1 .)1002(The First Hundred Years of Psychoanalysis: A Century of Internal Resistance. Free Associations 8D: (4) 576-590 Saul S. Haimovich My aim in this paper is to show the strong resistance to the empirical application of Freudian research principles, especially of the ‘fundamental rule’ for the discovery of the unconscious, that marks the first hundred years of psychoanalysis. Research by means of free association is deeply rooted in Freud's concept of the unconscious as a realm in which logical rules are not valid. Though it is not possible to reach a full reconstruction of the unconscious by conscious means, free association allows the nearest approximation. Below I offer a comparative analysis of the main aspects of traditional psychoanalysis - social, educational, theoretical and technical - as they developed in the hundred years after the publication of The Interpretation of Dreams (Freud, 1901) and the beginnings of the psychoanalytic movement (1902). I will examine these to find out if, in their present form, they allow the application of the analytical method. My assumption is that if such application is impossible and free association processes in personal analysis are even obstructed, then psychoanalysis as it is being practiced now is driven by defensive needs. )2The Social and Educational Aspects of Psychoanalysis I examine these two aspects jointly because psychoanalysts' education determines the social structure and dynamics of psychoanalytic - 675 institutes. These educational and social aspects have been fully described in literature elsewhere (Kirsner, 1998; Rustin, 1991; Young, 1990, 1996). Kirsner studied the structure, dynamic and development of American societies and institutes and we can generalize his findings to all societies belonging to the International Psychoanalytic Association as they all have the same structure. Psychoanalytic organizations are divided into two, the psychoanalytic association and the institute. One part, the psychoanalytic association, is composed mainly of those who completed the educational program. Teachers and candidates, on the other hand, make up the institute, the educational part. An educational committee consisting of didactic psychoanalysts directs the institute: they are in charge of education and nomination of new analysts. The association functions as a stage for lectures and it does not have any control over education. Rustin and Kirsner agree that psychoanalytic education is the central element to be considered if we want to understand the structure, dynamics, politics and changes that characterize these organizations. According to the psychoanalytic educational model, a candidate must participate in seminars, and take supervision and didactic analysis. Psychoanalysts who are educated by means of another type of programme are not considered as qualified (Bergmann, 1997, p. 81.) Kirsner argued that these organizations suffer from endemic problems (see also Bergmann, 1997; Eisold, 1994; Kernberg, 1986, 1996; Stelzer, 1986; Wallerstein, 1993). Besides sectarianism, dogmatism and the schools' phenomena, didactic analysts' have disproportionate power, originating in their right to analyze candidates and to decide who will qualify as an analyst. Kirsner described phenomena like nepotism, favouritism, and candidates' fear to express uncommon opinions or new ideas. Political and ideological struggles and rivalries are fought around issues like, who will be appointed as supervisor, and who has the right to train? (Arlow, 1972, p. 559; Kirsner, 2000, pp. 13-71.) 2 Kirsner concluded that most psychoanalytic institutes are unfree associations of psychoanalysts that have lost the spirit of free inquiry. They teach the truth of the ‘anointed’, conformity is awarded and those who ask questions and expose differences are rejected (Kirsner, 2000, p. 10.) Rustin interpreted similar findings differently. He argued that the oligarchic, authoritarian and arbitrary nature - 677 of the International Psychoanalytical Association is not only understandable but even indispensable to psychoanalytic work. Since psychoanalysis crucially involves the sharing of secrets, he argued, this requires of these organizations, much like other secret societies, to have a hierarchic, secret, ceremonial structure (Rustin, 1991, p. 4.) While not denying the importance of Kirsner's research, I think that his ethical and political criticism does not fully refute Rustin's argument. Though these ethical and internal political problems are serious, they are not psychoanalysis' main trouble. Psychoanalysis' big problem is a scientific one, namely the inappropriateness of its social-educational structure to the kind of scientific work psychoanalysts must do. Though historical and sociological academic studies, like Kirsner's, are important to expose collective defences against the application of psychoanalysis, much work could be saved through an early examination of the way in which psychoanalysis is practiced. This early examination would consist in a simple comparison and evaluation of any theoretical, social, technical and educational feature of the work of psychoanalysts in terms of how they accord with psychoanalytic principles. As said, psychoanalysis demands the study of our free associations: the work of psychoanalysis is not accomplished when this crucial condition is ignored. In order to make psychoanalysis possible, both as a praxis and as a theoretical-scientific model, organizations should not obstruct free association. The examination of psychoanalytic organizations and their educational model shows that they cannot do proper psychoanalytic work. The way in which didactic analysts teach and evaluate candidates obstructs any true psychoanalytic process of free association. When the analysand must agree with his analyst's and supervisor's opinions and theories true psychoanalysis is impossible. When psychoanalysts and supervisors also evaluate they become representatives of the superego; they cannot consequently analyze their own ambition for power, authority and prestige. Free association is abandoned as a central research principle when the analyst who teaches the method must serve other lords. Therefore, paradoxically, it is not possible to educate psychoanalysts at ‘psychoanalytic’ institutes, simply due to their basic institutional-educational structure. This leaves us with a disturbing question: can we imagine any social organization that will fit the demands of free - 675 association? And if the answer to this question is no, then is true psychoanalysis grounded on free association possible at all? I shall not attempt to answer these questions here. I would only like to point out that the typical structure of current psychoanalytic organizations does not reflect a sufficiently profound consideration of their own implementation of the principles of Freud's new science. That is to say, psychoanalysts have not bothered to examine the relationship between their institutions and Freudian working methods. As a result they contribute to a distorted public and academic conception of psychoanalysis. It must be said that Freud himself was not fully aware of the fact that he built the foundations for a movement that would, to a significant extent, contradict his science. I believe that 3 psychoanalysts committed to free association will be able to create social organizations fitted to it. )1The Theoretical Aspect The theoretical aspect is an important element of the collective defensive structure that has developed among psychoanalysts. Barratt stated that psychoanalysts ‘only rarely’ explore their own ‘rationalities’ and their resistance to the psychoanalytic process as they become expressed in their theoretical activity (Barratt, 1994, pp. 6978). This state of affairs becomes even more serious when analysts adopt a theory or concept because it is accepted in their professional milieu without questioning its fitness to their associative world. To my best knowledge only Barratt proposed to study analysts' theoretical activity by trying to classify different kinds of defensive attitudes. In addition to this I believe it is of special importance to analyze the defensive theoretical foundations of psychoanalysis as it is practiced. What I will do below is exactly that. Before setting out on this I shall offer some clarification about psychoanalysts' theoretical activity. Freud's statement that free association is the ‘fundamental rule’ for the study of the unconscious created a new scientific situation which has until now not fully been understood, either by psychoanalysts or by anyone else dealing with psychoanalysis. What has been especially ignored is that with the foundation of this principle the concept of theory as foundation of science changed radically, at least in the field of psychoanalysis. In Freudian science, the theory that - 675 analysts use is part of the empirical phenomena that they must study. Its social character, that is, the fact that a large group accepts a theory, cannot be used as a justification for not analyzing and considering it as external to associative phenomena. But psychoanalysts do not scrutinize their theories and concepts in analysis. In this they follow scientific method as it is practiced in physics and philosophy. This adoption by psychoanalysis of the theoretical foundation of other empirical sciences, according to which theory and empirics are distinguished, has greatly affected the nature of psychoanalysis. The theory-empirics dichotomy may be sustainable when the objects of study are physical but it fails in the study of human phenomena because here theories themselves are part of the matter under observation. This situation is well demonstrated in clinical presentations, when empirical material is always misleadingly exposed to exemplify a concept or a theory. A possible objection against my argument is that the analysis of theories itself will always again be informed by some other theory or concept. I fully accept this but claim that it does not contradict the view previously presented. An important element of Freudian analytical method is the assumption that the researcher cannot be aware of everything: analysts must decide when they stop their analysis of foundations and establish the most convenient working principles for themselves, while being aware that these principles will at some point be the object of further analysis. What matters is not that they are influenced by this or that theory but rather if they take their theoretical decisions after careful reflection on the appropriateness of these decisions to their own associative world, so as to avoid inconsistency between what they do in their work and what they say they do. Theoretical decisions should not be a result of blind adoption and internalization of theories merely because they are accepted in the professional milieu. At this stage in the history of psychoanalysis it is especially important to analyze the concepts and theories considered essential to psychoanalysis because they tend to function as 4 defensive mechanisms. The scope of this paper forces me to postpone the treatment of the subject of how to develop good psychoanalytic theories and concepts, i.e. theories and concepts that suit analytic work. As said, in this part of my paper I will show only how we can investigate the suitability of theories, concepts, theoretical - 650 mechanisms and theoretical activity (in general, what analysts say they do) to work by means of free association (that is, what analysts should be doing). I propose that the analytical process should always include such an examination so as to avoid defensive fixation of concepts and theories and the consequent failure of free associative activity. To exemplify the procedure I have in mind, I will look at psychiatric concepts that form the basis of psychoanalytic work. An Analysis of Psychiatric Psychoanalysis Psychopathological concepts and descriptions of illnesses in Freudian terms constitute a considerable part of psychoanalytic thought. It is one of the strongest social defences against a fuller application of Freudian scientific principles. Freud's attitude towards the relation between psychoanalysis and psychiatry was complex and contradictory. On the one hand, Freud himself warned us on many occasions against turning psychoanalysis into a branch of psychiatry. He was convinced that the adoption of psychoanalysis by psychiatry was no more than disguised resistance and hostility (Freud, 1926b, p. 183). He stated clearly that his science was to be considered part of neither medicine, nor medical psychology and psychopathology, but rather as constituting the very foundation of any psychology (p. 252). He even thought medical studies to be unnecessary to psychoanalysts (Jones, 1953-7, vol. 3, p. 289), and rejected any attempt to draw conclusions about the nature of psychoanalysis from its medical applications (Freud, 1926b, p. 252-3.) On the other hand, Freud did not categorically exclude psychiatric conceptions and kept a strong connection with psychiatric thinking by fitting his theories to psychiatric nosology. This compromise left its marks on psychoanalytic thought. While psychiatric thinking defines illnesses according to manifest symptoms and their combinations (Ackercknecht, 1957, pp. 60-81; Binswanger, 1936; Menninger et al., 1958, p. 6; Zilboorg and Henry, 1941, 379-478), Freud proposed to refer to what can be called ‘unconscious symptoms’. For this purpose he used his and Breuer's formula for the definition of hysteria as distortions of ideo-energetic processes resulting from different mechanisms of repression of painful thoughts and feelings (see - 652 Haimovich, 1995, pp. 150-164; 183-202). Freud defined hysteria as the outcome of the repression to the unconscious of a painful idea and the subsequent displacement of its energy to the body. Freud named this process of transformation of psychic into somatic energy ‘conversion’. He then explained obsession as the result of the isolation of the idea from its energy, with both (idea and energy) remaining conscious. Free painful energy becomes attached to another, not painful idea which from now on will appear compulsively. From this it should be clear that Freud abandoned neither psychiatric terminology and classification, nor the conception of psychic disorders as illness. This became psychoanalysts' common usage. Freud's two opposed attitudes towards psychiatry reflect the general contradictory character of Freudian texts. These contradictions result from the coexistence in Freud's thought of both revolutionary and conservative conceptions (Haimovich, 1995). On the whole, Freud did not abandon conceptions he adopted at the earliest 5 stages of his work. He rather transformed them while also creating new revolutionary ones. Frequently he formulated compromise conceptions, as in the case of psychoanalytic psychiatry. I have argued that one aspect of Freud's genius was reflected by his struggle with the basic dichotomies of modern scientific and philosophical thinking about human phenomena. On the one hand, there is the mind-body, biology-psychology problem, which he addresses in the early period of his work (1886-1900), and which I call ‘prerevolutionary’. On the other, there is his engagement with the individual-social, psychology-sociology dichotomy, which characterizes the revolutionary (1900-1905) and post-revolutionary (1905-onward) periods. When working with these problems, Freud's views are never one-sided. He often adopted two opposing conceptions. This leads me to state that we cannot understand Freud without distinguishing between the revolutionary and the conservative aspects of his complex thinking and without taking into account these contradictions. The question then arises: why did Freud firmly and unequivocally assert that psychoanalysis is not a branch of psychiatry and medicine and simultaneously use psychopathological terms and classifications? Why, moreover, did he not abandon the medical concept of illness? How did Freud ground his belief that psychoanalysis does not pertain to medicine, - 651 medical psychology, or psychopathology and cannot even be considered part of psychology, but rather constitutes the latter's foundation? I argue that Freud chose the wrong approach when trying to establish his differences with psychiatry. Throughout his work he tended to do this through a theoretical approach; his attraction to philosophy, to theoretical systems - a tendency which he himself bitterly criticized (Freud, 1926, p. 96) - did not serve him well in this respect. Without denying the importance of his theories, I have tried to show (Haimovich, 1995, pp. 6-97) that the essential difference between Freud's conceptions and those of psychiatry must be looked for in the manner in which he perceived the phenomena he studied, and not in his explanatory theories. It is important to emphasize that the abyss between Freud's work and psychiatry opened up very early in his work, in his book on hysteria (Breuer and Freud, 1895). Already here, Freud attributed special importance to the stories told by his patients. This tendency increased gradually from case to case and it was this, more than anything else, that shaped his work with analysands. The associations, memories and ideas reported by his patients, embedded in their particular narrative sequence, became the phenomena that Freud wished to explain. This was completely alien to the traditional psychiatric approach to empirical phenomena. Psychiatrists, now as much as then, build up their picture of an illness by the combination, organization and classification of symptoms. According to this approach the symptom has no meaning beyond its identification and classification. The empirical approach that Freud developed in Studies on Hysteria is very different from this. For Freud a symptom obtains its special identity and significance according to its position in the patient's story. We can say that for him no symptom will ever be the same symptom. Elizabeth's paralysis cannot be the paralysis of any other patient. Freud's approach and the symptomatic approach differ on three main points: First, instead of trying to localize and classify symptoms in order to diagnose illnesses, Freud exposed and tried to understand his patient's story. 6 Second, each element in the story derives its identity in relation to other elements (e.g., in the famous case of Elizabeth, the nature of her paralysis is determined in relation to other - 655 narrative components: the walks she used to take, her guilt feelings, etc.). The sign that there may be a problem is inconsistency in the narrative rather than any abnormal behaviour. Third, psychiatry studies abnormal phenomena, with normal phenomena only featuring as their background. When the research object is the story, every element in it, regardless of its (ab)normality, can be important. In fact, while the symptomatic conception will ignore most narrative elements because they are ‘normal’ (e.g., in Elizabeth's case: sitting near her father's bed, walking with her lover, guilt feelings, etc.), Freud's early work, by abandoning the distinction between the normal and the pathological, becomes the study of the normal and quotidian (which now includes ‘abnormal’ phenomena.) So, though Freud could not furnish a successful explanation, his belief that his science differed essentially from psychiatry was right. But the difference was not grounded in any theoretical distinction. Though psychiatry has assimilated Freud's theories and succeeded to digest even his theory of the unconscious, it has not taken account of this essential difference in attitudes to human phenomena. Freud's confidence that he had created a different science originated in his new definition of psychiatric phenomena and his development of a different way of perceiving these phenomena. Compared with Freud's new approach, psychiatric perception is a primitive one because it removes the object of study from its context. Freud's rejection of the symptomatic view has been considered a result of his humanistic approach, which led him to focus on the individual (Zilboorg and Henry, 1941, pp. 499-500; 524-5, 1954, pp. 93-4). Zilboorg argued that Freud was ‘a true disbeliever’ in psychiatric nosology and accused ‘academic scientific psychiatry’ to be unable to acknowledge the practical importance of ‘individualization’ for a ‘true’ psychopathology. Unlike Zilboorg, I argue that individualism, beyond its humanistic significance, played a scientific role in Freud's development. Humanism alone cannot explain why Freud abandoned the symptomatic conception, even if we are convinced that this ethical factor had a central role. Zilboorg erroneously tried to give an ethical explanation to a scientific rupture. The assumption of the categorical, systematic identity of individually different phenomena is the principle on which any psychopathology and symptomatology are grounded. This is not so in true psychoanalysis, which makes no compromise - 655 about the principle of free association. What is important for Freudian phenomenology is the specificity of each phenomenon and of each individual person, rather than the commonalities. The central argument of this section is, indeed, that the use of psychopathological concepts to refer to psychic phenomena disregards the latter's uniqueness and individuality. We must, therefore, see the attempt to consider different phenomena in their similarity as a defensive device directed against a full perception of empirical phenomena and their meaning. Another aspect of this device is to consider these phenomena in detachment from their natural context - the life story of a person. Contrary to the symptomatic approach, the method of free association expounds the need to consider each phenomenon in its individuality. If this need is not met the application of the method is incomplete. We can say that any use of 7 psychopathological terms is evidence of the adoption of a pre-Freudian symptomatic conception and resists the application of psychoanalysis. We can also claim that psychoanalysis is more scientific than psychiatry because it considers phenomena in their context. It must, then, be concluded that every ‘psychoanalytic’ psychopathology is an expression of resistance to a full implementation of the principles of Freudian science. The fact that the source of this hybrid approach is in Freud himself should not reduce the force of my argument. )5The Technical Aspect According to members of the International Psychoanalytical Association, true psychoanalysis is possible only when analyst and patient meet five times a week for fifty-minute sessions. The patient must lie on a couch and the therapist must sit in an armchair (preferably one similar to Freud's own famous armchair; the style of the couch allows for more freedom…). These rules are known as the setting of the analytic treatment and are considered indispensable to it. Traditionally psychoanalysts must focus on the analysis of the transference and counter-transference and must use interpretation as its main therapeutic instrument. In addition, psychoanalysts must take care to be neutral and objective in their relation with patients. When psychoanalytic theories began to proliferate away from their source, it became more important to psychoanalysts to - 656 stress homogeneity in spite of diversity. With the support of a techno-clinical definition of psychoanalysis, Wallerstein has been able to argue that despite the multiplicity of psychoanalytic conceptions, psychoanalysis as such is still quite unitary since psychoanalysts agree on the character of their clinical work (Wallerstein, 1988; also see Esman, 1991, p. 289). Even though there has been criticism from within psychoanalysis, this has not led to change of the old model: We may have our doubts about the ideal of the-analyst-as-reflecting-mirror and want to feel we have left it behind, but we have not yet really replaced it; we have just made it more user-friendly by not taking it entirely seriously. (Renik, 1995, p. 468) An important representative of traditional psychoanalysis, Etchegoyen, has admitted that the technical elements of the model have not undergone any essential change since Freud formulated them in the first decade of the twentieth century (Etchegoyen, 1986, p. 498). Aware that Freud did not regard all the components of the common model as imperative and presented them as suggestions which analysts may adopt at their convenience, Etchegoyen states that Freud's followers nevertheless took them over, regarding them as indispensable to psychoanalytic work. So for instance Etchegoyen dwells extensively on the question of whether or not psychoanalysis is possible when analyst and patient meet only four times a week, and then states categorically that it is possible only when there are five meetings: ‘The frequency and duration of the sessions are absolute rather than relative constants’ (p. 512). Why? Etchegoyen's pseudoscientific argument runs as follows: Freud deduced the defining hypotheses of psychoanalysis from empirical observations, and ‘the rules that constitute the setting and without which psychoanalysis cannot occur’ derive from these hypotheses (p. 509). ‘The constants of the setting are, then, empirical rules dictated by Freud on the basis of his clinical experience, which led him to set up a definite and strict framework in his relation to the patient, so that the treatment could develop in the best way possible, with the least possible disturbance’ (p. 511.) In addition there is the ‘therapeutic argument’: the setting is necessary for the patient's sake (p. 511), and the ethical - 655 - 8 argument: he who does not keep the setting is regarded as cither childish or perverse! (p. 13). And if all this is not enough to intimidate independently-minded candidates, Etchegoyen offers a religious, even mystic, argument, in which Freud rises to the level of divinity: ‘In the beginning, as stated in Genesis, there was chaos. There were only variables. Freud arrives and establishes order: there will be six sessions per week, one a day; a particular hour belongs to a particular patient, and neither the patient nor Freud change it, and so forth’ (p. 510.) Etchegoyen is paradigmatic of the many publications that all aim to prove that psychoanalysis is possible only if the setting established by Psychoanalytic Association is kept. The analysis of psychoanalytic technique and its theory reveals the same fixation and denial of individualism that I mentioned in earlier sections of this article. As shown before, these features do not allow work by means of free association. )5Psychoanalysts' Collective Defences and their Resistance to the Application of Psychoanalysis My simple comparison between the conditions that must be fulfilled to work with free association, on the one hand, and today's psychoanalytic practice, on the other, leads to two conclusions. First, there is a tendency in the field of psychoanalysis to fixate behaviours and concepts that impede the free stream of associations and their observation. Second, there is a marked trend to violate the basic logical and scientific demand of free association. According to this principle each association must be considered in its individuality and specificity despite its similarities to other associations. This does not disqualify classification of associations according to different criteria, so long as the principle is preserved. What must be rejected is those approaches that classify associations according to external criteria, that is, criteria that have not evolved from the observation of associations and their characteristics, as is the case with psychiatric classifications. Moreover, the logic of free association precludes fixing the meanings of phenomena. I argue therefore that disregard for the necessary conditions of free association constitutes the main feature of twentieth century psychoanalysis. This results from a powerfully - 657 defensive process, which has many expressions and plays an important role in the building of therapists' certainties and sense of security. Those who join psychoanalytical organizations internalize these defensive social, theoretical and behavioural structures and attitudes and thereby become part of an historical process opposed to psychoanalytic work. The insertion of the individual in these structures occurs through the same type of primitive identifications and idealizations as depicted by Freud in his book on the ego and mass psychology. In it, Freud indicated that abstract ideas could fulfil a role similar to that of the Pope or the chief of an army (Freud, 1921, p. 100). People identify with them and by means of this identification identify with each other. Jaques (1955) argued that social systems do not only serve constructive aims and do not express only libidinal drives. According to him one of the main ties uniting people in organized societies is the defence against psychotic anxieties. Finally, I would like to repeat that the aim of the depicted defensive social processes which characterize psychoanalysis today is to stop the development of Freudian science through resistance to work according to the principle of free association. There is no doubt that the full implementation of this principle has a very high anxiety 9 potential. And it is precisely these anxieties that psychoanalysts try to stave off through the fixation of their educational, institutional, theoretical and technical ideas. ‘Primary’ social structures like the ones referred to here do not allow true psychoanalytic work because they do not allow free association. To enable true psychoanalytic work, which is attentive to, and preserves, psychoanalytic scientific principles, psychoanalysts must study in and belong to institutions with ‘secondary’ mature structures, in which individuality is strictly respected. I believe that careful application of the scientific conditions of the ‘fundamental rule’ of free association will also lead to development of mature social processes among psychoanalysts. References Ackercknecht, E.H. (1957) Short History of Psychiatry, S. Wolff, trans., 2nd. ed. New York: Hafner (1968.) - 655 Arlow, J. (1972) ‘Some dilemmas in psychoanalytic education’, J. Amer. Psychoanal. Assn. 20: 556-66.[à]APA.020.0556A Barratt, B.B. (1994) ‘Critical notes on the psychoanalyst's theorizing’, J. Amer. Psychoanal. Assn. 42: 697-725.[à]APA.042.0697A Bergmann, M.S. (1997) ‘The historical roots of psychoanalytic orthodoxy’, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 78: 69-86.[à]IJP.078.0069A Binswanger, L. (1936) ‘Freud und die verfassung der klinischen psychiatric’, Schweizer Archiv fuer Neurol. und Psychiatrie 37: 177-99. Eisold, K. (1994) ‘The intolerance of diversity in psychoanalytic institutes’, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 75: 785-800.[à]IJP.075.0785A Esman, A.H. (1991) ‘Review of “The technique at issue: controversies in psychoanalysis from Freud and Ferenczi to Michael Balint” by A. Haynal’, J. Amer. Psychoanal. Assn. 39: 290-2.[à]APA.039.0290A Etchegoyen, H. (1986) The Fundamentals of Psychoanalytic Technique, P. Pichon, trans. London: Karnac Books (1991).[à]ZBK.040.0001A Freud, S. (1921) ‘Group psychology and the analysis of the ego’, in James Strachey, ed., The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, 24 vols. Hogarth, 1953-73. vol. 18, pp. 65-143.[à]SE.018.0065A Freud, S. (1926) ‘Inhibitions, symptoms and anxiety’, S.E. 20, pp. 75175.[à]SE.020.0075A Freud, S. (1926) ‘The question of lay analysis’, S.E. 20, pp. 177258.[à]SE.020.0177A Haimovich, S.S. (1995) ‘Prolegomena to psychoanalysis: Freud's researches 18921896’, University of Tel Aviv, Ph.D. thesis. Jaques, E. (1955) ‘Social systems as defence against persccutory and depressive anxiety’, in New Directions in Psychoanalysis, M. Klein, P. Heimann & R. MoneyKyrle, eds. New York: Basic Books, pp. 478-498. Jones, E. (1953-57) The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud. New York: Basic (1957).[à]ZBK.045.0001A Kernberg, O.F. (1986) ‘Institutional problems of psychoanalytic education’, in J. Amer. Psychoanal. Assn. 34: 799-834.[à]APA.034.0799A Kernberg, O.F. (1996) ‘Thirty methods to destroy the creativity of psychoanalytic candidates’, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 77: 1031-40.[à]IJP.077.1031A Kirsner, D. (2000) ‘Unfree Associations inside psychoanalytic institutes’. London: Process Press. Menninger, K., Ellenberger, H., Pruyser, P., and Mayman, M. (1958) ‘The unitary concept of mental illness’, Bull. Mennin. Clinic. 22: 4-12. 10 Renik, O. (1995) ‘The ideal of the anonymous analyst and the problem of self disclosure’, Psychoanal. Q. 64 (3):466-95.[à]PAQ.064.0466A - 655 Rustin, M. (1985) ‘The social organization of secrets: towards a sociology of psychoanalysis’, in Rustin (1991), pp. 87-113. Rustin, M. (1991) The Good Society and the lnner World. London: Verso. Stelzer, J. (1986) ‘The formation and deformation of identity during psychoanalytic treatment’, Free Associations 7: 59-74.[à]FA.001H.0059A Wallerstein, R.S. (1988) ‘One psychoanalysis or many?’, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 69: 521.[à]IJP.069.0005A Wallerstein, R.S. (1993) ‘Between chaos and petrification: a summary of the fifth IPA conference of training analysts’, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 74: 154-78.[à]IJP.074.0165A Young, R.M. (1990) ‘The culture of British psychoanalysis’. http:www.humannature.com Young, R.M. (1996) ‘The psychodynamics of psychoanalytic organizations’. http:www.human-nature.com Zilboorg, G. (1954) ‘Freud's fundamental psychiatric orientation’, Int. J. Psycho-Anal. 35: 90-4.[à]IJP.035.0090A Zilboorg, G. and Henry, G.W. (1941) A History of Medical Psychology, New York: Norton. - 650 Article Citation Haimovich, S. S. (2001). The First Hundred Years of Psychoanalysis: A Century of Internal Resistance. Free Associations 8D: 576-590