Reflection & Education 1: Theory Linguistically, the word ‘reflection’ may be seen as a meditative form of looking at oneself, and as such may be seen as a form of experiential learning. Certainly, it is something that we do implicitly as part of being human, underpinning our identities through a process of negotiation between our sense of self and our experiences of others (Demetriou, 2000, p.210). However, efforts to shift from the implicit to the explicit, pragmatic and measurable have been driven by subjective understandings of the term and its functions, and subsequently reflection as an educational process has remained a poorly defined concept. This is not to say that it lacks a history of educational application. Within established educational models, such as Kolb (1984), reflection has been defined as central to the ways in which knowledge and learning can be driven through a cyclical process of identification, review, questioning and reconstruction. Here, ”Knowledge is continuously derived from and tested out in the experiences of the learner.” (Kolb, 1984, p.27), and this can only take place where those experiences can be reviewed and analysed retrospectively. Essentially, however, how one views reflection may be guided by the specific purpose through which it is approached, as can be seen within the work of the key reflective theorists. Dewey – Reflection as rationality John Dewey, saw reflection as a further dimension of thought, and as such in need of education; “while we cannot learn or be taught to think, we do have to learn to think well, especially acquire the general habit of reflection” (Dewey, 1933). For Dewey, reflection is a rational and purposeful act, an “active, persistent and careful consideration of any belief or supposed form of knowledge in the light of the grounds that support it, and further conclusions to which it leads… it includes a conscious and voluntary effort to establish belief upon a firm basis of evidence and rationality” (Dewey, 1933). Interestingly, from a modern educational perspective, Dewey’s reference to different forms of belief and knowledge may reveal his willingness to apply objective rationality to more affective and emotional concerns. Further Reading: Key texts and references Boud, D., Keogh, R., & Walker, D. (1985), Reflection, Turning Experience into Learning, London , Kogan Page Boud, D., & Walker, D. (1998), Promoting Reflection in Professional Courses: the challenge of Context, Studies in Higher Education, Vol. 23, No. 2 Brookfield, S. D. (1987), Developing Critical Thinkers: challenging adults to explore alternative ways of thinking and acting, San Fransisco, Jossey-Bass Brookfield, S. D. (1995), Becoming a Critically Reflective Teacher, San Fransisco, Jossey-Bass Demetriou, A. (2000), “Organization and development of selfunderstanding & self-regulation: towards a general theory”, in Boekaerts, M., Pintrich, P. R., & Zeidner, M. (Eds), Handbook of Self-Regulation, London, Academic Press Dewey, J. (1933), How We Think, Boston, D. C. Heath & Co. Dewey, J. (2007), Democracy and Education, Teddington, Echo Library Kolb, D. A. (1984), Experiential Learning, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice Hall Further Reading: Key texts and references Mezirow, J. (1990), Fostering Critical Education in Adulthood: a guide to transformatory and emancipatory learning, San Fransisco, Jossey-Bass Moon, J. (1999) Reflection in Learning and Professional Development, London, Kogan Page Moon, J. (2001), PDP Working Paper 4: Reflection in Higher Education Learning, LTSN Generic Centre, http://www.heacademy.ac.uk /resources/detail /id72_Reflection_in_ Higher_Education_Learning Schön, D. A. (1983), The Reflective Practitioner, London, Temple Smith Schön, D. A. (1987), Educating the Reflective Practitioner, San Fransisco, Jossey Bass Tomlinson, P. (1999), Critical Reflection and Implicit Learning in Teacher Preparation, Part 1: recent light on an old issue, Oxford Review of Education, Vol. 25, No, 3 Schön – Reflection and the professional Schön, however, concentrated on the use of rational reflection within the understanding and development of professional practice. Schön argued that the application of theory within practice is driven by reflection, the use of such a process ultimately leading to a state of expertise. His goal was therefore to make the tacit knowledge which epitomises expertise explicit so that it could be considered and improved, and that reflection-on-action, the retrospective analysis of experience, would drive that process. Interestingly, Schön also proposed a form of reflection-in-action, in which reflection is seen as part of active thought. Boud & Walker – Reflection as holistic act Interestingly, while Dewey only mentions emotions implicitly and Schön avoids them through his focus on professional expertise, Boud & Walker (1998) specifically question the appropriateness of a reflective process in which personal emotional subjectivity is avoided, highlighting the need to explore a wider range of experiential dimensions. Boud and Walker seek to avoid the dehumanization of the reflective process by offering “the challenge of incorporating ideas about reflection, which in some cases are only partially understood, into teaching contexts which are not conducive to the questioning of experience – that is, situations which do not allow learners to explore ‘a state of perplexity, hesitation, doubt (Dewey 1933), ‘inner discomforts’ (Brookfield, 1987), ‘distorting dilemmas’ (Mezirow, 1990), uncertainties, discrepancies and dissatisfactions which precipitate, and are central to, any notion of reflection” (Boud & Walker, 1998, p. 192). Moving forward Ultimately, reflection as a retrospective dimension of thought remains common within the work of all three writers, however, Moon (1998) suggests that the differences between them lies within their point of focus; holistic or specific, professional or personal, and that our adoption of any reflective model may be shaped by our underlying reason for using it – our processes, our goals and even our methods of assessment (Moon, 2001, p. 4). Certainly, when considering the practical models of reflection, these aspects may well prove to be of fundamental importance.