Evolution (organic). The notion of Darwinian evolution of forms and entities, according to which all organic species descend from a common ancestor through various processes among which natural selection is the most crucial, forms the framework of current biological investigations. Although biology underwent deep transformations and conceptual shifts since 1859, the initial formulation of this modern idea of evolution is due to Darwin’s Origin of species. This promoted a new interpretation of major biological concepts such as adaptation or function, and raised new problems for researchers. The notion of biological evolution entails important consequences regarding the idea of time, especially concerning the time of biological processes and forms, as well as the use of temporal processes in biological explanations. The first section will sketch the historical context of the rise of evolutionism. The second section will explain the major concepts of biological evolution, according to the contemporary version of Darwinism. The third section will then focus on some major controversies that recurrently appeared in the history of evolutionary biology, concerning the process and the pattern of evolution. History of the idea of organic evolution. The idea of an evolution of species traces back far prior to Darwin. However, he is the father of modern evolutionism because he argued not only for a pattern of descent between species – the Tree of life – but for a process likely to explain this pattern – natural selection. Among prior tenets of what was called “transformism”, some 18th century writers like Robinet, Benoit de Maillet, or later most famously Jean Baptiste Antoine de Lamarck, held versions of evolutionism that explained evolution, yet through rather implausible mechanisms. Several problems met by naturalists were reasonably stimulating biologists to conceive of a general evolution of species. First of all, whereas big differences between species are obvious, it is not so clear sometimes whether two individuals are of distinct species, or of distinct varieties of one species. Therefore lots of classes held to be distinct species, hence distinctively created by God, might turn out to be varieties of one single species. A mechanism would then account for the derivation between them. Linnaeus, author of the most general system of classifying species, and tenant of species as distinctively created by God (“fixism”), yet faced in this way the problem of hybrids. His contemporary and rival Buffon defined a concept of species in terms of the ability to interbreed and have fertile offspring, a concept that fared better than a purely morphological concept of species like Linnaeus’s, but that was not generally applicable. Moreover, as Kant famously explained in the Critique of Judgment, naturalists until the 19th century noticed more and more frequently that the types of various species are often quite similar to one another, as if for example all the vertebrates were variations on a same theme - what Goethe called “original type”. Famously, Geoffroy Saint Hilaire in 1820 claimed that whereas the two major orders, vertebrates and arthropods (like crustaceans) seem absolutely separate (as held his rival Cuvier), they were variants of a same type, the arthropod living inside its spine and the vertebrate outside of it. Therefore, several thinkers, particularly from the school of Naturphilosophie in 19th century Germany, conceived of a general evolution of species from the simplest to the most complex forms – though often a logical evolution of forms rather than a historical process - as an explanation of this pattern of similarity. Religion has obviously been an obstacle to accepting evolution. The Church said that the earth was only 6000 years old, which makes quite unconceivable a process of transformation of species, since at the scale of human civilization no one witnessed any such change. But this difficulty, which was still precluding Buffon to accept explicitly evolution of species (even if he would accept transformation of varieties) slowly vanished during the 19th Century, because, among other reasons, of the discoveries of fossils of unknown animals and of the advancement of geological theories of Earth. George Lyell, who was Darwin’s friend, wrote the important Principles of geology (1830–33), which claimed that Earth could have been shaped several millions years ago. For those reasons, a general audience became more familiar to the ideas of evolution. Just before Darwin, Robert Chambers wrote Vestiges of the Creation, a widely read book which sketched a picture of the evolution of organic forms, without a scientific theory supporting it. At the time, philosophers such as Herbert Spencer elaborated general theories of evolution, which in general relied on a formal scheme of complexification. Before him, Lamarckism, the most accomplished transformist theory before Darwin, appealed to two forces, the first one being precisely complexification (which explains why in the same genus simple forms are likely to give rise to more complex) and the second being “adaptation to circumstances” through inheritance of acquired characters (this one is in general the only one people think of when they refer to Lamarckism). Evolution by natural selection is one nice example of simultaneous discovery in the history of science: while Darwin, after a long journey on the Beagle, came to this idea through reflections on the geographical distribution of species, on morphology, and on domestication, in the same time naturalist Arthur Wallace had the same idea. This anecdote indicates that in the 1850s time was ripe for evolutionary theories. They presented their results in 1844 in a joined meeting that anticipated the publication of the big book Darwin wanted to write patiently during several years, and published in 1859, before revising it extensively along the five next successive editions. The book is “one very long argument”, and whereas most chapters use arguments from various field such as embryology, morphology, biogeography or paleontology, to support the idea of evolution by natural selection, several other chapters are devoted to a rebuttal of objections that Darwin foresaw: the lack of intermediary forms in the fossil record, the very complex organs like eyes, the evolution of instincts, etc. In general however, lots of biologists were convinced by Darwin’s demonstration of an evolution of species. The general audience was more reluctant for religious reasons. However the fate of Darwinism is more concerned with the reactions to the process hypothesized by Darwin to account for evolution, i.e. natural selection. Darwin was indeed pluralist regarding the processes generating evolution; he accepted for example Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characters. The major question then was the relative impact of those several processes onto evolution, and this is perhaps the main general issue that following biologists have to deal with. What we call “Darwinism” might be born when German biologist August Weissmann, working on heredity, conceived of a separation between the “somatic cells” and the “germinal cells”, id est the characters proper to an individual (and likely to change) and the characters that she inherited from her parents and passes to her offspring. This prevents any inheritance of acquired characters and leaves natural selection as the most plausible general mechanism of evolution. The history of Darwinism in the 20th Century means first the Modern Synthesis, initiating “neo-Darwinism” in the 30s. Briefly said, natural selection, according to Darwin, sorts individuals that vary and have various offspring. The process of selection will occur no matter how the variation is caused, so Darwin’s theory was neutral regarding an explanation of hereditary variation (i.e. why all offspring of a couple of zebras are on the one hand alike - as zebras – and different – as differing to some extent from their parents). But in the 1900s, Mendelian genetics came into play. At first sight, genetics and Darwinism seem at odds, since Darwin was talking of evolution through selection of small differences, whereas genetics treats combinations of discrete characters, which seems non-gradual. Hence, a controversy opposed Darwinians and Mendelians until the 20s. Then, Ronald Fisher, Sewall Wright and J.B.S. Haldane showed by devising probabilistic models of the evolution of genetic frequencies in populations (a field called population genetics) that, far from opposing Darwinism, the Mendelian heredity is an explanation of heritable variation that makes natural selection necessary and powerful. Mutation of genes and recombination during meiosis and fecundation (in the case of sexual reproduction) provide the variation upon which selection operates. This synthesis between Mendelism and Darwinism is the origin of today biology. Later, such synthesis extended to systematics (with Ernst Mayr), paleontology (with George Simpson), etc. However, the preeminence of population genetics in the modern account of the processes of evolution entailed that evolution is now conceived of as the “change of genes frequencies in a population”, whereas the first Darwinians were thinking, more loosely, in terms of change of organic forms. Darwinian evolution The concept of natural selection Darwin thought of natural selection as the result of “struggle for life”: since the resources are in general rare in an environment, and since the rate of increase of a population exceeds in general the availability of resources (an idea that he famously took from Malthus’s Essay on the Principle of Population, 1798) it follows that only the ones who are better equipped to get resources will survive and reproduce, being then likely to pass those abilities to their offspring. The frequency of those traits supporting those abilities increase, and this continued process, on the long run, explains a general change of the type of the species, which finally leads to a novel species (some individuals being so different than the initial ones, or so distant, that they could not interbreed with them any more). More concretely, this competition (mostly between members of a same species) consists in getting food, sexual partners, and escaping predators. A more abstract formulation of natural selection, less tied to this biological case, can be given. Following Richard Lewontin, any population of individuals satisfying three conditions will undergo natural selection : those individuals vary regarding some traits (variation); they have offspring that do vary from them and between one another, in a way that the variation between offspring and the mean of the population positively correlate with the variation between their parents and the mean of the population (heritability); and those properties according to which they vary are relevant in their expectation of having some number of offspring. (If several organisms replicate and vary, but that the properties transmitted have no consequences upon their probability of reproduction, there will be no selection at all.) With this third property we can define “fitness”. Whereas still intuitive for Darwin when he talked about “survival of the fittest” (following Spencer, and wanting to reject any intentional connotation of the word “selection”), “fitness” is now a technical term which means both survival and expectancy of offspring. Defining the fitness of a trait implies assuming that this trait somehow correlates with the offspring expectancy. [Fig. 1. Diagram of a selection process in neo-darwinism, about there.] What the selected individuals really are, their nature, is not relevant in this formulation. Hence there logically can be selection on organisms, which was what Darwin thought of, but also on groups, on species, and, at a lower level, on genes. One of the most debated question in the philosophy of biology, indeed, is the “units of selection” controversy, namely the question of what, among those kinds of things, are the ones onto which selection takes place. George Williams in Adaptation and natural selection (1966) convincingly argued that selection apparently acting on groups - for example altruist behaviors that seem to increase the well being of the group while threatening the organisms that achieves them - can in fact be explained in terms of selection acting on individuals (organisms or genes). After William Hamilton, biologists call “kin selection” a selection acting on one gene carried by several individuals: selection will retain an organism that acts against its “interests” if the consequences can favor one of its kin. On this basis, Richard Dawkins argued that natural selection indeed acts upon genes rather than organisms. Genes do “replicate” - they are “replicators” in Dawkins’ language - but the rate at which they successfully replicate depends upon the interactions between organisms that they contribute to shape. Thereby, philosopher David Hull suggested another formulation of selection: natural selection is the process according to which “replicators” differentially reproduce due to the interactions of entities named “interactors” (in the usual case of biology, it is the organisms). This formulation allows one to realize that natural selection could occur about various objects to the extent that they “replicate”, for example Dawkins talks of cultural selection, because cultural entities seem to replicate. Explaining through natural selection The diversity of species (in time and in space, for example: why are there kangaroos in Australia but not in South America?) and the adaptation of organisms to their environments, are explained through Darwinian evolution. First, the taxonomy of species receives a historical interpretation. The only diagram in The Origin (Fig.2) represents a pattern of branching between species, or genera, or any biological taxon. All the taxonomic relations (being part of a same genus, etc.) were reinterpreted by Darwin in terms of history: the closer two species are in a morphological taxonomy, the closer they are in the temporal sequence of evolution. [Fig.2. Darwin’s diagram of evolution, about there.] Concerning adaptation, the old explanation referred to the divine will or a providence that would account for the amazing fit between organisms and their environment – for example, the beak of species of finches that fits to the depth of the holes within which they chase insects. The Darwinian explanation of adaptation is natural selection: such process obviously led to the fit of the beaks with the holes – and in the same time to the divergence of the Galapagos finches into several species, all being specialized in one kind of holes, and characterized by one length of beak. This Darwinian example illustrates how natural selection accounts in the same time for a process of diversification of species and for adaptation. Philosophically speaking, natural selection provides also a way to escape the suspicion of teleology that constantly assaulted biology. Modern natural sciences exclude explanations in terms of intentions or goals, because by principle nature has no desires. However, talking of functions of organic parts means that those parts are here in order to do such and such: such proposition seems teleological. Although not really embarrassing for biologists, this problem puzzled philosophers of science – especially, since the times when funding science on theology was not admitted any more. Typically, Kant devoted half of the Critique of Judgment to the problem of legitimizing teleological judgments in life sciences without appealing to a Creator. Yet in the Darwinian framework, functional statements do not object to naturalism: philosophers Larry Wright and Ruth Millikan suggested to interpret “the function of X is Z” by “X has been selected because it was doing Z”, which does not appeal to any transcendent intention. Natural selection might legitimate the functional talk traditional in biology. Evolutionism within biology Proximate and ultimate causes. The emergence of evolutionism entailed a whole transformation of biology. During the rise of molecular biology, after Watson and Crick’s discovery of the DNA as the substance of genes (1953), Ernst Mayr reflected upon the Synthesis to which himself contributed. He argued that causal explanations in biology can take two forms: proximate and ultimate. Proximate causes are the processes and events that cause a feature in the life of organisms, e.g. the “genetic program” of some bird accounts for its migrating behavior and the physiology of its muscles accounts for the way it flies. Molecular biology, physiology, biochemistry, embryology, all unveil proximate causes and constitute “functional biology”. The other part is “evolutionary biology”, and aims at accounting for why the organism is likely to be the way it is, e.g. it searches for the evolutionary history which led to the genetic program embodied by the migrating bird. Those “ultimate causes” of course extend far prior the existence of the organisms or species considered. Paleontology, behavioral ecology, ecology, systematics, population genetics, constitute the main disciplines of this “evolutionary biology”. Mayr added that whereas “proximate causes” amounts to explanations of the same kind than those usually found in physics and chemistry, “ultimate causes” require another kind of explanation, since they mostly rely on natural selection and have to integrate knowledge of history as a background condition. This makes of course evolutionary biology the core of biology, upon which relies the specificity of biology regarding other natural sciences. This implies that biology has an irreducible historical dimension, contrasting with lots of natural sciences which search for unhistorical laws or correlations, striving only for what philosophers after Ernst Nagel call “nomothetic explanations”. Moreover, most of the conditions of evolution are themselves product of evolution (for example, the process of fair meiosis assumed by all the Mendelian rules.) The science of organic evolution therefore required that scientific explanation consist also in depicting contingent temporal processes. Form and function. In 1916, historian E.S. Russell published Form and function, an important book revisiting the history of biology as a fight between two general approaches of living phenomena: focusing on functions, or being interested in forms. Those features, forms and functions, are obviously proper to living beings (brute matter does not display transmitted forms). Russell saw the famous debate that opposed Cuvier and Geoffroy Saint Hilaire at the Museum (Paris) in 1830 as one major episode in this longstanding debate. Geoffroy, arguing in favor of one general type of organisms realized in all orders, was a tenet of form-biology, while Cuvier was mostly interested in functions, and called “principle of the conditions of existence” the principle according to which all functions in an organism have to be feasible and compatible. For this reason, because one could not change one function without altering the whole and then making the organism unable to fulfill the principle of conditions of existence, Cuvier opposed Lamarck’s gradual transformism. On the other hand, for Geoffroy the general types are only fine-tuned by local adaptations, but their main morphological rules are something universal in the living realm, hence not connected to specificities of the various environments within which various species came to life: for this reason, adaptation can not account for those rules. The spine, for example, pervasive across all order of organisms, exemplifies such a formal feature. In The Origin, Darwin considers this debate from the viewpoint of evolution by natural selection. He admits that there are two most general principles of biology: the one of “conditions of existence” (i.e. Cuvier’s) and the one of unity of types (i.e. Geoffroy Saint Hilaire). He inquires into their connection, namely whether functions of organisms, shaped by natural selection, are the main factor accounting for the various features of the species, or whether some general formal features, independent of the successive environments of organisms but historically transmitted, are the major constraints on the history of life. He answers that the principle of the conditions of existence resumes to natural selection, whereas unity of type specifies the stable persistence of organic forms. However, because those inherited forms are themselves constituted through evolution by natural selection, those types in the end rely on the action of natural selection and the “unity of type” gets subsumed under the other principle. This means that Darwinian biology subordinates form biology to function biology. Major longstanding issues in evolutionary biology. Issues relevant to the process of evolution Even if selection is acknowledged as one of the main cause of evolution - Lamarckian evolution being excluded - other mechanisms have been conceived of by biologists. One classical formulation of the question of evolution in population genetics is analogous to mechanics, as argued by philosopher Elliott Sober in The nature of selection (1984). Considering some varying traits in a population, geneticists first write the equations that would rule the change of gene frequencies in a pure Mendelian case with no selection, no mutation and no migration - called the “Hardy-Weinberg equilibrium”. Then they compare to the actual case. Any deviation from the expected equilibrium frequencies should have a cause, possibly natural selection. Yet, Sewall Wright in the 30s showed that in small populations a kind of sampling error occur which can lead to the fixation of some genes independently of their selective value. This “random drift” would disappear in infinite populations, but since real populations are always bounded, random drift surely matters in the actual evolution of gene frequencies. Thus, apportioning the causes of evolution, especially selection and drift, is a constant problem faced by population geneticists. Several important controversies in the course of evolutionary biology revolved around such issue. At the origin of the Synthesis, Fisher argued against Wright about the role of drift. If drift is important, as claimed Wright, mean fitness of populations is not always maximized, whereas Fisher opposed a mathematical formula he proved, the “fundamental theorem of natural selection”, meaning that mean fitness necessarily increases until the exhaustion of genetic variance. Deciding this point implies an empirical knowledge of the size of natural populations. Later, the question involved an investigation of the reasons of genetic variability – “polymorphisms” - in populations. Biologists like Dobzhanski and Müller, among others, forged theories to account for this maintenance. Afterwards, Motoo Kimura vindicated the so called “neutralist theory of evolution”, claiming that most of the evolution at the level of nucleotides (the molecules composing the DNA) is neutral, due to drift, because most of the mutations of nucleotides are selectively neither advantageous nor deleterious. Although theoretically important, this theory does not truly oppose Darwinism since it is only concerned by the molecular level, and leaves intact the idea that the evolution of genes themselves and of phenotypes is due to selection. However, the neutralist theory emphasized that evolution is a constant process occurring at many levels according to various mechanisms. It is often difficult to consider evolution of one population of one species, because ecologically the fates of several species are tied - each one defining selective pressure for the others. Cases of parasitism, of mutualism, etc., belong to a general study of “coevolution”, for example between figs and wasps, ants and plants, or of course men and intestinal bacteria, that accounts for innumerable features of the organic world. Other important controversies arise when we turn our gaze from “microevolution”, which concerns rather short time scales and not-too-changing environments, to “macroevolution”, or evolution at a higher level, concerning for example the appearance of new classes of organisms. It has been debated since the founding fathers of the modern synthesis whether macroevolution is microevolution at a larger scale or whether it requires novel principles. Simpson and Mayr for example defended the former position, because they thought that an appeal to novel principles, for example “macromutations”, would threaten Darwinism itself. Some biologists nevertheless, like Stephen Jay Gould, Nils Eldredge, Elisabeth Vrba or Sean Rice will consider natural selection of species. In those cases, the properties selected (for example the geographic range of a species, the genetic variability, etc.) are properties of the species itself, unlike the mechanisms accounting for microevolution, that have all to do with traits of individuals. But the main challenges concerning this question of macroevolution came recently from evolutionary theory of development or Evo-Devo. In microevolution, actually, natural selection shaping adaptations for some functions is plausibly the main cause of evolution. This exemplifies the Darwinian bias in favor of function biology. However, in The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary biology (2005) Ron Amundson argues that the tenants of form biology constantly opposed this Darwinian demonstration of the supremacy of function-biology. Their challenge gets now much more consistent because they invoked some novel style of laws of forms that scientific investigation has been pinpointing for three decades. Briefly said, neodarwinians thought that mutation (and recombination) forms the material for natural selection. They separated two ideas traditionally joined: inheritance (namely transmission of characters from parents to offspring) and development (namely the ontogenetic process of an individual). Selection acts on traits, no matter the process through which the individual came to display those traits, so development seemed relatively external to evolution. Yet, some developmental theorists emphasized that development can both constrain variations, and provide variations only by changing the rhythm or order of the process, as Stephen Jay Gould summarized this in his classical Ontogeny and phylogeny (1977). Evo-Devo researchers contend that the changes relevant to macroevolution, for example “key innovations” like the wing of insects, the thermoregulation system of mammals, etc., involve the effect of developmental constraints, and are not understandable solely as effects of natural selection acting on punctual mutations in the DNA. (But for them evolutionary theory is therefore more concerned by explaining across-taxa features, like the vertebrate limb, rather than change within taxa and thus adaptations.) This debate is obviously related to the set of problems posed by the understanding of the phylogenetic pattern in general. Issues relevant to the pattern of evolution. The Tree of life raises three types of questions, both crucial to current evolutionary biology: the shape of evolution, its orientation, and finally its origins. Gradualism and discontinuities. For Darwin, evolution of the species was a gradual branching process. Neo-Darwinism emphasized the gradualism, since variation would rely on small mutations. For this reason, Neo-Darwinism has constantly been puzzled with discontinuous evolution, for example “key innovations”. In the 70s, paleontologists like Stephen Jay Gould and Nils Eldredge challenged the general gradual view of phylogeny, arguing that changes in evolution display a discontinuous pattern : a fast (at the geological timescale) burst of novelty, and a very long period of “stasis”, where one notices only minor modifications possibly due to adaptation to local conditions. This theory of “punctuated equilibria”, albeit neutral regarding the mechanisms of evolution, does nicely fit with theories from Evo-Devo (held by Gould), which contrast very big changes relying on transformations in developmental processes with minor changes due to selection on point mutations. This issue mostly rests on the interpretation of the fossil record: Darwin claimed that its lack of transitional forms was due to geological reasons, whereas tenets of “punctuated equilibria” claim that the record is, as such, quite reliable, and constitutes an evidence for the stasis-burst schema of macroevolution. In this case, macroevolution would not be easily reducible to mechanisms of micro-evolution, and Neo-Darwinism in general - since its core is population genetics – would have to be qualified. The emergence of the most general plans of organization - for example the one taking place in the Cambrian and explaining most of the extant phyla – is not accountable solely by micro-evolutionary principles. In 1995, John Maynard Smith and Eors Szathmary initiated a theory of the ”major evolutionary transitions”. Those are the fundamental events in evolution, through which the forms of inheritance and replication changed. Replicating macromolecules, single cells, multicellular organisms, social organisms and organisms with language are the steps of this evolution. Each time, natural selection both contributes to the transition and becomes changed through it, because new selectable entities arise. In this perspective, evolution by natural selection is not absolutely tied to genes or life, and extends from molecule to talking beings. Such a globalised theory casts a new light on the problems of discontinuity in the mere history of life. “Cooperation” between entities, e.g. genes in chromosomes or insects in colonies, is a pervasive pattern of explanation of those transitions, and requires understanding how natural selection could favor cooperative behaviors while selfish defection would be at first sight selected for. Direction. A common view of evolution sees it as oriented towards greater perfection and achievement. Yet this is precluded by the very logics of Darwinism, for which natural selection optimizes populations regarding their environments – hence, two organisms of two different species, belonging to different environments, cannot be compared or considered as stages of a continuous improvement. In the same time, it is difficult not to notice in a given branch of the Tree of life, for example the vertebrates or the mollusks, trends of increasing complexity : diversification of functions, finessing of detecting devices, increase of some quantities related to the size of genes, etc. Darwin himself was ambiguous regarding this issue: while opposing the notion of absolute perfection, he was led by common intuitions about progress in evolution. The major conceptual issue however is still to figure out a concept of complexity likely to capture those contrasted intuitions. Biologist Dan Mac Shea has shown in recent papers that a “complexity” thought in pure formal terms (diversity of parts with no functional considerations) makes visible some phylogenic trends in increasing complexity. This notion is yet far from the intuitive one and it seems then that no theory could decipher in the history of life this constant progress culminating in human species that we ordinary believe in. Origin. Evolution by natural selection commits one to say like Darwin that all forms of life came from one single organism (which of course irritated all religions). The fact that all species share a same genetic code is nowadays another evidence of this single evolutionary history. From a Darwinian viewpoint, the question raised here is the genesis of an entity satisfying the conditions of natural selection. This problem involves both chemists and paleontologists – people seeking traces of what happened and people conceiving processes that could have happened. Besides, within evolutionism questions of origins are crucial: origin of sexual reproduction (why consenting to pass on only 50% of your genes to the next generation, while asexual reproduction does 100%?), origin of mind and culture. Whereas no theory is still satisfying, clearly natural selection plays a fundamental role in those events. See: DNA; Extinction; Darwin, Charles; Origin of life; Evolution, cultural; progress; fossil record; Tree of life, Gradualism versus saltationism; Paleontology Philippe Huneman. Institut d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques (CNRS/ Université Paris I Sorbonne), Paris. Further readings. Arthur, W.. The origin of bodyplans. Brandon, R. (1996) Adaptation and environment. Cambridge: MIT Press. Dawkins, R. (1982). The extended phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Eldredge, N. The unfinished synthesis. Gayon, J. (1998) Darwinism’s struggle for survival. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gould, S. J. (1980) The panda’s thumb. London: Penguin. Hodges,J.& Radick G. (eds.) (2003). The Cambridge Companion to Darwin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kimura, M.. The neutralist theory of evolution Lewontin, R. Evolutionary genetics. Maynard Smith, J. & Szathmary, E. (1995). The major transitions in evolution. Mayr, E. (1961) “Cause and effect in biology.” Science, 134: 1501-1506 Mayr E. & Provine W. (1980) The evolutionary synthesis. Perspectives on the unification of biology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Michod, R. & Bernstein H.(eds.) Evolution of sex. Michod, R. (1999) Darwinian dynamics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Richards, R. (1992) The meaning of evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Odlin-Smee J., Laland K. & Feldman M. (2003). Niche-construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Sloan, P. (2005) “Evolution” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on-line. Sober, E. (1984) The nature of selection. Cambridge: MIT Press. Williams, G.C. (1992) Natural selection: domains, levels and challenges. Oxford: Oxford University Press