‘Social scientific practice is an imaginative process of attempting to discover an empirical world that is so complex that it often escapes attempts to comprehend it – so researchers should be involved in the everyday lives of social actors.’ Critically evaluate this claim and the research strategies and approaches to knowledge construction that endorse it. This claim regarding the way social scientific research practice should be oriented could be endorsed by several approaches, all of which are part of the current of thought known as idealism. More precisely, the first part of this claim could be attributed to idealism as a whole in the way it acknowledges the complexity of the social world, while its second part suggests the pertinence of the use of qualitative research methods as advocated by the interactionist, phenomenological or ethnomethodological idealist approaches, which focus on the importance of the involvement of the social researcher with its object of study, and could be contrasted with the detachment traditionally advocated by empiricists. Idealist approaches permitted the elaboration of new research methods for the investigation of social life, based on a novel philosophical standpoint placing the role of the human mind as central in the “processing” of experience. In the social sciences, currents of thoughts such as phenomenology or ethnomethodology embrace this approach unreservedly by proposing a range of theories and research methods acknowledging the complexity of the social world and focusing on the subjective point of views of social actors, which differ from other idealist currents of thought such as neo-Kantianism, which have a more nuanced approach by trying to find a middle ground between the development of general laws to explain causal relationship between social phenomena and the central importance of subjective values in the study of social objects, or from rational choice theory, which sees social actors as “minimaxers” solely motivated by their subjective interests and pursuing those interests through the use of rational thinking. These different visions of scientific practice could also be linked to the ideas of sociologists of science such as Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend, Barry Barnes or David Bloor who focus on the study of science and more generally knowledge construction as a socially and historically situated social process, challenging preconceived ideas regarding the validity and supremacy of taken-for-granted types of knowledge construction. Overall, the philosophical framework on which rely idealist approaches allowed social scientists to gain a different vision of the relationship between theory and observation, as well as new ways to tackle the problem of the separation of facts from values by proposing a different perspective for tackling these dilemmas. More precisely, Kant’s legacy to the social science could be seen as the new conceptual framework he introduced by proposing to solve the tension between rationalist and empiricist approaches to knowledge construction. For Kant, the mind makes sense and organises human perceptions according to preexisting mental constructs. Henceforth, this new perspective entailed a new attitude towards the practice of the social sciences in terms of methods, with a particular focus on the subjective meaning of social phenomena and on the subjective experiences, mental constructs and interests of social agents. Interactionism, phenomenology and ethnomethodology embrace this new perspective by considering as central the importance of subjective meanings and cultural values in the study of social phenomena. These approaches consider that if the consequences of social phenomena or objects are considered real by social actors, they are valid objects of study, which provides a new perspective for a critical appraisal of the empiricist standpoints (and particularly their advocacy of naturalism), by allowing us to consider them as historically and sociologically situated attempts to make sense of the social world (this particular statement could be linked to Kuhn’s conventionalist view of the history of scientific knowledge construction, and more widely to post empiricist accounts of science). Phenomenology directly challenged the validity of the assumption that it is possible to define objects of study, such as the family, as doing so would impose the imprint of the researcher’s subjective assumptions about the concept of family on his or her results. This entails a new vision of the practice of social sciences: instead of trying to achieve a hypothetical detachment towards an object of study they defined under the influence of their own values, researchers should be seen as being themselves social actors trying to make sense of the world with their own subjective values, point of view and interests. Moreover, the distinction between tacit, unconscious knowledge and “textbook” knowledge made by thinkers such as William James or Harold Garfinkel, the father of ethnomethodology, provided additional tools and concepts for the analysis of the daily lives of social actors in the framework of novel research methods such as in-depth, semistructured interviews or ethnographic studies. However, although a certain connection has been made between qualitative research methods and idealist approaches to knowledge construction in the social sciences, the use of quantitative methods such as surveys or more structured interviews could indeed be used as a way to gain a complementary understanding of the object of study, as illustrated by Judith Okely’s account of the life of Gypsies in Great Britain (Okely, 1994). Thus, Kant’s conceptual framework could be seen as a way to overcome the limitations of empiricist theories about the way social science should be conducted by emphasising the central role played by human imagination in the way we understand the social world, as well as by challenging the idea that the paradigms of the natural sciences could be adapted to the study of social phenomena. The assumptions underlying the empiricist standpoint are challenged by idealists and post empiricist accounts of science for several reasons, revolving around the topics of the complexity of the social world (and the validity of the assumption that it can be modeled, or simplified using the concept of closed systems, or by using theoretical devices such as “ceteris paribus” clauses), the tension between explanation and understanding of social phenomena, and the hypothetical detachment from the object of study advocated by empiricists. Moreover, the concept of science itself could be put into question and seen as a social product, which challenges both positivist and idealist assumptions such as the definition of scientific progress as an iterative accumulation of scientific knowledge. First, we could argue that in a hard science such as physics, the objects of study could be considered as constant and relatively predictable: for instance, a planet will not decide “out of the blue” to exit its orbit to travel around the galaxy, while it is absolutely acceptable to expect this kind of erratic behaviour from a human being. This inherent unpredictability of the social world greatly puts into question the scientific validity of the use of man-made simplifications such as the empiricist use of closed system, or the modeling of human behaviour performed in the framework of studies relying on rational choice theory. In addition, post empiricist views of science, such as conventionalism or epistemological relativism respectively argue that escape clauses are built in empiricist theories in order to escape falsification and that when approached as a social product, science reveals itself as socially and historically situated, which challenges taken-forgranted concepts such as ‘progress’ or ‘universal truth’, and brings forward the question of the dominant position of science in the field of knowledge construction. Second, we can argue that by acknowledging the intrinsic complexity of the social world, idealist approaches seem to be more successful in providing deep understanding of a particular social phenomenon. Judith Okely’s study of the Gypsy population in Great Britain (Okely, 1994) is a great example of the richness and relative exhaustivity allowed by the use of idealist research methods such as ethnography, although they could appear to be more limited in providing precise explanations and predictions, which empiricist approaches claim to be able to make. However, the assumption that clear-cut and precise predictions or explanations of social phenomena from a hypothetically detached observer are possible is greatly challenged by the flagrant impact the subjective values and expectations of social researcher have on the definition of their object of study and on their findings, greatly illustrated by the mere title of studies such as Hans Eysenck’s The intelligence of American negroes (Eysenck, 1971). Therefore, we could see another advantage in idealist approaches in the way they seem to resolve the empiricist contradiction between the edification of general laws on the basis of value-laden accounts of the social world. Thus, by acknowledging the social world’s complexity, interactionists, phenomenologists and ethnomethodologists limit their conclusions to the elicitation, explanation and prediction of particular patterns in social life and/or a deep understanding of an intentionally restricted object of study. Methodologically, this entails an inclination towards a more qualitative approach to the collection and analysis of empirical data – in contrast to the generally quantitative approach advocated by empiricists – taking the form of innovative qualitative research methods such as in-depth, semi-structured or unstructured interviews, participant observation and ethnographic studies, which can be contrasted with empiricist methods such as structured interviews or the statistical analysis of quantitative data, and to the neo-Kantian approach of using quantitative research in an idealistic conceptual framework, acknowledging the important impact of subjective values on the research process by using theoretical devices such as Max Weber’s ideal types, or Heinrich Rickert’s concept of value relevance. This focus on qualitative data is advocated by its supporters for several reasons: First, they argue that it allows the collection of richer, more valid data. Indeed, qualitative data collection is less likely to be shaped by methodological constraints as it is the case in the framework of traditional empiricist studies, where structured interviews or questionnaire “mold” the results in a particular way (Dey, 1991). In addition, the multiplicity of sources from which qualitative data can be gathered makes it a much more fertile ground for analysis, as for its practitioners, “all meaningful human actions or artifacts and all social practices are legitimate sources” (Yates, 2003, p.139). However, and although phenomenological or ethnomethodological research methods can be very successful for gaining a significant understanding of a particular social context, they are not exempt from problems inherent to the difficult balance one has to keep between the necessary involvement with the social actors being studied and the need for objectivity in the researcher’s analyses and conclusions. Moreover, it is useful to keep in mind that the choice of a particular research method or the combination of several methods is also quite dependant on the practicalities of a particular research context. Indeed, one could argue that the advantage of idealist frameworks is the nonexclusiveness of certain types of research methods: although qualitative research is what distinguishes idealist research strategies from empiricism, the study of quantitative data can also be very meaningful and used to deepen the understanding of the object of study. Another important point, as identified by Laud Humpreys in The Sociologist as Voyeur (Humpreys, 1997), is the problem caused by the fact that presence of the researcher and its interaction with the social group being studied could produce interferences which disturb the normal activities of the actors being observed. Different strategies could be devised to solve this problem, such as having a role in the activities of the social group, thus striving to have as less of an impact as possible (in this case, Humpreys took the role of a lookout in the framework of his participant observation of homosexual encounters in public restrooms). In addition, the fact that researcher engaged in such studies deal with issues that can be very personal to the social actors they interact with raises important ethical issues that need to be carefully taken into account in the actual practice of the researcher, and can cause some difficulties for the researcher to be accepted by the social group he or she wants to study. Overall, it appears from all of this that the practice of these qualitative methods of data collection and analysis appears to require certain specific skills from social researchers, entailed by the paradoxical aspect of qualitative social research, in which a certain objectivity must be achieved through involvement with social actors. Moreover, the analysis and presentation of the results of such research, although relatively straightforward in the case of empiricist studies, can be more demanding and difficult in the framework of qualitative study. As noted by Okely (1994), communicating such results to a wide public of non-specialist policy makers could reveal itself difficult, as qualitative research may lack the apparent “scientificity” of more traditional empiricist studies. In conclusion, we could argue that although empiricist and idealist approaches have important differences, they both rely on a certain idea of science that finds itself challenged by theories questioning the very foundation of the concept of progress and of science in general. However, these theories are counterbalanced by Imre Lakatos’s sophisticated methodological falsificationism, which accepts the sociological and historical situatedness of science but emphasises the usefulness of falsificationism in allowing the creation of valid knowledge. From a more pragmatic point of view, making a synthesis of both approaches in the context of real-world social scientific research by using the most appropriate tools in regards to a particular object of study could be a way to tackle this dilemma. References Dey, I. (1993) Qualitative Data Analysis, London, Routledge, reprinted in Yates (2003, pp. 147-53). Eysenck, H. (1971) Race, Intelligence and Education, Maurice Temple Smith Ltd, courtesy of Dr Sybil Eysenck, reprinted in Smith, M.J. (1998, pp.123-24). Humpreys. L. (1997) The Sociologist as Voyeur [1970], reprinted in Redman et al. (2003, pp. 91-106). Okely, J. (1994) Thinking through fieldwork, in Bryman, A. and Burgess, R.G (eds) Analysing Qualitative Data, London, Routledge, reprinted in Yates (2003, pp.193 - 96). Smith, M.J. (1998) Social Science in Question, London, Sage/The Open University. Yates, S.J. (2003) Doing Social Science Research, London, Sage.