Tinbergen's Four Questions 591 words of text and 1 table should fill 1 page in Nature as a “Concepts” contribution Randolph M. Nesse The University of Michigan 426 Thompson St, Room 5261 Ann Arbor, MI 48104 (734) 764-6593 Fax (734) 647-3652 nesse@umich.edu Contact information until May 7, 2003 Randolph M. Nesse, M.D. Dept. Anthropology University College London Malet Court London WC1E 6BT UK Phone: 44 (0)20 7679 3381 Fax: 44 (0)20 7679 7728 1 In 1963, to honor Konrad Lorenz’s 60th birthday, Nico Tinbergen wrote an article titled “On the aims and methods of ethology.” On the 40th anniversary of its publication, the conceptual foundation it provides is more influential than ever, not only for animal behavior but for biology in general. The paper is organized according to Tinbergen’s now-famous Four Questions. He called them “causation, survival value, ontogeny and evolution.” Now they are more commonly referred to as mechanism, selective advantage, ontogeny and phylogeny. As Dewsbury has noted, such categories are never completely new. In 1961, Mayr clarified the distinction between proximate causes of structures and functional mechanisms in individuals as contrasted with evolutionary (“ultimate”) causes of traits in a population. Tinbergen’s Four Questions augment this dichotomy by calling attention to the differences between explanations that address a slice in time as compared to a historical sequence. Perhaps equally valuable is his emphasis on the independence of each question. They are not competing alternatives but four complementary components of a complete biological explanation. Confusion on this point still gives rise to much useless controversy. Questions about Mechanism have also been called “causal,” “structural,” “proximate” or “immediate.” This question actually has incorporated two somewhat different kinds of inquiry— those about intrinsic mechanisms and the body’s structures and how they work to carry out their functions, and those in which behavior is explained by extrinsic factors that immediately precede a behavior or other response. Both Nesse 2 2/17/2016 inquiries provide explanations of individuals based on mechanisms and current circumstances. The other three questions all explain the origins of the mechanisms. The second proximate question is about Ontogeny, the explanation of traits in terms of the mechanisms that transform precursors into their successors in developmental sequences. Mechanism and ontogeny help to explain each other; all developmental transitions needs mechanistic explanations and all structures need developmental explanations. Evolutionary questions ask why a population is the way it is, in the sense of “How come?” More specifically, they describe the forces, natural selection and others, which account for a trait’s transformation from its phylogenetic precursors. Selective Advantage was called “survival value” by Tinbergen, who wrote just prior to recognition of the importance of reproductive success. These questions have also been called “functional,” with much resulting confusion because Mayr used the same word to refer to the area of biology that studies structure and mechanisms. The core concept is adaptive utility that gives a fitness advantage. Of course, it is not the trait itself that is preserved, but only a DNA sequence. In this sense, questions about Selective Advantage are, as Mayr noted, fundamentally about why this species has its particular sequence of DNA. Agreement on methods for testing hypotheses about adaptation continues to be elusive, but there is growing recognition that the applicable research strategies—the comparative method, assessment of design for a function, experimental perturbation of adaptive mechanisms, and observing selection—are Nesse 3 2/17/2016 quite different from the experimental methods that are the mainstay in proximate biology. Questions about Phylogeny address the evolutionary history of a trait or a species. Every attribute, from a Hox gene to a peacock’s tail has an evolutionary history, with precursors varying by mutation and shaped by selection and drift to the observed form. The focus has expanded from paleontology to new areas of paleobiology including methods for inferring phylogeny from genetic sequences and other rapid advances at the intersection between evolutionary and developmental biology. Tinbergen’s Four Questions are not a panacea for preventing conceptual confusion in biology. They do, however, provide a vital framework of enduring utility for clarifying research questions and preventing useless controversy. Acknowledgements Thanks to Donald Dewsbury for valuable comments on a draft. Correspondence and Requests for materials should be addressed to: Randolph M Nesse University of Michigan 426 Thompson St, Room 5261 Ann Arbor, MI 48104 nesse@umich.edu FURTHER READING Tinbergen, N. On the aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie 20, 410-463 (1963). Dewsbury, D. A. The proximate and the ultimate: past, present and future. Behavioural Process 46, 189-199 (1999). Nesse 4 2/17/2016 Tinbergen’s Four Questions SLICE IN TIME An aspect of an organism at one phase in the life cycle/one time in phylogeny PROXIMATE EVOLUTIONARY (causal, immediate, structural) (distal, ultimate, Darwinian) Explains what individual organisms are like and how bodily mechanisms work Explains how populations of organisms came to be the way they are MECHANISM SELECTIVE ADVANTAGE (structure, physiology, immediate) (adaptive, functional, survival value, fitness, teleonomic) What is the structure, how do mechanisms work, and how do they respond to extrinsic factors? What selective forces in prior environments explain characteristics of the trait? Dewsbury, D. A. On the problems studied in ethology, comparative psychology, and animal behavior. Ethology 92, 89-107 (1992). Mayr, E. Cause and effect in biology. Science 134, 1501-1506 (1961). Nesse 5 2/17/2016 HISTORICAL SEQUENCE How precursors were transformed into the current trait Nesse ONTOGENY PHYLOGENY (developmental) (evolutionary historical) What developmental precursors and mechanisms explain the trait at this life stage? What phylogenetic precursors and mechanisms account for the trait in this evolutionary epoch? 6 2/17/2016