Session Five Notes

advertisement
English 421
Semantics and Pragmatics
Session Five Notes
Goals/Objectives:
1) To examine the meaning and nature of nouns
2) To examine the nature of the so-called “has-relation”
3) To review concept of prototypes
4) To examine the notion of spatial parts
5) To examine the notion of metaphors
6) To examine the notion of hyponymy
7) To examine the notion of incompatibility
 Nouns
Questions/Main Ideas
(Please write these down as
 Nouns form the majority of words in the vocabulary of English
you think of them)
 In contrast to the relatively unidimensional meanings of adjectives, nouns typically “denote
rich, highly interconnected complexes of properties” according to our author
 Nouns
 The “things” denoted by some nouns have parts, which may figure in the noun’s meaning
 For example, a square has four equal sides and it has 90 angles
 In saying what a square is, one cannot avoid talking about its four sides and right angles
 Nouns
 Nouns can also be grouped into semantic categories
 For example, squares, circles, and triangles belong together as shapes
 Nouns can also be classified as being either count or mass nouns
 All this needs to be explained
 Nouns
 The has-relation
 The everyday words square, circle, and triangle are also technical terms in geometry, where
they have tight definitions
 For example, a closed, straight-sided figure is a triangle if, and only if, it has exactly three
sides
 Nouns
 In other words, there is an entailment here:
 1) That figure is a triangle  That figure has three sides
 For many words, however, we can only be sure that all the parts are there if the so-called
“has-relation” is stated in terms of prototypes
 Nouns
 Prototypes are clear, central members of the denotation of a word
 Think of what you might advise a child drawing a face to put in:
 Probably eyes, a nose and a mouth
 How about a child drawing a house?
 Nouns
 Probably you would expect there to be a roof, a door, and windows
 Prototypes among the things denoted by the English word face have two eyes, a nose and a
mouth
 However, this is also a face
 Nouns
 Nouns
 The face of a Cyclops, with its single eye, is a face, but not a prototypical face
 You can also have a windowless house, such as this:
 Nouns
 Nouns
 It may be incontestably a house, but it is not a prototype for the denotation of house in
contemporary English
 Some information needs to be built into an understanding of these words that reflects certain
semantic facts:
 Nouns
 A prototype face has two eyes
 A prototype face has a nose
 A prototype face has a mouth
 A prototype house has a roof
 A prototype house has a door
 A prototype house has windows
 Nouns
 Granted, prototype faces and house may have other parts besides those listed
 Cheeks and chin, etc.
 What is probably more important, though, are the many things that the prototypes do not
have, like blemishes or a carport
 Nouns
 These, obviously, may be parts of many real faces and houses, respectively
 Restricted to prototypes, the has-relation makes available entailments
 For example:
 Nouns
 2) There’s a house on the corner  ‘If it is like a prototype for house then it has a roof’
 3) The child drew a face  ‘If the face was prototypical, then the child drew a mouth’
 Nouns
 In our previous discussion, entailments were introduced as guarantees
 Here, the guarantees are weakened by making them conditional on prototypicality
 Nouns
 The entailed propositions in 2 & 3 start with “if” because it seems that average English
words are not as tightly defined as technical words like triangle
 Nouns
 Pragmatic inferences from the has-relation
 The has-relation, restricted to prototypes, is the basis for some of our pragmatic expectations
in language use
 This can be seen in the switch from indefinite to definite articles
 Nouns
 A noun phrase that first brings something into conversation is usually indefinite – for
example, marked by means of an indefinite article, a or an
 Nouns
 But on second and subsequent mention of the same thing in conversation it will be referred
to by means of a definite noun phrase – marked by, for example, the definite article the
 As in the following example:
 Nouns
 4) A: “I’ve bought a house.”
B: “Where’s the house located?”
NOT: “Where’s a house located?”
 5) (a child showing off a drawing)
























C: “I drawed a face.”
(adult responding to the child)
D: “I like the face you drew.”
NOT: “I like a face you drew.”
Nouns
However, if a whole that has a part has been mentioned, then the part can, on first mention,
be referred to by means of a definite noun phrase, as illustrated in the following:
Nouns
6) A: “I’ve bought a house.”
B: “I hope the roof doesn’t leak.”
7) C: “I drawed a face.”
D: “Where’s the nose?”
Nouns
Parts can have parts
Words denoting wholes bear the has-relation to the labels for their parts
But the parts can, in turn, have parts, and a whole can be a part of a large whole, as in the
following:
Nouns
A suburb
/
\
has
has


streets (a street) houses (a house)


has
has


curbs
windows
Nouns
Interestingly, we can’t posit an inverse relationship to the has-relation, one that would
guarantee the existence of the relevant large whole whenever a part of it is present
This is because parts can exist in the absence of the larger whole
Nouns
For instance, Home Depot and Lowe’s keep stocks of windows for houses that have not yet
























been built
Furthermore, the same kind of part can belong to different kinds of a whole
A given curb need not be part of a street – it could be part of a parking lot
Nouns
Spatial Parts
A prototype thing, such as a rock, can be said to have a top, a bottom, sides, and a front and
back
Two points need to be noted about these words
Nouns
One is that they are general: very many different kinds of thing – windows, heads, faces,
feet, buses, trees, canyons, to randomly name just a few – have tops, bottoms, sides, fronts,
and backs
Nouns
A thing has spatial parts, making the possession of such parts characteristic of prototypes in
the thing-category
The other notable feature of spatial part words is that they are often deictic
Nouns
Pragmatics enters the interpretation of deictic words
The meaning of a deictic word is tied to the situation of utterance
The front of the rock faces the speaker and the back of the rock faces away from the speaker
Nouns
The sides are to the left and right from the point of view of the speaker
What counts as the top of the rock and what counts as the bottom of the rock depends on
which way up the rock happens to be lying at the time of utterance
Nouns
However, many things – bus, for example – inherently have a non-deictic top, bottom, front
and back, and sides
The top of the bus is its roof, even in the dire case of one lying overturned at the side of the
road
Nouns
The front of the bus is the driver’s end of it, regardless of where the speaker is viewing it
from
It is with things that do not inherently have these parts that the deictic top, bottom, front,































back and sides come into play
Nouns
Notice that a rescue worker who is standing “on top” (deictically) of an overturned bus is not
on the top (part) of the bus
Here are some examples of things that have inherent spatial parts:
People
Houses
Nouns
Trees (top, base, sides)
Hills (top, base, sides)
Animals
Pianos
Here are some things that have spatial parts only deictically:
Wheels
Nouns
Planets (in the talk of amateurs looking through a telescope)
Trees (front, back)
Hills (front, back)
Ends and beginnings
Long, thin things have ends
Nouns
Sometimes two different kinds of ends are distinguished: beginnings and ends
Here are some things that prototypically have ends:
Ropes
(pieces of) string
Nouns
Roads
Trains
Planks
Nouns denoting periods of time have beginnings and ends
They also have middles
A) day, week, month, era, term, semester, century
Nouns
 B) conversation, demonstration, ceremony, mean, reception, process
 The words in B do not denote concrete entities that you could touch, but the events and
processes that they can be used to refer to are nonetheless located in time and space
 Nouns
 Which is to say that it is reasonable to wonder when and where conversations,
demonstrations, and so forth took place
 The can also have beginnings, middles, and ends
 (a full understanding of this will entail understanding verb endings)
 Nouns
 Some other parts
 The body is a source of metaphors
 For instance, losing one’s head, meaning “panic”
 Person is an ambiguous word denoting either a physical person – who can, for instance, be
big or ugly
 Nouns
 Or the psychological individual – who can be kind or silly and so on
 The physical person prototypically has a head, has a torso, has arms, has legs, and has skin
 These parts and some of the parts they, in turn, prototypically have can be laid out thusly:
 Nouns
 A person has a head, a torso, arms, legs, skin
 A head has a face, hair, forehead, jaw
 A face has a mouth, nose, chin, eyes, cheeks
 A mouth has lips
 Nouns
 Remember that a semantic description is different from the compilation of an encyclopedia
 Semantics is not an attempt to catalogue all human knowledge
 Instead, semanticists aim to describe the knowledge about meaning that language users have
 Nouns
 Simply because they are users of the language
 Specialists will have more detailed vocabulary for talking about body parts
 But it is safe to assume that any competent user of English knows the meanings of these
words
 Nouns






























A prototype chair has a back, seat, and legs
Interestingly, the words back and leg are also body part labels
The body part labels head, neck, foot and mouth are used to label a wide range of things
Nouns
For example, a mountain has a head and a foot
Lampposts and bottles have necks
Caves and rivers have mouths
Presumably, this indicates a human tendency to interpret and label the world by analogy with
what we know and understand
Nouns
Hyponymy
This relation is important for describing nouns, but it also figures in the description of verbs
and, to a lesser extent, adjectives
It is c0ncerned with the labeling of subcategories of a word’s denotation:
Nouns
What kinds of Xs are there and what different kinds of entities count as Ys
For example, a house is one kind of building
A factory and a church are other kinds of buildings
Nouns
Further, buildings are one kind of structure; towers and dams are other kinds of structures
The pattern of entailment that defines hyponymy is illustrated like this:
8) There’s a house next to the gate
9) There’s a building next to the gate
Nouns
10) (8  9)
11) ( 9  8)
If it is true that there is a house next to the gate, then (with respect to the same gate at the
same point in time) it must be true that there is a building next to the gate
It cannot be otherwise
Nouns
On the other hand, it we are given 9 as true information, then we cannot be sure that 8 is true
It might be, but there are other possibilities
For example, the building next to the gate could be a barn or any other kind of building

























Nouns
That is why 11 has been scored through
Though it could follow , 8 does not have to follow from 9
In the terminology of semantics, building is the superordinate for house and nouns labeling
other kinds of buildings
Nouns
House, barn, church, factory, hanger and so forth are hyponyms of building
It is possible to generalize about the pattern shown
Nouns
A sentence, such as 8, containing a hyponym of a given superordinate entails a sentence that
differs from the original one only in that the superordinate has been substituted for its
hyponym, as in 9
Nouns
The sentence with the hyponym entails the corresponding sentence with the superordinate
replacing it, but the entailment only goes one way – not from the sentence containing the
superordinate
(this doesn’t work so hot for negative sentences)
Nouns
This essentially highlights the fact that there being a building by the gate is a necessary
condition for there to be a house by the gate
If there is no building at the gate, then there cannot be a house there
Nouns
Intuitively, it is reasonable to say that ‘building’ is a component of the meaning of house
A house is a ‘building for living in’
Prototypicality has to be brought into consideration for the has-relation, but is not needed for
hyponymy
Nouns
Hierarchies of Hyponyms
House is a hyponym of the superordinate building, but building is, in turn, a hyponym of the
superordinate structure, and, in its turn, structure is a hyponym of the superordinate thing
Nouns
A superordinate at a given level can itself be a hyponym at a higher level, as in:
Nouns



























Thing – superordinate of structure
Structure – hyponym of thing; superordinate of building
Building – hyponym of structure; superordinate of house
House – hyponym of building
Nouns
The hyponym relation passes through intermediate levels in the hierarchy
Which means that house is not only a hyponym of building, but is also a hyponym of
building’s immediate superordinate, structure
Nouns
And, via structure, house is also a hyponym of thing
Thing is a superordinate for all the words on lines that can be traced down from it in the
hierarchy, and so on
Nouns
Thing – superordinate of structure, building, and house (and others words)
Structure – hyponym of thing; superordinate of building and house
Building – hyponym of thing and structure; superordinate of house
House – hyponym of thing, structure, and building; superordinate of other words
Nouns
The significance of hyponymy passing through intermediate levels is that a hierarchy of this
kind guarantees numerous inferences
Thus, if someone who is speaking the truth tells us about a house, we know, with certainty
and without asking, that the entity in question is a building, a structure, and a thing
Nouns
Obviously, such hierarchies show only a fragment of the possibilities
There are many other kinds of things, for example
And there are also words that are hyponyms of house – cottage and bungalow, for example
Nouns
High in the hierarchy, the senses (denotations) of words are rather general and undetailed,
which has the consequence that these words denote many different kinds of entities
At successively lower levels, the meanings are more detailed, denoting narrower ranges of
things
Nouns
The meaning of a hyponym can be seen as the meaning of its immediate superordinate



























elaborated by a modifier
So the meaning of house is the meaning of building modified, in this case by the modifier
‘for living in’
Nouns
Because building is itself a hyponym one level below structure, its meaning can be seen as
that of a structure plus a modifier, ‘with walls and a roof’
Nouns
Hyponymy and the has-relation
These two semantic relations should not be confused
Hyponymy is about categories being grouped under superordinate terms
But the has-relation concerns parts that prototypical members of categories have
Nouns
There is nonetheless a link between the two relations
Hyponyms ‘inherit’ the parts that their superordinates have
If a prototype superordinate has certain parts then prototype members of that superordinate’s
hyponyms also have those parts
Nouns
For example, a prototypical tool has a handle, and prototypical members of hyponyms of
tool have handles too, by inheritance
Prototypical saws have handles
Prototypical garden tools have handles – rakes and hoes
Nouns
Prototypical kitchen tools have handles – spatulas and egg whisks
A non-prototypical kitchen tool, such as a mixing bowl, need not have a handle
The inheritance passes down through hyponymy
Nouns
Incompatibility
Breakfast, lunch, and dinner are hyponyms of meal, their immediate superordinate word
Hyponymy guarantees that if we hear that some people have breakfast in Bakersfield, then
we know they had a meal in Bakersfield
Nouns
Breakfast is one kind of meal
However, there is no similarly straight entailment from a sentence with the superordinate –

























from a sentence containing meal to the corresponding sentence with one of its hyponyms
Nouns
If we are told that some people has a meal in Bakersfield, we cannot conclude, just from that,
that they had breakfast there
It might have been lunch or dinner
So what is the relation between hyponyms like breakfast, lunch and dinner?
Nouns
A semantic relation called incompatibility holds between the hyponyms of a given
superordinate
Hyponymy is about classification
Breakfast, lunch and dinner are kinds of meals
Incompatibility is about contrast
Nouns
Breakfast, lunch and dinner are different from each other within the category of meals, since
they are eaten at different times of day
Here are the patterns of entailment
Nouns
12) This is Fred’s breakfast
13) This is Fred’s lunch
14) This is Fred’s dinner
15) (12  NOT13) & (12  NOT14) & (13  NOT12) & (13  NOT14) & (14 
NOT12) & (14  NOT13)
If one of these sentences is true, the other two cannot be true
Nouns
On the other hand:
16) (NOT12  13) & (NOT12  14) & (NOT13  12) & (NOT13  14) & (NOT14 
12) & (NOT14  13)
A comparable set of entailments is not available from negative versions of the sentences
Nouns
Knowing that Fred did not eat breakfast does not allow you to know that he ate lunch – it
might be dinner
Hyponyms of a word immediately superordinate to them are not only incompatible with each
other, but are also incompatible with hyponyms of their higher-level superordinates









Summary/Minute Paper:
Nouns
Superordinate
Hyponyms
Drinking vessel
glass, cup, mug
Glass
wine glass,
martini glass,
tumbler
Cup
coffee cup, tea
cup
Mug
coffee mug, beer mug
Nouns
A tea cup is not only not a coffee cup or any other kind of cup
It is also not a glass or a mug nor any of the hyponyms of glass or mug
Download