Replication and the Experimental Ethnography of Science By Ryan D. Tweney Department of Psychology Bowling Green State University Bowling Green, OH 43403 USA 419/372-2301 419/372-6013 (fax) tweney@bgnet.bgsu.edu [In press, Journal of Cognition and Culture] 2 Replication and the Experimental Ethnography of Science Ryan D. Tweney* ABSTRACT The present paper attempts to define an experimental ethnography as an approach to the understanding of scientific thinking. Such an ethnography relies upon the replication of contemporary and historical scientific practices as a means of capturing the cultural and cognitive meanings of the practices in question. The approach is contrasted to the typical kind of laboratory experiment in psychology, and it is argued that replications of scientific practices can reveal dimensions of the microstructure of science and of its context that otherwise may remain invisible. An extended example is presented, based upon replications of the experimental procedures used by Michael Faraday (1791-1867) in 1856 during his examination of the optical properties of gold. Introduction In the popular imagination, the image of science is replete with material objects; bubbling flasks, microscopes, sparking coils and the like, all presided over by a white-coated figure with an expression of quiet confidence, passionate certainty, or – sometimes – sheer madness. Indeed, with some of the facial expressions of scientists being a possible exception, the lab coat does have its place in science, flasks and microscopes are still in use, and the sparking coils, while anachronistic now, once did signal the forefront of electrical research. Clearly, science occurs in a realm of materiality, a realm that has recently produced a huge outpouring of scholarship by scholars. Clearly also, this materiality provides an important dimension of inquiry for a cognitive anthropology of science. * Ryan D. Tweney, Department of Psychology, Bowling Green State University, Bowling Green, OH 43403; email: tweney@bgnet.bgsu.edu. The author gratefully acknowledges helpful comments on an earlier draft by Christophe Heintz and by an anonymous reviewer. This paper has benefited greatly from earlier discussions with Elke Kurz-Milcke; she is of course not responsible for any misuse of the ideas that originated in those conversations. 3 The present paper is an attempt to define how an experimental approach to a cognitive ethnography can contribute to the understanding of scientific practices. By experimental ethnography, I mean the attempt to understand scientific practices, both contemporary and historical, using procedures that replicate the practices under study, in an effort to more fully characterize their nature. Such methods are ethnographic insofar as they are meant to capture the richness and cultural meaning of the practices in question, and they are experimental in that the agency of the inquirer is used to directly create, manipulate, and participate in the epistemic practices under examination. There are two broad categories of such replication that I will consider in this paper. The first stems primarily from cognitive psychologists and involves the attempt to isolate the essential processes of scientific practice. The second grows out of recent work on “cognitive history” and derives from earlier work on historical issues. The goal in most laboratory research in psychology has of course been an abstractive one, that is, one in which general laws of cognition and behavior are to be abstracted from the particularities of actual behavior, usually the aggregated performance of statistically large numbers of individual “subjects.” The historical emergence of the “subject” as a faceless “object” of psychological investigation has been documented by Danziger (1990), who argued that the clients of American psychology in the first half of the 20th century, primarily bureaucratic elites in education, the corporate world, and the military, were not interested in the inner workings or experiences of individuals and instead wanted the ability to predict and control the behavior of large numbers of people. As a result, the goals of psychological science shifted in the direction of seeking “nomothetic” laws instead of “idiographic” understandings. This aggregative approach had its critics (e.g., Allport 1940), but nonetheless, by mid-century, the dominance of an aggregative approach within psychology was overwhelming. Coupled with the use of statistical analysis (in part as a legitimating procedure for psychology’s “scientific” status, Tweney 2003), the reductive character of experimental psychological method opened a large gap between psychology and the methods of ethnography. By the end of the century, the contrastive “normative” rules of research given by Fetterman (1998) for anthropologists, versus those outlined by Rosenthal & Rosnow (1991) for psychologists, reveal almost no common 4 ground. In the end, most anthropologists would consider the laboratory setting of psychological tasks to be far too artificial, and hence useless as adjuncts to the methods of ethnography, while most psychologists consider the methods of ethnography to be too limited as approaches to nomothetic laws and as little better than anecdotal in character. In an early signal that this division was perhaps too sharply drawn, Herbert Simon (1967/1996) used the metaphor of an ant crossing a sandy beach. The ant is a relatively simple behavioral system, but the geometry of its path across a beach is apparently very complex. The complexity, however, resides in the environment, not the ant. Simon argued that a similar consideration applied to human problem solving; the apparent complexity is in the symbolic environment of thought not the thought itself which follows, according to Simon, a relatively simple set of heuristic principles. For Simon, broadly general principles of problem solving could be used to untangle the complex environmental manifestations of the problem solving of a single individual. His approach was strikingly successful in such domains as chess playing, and its reach has even been extended to include claims about scientific discovery (e.g., Klahr 2000; Langley, Simon, Bradshaw, & Zytkow 1987; Kulkarni & Simon 1990). In contrast to most psychological research, Simon and his colleagues tended to downplay the aggregative methods of experimental psychology in favor of computer simulation, often based upon single-subject protocols of great complexity. Simon’s tradition of research has led others to a broader range of methods that begin to resemble the ethnographic approaches that I consider in this paper. Thus, Kevin Dunbar (1999) used laboratory analogs of real-world scientific experiments in genetics as a means of refining the questions used in his in vivo studies of four molecular biology laboratories. These latter were based upon extensive video recorded observations of lab meetings and interviews held over an extended period. Some such studies within cognitive science have converged in scope and richness with efforts in which computer models of scientific thinking have been based upon instances of “real science” (often elaborated in a historical context), for example the studies of Darden (1992) on the processes of theory change in modern genetics, or the simulations by Kulkarni & Simon (1990) of the discovery of the ornithine cycle by Hans Krebs, a simulation of experimental practice based upon a historical analysis of Krebs’s diaries (Holmes 1980; 2004). 5 In my own case, the work of my colleagues and I initially used laboratory-based “model systems” and an aggregative approach as methods for the understanding of scientific thinking (Mynatt, Doherty, & Tweney 1978; Tweney, Doherty, & Mynatt 1981). Having found, in these studies, evidence for several heuristics involving the assessment of evidence, we sought to confirm our findings in real-world contexts, an attempt that eventually led to my studies of Faraday’s practices (described later in this paper). Our first efforts were conceived under the assumption that the simpler environment of laboratory studies of science would prove superior to a direct immersion in the messy world of “real science.” Thus, my first efforts to understand Faraday (Tweney 1985; Tweney & Hoffner 1987) were essentially hypothetico-deductive in character, in the sense that I was trying to test hypotheses derived from our laboratory work. Only later did I realize that the messiness of Faraday (to take the example closest to my gaze at the time) was only apparent. It appeared so only to one whose hypotheses-laden vision was constricted to selected aspects of Faraday’s work. In fact, broader approaches were necessary. In the present paper, I adopt a perspective that emerged from this experience, to wit, that everything in the record left by Faraday – his publications, his diary, and now even his specimens – is potentially relevant. The task of the scholar is to understand how to interpret this record in the light of the best available theory, whether that theory derives from cognitive science, from sociology, or from anthropology, and the methods must be at least in part ethnographic in character. The second broad category of research that I consider is based upon a historical-cognitive approach within the history of science and cognitive science. Nancy Nersessian (1995) introduced the term “cognitive history” to describe this body of work, characterizing it as an attempt to understand the processes by which “vague speculations get articulated into scientific understandings, are communicated to other scientists, and come to replace existing representations of a domain” (p. 194). Here, the goal has been to use insights derived from cognitive science to understand historical cases of scientific thinking and practice, as well as to import findings from the history of science into cognitive science itself. For example, Nersessian (1999) used Maxwell’s development of his field theory as a source problem for 6 claims within cognitive science about the generative role of analogy in scientific thinking. For some in this tradition, the replication of specific historically relevant cases has played an important role. For example, Gooding (1989; 1990) was able to understand some aspects of Faraday’s 1821 experiments on the rotation of a current-carrying wire in a magnetic field by replicating the procedures used by Faraday. In the process, he discovered that the apparently straightforward discovery recorded in Faraday’s notebooks of circular motion (the result of transverse forces rather than radial forces) actually must have involved a long series of interactions between “eye,” “hand,” and “mind.” Only through replication was Gooding able to reconstruct a path by which a seemingly chaotic phenomenon was gradually ordered and shaped by the experimenter’s activity (Gooding & Addis 1999). In Gooding’s words, “Empirical results are never completely independent of the practices that produce them. Facts are practice-laden as well as theory-laden.” (1989, p. 64). Such examples of the implicitly ethnographic use of replication will constitute many of my examples in the remainder of this paper. Nersessian (1995) argued that the relationship between the disciplines of cognitive science and the history of science was reciprocal; the findings and methods of cognitive science had a great deal to offer history of science, but so also did history of science have much value for the cognitive sciences themselves. Thus, one goal of the present paper is to expand upon the examples of the second kind, to show that an experimental ethnographic approach can draw upon the resources of historical case studies of science in ways that enlarge the scope of current work on cognition itself. Both kinds of research in cognitive history, the cognitive scientific research (like Simon’s), and the cognitively minded historical work (like Gooding’s and Nersessian’s) suggest a need to provoke discussion about the role of the active replication of scientific experiments and scientific observations as a means of opening a window on otherwise invisible processes of science. The intent is to recover the everyday practices of science from the mostly textual representations of those practices found in published papers and books, in diaries, and in lab notebooks. I argue further that, like an archeologist seeking the limits of pyramid-building technology by “trying my hand at it,” replication of procedures is essential to understanding what can and cannot be happening prior to the instantiation of scientific thought in text. Thus, 7 like research notebooks, the intent is to use replication as a means to open “particularly powerful avenues of access to the microhistorical processes of scientific change” (Holmes, Renn, & Rheinberger 2003, p. xii). I begin with a case history of experimental ethnography, presenting some of my recent work in which replication was used to uncover some of the experimental and theoretical aspects of Michael Faraday’s research on the optical properties of gold. The project has historical implications for the understanding of Faraday’s research, and implications for cognitive approaches to the understanding of science in general. As a contribution to the history of science, the case study documents an unusually complete record left by a great scientist, one that forces certain reinterpretations of a portion of his work. These reinterpretations are aided by the replications. As a contribution to cognitive science, the case study illustrates how scientific discovery is imbedded in the concrete practices of a set of artifacts, requiring attention to the entire dynamic cognitive system involved in scientific discovery -- the scientist, in a laboratory, making and using artifacts. Here, replications contribute to the understanding of the dynamics of cognition and action. I. Understanding Scientific Artifacts using Experimental Ethnography. In 1856, Michael Faraday (1791-1867) carried out an extensive program of research to explore the properties of thin films of metallic gold (Faraday 1857; see also James 1985, for an overview of Faraday’s research on optical phenomena). These films had long been of interest to him because they possess the peculiar property of appearing gold in color by reflected light, but green by transmitted light. Faraday therefore hoped that gold could serve as a model for the general interaction of light and matter. Encouraged perhaps by his earlier finding that magnetic fields could affect a beam of polarised light passing through a highly refractive substance, Faraday was hoping for even more general phenomena by which the integration of field theory and chemical theories of matter could be integrated (Faraday 1839-55). In the course of the research, Faraday discovered the first metallic colloids and what is now known as the “Faraday Tyndall Effect” (actually a case of Rayleigh scattering of light). Thus, although his major theoretical goals were not realised, the investigation resulted in two important discoveries. 8 In attempting to construct cognitive psychological models of scientific thinking, Michael Faraday’s extensive diaries (Martin 1932-36) had been an important resource for my own investigations, as they have been for others (for examples, see Anderson 1994; Fisher 2001; Gooding 1981, 1990; Steinle 1996; 2003; Tweney 1985, 1992). The stretch of diary covering his work on gold, however, had long been puzzling, both to myself and to others. Thus, Faraday’s principal modern biographer, Pearce Williams (1965), suggested that Faraday was beginning to lose his grip in 1856, and that signs of ageing were apparent. Indeed, a reading of his diary for this period made such a claim plausible, in that there is a seeming aimlessness about much of the record. In fact, however, a recent discovery has cast a different light on Faraday’s efforts during 1856. In the course of his experimentation on gold, which lasted nearly the entire year, Faraday prepared a variety of specimens – colloids, precipitates, solutions, and so forth. Recently, in the Museum of the Royal Institution of Great Britain, I discovered the nearly-complete set of metallic specimens used by Faraday in his 1856 research on gold films, most of which are thin gold deposits on ordinary microscope slides.1 A few of his colloids still survive (although too few to permit much by way of additional interpretation of the diary), but the slides had been overlooked until recently. The slide specimens are numbered and cross-referenced within his dated diary records. When examined (Tweney 2002), they provided an amazingly complete record – over 95% of some 700 of his slide specimens have been found, along with many other kinds of specimens – dried deposits on watch glasses, heated tubes of metallic matter, and so forth. Simply viewing these specimens in conjunction with reading the diary opened a new window on this entire year of Faraday’s research. It is now clear that he intended the numbered and catalogued specimens as an integral part of the diary. Indeed, “reading” the specimens and the diary together gave a kind of “illustrated text,” an opening to an understanding of the research. Ronald Anderson (in press; see also Steinle 2003) has recently elaborated the way in which Faraday “read nature” The specimens 1 I am deeply indebted to Frank A.J.L. James, Reader in History and Philosophy of Science and Keeper of the Collections, Royal Institution of Great Britain, for his assistance in granting access to the slide specimens and for much help in understanding their import. 9 + diary now available makes clear how this can be reconstructed and read even more deeply. Such a reading ruled out the possibility that Faraday was showing an age-related decline – the specimen + diary record can be interpreted and seen as a coherent and goal-driven enterprise by a mature scientist pursuing an elusive goal (Tweney 2002). So far, my description of Faraday’s researches on gold supports the notion that an ethnography is possible. Even absent replications, the slides are a valuable addition to the historical case study in question, subject to analysis, cultural artifacts like any others. However, in addition to studying the specimens themselves, we have reconstructed some of Faraday’s chemical and electrical procedures for making gold colloids, gold solutions, and thin gold film deposits. This has permitted reconstruction of some of the “invisible” dimensions of his thought and practice in the making of these “epistemic objects.” The replications thus constitute an experimental ethnography. In general, and this will probably not surprise the reader, many of Faraday’s procedures turned out to be surprisingly tricky to replicate. For example, Faraday used “deflagrating” (exploding) gold wires in order to obtain fine particulate deposits of gold upon glass slides (wires can be exploded or vaporised, rather than simply melted, if a sufficiently rapid current is passed through a very fine wire). Replicating this seemingly straightforward process proved dependent upon aspects of the specific electrical technology used by Faraday, aspects that were not evident in the diary records. Thus, he used a source of current known as a Grove’s Cell to generate his currents initially, later turning to a much more elaborate process in which a series of Leyden jars were charged by an electrostatic machine. Both procedures would have been expensive and time consuming for us to replicate – and for Faraday to implement as well! -- but we discovered the hard way why Faraday had used them. In fact, although this is never stated in the diary, he needed a source with a rapid “on time” and a very low internal resistance2. Our most economical way of achieving this relied upon a bank of modern condensers charged by a lab bench power supply plugged into the wall. This of course “cheats” in one sense, but the net result, an understanding of how and why Faraday had used the sources he used was not affected. In the end, our slides appeared to be exactly like his (cf. Tweney, Mears, & Spitzmüller in press). Note that our efforts to 2 Allan Mills (2003) recently described some of the technology of batteries during Faraday’s time, and used replications to establish quantitatively the parameters of their function. 10 replicate Faraday’s procedures were not so apparatus-oriented as those of, for example, the group at Oldenburg University; see, e.g., Heering (1994) and Sibum (2001), and the extensive catalog of devices replicated at the Institute für Physik of Oldenburg University, best viewed on their web site (Oldenburg 2004). Instead, we focused upon procedures that relied primarily upon simple chemical apparatus, of the sort described in Faraday’s much earlier Chemical manipulation (1827). Our goal was the reconstruction of practices and specimens, not apparatus as such. In a few cases, what we had expected to be difficult turned out to be quite straightforward, for example Faraday’s use of a phosphorus reduction technique to make thin gold films (Tweney in preparation). As part of his research in 1856, Faraday needed to prepare exceptionally thin films of gold metal, films even thinner than commercially available gold leaf. The technique he settled upon (which he obtained from his friend Warren De la Rue) used the reduction of a gold chloride solution to metallic gold using phosphorous vapour over a solution of phosphorus in carbon disulphide. Contrary to our original reading of the diary, his somewhat opaque descriptions did not conceal a particularly difficult procedure.3 One simply dissolves phosphorous in carbon disulfide, placing a small amount of this in a watch glass. A flat glass surface to which a thin layer of gold chloride solution is adhering is then inverted over the phosphorus solution. After ten minutes or so, one can see a thin film of metallic gold forming on the surface of the gold chloride. The films can then be floated off and washed in a bowl of water, picked up on a microscope slide, and dried for observation. The films are so thin that they adhere nicely to the glass slide and are thus easily examined and manipulated. We easily succeeded in making films very like Faraday’s (if not quite so neatly mounted – a tribute to his magnificent dexterity!) Our prepared slides opened a new window on the preparations Faraday used, allowing the kinds of risky manipulations that he employed (heating, burnishing, and so on), manipulations that could not be carried out on the museum originals. And, as a bonus for our efforts, we unwittingly found that we had also replicated the circumstances of his discovery of colloidal gold, in that the pinkish solution that remained after we had made the films (“the mere washing” as Faraday put it), proved to be a 3 Instead, what proved difficult was obtaining the materials and learning how to coordinate the procedures with modern requirements for safe handling of hazardous substances. We are especially grateful to Lawrence Principe for his assistance in navigating these tricky waters! 11 colloid and “caught our eye,” as it presumably had caught his. It is interesting to note that we were unaware of this in our first experiments, simply because we had used a dark enamelled bowl to hold the fluids. Only on our second run-through of the procedure (a “replication of the replication,” carried out to allow an opportunity for photography of the results), did we notice the pinkish fluid – because we inadvertently used a white ceramic bowl, in which the faint color could be seen. One of our first replication attempts is especially revealing for the purposes of this paper, because what began as a mere “warm up” exercise for myself and my students opened a surprisingly rich view into how Faraday’s conceptualisations of gold affected the course of his first experiments. In our first chemical manipulations, we thought that preparation of simple precipitates of gold from gold chloride solution would give us the chance to firm up our lab skills, test out reagents, and so forth (Tweney, Mears, Gibby, Spitzmüller, & Sun 2002). In fact, these studies revealed to us the surprising complexity of gold and its compounds, and we found that Faraday (who at our first reading also seemed to be “warming up” with these seemingly simple initial preparations) was in fact confronted with a phenomenologically rich but theoretically confusing realm. In this context, the appearance of his first colloidal preparations (the pinkish fluid that is described in the previous paragraph) must have confused the picture even further. Historically, our replication shed light on the way in which Faraday reconceptualized the domain he was faced with, and the way in which his deepest theoretical notions about the nature of matter was in play during these early experiments. Our conclusion was that Faraday was faced with the need to construct a new hierarchical organisation of the various kinds of substances involved, one that made sense only if he adopted a specific view about the particulate nature of matter. Such cognitive reorganisations have been observed elsewhere in the history of science, for example by Hanne Andersen (2002) in an analysis of changes in the history of particle physics, and by Xiang Chen (2003), who argued that John Herschel failed to fully understand polarised light in part because his concept of the phenomena related them to an object framework, rather than an event framework. Using a dynamic frames approach (Barsalou 1992), Chen argued that this cognitive dynamical explanation was relevant to larger questions in understanding the reception of the wave theory of light. For our purposes, it is also relevant to the understanding of the cognitive dynamics of scientific thinking. 12 Our replications of Faraday’s precipitates, colloids, and solutions allowed a similar argument to be made about the cognitive nature of Faraday’s reorganisation of knowledge. Thus, where the traditional way to organise the differing substances grouped colloids and solutions in one category and precipitates in another (because colloids and solutions are both transparent and do not “settle out”), the new arrangement put colloids together with precipitates – because both scatter light. This led Faraday to the theoretical claim that both precipitates and colloids were particulate gold, although of differing sizes of particle. But why did he make this change? After seeing for ourselves the complexity of the phenomena that Faraday was faced with, we were able to reconstruct a plausible scenario about how this could have happened. In brief, Faraday must have been faced with a series of “confusions,” by which I mean something a bit more primitive than the more commonly studied notion of an anomaly.4 Elizabeth Cavicchi (1997) first alerted us to the importance of this earliest of all phases of empirical work, the appearance of something that simply appears chaotic and yet is taken as relevant to the larger goals of the project. Whereas an anomaly must be defined with respect to an existing body of otherwise coherent and “understandable” phenomena, a confusion is simply that – a set of appearances that simply make no sense. These become coherent only after the fact, in the present case, only after we recognised the reorganisation of the perceptual domain facing Faraday. Cavicchi (1997) had noticed the importance of confusions while conducting two parallel research programs, one aimed at replicating some of Faraday’s experiments on diamagnetism, and one directed at understanding student confusions in learning about science. She argued that confusions, like those she observed in her own mind while replicating Faraday, were an aspect of learning in general. She found similar confusions when she compared her replications to the experiences of a group of adult learners engaged in experimenting with magnets, wires, and batteries. In a later paper, (Cavicchi 2003) she found similar results while replicating some aspects of the development of induction coils in the late 19th century. In particular, she showed that there were periodic 4 For cognitive accounts of the role of anomalies in scientific thinking, see Darden (1992), Gentner, Brem, Ferguson, Markman, Levidow, Wolff, & Forbus (1997), and Trickett, Fu, Schunn, & Trafton (2000). 13 confusions at a number of levels in the long history of the development of such coils, confusions that could be found even in many of the published textual materials available. Until her own experience detected and resolved these confusions, she was unable to make progress in replicating historically accurate coils. In the case of our replications of Faraday’s precipitates, colloids, and solutions, note that the entities that were reorganised were in some sense very close to a “basic level” of cognition – it was the grouping by appearance of the colloids, precipitates, solutions that changed, and these changes in turn allowed Faraday to focus upon what became anomalies (not confusions). Ultimately, he was able to relate these anomalies to the changes in his theoretical understandings of the nature of matter. We did not initially see these as anomalies, and neither did Faraday. Instead, what appeared to us as confusions must have seemed so to Faraday as well, and must also have motivated his continued involvement with these substances until he could properly frame the research questions. In effect, the confusing appearance of colloids (why do they scatter light if they are just a kind of solution?) became an anomaly instead; Why are colloids able to scatter light when there are no visible particles? The answer to this question, which says roughly that colloids are particulate also, is, in the end, the scientific resolution of the anomaly. By the end of 1856, Faraday had enough evidence to publish his findings. He was remarkably diffident in his expression of these results: “Those [results] I have obtained seem to me to present a useful experimental entrance into certain physical investigations respecting the nature and action of a ray of light. I do not pretend that they are of great value in their present state, but they are very suggestive” (Faraday 1857, p. 393). Faraday’s diffidence is not hard to understand, given that his original goal was to understand the interaction of light and matter in general terms. Although his findings were “suggestive” that such interactions could be understood in ways consistent with his field theory, he was not able to finally answer the larger questions, in spite of his success in discovering new empirical phenomena.5 5 For an account of the relation of Faraday’s attempts to reconcile electric and magnetic fields with his theory of matter, see Gooding (1982), James (1985), and Williams (1965) – the latter of which, as noted earlier, downplays the significance of Faraday’s work on gold. Faraday 14 Issues for the Cognitive Ethnography of Science In the introduction, I described two general trends that each lead to an ethnographic approach to the understanding of science. First, there have been efforts by cognitive scientists that began with laboratory studies, moved through an application of Simon & Newell’s (1972) theory of problem solving, and has recently moved toward greater appreciation of field studies and approaches that begin to appear ethnographic (e.g., Dunbar 1995). Second, there have been approaches to the history of science that have emphasized the practices of science, many of which have used the replication of historically significant apparatus and procedures. The two trends can be bridged by the consideration of experimental ethnographies, as I now attempt to show. Two central issues will be discussed: the role of context and the need for analysis of the “microstructure” of scientific thought. While a full review of each issue is beyond the scope of the present paper, select examples can highlight the way in which application of cognitive ethnography to scientific practices is potentially interesting. Context. While few would deny that context affects human thought and behavior, nevertheless there are striking differences of emphasis in how investigators have accommodated this fact. For the present purpose, the role of context can be approached by considering the work of practiceoriented historians of science, e.g., Lorraine Daston (2000), and by social scientists like Karin Knorr-Cetina (1999). Both Daston and Knorr-Cetina assume the necessity of a contextualist approach, Daston with a particular interest in the historical growth and development, the “biographies,” of scientific objects -- dreams, atoms, society, and many others -- and Knorr-Cetina with an eye toward an expanded notion of culture in which the patterns and dynamics of expert practices are the focus, in order to enable a better understanding of knowledge cultures in the modern world. By contrast, for much of cognitive psychology, accounts of scientific thinking have often proceeded in the absence of explicit attention to a larger context. For example, Gentner, et al. (1997) analyzed the conceptual change underlying Kepler’s account of planetary motion. Using presented many of his views on the relation of matter and force in brilliantly clear fashion in a series of juvenile lectures in 1859-60 (Faraday 1860). See also Faraday (1856). 15 concepts from the psychological understanding of analogical change, they described Kepler’s reasoning as an instance of such reasoning. While the result is illuminating for some aspects of Kepler’s understanding, the approach treats Kepler as if he could be isolated from the historical, social, and cultural context of his work. In effect, the context of thought is in danger of becoming just another “factor” to be “held constant.” Within cognitive psychology, there have been a number of recent alternatives to such approaches. Thus, Greeno, et al. (1998) characterized a “situativity” approach in terms that refused to dissociate the context from the cognition. Greeno emphasized the need to study “intact activity systems” in terms that closely resemble those used by ethnographers. He thus suggested broadening the scope of certain cognitive concepts to reflect a more contextual focus. For example, the standard concepts of schemata and procedures (or scripts, as they are more commonly called) were assimilated by Greeno to two larger concepts, constraints and affordances. Greeno (1994) argued that these concepts, first described by James J. Gibson (1966), could be formalized in ways that allowed understanding and analysis of the interaction between agents and situations. Both constraints and affordances were defined in terms of “If ... Then ...” relations, and they thus superficially resemble the more familiar “production rules” used to model cognition in the standard Newell & Simon (1972) approach. However, Greeno defined the broader terms across entire systems of cognition, rather than as internal properties of an intelligent agent, arguing that the problem space formalisms used by Newell & Simon were in fact too constricted to accommodate the situations perspective. Goodwin (1997) used a similar approach to the understanding of the perceptual practices in a field study of a laboratory group (see also Trafton, Trickett, & Mintz in press, for a different approach to this issue, one closer to the Newell & Simon tradition). Contextual grounding is of course necessarily part of any meaningful replicative process. Hence, replication-based ethnographies must seek to provide an essential balance in this regard. One powerful way to achieve that balance is to use a historical grounding. In historically-grounded replication, the available evidence for such contextualization can be far greater than that available for studies of “real time” science. This is because the passage of historical time permits, for some cases, extended opportunities for coding, representing, and interpreting events at a variety of scales from the macro level of political and economic context to the micro level of instrumental detail 16 and biographical insight derived from studies of “investigative pathways” (Holmes 2004). Rather than an impoverished data base, then, an historically grounded experimental ethnography can sometimes enjoy a richer data base than is available even for the student of an ongoing present culture. In the present case, for example, our knowledge of the history of physics after Faraday’s time made it possible to see that his larger goal, to understand the interaction of matter and light, was not possible in the way he envisioned, since too little was then known about the nature of light itself. Further, given the diffidence with which he reported his results, it is likely that he himself did not see the importance of the two discoveries that he did make, namely the first preparation of a metallic colloid and the discovery that colloids could scatter light. Only later was it clear that these were foundational steps in the history of colloid chemistry. Note also that the availability of narrative detail available from Faraday’s later biographers provides a rich and essential context as well. From this material, we can reconstruct his social interaction (with De la Rue and others), his religious and political values and their impact on his views of the nature of matter (see Cantor, 1991), and even his larger epistemic goals, in ways that would not be possible for a living scientist, for whom such intensive analyses have not been undertaken. This consideration inverts a common misconception about historical cases (e.g., that voiced by Klahr & Simon 1999), namely, that historical cases never provide as much information as do concurrent cases. For some purposes, exactly the reverse is true. It is interesting to note that Danziger (1996) has argued that investigative practices in psychology, especially experimental practices, are especially prone to becoming “invisible.” Indeed, his earlier analysis (Danziger 1990) of the historical emergence of the construct of the “subject” in psychological research suggested that the objectification entailed by this term was in the service of a prediction and control orientation that was willfully blind to the social context of investigative practice in psychology. Within this tradition, context “effects” (e.g., the effects of experimenter bias in conducting experiments, Rosenthal & Rosnow 1991) are simply problems to be eliminated by careful experimental design. On my argument, however, exactly the situatedness of psychological research that constituted a problem for traditional psychological approaches 17 seeking to marginalize context is in fact a virtue in an ethnographic approach. Thus, it is the context sensitivity and the reflexivity of replication that gives it strength. The social dimensions of practice, both that of the current investigator and that of the historically grounded “subject” scientists, can become visible in such replication. Thus, in the case of Faraday’s research on gold, we were able to reveal some of these previously invisible practices. Just as Faraday’s diary records often reveal the course of his symbolic representations of his research practices, so also, in this case, do the surviving specimens reveal even more, and the surviving specimens, together with our replications of some of his practices open up even more of the grounded context, the situativity, of his work. To see the potential contribution to understanding, note first that, had Faraday had available color images of his specimens (and been able to include them in his diary), much more could have been made of the diary in the first place.6 But even such an “illustrated diary” could not reveal the invisible dimensions of practice that our replications were able to detect. The material context of his thought, one filled with equipment, chemical substances, and specimens of his own making (and occasionally those made by others) is a dynamic one, a constantly changing cognitive system that requires both diachronic and synchronic analysis. It is precisely this dynamic character that requires replication to be understood.7 The “representational determinism” of cognitive artifacts demands the analysis of the “psychology” of artifacts (Norman 1993; Zhang & Norman 1994). So also does the understanding of scientific practices demand that at least some of these practices be actually carried out – the artifacts alone tell only part of the story, and in this respect an experimental ethnography is essential to the cognitive anthropology of science. 6 We are presently at work constructing an illustrated catalog of the surviving slide specimens; Tweney, Friedrich, & Berg in preparation 7 Although length prohibits full discussion, our replications also allowed us to understand the importance of Faraday’s relation to his friend Warren De la Rue, and hence contributed to an understanding of the social context of his views on gold. This is discussed at more length in Tweney, Mears, & Spitzmüller (in press). 18 The “Microstructure” of Science. Attention to the microstructural detail of scientific thinking, which needs little justification for anthropologists, has been a contentious issue in the history of science. The historical objections have been well articulated recently by Ursula Klein (2003). In commenting upon a call for microstructural studies that permit the reconstruction of investigative pathways of individual scientists (Holmes 1987; 2003; 2004), Klein wondered “how many volumes will it fill?” (p. 229) and implied that one could easily become overwhelmed with the sheer bulk of such material. In addition, Klein suggested that scientific thought was in fact an emergent from the efforts of multiple individuals in a social context, and that studies of individual pathways could only obscure the larger scale relationships. Such an emergentist view presupposes a particular metaphysical position about the nature of scientific thinking, one that in effect excludes the relevance of cognitive approaches (as these are understood by cognitive scientists), in favor of a socially-grounded account of science. Yet, metaphysical stances aside, there are strong epistemological arguments against Klein’s conclusion. Taken literally, her objection challenges the validity of studies in experimental ethnography, since she suggests that the very richness of detail obtained by these methods can obscure the emergent properties of the social dynamic within which the “real” movement of science occurs. Yet the historical analysis of objects and artifacts has already been shown to contribute to the understanding of the history of science. In fact, this is one of the major claims made by Klein herself, in her discussion of the role of “paper tools,” the chemical formulas first developed by Berzelius which have become a standard mode of representation in chemistry. For Klein, these tools were essential parts of her analysis of the history of the impact of Berzelius’s research. Similarly, others have analyzed the explicit models of molecular structure used by Linus Pauling (Nye 2001) and the use of paper models in the history of stereochemistry (Ramberg 2003). For Klein, of course, even artifacts can be seen as emergent, inherently social, objects. This is in fact her point. But from my perspective, this is not a necessary step, nor does it avoid the risk of simply “defining away” the interesting cognitive dynamics, dynamics which can be successfully studied using experimental ethnographic approaches. The paper models described by Klein, Nye, and Ramberg must indeed be described from a social perspective -- but they must also be described as cognitive artifacts. 19 But if this is so, then there can be no a priori reason why even internalized “cognitive tools” should be read out of the endeavour. Science has many such tools -- the calculus, the long-term memory of a scientist for a particular background literature, and so on -- and these grant exactly the point at issue, namely, that there is a cognitive level that requires analysis for a complete historical understanding. That such analysis is both possible and fruitful is shown by a growing number of examples. For example, Kurz (1998) used a historical cognitive approach to analyze the way in which experts use calculus in searching for a representational basis needed for a problem solving task, and Kurz & Hertwig (2001) used replication to explore the context of an early experiment by the psychologist Egon Brunswik. Cavicchi’s (2003) replications of Faraday’s experiments make a similar point. An especially clear case is Lawrence Principe’s (1998) use of replication to understand the “alchemical” practices of Robert Boyle. He showed by replication that alchemical recipes once thought to describe only symbolic or allegorical states of mind were in fact elaborately coded chemical procedures with determinate effects. Principe thus “materialized” what had been seen as a purely verbal or textual discourse, and, in doing so, made the history of alchemy and early chemistry open to a cognitive analysis. In a similar (if less dramatic) fashion, our analysis of Faraday’s specimens and our replications of his practices restores coherence to what had appeared as almost aimless wanderings by a somewhat senile scientist. For Klein, the danger of excessive use of microstructural detail resided in the danger of overlooking the social and cultural context of science. In a recent paper, Heintz (2002) argued that the history of mathematical concepts can be subjected to cultural analysis, showing, basing the argument on a consideration of the development of calculus in 17th and 18th century France. Heintz showed that the social interactions among mathematicians over the controversial issue of whether or not to admit infinitesimals into mathematics can be understood if the dynamics of the social and cultural process by which they were debated, instantiated, and institutionalized is taken into account. On Heintz’s view, even so abstract and “reasoned” a topic as the emergence of a new definition of a mathematical object is subject to social processes that account for its origin and 20 acceptance. Note that Heintz thus has shown the necessity of a social analysis, but he does not argue its sufficiency -- unlike Klein, for whom the social analysis is taken to be sufficient. In a sense, then, my argument proceeds in the reverse direction from that of Klein and of Heintz; a social and cultural analysis alone is necessary but it is not sufficient. In the case of Faraday, the way to keep the microstructure from overwhelming the account is to keep in mind the need to work in both directions – from the wider context to the artifact (as Heintz and Klein have done), and from the artifact to the wider context (as we have done in our studies of Faraday’s slides). Conclusions In a recent review, Klahr & Simon (1999) argued that experimentation can shed light on the general processes of hypothesis formation and change in science. Thus, Dunbar (1995) was able to establish a coordinated picture of the role of analogy in science by comparing his observations of molecular biology labs to observations made in his own laboratory on college student subjects given a simulated scientific inference problem. His observations of the in vivo laboratory interactions, together with his experimental results, suggest that the great majority of analogies used in scientific discussion among collaborators consist of “local” analogies that relate a given result, whether surprising or unexpected, to closely similar situations. In a similar pattern of generalization from the lab to the real world, the heuristics used by some of the scientist-subjects described in the “artificial universe” studies of Mynatt, Doherty, & Tweney (1978) were later observed by Tweney (1985) in Faraday’s diaries as well as by Dunbar (1995) in the molecular biology labs. In particular, a sophisticated “confirm early/disconfirm late” heuristic was observed in all of these situations, suggesting that early in the discovery or evaluation process tentative ideas need to be evaluated using primarily confirming evidence. Only when such ideas have achieved a basis of such evidence is it effective to seek to disconfirm them deliberately. Yet generalizing the results of lab studies is a challenging process in psychology, in part because the context of the psychology experiment itself is known to have substantial effects on human behavior -- it is not always clear that these can be “corrected for” in the generalization. Egon Brunswik (1956) was especially alert to this problem, arguing that there was a lack of 21 “representative design” in the usual psychological experiment. In general, the infatuation of psychology for specific kinds of statistical analysis has further hindered its ability to deal with such issues (see Gigerenzer 1993; Krüger, et al. 1987) Even so, the recent emphasis on the practices of science by cognitive historians of science (like Gooding 1990), and the rebirth of detailed individual analyses within psychology, e.g., the analysis of navigation by Hutchins (1995), of design practices by Norman (1993), and the “in vivo” observations of science by Dunbar (1999) suggests that a new attitude is emerging. Indeed, answering Brunswik’s objection is easier today than in his day – the emphasis on cognitive artifacts is, in essence, one part of the answer. Just as replication itself can bridge the gap between history of science and cognitive science, so also does the study of scientific artifacts and practices bridge the gap between laboratory studies of scientific thinking and the historical study of scientific practices and artifacts. Gorman (1992) has used a cognitive “mental models” framework to analyze the technoscientific creativity involved in Alexander Graham Bell’s invention of the telephone. Gorman showed how the laboratory study of scientific thinking can be used as the basis for a deep understanding of thinking in a domain closely related to that of scientific discovery. Like Cavicchi (1997), his work has used the replication of objects in the service of both understanding and as a tool in education. There are three kinds of artifacts recently described within the context of ethnographic approaches in cognitive science and the history of science. Cognitive Artifacts (as used by Hutchins 1995 and Norman 1993, for example; see also Zhang & Norman 1994) come closest to the kind of cultural artifacts typically focused upon by anthropologists. Rheinberger’s Epistemic Things (1997) expanded the scope of such artifacts, showing how cognitive artifacts become specialized within communities of scientific practitioners. For Rheinberger, cognitive artifacts become epistemic things in the course of social and cognitive processes: “Experimental representation ... may be taken to be equivalent to bringing epistemic things into existence. In their transiently stable forms, they may act as embodiments of concepts” (p. 107). As a result, epistemic things become, in a sense, “uninteresting” to the scientist, according to Rheinberger: “They remain interesting only as tools, as technical objects for constructing novel research arrangements.” On my analysis, a third category is necessary, that of Epistemic Artifacts (Tweney 2002). These constitute a beginning stage in which invented (but not yet conventionalized) artifacts serve an 22 agentive role in the investigative process. In this third case, “surprise” is a necessary element of a cognitive description, making replication of these artifacts essential for the understanding of how science can attain novel descriptions and understandings. Note that, in effect, we answer the Brunswikian objection about the “naturalness” of the laboratory study by making the laboratory study itself the object of our interest. The replication of scientific procedures can address many of the shortcomings of the experimental psychological approach to science, constituting, in fact, a step toward a new “experimental ethnography.” Consider three roles that replication has taken in historical studies of science: (1) The replication of instruments in the service of understanding key experiments in the history of science. For example, Heering (1994) replicated Coulomb’s torsion-balance experiment and showed that the published report of that experiment must have been either incomplete or fabricated. (2) The replication of a series of experiments, as a means of understanding the practices of scientific investigation. Our replications of Faraday’s experiments fit this description, as do Cavicchi’s (2003) replications of some of Faraday’s experiments on electricity and magnetism. (3) Finally, replication of observation and experiment is a way to understand the emergence of theory. Thus, Gooding (1990) used replication to detail the steps by which Faraday progressed from “vague construal” to a coherent portrayal of the seemingly chaotic movements of a magnetized needle near a current-carrying wire. And our replications of Faraday’s gold research shows a similar struggle (largely unsuccessful, in this case). Our work showed that Faraday’s research was not a “merely empirical” exploration of puzzling phenomena, nor was it a blind “stumbling around.” It was instead a theoretically driven exploration of the nature of light and matter, but one in which his cognitive “discourse” with nature depended upon his constructed specimens. Thought went on in close proximity to the specimens, to their appearance, their tactile properties, their relation to each other and to other kinds of artifacts. They are epistemic artifacts precisely because they are agentive entities that are integral to the thinking process. We cannot imagine Faraday reaching his conclusions without them, and, similarly, we would not have been able to imagine our final narrative account of Faraday’s research had we not carried out these replications. 23 The full understanding of scientific practices suggested by these considerations greatly expands previous attempts to understand science as a reflection of something that occurs “merely” in the head of the scientist. In their absence, even a laboratory diary is a text that can hide its origins in thought and action, a text that appears “finished” rather than alive with the dynamics of a cognitive system at work. In this sense, the image of science -- replete with bubbling flasks, sparking coils, and the active and passionate participation of the scientist -- is more right than we might have imagined. The image, like the reality, is alive and dynamic, both cognitive and cultural to its deepest roots. REFERENCES Allport, G.W. 1940 The psychologist’s frame of reference. Psychological Bulletin 37, 1-28. Andersen, H. 2002 The development of scientific taxonomies. In L. Magnani & N.J. Nersessian (Eds.), Model-Based Reasoning: Science, Technology, Values. New York: Kluwer Academic/ Plenum. Anderson, R. 1994 The Whewell-Faraday Exchange on the application of the concepts of momentum and inertia to electromagnetic phenomena. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 25, 577-594. (in press). Language and representation in Faraday’s “Experimental researches in electricity,” Perspectives in Science. Barsalou, L. 1992 Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields. In A. Lehrer & E. Kittay (Eds.), Frames, fields, and contrasts: New essays in semantical and lexical organization. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Brunswik, E. 1956 Perception and the representative design of psychological experiments. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. 24 Cantor, G. 1991 Michael Faraday: Sandemanian and scientist. A study of science and religion in the Nineteenth Century. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Cavicchi, E. 1997 Experimenting with magnetism: Ways of learning of Joann and Faraday. American Journal of Physics 65, 867-882. 2003 Experiences with the magnetism of conducting loops: Historical instruments, experimental replications, and productive confusions. American Journal of Physics 71, 156-167. Chen, Xiang 2003 Why did John Herschel fail to understand polarization? The differences between object and event concepts. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 34, 491-513. Danziger, K. 1990 Constructing the subject: Historical origins of psychological research. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1996 The practice of psychological discourse. In Carl F. Graumann & Kenneth J. Gergen (Eds.), Historical dimensions of psychological discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Darden, L. 1992 Strategies for anomaly resolution. In R. N. Giere (Ed.), Cognitive models of science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Daston, L. (Ed.) 2000 Biographies of scientific objects. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Dunbar, K. 1995 How scientists really reason: Scientific reasoning in real-world laboratories. In R. J. Sternberg & J. Davidson (Eds.), Mechanisms of insight. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1999 How scientists build models: In Vivo science as a window on the scientific mind. In L. Magnani, N.J. Nersessian, & P. Thagard (Eds.) Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery New York: Kluwer Academic. Faraday, M. 1827 Chemical manipulation: Being instructions to students in chemistry, on the methods of 25 performing experiments of demonstration or of research, with accuracy and success. London: W. Phillips. 1839-1855 Experimental Researches in Electricity (3 volumes), London: Taylor & Francis. 1856 Experimental researches in electricity, Series XXX: 38. Constancy of differential magnecrystallic force in different media, … Philosophical Transactions, 159-180 (read 1855, Nov. 15 and 22). 1857 Experimental relations of gold (and other metals) to light, Philosophical Transactions, 145181 (read Feb. 5, 1857). Reprinted in Michael Faraday (Ed.) (1859), Experimental Researches in Chemistry and Physics, pp. 391-442. London: Richard Taylor & William Francis. 1860 A course of six lectures on the various forces of matter and their relations to each other. Ed. by William Crookes. London: Richard Griffin. Fetterman, D. M. 1998 Ethnography, Step by step (Second Edition). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Fisher, H.J. 2001 Faraday’s Experimental researches in electricity: Guide to a first reading. Santa Fe, NM: Green Lion Press,. Gentner, D., Brem, S., Ferguson, R.W., Markman, A.B., Levidow, B.B., Wolff, P., & Forbus, K.D. 1997 Analogical reasoning and conceptual change: A case study of Johannes Kepler. Journal of the Learning Sciences 6, 3-40. Gibson, J.J. 1966 The senses considered as perceptual systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co. Gigerenzer, G. 1993 The Superego, the Ego, and the Id in statistical reasoning. In G. Keren & C. Lewis (Eds.), A handbook for data analysis in the behavioral sciences: Methodological issues. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Gooding, D.G. 1981 Final steps to the field theory: Faraday’s study of magnetic phenomena. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 11, 231-275. 1982 A convergence of opinion on the divergence of lines: Faraday and Thomson’s discussion of diamagnetism. Notes and Records of the Royal Society 36, 243-259. 26 1989 History in the laboratory: Can we tell what really went on? In F.A.J.L. James (Ed.), The development of the laboratory: Essays on the place of experiment in industrial civilization. New York: American Institute of Physics. 1990 Experiment and the making of meaning: Human agency in scientific observation and experiment. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Gooding, D.C. & Addis, T.R. 1999 A simulation of model-based reasoning about disparate phenomena. In P. Thagard, N. Nersessian, & L. Magnani (Eds.), Model based reasoning in scientific discovery. Dordrecht: Kluwer/Plenum. Goodwin, C. 1997 The blackness of black: Color categories as situated practice. In L.B. Resnick, R. Säljö, C. Pontecorvo, & B. Burge (Eds.), Discourse, tools, and reasoning: Essays on situated cognition. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Gorman, M. E. 1992 Simulating science: Heuristics, mental models, and technoscientific thinking. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Greeno, J. G. 1994 Gibson’s affordances. Psychological review, 101, 336-342. Greeno, J. G. & the Middle School Mathematics Through Applications Project Group 1998 The situativity of knowing, learning, and research. American Psychologist 53, 5-26. Heering, P. 1994 The replication of the torsion balance experiment: The inverse square law and its refutation by early 19th-century German physicists. In C. Blondel and M. Dörries (Eds.) Restaging Coulomb: Usages, Controverses et Réplications Autour de la Balance de Torsion, Firenze: Leo S. Olschki. Heintz, C. 2002 Can mathematical meaning allow cultural analysis? An illustration. In J. Goggin & R. Burkes (Eds.). Travelling concepts II: Frame, meaning, and metaphor. Amsterdam: ASCA Press. Holmes, F.L. 1980 Hans Krebs and the discovery of the ornithine cycle. Federation Proceedings 39, 216-225. 27 1987 Scientific writing and scientific discovery. Isis 78, 220-235. 2003 Laboratory notebooks and investigative pathways. In F.L. Holmes, J. Renn, J., & H-J. Rheinberger (Eds.) Reworking the bench: Research notebooks in the history of science. (Published as Archimedes, Vol. 7). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. 2004 Investigative pathways: Patterns and stages in the careers of experimental scientists. New Haven, CN: Yale University Press. Holmes, F.L., Renn, J., & Rheinberger, H-J. (Eds.) 2003 Reworking the bench: Research notebooks in the history of science. (Published as Archimedes, Vol. 7). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Hutchins, E. 1995 Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. James, F.A.J.L. 1985 “The optical mode of investigation”: Light and matter in Faraday’s natural philosophy. In D. Gooding & F.A.J.L. James (Eds.), Faraday rediscovered: Essays on the life and work of Michael Faraday, 1791-1867. Basingstoke, UK: Macmillan. Klahr, D. 2000 Exploring science: The cognition and development of discovery processes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Klahr, D. & Simon, H.A. 1999 Studies of scientific discovery: Complementary approaches and convergent findings. Psychological Bulletin 125, 524-543. Klein, U. 2003 Experiments, models, and paper tools: Cultures of organic chemistry in the Nineteenth century. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Knorr-Cetina, K. 1999 Epistemic cultures: How the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Krüger, L., Daston, L.J., & Heidelberger, M. (Eds.) 1987 The probabilistic revolution, Vol. 1: Ideas in history. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kulkarni, D., & Simon, H. A. 1990 Experimentation in machine discovery. In J. Shrager & P. Langley (Eds.) Computational 28 models of scientific discovery and theory formation. San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann. Kurz, E.M. 1998 Representation, agency, and disciplinarity: Calculus experts at work. In M.A. Gernsbacher & S.J. Derry (Eds.), Proceedings of the twentieth annual conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Kurz, E. M. & Hertwig, R. 2001 To know an experimenter. In Kenneth R. Hammond & Thomas R. Stewart (Eds.), The essential Brunswik: Beginnings, explications, applications. New York: Oxford University Press. Langley, P., Simon, H.A., Bradshaw, G. L., & Zytkow, J. M. 1987 Scientific discovery: Computational explorations of the discovery process. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Martin, T (Ed.) 1932-36 Faraday’s Diary … During the years 1820-1862, (7 volumes) London: G. Bell. Mills, A.A. 2003 Early Voltaic batteries: An evaluation in modern units and application to the work of Davy and Faraday. Annals of Science 60, 373-398. Mynatt, C. R., Doherty, M. E., & Tweney, R. D. 1978 Consequences of confirmation and disconfirmation in a simulated research environment. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 30, 395-406. Nersessian, N. 1995 Opening the black box: Cognitive science and history of science. Osiris 10, 194-214. 1999 Model based reasoning in conceptual change. In L. Magnani, N.J. Nersessian, & P. Thagard (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery. New York: Kluwer/Plenum. Newell, A. & Simon, H. A. 1972 Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Norman, D.A. 1993 Things that make us smart: Defending human attributes in the age of the machine. Reading, MA: Addison Wesley Publishing Co. Nye, M.J. 29 2001 Paper tools and molecular architecture in the chemistry of Linus Pauling. In U. Klein (Ed.), Tools and modes of representation in the laboratory sciences. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Oldenburg University, Institut für Physik 2004 Zur Replikationsmethode. Web site: http://www.uni-oldenburg.de/histodid/ forschung/ replikationsmethode.htm (accessed February 5, 2004). Principe, L.M. 1998 The aspiring adept: Robert Boyle and his alchemical quest. Including Boyle’s “lost” Dialogue on the transmutation of elements. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Ramberg, Peter J. 2003 Chemical structure, Spatial arrangement: The early history of stereochemistry, 1874-1914. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate Publishing Limited. Rheinberger, H.J. 1997 Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Rosenthal, R. & Rosnow, R.L. 1991 Essentials of behavioral research: Methods and data analysis. New York: McGraw-Hill. Sibum, H.O. 2001 The golden number of the century: The history of a scientific fact. In L. Daston, S. MüllerWille, & H.O. Sibum (Eds.), A history of facts. Berlin: Max-Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte, “Preprint 174.” Simon, H. A. 1996 The sciences of the artificial. (3rd ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press. (First published 1967) Steinle, F. 1996 Work, Finish, Publish? The formation of the second series of Faraday’s "Experimental researches in electricity," Physis 33, 141-220. 2003 The practice of studying practice: Analyzing research records of Ampère and Faraday. In F.L. Holmes, J. Renn, J., & H-J. Rheinberger (Eds.) (2003), Reworking the bench: Research notebooks in the history of science. (Published as Archimedes, Vol. 7). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Trafton, J.G., Trickett, S.B., & Mintz, F.E. 30 (in press) Overlaying images: Spatial transformations of complex visualizations. Foundations of Science. Trickett, S.B., Fu, W.-T., Schunn, C.D., & Trafton, J.G. 2000 From dipsy-doodles to streaming motions: Changes in the representation of visual scientific data. Proceedings of the 22nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Tweney, R. D. 1985 Faraday's discovery of induction: A Cognitive Approach. In D. Gooding & F. A. J. L. James (Eds.), Faraday rediscovered: Essays on the life and work of Michael Faraday, 1791-1867. New York: Stockton Press/London: Macmillan. 1992 Inventing the field: Michael Faraday and the creative “engineering” of electromagnetic field theory. In R. J. Weber & D. N. Perkins (Eds.), Inventive minds: Creativity in technology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2002 Epistemic artifacts: Michael Faraday’s search for the optical effects of gold. In L. Magnani & N.J. Nersessian (Eds.), Model-Based Reasoning: Science, Technology, Values. New York: Kluwer Academic/ Plenum. 2003 Whatever happened to the brass and glass? The rise of statistical “instruments” in psychology, 1900-1950. In D. Baker (ed.). Archival research in the history of psychology: Thick description and fine texture, pp. 123-142 & 200-205 (notes), Akron, OH: University of Akron Press. (in preparation) Replicating scientific discovery: Faraday, phosphorous, and gold. Tweney, R. D., Doherty, M. E., & Mynatt, C. R. (Eds.). 1981 On scientific thinking. New York: Columbia University Press. Tweney, R.D., Friedrich, J., & Berg, N. (in preparation) Faraday’s microscope slides: An illustrated catalog of the Royal Institution Collection. Tweney, R. D. & Hoffner, C. E. 1987 Understanding the microstructure of science: An example. In Program of the Ninth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Tweney, R.D., Mears, R.P., & Spitzmüller, C. (in press) The practice of discovery: Michael Faraday and the interaction of gold and light. In 31 M. Gorman, R.D. Tweney, D.G. Gooding, & A. Kincannon (Eds.) New directions for the cognitive study of science and technology. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Tweney, R.D., Mears, R.P., Gibby, R.E., Spitzmüller, C. & Sun, Y. 2002 Precipitate replications: The cognitive analysis of Michael Faraday's exploration of gold precipitates and colloids. In W.D. Gray & C.D. Schunn (Eds.), Proceedings of the twenty fourth annual conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Williams, L.P. 1965 Michael Faraday: A biography. New York: Basic Books. Zhang, J. & Norman, D.A. 1994 Representations in distributed cognitive tasks. Cognitive Science 18, 87-122.