Rob Compaijen 0401250 Reflective report Nietzsche-seminar 24-10-2008 ‘Nietzsche and Japanese Buddhism on the cultivation of body-mind’ (A. van der Braak) I. Text In his text ‘Nietzsche and Japanese Buddhism on the cultivation of body-mind’, André van der Braak compares Nietzsche’s philosophy to Japanese Buddhist philosophy. Van der Braak sees in Buddhist thought a philosophy that can help us comprehend Nietzsche’s philosophy better. The text under consideration explores the ways both philosophies understand the relation between body and mind. In the first part of the text van der Braak elaborates on Nietzsche’s views regarding this subject, while the second part deals with the views of Japanese Buddhist philosopher Dōgen, and points out the similarities between both philosophies, regarding the relation between mind and body. Van der Braak makes two claims: First, both Nietzsche and Dōgen practice philosophy by using the body (instead of the mind) as guide. And second, Nietzsche, as well as Dōgen, view the task of personal development not as a task undertaken by an I but as a ‘self-education of the drives’ (14). I.1 Nietzsche Van der Braak begins his article by writing that Western thought considered the mind and body as two separate substances. In that sense, Western philosophy understands the relation between both substances as dualistic. It is precisely this dualism that Nietzsche opposes according to van der Braak. Instead of viewing mind and body as two dualistically related substances, Nietzsche claims that the body is more fundamental than the mind. Put stronger: he views the mind as ‘a word for something about the body’ (1), (AsZ, 1.4). One consequence of this view is that the location of the process of knowing shifts from the mind to the body. Unsurprisingly, then, Nietzsche speaks of knowing or understanding in terms of incorporation (Einverleibung), and nutrition (Ernährung). This, in turn, means that the preconditions for our knowledge are formulated in purely physiological terms, or, as van der Braak puts it: “(…) which beliefs and views we hold is not determined by some kind of correspondence to/with reality, but by their usefulness for our bodily drives, and by our capacity to digest those views.” (3) 1 Next to describing the way human beings know and understand reality, Nietzsche adopts a more normative, or prescriptive standpoint as well: we should leave behind incorporated illusory perspectives, and replace them with more truthful perspectives. This, however, poses a problem: is the incorporation of truth even possible? Nietzsche famously formulated this problem in a question in Die fröhliche Wissenschaft: ‘To what extent does the truth bear incorporation?’ (FW 110). As this question indicates, there might be barriers that prevent us from knowing the truth. Indeed, van der Braak writes that the belief in a permanent subject is, for Nietzsche, one of the most persistent illusions that hinders the incorporation of truth. Being able to incorporate new and heavier truths, and shifting between perspectives requires what van der Braak calls a cultivation of the body. He describes this process as “the development of different physiological habits”, and “education of the drives”. (7) There is, however, no ‘I’ that is in charge of the process of cultivation. Instead, the drives have to educate themselves, that is: the body is involved in a process of self-education. According to van der Braak the Western philosophical paradigm does not enable us to understand properly what a self-education of the body entails. He believes that Nietzsche’s way of thinking is more closely related to Eastern thought. This is, he writes, clear when we compare Nietzsche’s philosophy to Eastern thought, in particular Japanese Buddhism. Both philosophies reject viewing the relation between mind and body as dualistic. Moreover, in contrast to most of Western philosophy, both Nietzsche and Eastern thought focus strongly on the perfection of the human being as a whole. Therefore, van der Braak writes, we should try to understand Nietzsche’s notion of the self-education of the body from the perspective of Japanese Buddhism. I.2 Japanese Buddhism In Japanese Buddhist thought, van der Braak asserts, ‘body and mind are not conceived as two different substances.’ In its conception of the human being as made up of five aggregates (skandhas) – 1) matter or form (rupa); 2) sensations or feelings (vedana); 3) perception (samnja); 4; volitional dispositions (samskara); 5) consciousness (vijnana) – Japanese Buddhism bears similarity to Nietzsche’s view of the human being as a constellation of bodily drives. Another central point of comparison between both Nietzsche and Japanese Buddhist thought is the emphasis they put on personal cultivation. Moreover, they both attach great importance to the body, and the role it plays in personal cultivation. It is here that van der Braak introduces the Japanese Buddhist philosopher Dōgen (1200 – 1253). This Japanese Zen-master stressed the central role the body plays in self-cultivation. 2 Just like Nietzsche claimed, Dōgen’s approach rejects the existence of a mind (or: ‘I’) that cultivates our bodily drives. On the other hand, the drives have to cultivate themselves. But how does this happen? Dōgen recommends the practice of ‘zazen’, that is, seated meditation practice, which can be seen as paying complete attention to the body. We can interpret, van der Braak writes, Nietzsche’s eight hour walks as serving the same purpose. Through these physical exercises the everyday dualistic perspective on the body and mind is cast off. A higher perspective can now be incorporated: the body and mind seen as a unity. This, van der Braak points out, expands our experience beyond our individual nature and gives it a cosmic dimension. II. Discussion II.1 The incorporation of knowledge The process of incorporating knowledge functions, van der Braak claims, according to a scheme that we find in a Nachlass text from 1881: Die Wiederkunft des Gleichen. Entwurf. 1. Die Einverleibung der Grundirrthümer. 2. Die Einverleibung der Leidenschaften. 3. Die Einverleibung des Wissens und des Verzichtendes Wissens. (Leidenschaften der Erkenntniss.) 4. Der Unschuldige. Der Einzelne als Experiment. Die Erleichterung des Lebens, Erniedrigung, Abschwächung – Übergang. 5. Das neue Schwergewicht: die ewige Wiederkunft des Gleichen. Unendliche Wichtigkeit unseres Wissen’s, Irren’s, unsrer Gewohnheiten, Lebensweisen für alles Kommende. Was machen wir mit dem Reste unseres Lebens – wir, die wir den grössten Theil desselben in der wesentlichsten Unwissenheit verbracht haben? Wir lehren die Lehre – es ist das stärkste Mittel, sie uns selber einzuverleiben. Unsre Art Seligkeit, als Lehrer der grössten Lehre. (…) (KSA 9, 11[141]) 3 Van der Braak understands this scheme, in line with paragraph 110 of Die fröhliche Wissenschaft, as illustrating five chronologically successive stages of human knowledge. He believes that Nietzsche wanted to make clear what stages of understanding we have to go through, in order to ultimately arrive at the incorporation of the idea of the eternal recurrence of the same. This is a process not so much of incorporation, but, instead, of ‘excorporation’ – a neologism that designates the process in which we free ourselves from the illusions that prevent us from seeing reality. Van der Braak’s interpretation of this enigmatic text is problematic. For example: freeing ourselves from our basic errors (Grundirrthümer) to reach truth is comprehensible, but what exactly does freeing ourselves from our passions (Leidenschaften) mean? Moreover, can we understand stage three as a form of ‘excorporation’? These unanswered questions are certainly shortcomings of van der Braak’s interpretation, which, therefore, make an alternative interpretation of the 1881 Nachlass-text necessary. One suggestion put forward is that because the idea of the eternal recurrence of the same is such a central idea in Also sprach Zarathustra that it might be useful to interpret the scheme in the light of the Zarathustra. One is then reminded of that other scheme important in the Zarathustra: the three metamorphoses of the spirit. In a first attempt to link these two schemes together, it is suggested that the camel corresponds to the first stage, the lion to the second and third, and the child to the fourth. This interpretation, however, faces a problem: because only the first four stages are taken into account, how should we understand the fifth stage? In trying to resolve this problem, it is claimed that we should acknowledge a state beyond that of the child, which corresponds to the child again. Another alternative would be that the fifth stage corresponds to Zarathustra, seen as the teacher of the child’s innocence. An objection against these attempt is that the status of the fifth stage remains unclear. A question that arises when examining the above scheme is what it involves, when it is viewed as describing stages of understanding not for the individual, but for humankind. It is claimed, that the scheme manifests a narrowing down. That is, most people are living in the first and second stage. The third stage, then, entails an elite community of so-called free spirits. The fourth stage consists of the lonely philosophers. The understanding of the eternal recurrence of the same involved in the fifth stage is inhumanly heavy: that is, no one is able to bear it. II. 2 The Will to Power 4 The will to power, which is a central element in Nietzsche’s philosophy, is completely left out of Van der Braak’s article. Leaving it out of this comparative study is understandable, because Nietzschean will to power is hard to reconcile with Japanese Buddhist thought. Japanese Buddhism, as van der Braak presents it, is aimed at attaining ‘the true human body’ (13), which ‘functions freely and authentically in harmony with the entire universe’ (idem), and in which ‘like and dislike [have] come to an end.’ (12). This account is on strained terms with the will to power, which denies an ultimate endpoint that is viewed as harmony and disappearance of the will. Moreover, whereas van der Braak seems to characterize the practice of ‘zazen’ as a form of disinterested perception in which one is open to that which is perceived, incorporation – as Nietzsche understands it – does not (want to) do justice to what is incorporated, but instead instrumentalizes it. Van der Braak responds to this criticism that the will to power is, in a certain sense, present in Japanese Buddhism: it has the character of the fight against ignorance and limiting perspectives. That is, the will to power manifests itself in the Buddhist practitioner as the will to replace illusory perspectives by adopting a wider variety of true perspectives. This, however, corresponds more to the Nietzschean virtue of Redlichkeit, than to the will to power. Is it, then, possible to understand Redlichkeit as a shared notion in both philosophies? Can we see both Nietzsche’s philosophy and Japanese Buddhist thought as seeking to overcome illusions and striving for truth, as van der Braak defends? Against this hypothesis it is objected that Nietzsche’s use of the notion ‘Redlichkeit’ and his corresponding elaborations on illusion and truth are ambiguous. For instance, when Nietzsche writes ‘I search the truth.’, we should not take this claim at face-value. We should read such claims strategically instead: that is, understand them Nietzsche attempting to adopt a standpoint in face of his opponents. Ecce Homo is a useful example, because it is a text that should be understood as a manifestation of a particular standpoint in the debate on, for instance, truth and illusion, rather then as a theory about what truth is, what reality ultimately entails, et cetera. II.3 Methodology Insufficiently addressed during the discussion, is van der Braak’s methodology. His comparative study on Nietzsche and Japanese Buddhism departs from the idea that Nietzsche’s philosophy cannot properly be understood when we limit ourselves to a Western philosophical paradigm. This is the case, because Nietzsche fundamentally breaks with assumptions that ‘are common within the Western philosophical tradition’ (9). We should, 5 therefore, use an Eastern philosophical paradigm. However, van der Braak’s attempt to found this comparative study is questionable for (at least) three reasons. First. Though Nietzsche indeed breaks with several core elements of Western philosophy, he cannot for that reason be seen as standing outside Western philosophy. Rather, by continually questioning and criticizing the Western philosophical tradition, Nietzsche places himself directly inside this very tradition; though, of course, he takes within this tradition a somewhat different position than other philosophers. Moreover, Nietzsche himself grew up, studied, and worked inside a Western philosophical framework, so he must have thought in terms of ‘the incorporated categories through which we traditionally understand the world and our experience’ (8), to quote van der Braak. Thus, the claim that Nietzsche cannot be understood from a Western philosophical paradigm seems to me unconvincing. Second. When, however, we do accept that we cannot properly understand Nietzsche’s philosophy because of our Western way of thinking, we face a fundamental problem: in addition to not being able to properly understand Nietzsche, we should, on the same ground, acknowledge that we cannot properly understand Japanese Buddhist thought. This means that van der Braak’s method of turning to Japanese Buddhist thought to provide a more complete picture of Nietzsche’s philosophy is doomed to fail. And this, in turn, seriously undermines van der Braak’s project of comparing Nietzsche’s philosophy to Japanese Buddhist thought, because, consequently, only readers who stand in both a Western and an Eastern paradigm of thought would be able to comprehend such a comparison. We could, moreover, ask whether it is even possible to stand in both paradigms of thought. Third. One example van der Braak provides for showing that Nietzsche is more intimately related to Eastern thought than to Western philosophy, is his focus on the perfected human being. Van der Braak writes that in the Western philosophical tradition ‘personal development has not been a major philosophical theme (…).’ (9). I believe this view is very difficult to defend. Two examples suffice to support this claim: a) Aristotelian virtue-ethics. This important philosophical-ethical theory focuses strongly on the theme of self-realization, which is the key to becoming a virtuous, and thus happy, human being. b) Kierkegaard. Core notions of his philosophy are ‘self becoming’ and ‘authenticity’. Conclusion A comparative study between Nietzsche’s philosophy and Japanese Buddhist thought can be both perfectly viable and rewarding. However, wanting to justify the necessity of comparing Japanese Buddhist thought to Nietzsche’s philosophy, as van der Braak wishes, seems to me 6 to be impossible. Especially when one sees, as van der Braak, both traditions as constituted by different paradigms of thought, which are, in turn, viewed as ‘incorporated categories’ (8). In any case, it creates serious problems. It might, therefore, be better if van der Braak, instead, makes clear that comparing Nietzsche’s philosophy to Japanese Buddhist thought is interesting, and can shed light on both Nietzsche’s thought and Japanese Buddhism, simply because both traditions are similar in several respects.Van der Braak should, however, highlight more clearly in his text the differences between Nietzsche’s philosophy and Dōgen’s thought. 7