1 FAITH AND REASON, PART 2: PLATO’S “LINE” Plato's Republic provides some excellent clues to the character of Western civilization and culture. The point is not whether he was right or wrong about how knowing works but that his account of the mind and of knowing has been at the foundation of European thinking for two and a half thousand years. Ralph Waldo Emerson observed that all of Western philosophy is a series of footnotes to Plato. Moreover, Platonist and neo-Platonist thinking provided the major theoretic framework not only for the secular world, but it was the primary and virtually unrivaled point of reference through which western Christianity rationalized itself until the intrusion of Aristotle in the High Middle Ages. For the religious consciousness generally, the Platonic vision remains an especially important approach to knowledge, as we shall see. Focus here will be on the place in the Republic (509d 6-511e 5) where Plato identifies four kinds of knowing activity and discusses their relationship to one another. In the history of philosophy this has been known as "Plato's Line." It can be represented graphically (see chart). NOESIS ARCHAI Meta-physics First Principles DIANOIA METHOD, LOGIC REASON MATHEMATIKA DOXA PISTIS ZOA KNOWING FROM DIRECT EXPERIENCE KNOWING DIRECT PARTICULAR THINGS EPISTEME ABSTRACT THINKING LEARNED CONCLUSIONS EXPERIENCE EIKASIA EIKONES IMAGING, IMAGINING SYMBOLS, ARTS (IMITATIONS) 2 Initially, we will use Plato's Greek terms for the components of his account. The English words have been argued about in many contexts, and they are open to too many meanings in popular usage. While I will disagree somewhat with Plato’s evaluation of Let us work through this diagram a step at a time. It will be useful to pay close attention to the diagram as the discussion moves along. 1. Notice that in the left hand column there is a division into two "states of mind." 1. The first is called episteme (epis-TEY-mey). The second is called doxa. 2. In Plato’s way of thinking, episteme is a "higher" state of mind because it knows what it knows. This state of mind is reflective, conscious; what it thinks is clear and distinct. 3. Doxa, on the other hand, is a less clear state of mind, less defined. It has commonly been translated as “opinion,” as we saw in our discussion of Parmenides. I prefer to translate it as “common sense.” What I am assuming here is that most of the time we do not go about saying things that we know are stupid, nonsensical or irrational. Most of the time we speak and think out of what makes sense given our experience. 4. Episteme and doxa are each divided into two kinds of knowing activity: Episteme includes noesis and dianoia. Doxa includes pistis and eikasia. Episteme is, for Plato, the highest and truest level of knowing. It is the state of mind that understands ideas, the forms, the patterns that give order and shape to all things. As such these ideas are abstract which are purely mental, beyond the limits of sense experience. I might see some round thing . . . a ball, an orange, the moon, but to grasp the idea of round-ness or circularity is to reach a more general state of knowing. When the idea or concept is grasped, it can no longer be con-fused with something else. For example, circularity, triangularly and linearity are clear and distinct ideas. As ideas they are in no way altered and in no way dependent on the appearance or the absence or the number of round things in experience. They describe equally all things that participate in the appropriate idea or form (although each particular round thing will only approximate the idea. None will be perfectly round. A central theme of The Republic is the search for the idea of justice. The old traditional order based on stories like those of the Homeric epics had been breaking up for some time. In a way the Greeks were victims of their own success. Expansion of Greek involvement with other peoples eroded the ancestral sense of identity. The common sense of an earlier time was being displaced by a wide variety of alternate narratives. There needed to be some basis of discussion that would allow people with different stories to talk to one another about important issues. Plato wanted to establish criteria (principles) by which one could describe (and bring about) a discussion of what could constitute a just society. To get a political order based on something besides the will of the strong or the expedients of getting along with the boss requires something like an idea of justice, i.e., something based on clearly understood principles and procedures. It involves getting people to transcend the 3 particularities of their individual or group experiences to achieve a clear definition of what needs to be accomplished. LEVEL 4: NOESIS There are countless ideas besides the idea of justice. The academic state of mind is full of them. Abstract ideas, their inter-relationships and their management constitute academic disciplines. So one goes to school and studies the laws of motion, the theory of relativity, personality types, literary criticism, art history, the theory of supply and demand, principles of accounting, organizational structure and behavior, systems analysis, human resource management, computer science, data structures, and a whole host of other ideas of which Plato never dreamed. Let us look at the chart. The right hand column lists the objects of knowing, the outcomes of the activities of the two states of mind. On the level of noesis, Plato identifies the object of knowledge as the archai. These are the first principles, the original forms, the ideal essences or patterns that underlie everything. Philosophers refer to this kind of knowledge as met-physics, things you think about after or beyond thought about the nature (physis) of things we know from experience and reason. Noesis is an activity of mind that grasps, understands the archai. Noesis seeks to know the ultimate conditions in reality that make knowing possible Plato seems to have thought that these fundamental ideas (archai) were existing entities -- at least ideas like the One, the Good, the True, and the Beautiful. Aristotle had a lot of trouble with this. But it doesn't change the fact that noesis is a distinctive state of mental activity and that Plato did a masterful job of describing it. Since our primary purpose here is not to do philosophy of metaphysics, we can put further discussion of this level aside for some other time. LEVEL 3: DIANOIA There is another mental activity that belongs to episteme: dianoia. This is a kind of knowing activity that moves from questions to hypotheses to conclusions by formal argument or reasoning. We might understand it as being "logical" the way mathematicians are. It is methodical, operating according to certain explicit rules and procedures. We are in that state of mind when we perform the act of balancing our checkbooks. It is a less fundamental kind of knowing, in Plato's view, but it is still "real" knowledge. We have to acquire a great deal of formal skill to do it well, but once we have “discovered” something, we can check and recheck (verify) our conclusions. We can “prove” (test) the outcomes (mathematika). Further, in principle, anyone and everyone can do it exactly the same way as everyone else does. An example: astronomers knew about the existence of the so-called planet Pluto long before it was directly observed. They figured out all kinds of things about Pluto, its size, mass, orbit and so forth because of measured variations in other planets' behavior when related to the theories of physics. This procedure for discovering things we don’t know already or for verifying what we think we know is called dianoia. So dianoia is a kind of "real" knowledge, of episteme. Such scientific knowing is a key element in the development and implementation of theoretic knowledge. Plato's 4 work illustrates his search for episteme through noesis and dianoia, the development and application of a theory of knowledge. In the right hand column on level 3, we see that the object of dianoia, what is known in that activity, is referred to as mathematika: learned conclusions reached through formal reasoning dianoia). As already indicated, this is most obvious in mathematical thinking because the formality is purest and most controlled in mathematics. But it applies to all forms of disciplined reasoning, to all inquiry governed by methodical procedures. All sciences, all academic fields, in so far as they attempt to find conclusions by reason, method, logic, are engaging in the state of mind, the kind of knowing that Plato calls episteme. Another way of saying this is that such knowing is explanatory knowing in the strict sense of the term. Explanation means literally "to (put or lay) out on a plane (flat surface)." The diagram we have been using is a kind of "ex-planation." Episteme is an "ex-planatory" state of mind. Dianoia is one way of acting in that state of mind. Science is always trying to explain things. Theories are attempts to "ex-plain." This book is an extended exercise in "ex-planation." Dianoia works from hypotheses, assumptions: “If this, then that.” One makes hypotheses [hypo- = “less than” + thesis = “a stand”) and then applies method to data to find out how the hypothesis works out. Inevitably there are many possible explanations for anything. Explanations might also be good explanations or poor explanations. Some explanations are better than others. In any case, explanations never explain things exhaustively. They always select and assume some hypothetical pattern or form as the basis for the explanation. The investigator’s attention will focus on some aspects of a situation and not on others. A methodical approach will also carefully manage and select the data it includes. The various academic fields of study have their own ideas about what counts as data, Psychologists attend to individuals, sociologists to groups, and so on. Here's an illustration. Suppose we have a box full of rocks gathered from here and there with no particular attention to anything other than the fact that they were rocks. We selected to collect only rocks and not beer cans, sticks, or flowers. We bring the box home and proceeded to "ex-plain" (lay them out) the contents on the dining room table. How can we explain further? How many ways can you ex-plain them? We could, of course, just dump them on the table in a heap and let it go at that. But let's suppose we are trying to be scientific. We want to sort them into kinds and to assess what we have. Which kinds? How many kinds? What will be the basis for the explanation? Is our motive monetary? Or strictly educational? Or are we seeking certain materials for an art project? Or to repair the rock wall in the back yard? There are many possible motives and many possible explanations. We could begin by sorting them out (ex-planing) them by size. Or weight. Or color. Or chemical composition. Or hardness. Or perhaps we are interested in some aesthetic qualities. In any event, we cannot explain them effectively until we have determined what we want the basis to be. And once we select one feature, we will ignore the others. Here it is critically important to grasp the relationship between this whole discussion and the study of religious traditions. Plato's privileging of episteme, his insistence that it is the only "real" or "true" way of knowing, has tended to discredit religious knowing generally, to relegate it to the realm of mere “opinion.” Consequently, 5 Western culture has a long history of conflict between "faith" and "reason," between "religion" and "science." We cannot blame this conflict entirely on Plato. In his day, the power and presence of episteme was minimal. It was just emerging. This is not so today. But much of the conflict between the ways of knowing is needless. Much of it is a consequence of category mistakes. COMMON SENSE KNOWLEDGE: DOXA, PISTIS, EIKASIA. It is pretty clear that Plato launched an all-out attack on doxa (common sense) knowledge. He wanted, especially, to run the poets, the purveyors of traditional knowledge, out of his ideal Republic. It is also clear that the way things developed in Western, European culture, there has been a longstanding battle to establish episteme as the privileged form of knowing. This is important for our present discussion primarily because it goes some way in explaining why people can be in many ways hostile toward the traditional knowledge of religious traditions. The tendency remains, and it prejudices the study of religious traditions in a variety of ways. Much of it is that they simply do not have the appropriate common sense to understand it. There are many reasons for Plato's devaluation of doxa. It was everywhere. In his mind it was represented by all of society's powers -- the rulers, the religious leaders, the educational authorities. Plato's teacher Socrates had been executed for "corrupting the youth," which meant encouraging them to get into episteme and to question the power of the establishment. There is plenty of evidence to suggest that the battle still goes on in and among segments of society. From the perspective of episteme, it is not hard to understand why typically doxa has been translated as "opinion," or, in some ways better, "public opinion.” "Common sense" presents special problems from the viewpoint of knowledge. It refers, after all, to “what people think,” to “what everybody knows,” to what a particular group takes for granted. Aware as we are of prejudice, ignorance and biases of various sorts, our suspicion of such “opinion” is often well founded. But there is more to the story. If we translate doxa as “common sense,” it takes on a different flavor. We perhaps recognize easily what it means for someone to lack common sense. He or she just doesn’t “get it.” Perhaps this is a clue. We are aware of a kind of knowing that originates and operates quite unlike scientific reasoning. At the same time we are aware of the importance of having such knowing. But it is hard to describe, let alone to define. It seems to have all sorts of variability, and it is difficult to control. It is difficult to teach common sense, particularly in a classroom. Practitioners in “the real world” often accuse academic people of not having much common sense. And sure enough, there is always the child psychologist who can't raise his or her own kids. And there's the newly graduated MBA who runs the company into the ground. Is "common sense” a legitimate -- even indispensable--kind of knowing? What characteristics does the state of mind we call "common sense" possess? How is it related to episteme? 1. Whereas episteme seeks the abstract and the general, common sense (doxa) understands the concrete and the particular. 6 2. There are as many "common senses" as there are concrete, particular human situations. There is a "common sense" of the family, of the work place, of the political arena, and even of the school. Yet the common sense of one family (mine) may differ markedly from another (yours). And the fact that we can't explain it adequately makes little difference. 3. Common sense is a state of mind that comes from direct experience, from being on the job, from having learned by trial and error. 4. Common sense is common, i.e., it is a sense of what is going on that is shared amongst people who share a situation. Generally people know "what goes" and what doesn't in their families, in their offices, in their classrooms. Newcomers and outsiders might not. They have to be initiated. Children usually lack many kinds of common sense. People who are older help them learn how to negotiate the world in which they live. 5. Common sense is based in community life and experience. Because I have common sense in one situation doesn't mean I have it in another. As a matter of fact, I almost inevitably will lack common sense when I enter some new situation. "Foolish" people do things without common sense and don't seem to learn from their mistakes. The human predicament always has lots of foolishness in it. We always try to find explanations for our foolishness. There are many explanations. As a rule such explanations don't help us much. 6. What we call “culture” is largely a generalized form of common sense. Reading a book on French culture probably won't protect me from doing foolish things (from the French point of view) when I go to Paris. Living in Paris for some time might. 7. It is very difficult to give one's common sense to someone else. It is relatively easy to communicate the result of dianoia. 8. Common sense is often best expressed through stories and other art forms. 9. Common sense is ordered to practical living. As such, it values human experiences and embodies them in tradition. Tradition is about handing on what we have found to work and not to work. 10. Dramatically changing conditions can seriously disrupt common sense. Episteme can aid but cannot replace common sense. Reading a book on friendship might help me understand my problems with social life. But it won't substitute for friends no matter how much I study. LEVEL 2: PISTIS As an activity of doxa, pistis commonly has been rendered in English as "belief." Pistis is the Greek New Testament word most commonly translated as "faith" or "belief." St. Paul denigrates the "wisdom of the wise" (the philosophers' episteme) in favor of the "foolishness" (pistis) of the believer. But his use of pistis owes as much to Judaic tradition as to the Greeks. And that's another story. Plato was much earlier, and he was concerned less with the "religious" flavor of the word (if the distinction would have meant anything to him at all) than in its reference to a certain kind of knowing activity. This becomes more evident when we translate doxa as "common sense," and pistis as a particular form of common sense. 7 If we understand pistis as a knowing activity rooted in direct experience, we could translate it as "the knowing of concrete particulars." Plato says that the object of pistis is zoa, "living things," but we can extend that to all existing particulars. Let's try an example. I might know (episteme) a lot about dogs by studying them, reading books, research reports and the like. I might learn about dinosaurs or Rhinocerotidae without getting near one on the hoof. But growing up around dogs, having one for a pet or using dogs to hunt ducks would provide me with direct experiential knowledge of dogs (pistis-zoa). This knowledge of dogs would be wedded to the particular breeds of dog I have experienced and the particular animals (Fido, Buster. . .) I have encountered of these breeds. If you listen to people alertly, you will probably find them talking more about this kind of knowing than any other kind. "Fords are lousy cars. I had one, and it was in the shop all the time." "That's not my experience. I have one with a million miles and never had a problem." Both could be right. The speakers are talking about their own experience. If the statement "Fords are lousy cars" is taken as episteme (noesis –mathematika) rather than as doxa (pistis), considerable careful research would have to be done to prove or disprove it. In the meantime, it would be merely a question ("Are Fords lousy cars?") or a hypothesis to be demonstrated. ("True or False: Fords are lousy cars.") There are lots of questions that we don't have the interest, the time or the resources to pursue this way. We might be happy with some "opinions" from people we trust to have "common sense" about cars. But there are other questions that don't yield well to scientific inquiry (episteme). These questions include existential questions: "Are you my friend?" "What is the meaning of my life?" "Can Jesus save me?" "Did the Virgin Mary appear to Juan Diego?" “Did the Buddha achieve nirvana?” It is pretty well fruitless to try to reduce such things to noesis or dianoia. They are objects of doxa, common sense, and remain so, despite the efforts of theologians and others to "explain" them. They are not mathematika to be figured out or explained. Pistis is an important part of the common sense that we call “friendship,” the experience of trust, of self-communication, of openness to the other, of fidelity to relationship. In such kinds of knowing, the experience of the person who experiences cannot be removed from the equation. It cannot be treated simply as an abstraction. Of course, that does not make it less real, less true, and less significant. Religious traditions are especially interested in pistis. As noted earlier, “religion” does not exist as a thing you can find in a parking lot. “Religion” is an abstract idea that we use to point to certain kinds of human experience. Particular traditions of comprehensive concern do exist and are observable. The primary focus of these traditions is not theory, not even religious ideas, but a particular kind of common sense. Religious traditions are interested in what works. Some religious traditions have developed "theologies," attempts to formulate ideas and to explain (episteme) their relationship, coherence and viability. But theology always remains subordinate to pistis, to the essentials, foundational experiences which constitute the tradition. Theologies always derive from the common sense of the persons who do it and the tradition experience of the tradition they purport to explain. Changes in theology usually 8 accompany changes in the common sense of a community and are often accompanied by considerable controversy. Pistis (in the religious context) is an approach to the Holy understood as lifegiving power. To perform in this state of mind is to experience everything under the aspect of the Holy and to seek to live in constant holiness, close to the power of your life and being. People often think of this way of knowing as a matter of simply entertaining certain "beliefs," propositions, creedal statements or the like. But religious pistis is more properly understood as situated in an attitude of commitment, an orientation of one's whole self toward another or toward others based on some significant direct experience. LEVEL 1: EIKASIA If episteme is grasped, stored, and expressed in methods, ideas, theories, explanations, doxa is embodied, stored, and expressed in symbol (eikones). Plato knew this clearly. This is why he wanted to run the poets out of his Republic. Their old (Homeric) stories (eikones) seduced people into obsolete common sense (pistis). The epistemic state of mind strives for maximum ex-plicitness. It wants to foldout or un-fold what is covered over, to dis-cover. Something ex-plicated is torn out of the density of concrete relationships, abs-tracted ("drawn away") and generalized. Symbols (syn-ballein = to throw together) work in the opposite manner. They throw things into concrete ("grown together", entangled) forms of expression. They are implicit ("folded or tangled in") and therefore full of implications. We have seen what epistemic (noesis and dianoia) activities of mind produce. What is produced by the mental activity called eikasia? We can see but also hear, touch, taste, smell, and feel such forms because they come to us through all the senses. All of the arts (as opposed to the sciences) involve us in concrete experience. Dance, sculpture, architecture, painting, music, story, poetry -- even the art of cooking, the arts of wine making and tasting are all iconic or symbolic forms of activity, thought, experience. Eikasia is the mental activity we call "imagination," making images. Its object, what it knows, is images, eikones ("icons"), symbols. Plato called them "shadows" because they lacked the clarity, distinctness and (for him) the reality of ideas. Instead of having a clearly defined single meaning, they are full of meanings. They convey not only abstract meaning, but also draw the knower into the experience that bears the potential for meaning. Myth and ritual are important religious forms of eikasia. It should be emphasized that art and science often can work together. Technology (literally "skill-talk") is a result of such co-operation. But it is important not to confuse these states of mind and mental activities. They are easily confused because our own mental experience is a seamless web. We do not readily advert to the constant movements of our consciousness from one state to the other; from one activity to the other although we can readily enough see the differences in our experience when we do advert to them. Thus, our science is always colored by our doxa, not only in what we decide to pay attention to but in the questions we ask and the method we devise. It is from our direct experience that matters of importance arise in our awareness. It is also from our direct experience that our sense of value and appropriateness arises. The culture we 9 belong to shapes our sense of what is important. Our cultural formation sets up the framework in which we interpret our experience. In fact, it determines in fundamental ways what our experience is, what counts as relevant experience, what is worth attending to. These confusions can be seen within the Euro-American culture itself. A classic example of confusion of episteme and doxa is still evident: the ongoing conflict between the advocates of a scientific account of world origins and the advocates of the six days of creation account in Genesis. One simply does not have to choose between them. They are products of quite different states of mind. It makes no more sense to pit them against one another than it makes sense to ask which is correct or true: modern psychology's account of human emotions or the last movement of Beethoven's “Ninth Symphony.” The scientist who thus rejects Genesis is not being scientific. He or she is simply being naïve about human expression. On the other hand, the advocate of "creation science” is inadvertently imposing scientific (epistemic) expectations on a mythic (eikasia, eikones) piece of expression. For Native Americans past and present who have run up against powerful people (politicians, educators, bureaucrats, and missionaries) who are confused about these things, the results can be devastating. One common mistake is to equate the "imaginative" with the "imaginary." C.G. Jung and others have taught us something our ancestors often knew: Symbols are not mere symbols. Real symbols draw us down into the deep mysteries of life and existence. They are not substitutes for ideas dressed up for consumption by the silly and childlike amongst us. In fact our symbol life establishes the substratum upon which everything else builds. If that level is impoverished, the rest of our life is likely to be impoverished also. Let's keep this in mind as we approach the symbolic forms in which the religious traditions express themselves. Cultural and religious traditions embody, preserve and express themselves primarily in symbolic forms, what we will shortly refer to as ceremonies. Understanding a cultural or religious system requires appreciating the symbols in which the tradition experience lives. Each state of mind (episteme and doxa) has its own contribution to make. No one substitutes for any other. Symbols are not a substitute for science or the result of the absence of science. Symbols are not explanations: e.g., origin myths are not explanations. Myths are not false because they fail to be scientific. They are distinctive modes of knowing that require experience to interpret and understand. Cultures, too, can be understood in terms of their involvement in these states of mind. Some sense of these is a critical part of the study of religious traditions generally. But let's get more concrete. What does eikasia, as a mental activity, produce? Eikones, icons, says Plato. All art forms fit under this heading: pictures, music, architecture, poetry, stories, songs, dances, gestures, ritual calendars. John Ruskin made this point effectively: Each tradition has its own particular eikones, and if you want to understand any tradition you have to encounter them. Of course one should study a tradition's ideas also, ideas like Athenian "democracy" or Medieval European feudalism or Soviet communism, or American egalitarianism. But these ideas will always sprout from the iconic soil of the tradition, and even if they are transplanted, they will take on 10 the character of the local tradition's iconic foundation. A tradition may think with ideas, but it lives in its icons.