovery of H2O. By contrast, the property of being water just is the property of being H2O. In order to keep straight this distinction between concept and property, Gibbard suggests the following technical vocabulary: the term ‘water’ expresses the concept of water; the property of being H2O realizes the concept of water; and the term ‘water’ signifies the property.8 Likewise, my proposal is that the term “dignity” expresses the concept of self-originating value; the property of being a purposive agent realizes this concept; and the term “dignity” signifies this property. My task in what follows, then, is to explain why the property of being a purposive agent realizes the concept of self-originating value. 8 Allan Gibbard, Thinking How to Live (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003), p. 115; see also pp. 29-33. 5 2. Purposive Agency and “Willful Integrity” Why should we think that purposive agents have the special sort of value necessary for dignity? This is a hard question to answer, and my thoughts in this regard are somewhat speculative. Let us use the term "purposive agents" to refer to creatures that possess powers of purposive agency that fall short of rational agency. My suggestion is that purposive agents still possess an integrity that rocks and blades of grass and drops of rain and other natural phenomena lack. Purposive agents like elephants and eagles are still in some important sense capable of living a life, unlike the other natural items just listed. They are not merely pushed around by forces wholly external to themselves, devoid of any significant powers of their own. They are not merely "dust in a wind," to borrow a phrase from the popular 70s rock tune by that title (an effective metaphor indeed if one wishes, like the band Kansas who wrote the tune, to puncture our typically exalted view of ourselves). To put the point slightly differently, it is easy to view an entity that is devoid of significant powers of its own as merely a bit part of a much larger system, and hence as devoid of a separate integrity of its own. By contrast, it is much harder to view a conscious creature with powers of its own in this way; the integrity such creatures possess seems to me to be a plausible source of value. I want to stress that in my view not just any integrity will suffice for dignity. For instance, I suppose that a snowflake could be said to possess a type of integrity (compare it to, say, a snow drift), but in my judgment it is too much of a stretch to speak of the "dignity" of a snowflake (imagine scolding children who are busy making snowballs for failing to respect the dignity of individual snowflakes!). Instead I have in mind the integrity that comes with powers of one's own, and in particular with what I have called the powers of purposive agency (this latter qualification seems necessary, otherwise we might have to reckon hurricanes to possess dignity, inasmuch as they possess both a sort of integrity and powers of their own). Perhaps we 6 can refer to the powerful sort of integrity that realizes dignity as "willful integrity," inasmuch as non-rational purposive agents can be said to have a "will" of some sort, even if this will is not as free as (we like to think) ours is. As an aside, it is worth noting that the connection I am positing between power on the one hand (in particular, the power of purposive agency) and dignity on the other should not really be surprising, I think. Not so long ago, after all, only those people who had significant power over others were believed to possess dignity. (Indeed, this substratum of meaning still persists in our use of the term "dignitaries" to refer to individuals in positions of power.) Nowadays doctrines of equal human dignity are more likely to hold sway; these doctrines sever the connection between dignity and power-over-others, finding instead the locus of morally valuable power to lie within each human individual. It is hence unsurprising that a further expansion of the "circle of dignity," so to speak, to include nonhuman animals should retain a connection with power of some sort. 9 Returning to the idea of purposive agency constituting a sort of “willful integrity,” I believe that the connection between this idea of willful integrity and the idea of self-originating value—which I earlier took to define the concept of dignity—is not hard to fathom. For surely the idea of a self brings with it the idea of an integral whole—a self as a being separate from other selves. (Putting it this way suggests that the idea of integrity lies implicit in John Rawls’s famous notion of “the separateness of persons”: persons [that is, selves] are not just some cogs in a larger whole but are wholes themselves, and hence are separate in some important sense from other wholes.) And the reference to “will” in the phrase “willful integrity” carries with it the idea of a power to originate action. As a result I believe the idea of willful integrity can serve as 9 For some further brief speculations on the connections between dignity and power, see Joel Feinberg, "Some Conjectures About the Concept of Respect," Journal of Social Philosophy 4:1-3 (1973). 7 a bridge linking the ideas of purposive agency, on the one hand, and self-originating value, on the other hand, as the following schema suggests: Hence I conclude it is plausible to believe that the property of purposive agency realizes the concept of dignity. 3. Non-Animal Dignity? We ought to ask, however, whether the view defended above is too restrictive. For it is not unheard of for people sometimes to speak of, say, giant redwood trees and mountains as possessing dignity. Americans sing of "purple mountains majesty" in "God Bless America," for instance; does this not impute a dignity to mountains? My account of dignity in terms of agency, however, rules out such an imputation as at best misguided, at worst unintelligible, for surely mountains and trees, lacking any sort of consciousness, are not purposive agents. It is true that a tree's growth is sometimes susceptible to teleological explanation (e.g. when it grows toward the sun). Surely, though, this is not enough to qualify it as a purposive agent, otherwise a refrigerator, say, would likewise qualify since its "behavior" too can be described in teleological 8 terms ("it began its cooling cycle in order to bring the temperature back to the level of the thermostat"). Even if this counterexample could be avoided on the grounds, say, that refrigerators are human-made artifacts, other counterexamples threaten. For all I know, for instance, the "behavior" of mold can be teleologically explained, but pace "biocentric egalitarians" like Paul Taylor, mold surely does not thereby possess a dignity deserving of respect.10 Hence I conclude that an account of dignity rooted in the notion of purposive agency cannot ground a literal attribution of dignity to non-animal natural objects. But as just noted, people sometimes talk this way. Thus this may be thought a problem for my account. In reply, I want to make two points. First, it is not clear to me we should accept such imputations of dignity. Perhaps instead of recognizing the dignity of mountains, for instance, those who speak of this are best interpreted as displaying awe at their size, or reverence for their beauty. In an engaging, recent discussion of reverence, for instance, Paul Woodruff defines it as follows: “Reverence is the well-developed capacity to have the feelings of awe, respect, and shame when these are the right feelings to have.”11 In Woodruff’s view, then, reverence is a broader phenomenon than respect, inasmuch as it encompasses shame and awe as well.12 Hence, I suspect that the feelings frequently inspired by mountains, trees, and so on, are better described as feelings of awe at these objects’ presence rather than feelings of respect for a dignity they possess. Suppose, though, that I am wrong about this; suppose those who speak of the dignity of such natural objects insist that it is indeed dignity they mean to speak of. In this case I would wish to make a second sort of reply from within my account of dignity in terms of purposive agency. According to this reply, the cases in question are the exceptions that prove the rule, so 10 11 Paul W. Taylor, Respect for Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press) Paul Woodruff, Reverence: Renewing a Forgotten Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 8. 9 to speak. For there seem to be two natural ways of explaining our willingness to speak of such entities as dignified. To begin with, it is natural to speak of a mountain "imposing its will" on us, in the sense of standing as an obstacle potentially blocking our way; we might also speak of a mountain-climber "struggling against" the mountain. The metaphorical reference to a mountain's will—that is, the metaphorical reference to its agency—makes it natural to speak figuratively of the mountain's "dignity." I am not sure this idea is enough on its own, however. If we rely exclusively on this line of thought to impute dignity to a mountain, we might also be forced, alas, to impute dignity to a hurricane, for it can certainly "impose its will" on us. An additional line of thought provides the necessary assistance. For surely it matters that mountains (and some types of trees) endure for dramatically long periods of time, whereas hurricanes do not. It is easy to view this endurance metaphorically as an achievement, as the impressively successful execution of a purposive striving to stay in existence. Consider for instance this passage from “The Bleeding Heart,” a “prose poem” by Mary Oliver: I know a bleeding heart plant that has thrived for sixty years if not more and has never missed a spring without rising and spreading itself into a glossy bush, with many small red hearts dangling. Don’t you think that deserves a little thought?13 More explicit in its affirmation of respect is the following passage by John Steinbeck: The redwoods, once seen, leave a mark or create a vision that stays with you always. No one has ever successfully painted or photographed a redwood tree. The feeling they produce is not transferable. From them comes silence and awe. It’s not their unbelievable stature, nor the color which seems to shift and vary under your eyes, no, they are ambassadors from another time. They have the mystery of ferns that disappeared a million years ago in to the coal of the carboniferous era. They carry their own light and shade. The vainest, most slap-happy and irreverent of men, in the presence 12 13 See ibid., pp. 9, 65-66. Mary Oliver, Blue Iris: Poems and Essays (Boston: Beacon Press, 2004), p. 17 10 of redwoods, goes under a spell of wonder and respect. Respect—that’s the word. One feels the need to bow to unquestioned sovereigns.14 In short, I contend that attributions of dignity to natural objects, though not literally true, draw their metaphorical strength from the ease with which we speak of some natural objects as imposing their wills on us, as well as the ease with which we speak of endurance through the ages as an achievement. If I am right about this, then even apparent exceptions to the connection between dignity and purposive agency end up confirming it. 4. Conclusion I have defended an account of dignity according to which the concept of dignity is defined by the idea of self-originating value. I have furthermore argued that beings that are purposive agents—beings that can act for a purpose—are beings that possess dignity in this sense. They are a source of value in virtue of their being something other than a mere bit part of larger system that is completely subordinate to the system’s ends—that is, they are valuable in virtue of possessing an integrity that comes from possessing a will. Admittedly, this is a rather barebones account. Much more remains to be said. Are nonhumans equal in dignity to humans? (My answer to this would be No.) What sort of duties does this sort of purposive agency ground? Do we have the same set of duties toward non-human animals that we have toward humans? (Again, no.) I hope to answer these questions on another occasion. For now, I will be content if I have shown that the foundational notion of dignity can plausibly be broadened to encompass the non-human animal world. Word Count: 3824 14 John Steinbeck, Travels with Charley (New York: The Viking Press, 1961), pp. 168-69 (emphasis added); quoted in Woodruff, op. cit., p. 222. 11