To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) The Spatial Restructuring of National Welfare States within the European Union: the Contribution of Union Citizenship and the Relevance of the Treaty of Lisbon Michael Dougan* 1. Introduction This paper explores the contribution of Union citizenship to the emergence of a “European welfare space”, characterised by the continued pre-eminence of national systems of social solidarity, but complemented by novel subnational and supranational dimensions to individual welfare rights and expectations (section 2). In particular, we shall explore the caselaw of the Court of Justice on the residency, equal treatment and movement rights of migrant Union citizens vis-à-vis their host and home states, highlighting the two main bodies of academic criticism prompted by that caselaw (section 3). First, the allegation of social engineering, i.e. that Community law is interfering in a top-down fashion with complex national welfare processes, so as to promote an understanding of social solidarity at odds with the traditional relationship between individual rights and collective interests. Secondly, the allegation of judicial activism, i.e. that the welfare rights and obligations associated with Union citizenship have been forged by the Court of Justice, despite the limited regulatory competences conferred upon the Community by the Treaty, and sometimes even in the face of the legislative choices expressed by the Union’s accountable political institutions. Although the Treaty of Lisbon 2007 itself appears to have little formal impact on this debate,1 it is arguable that the broader post-Laeken constitutional reform process (including the negative referenda in France, the Netherlands and Ireland) exposes the fragility of the normative basis upon which this controversial judicial experiment has been constructed, thereby raising difficult questions for the future direction of the Court’s caselaw (section 4). 2. The Restructuring of Welfare State Spaces within the European Union 2.1. Global restructuring reterritorialisation and processes of deterritorialisation and In his work on New State Spaces, Neil Brenner highlights the fact that, for much of the 20th century, social science scholarship was able to assume the nation state to be the normal geographical container for the operation and understanding of social, economic, political and cultural relations.2 With time, however, analysts came to understand that such a state-centric model of territorialisation could not be taken as a natural given. In fact, the emergence of globalisation (or global restructuring) means that previous assumptions about enclosing social etc relations within such a bounded * Professor of European Law, and Jean Monnet Chair in EU Law, Liverpool Law School, University of Liverpool. I am very grateful to participants at the Copenhagen conference in August 2008, and the UACES conference in Edinburgh in September 2008, for their comments and discussion. I am also indebted to Samantha Currie, Charlotte O’Brien and Eleanor Spaventa for their helpful suggestions. 1 [2007] OJ C306 and [2008] OJ C115. 2 N Brenner, New State Spaces: Urban Governance and the Rescaling of Statehood (OUP, Oxford, 2004) pp 28-29. 1 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) geographical space must now be viewed as deeply problematic.3 Nevertheless, the task of identifying new and alternative modes of spatial analysis has proven difficult. In particular, contemporary processes of global restructuring have entailed neither the absolute reconstitution of previously diverse societies onto a new global scale; nor their complete disintegration into a “distanceless, placeless, or borderless space of flows”.4 Rather, globalisation might be understood as having prompted a process of deterritorialisation and reterritorialisation. On the one hand, deterritorialisation refers to the circumvention and dismantling of historically entrenched scalar hierarchies, whereby familiar nationally defined configurations of social etc organisation are unsettled and rearticulated.5 On the other hand, such deterritorialisation is closely intertwined with a phenomenon of reterritorialisation, through which new subnational and supranational socio-spatial configurations are being constructed, though without entailing the outright denial of the nation state’s continued relevance as a major locus of social etc organisation.6 The national territorial state – albeit significantly rescaled – therefore serves as the crucial geographical infrastructure for an ongoing dialectic: mutually constitutive, if highly conflictual, processes of deterritorialisation and reterritorialisation succeed in reshuffling entrenched hierarchies of scalar organisation; social etc spaces are continually produced, reconfigured and transformed; qualitatively new geographies of state regulation emerge – albeit through a process which is highly variegated and path-dependent, according to a host of context-specific institutions, actors and influences.7 Brenner’s vision of the interface between historically inherited and newly emergent state spaces, as a focal point for understanding the restructuring of social, economic, political and cultural geographies in contemporary capitalist societies,8 will no doubt ring many familiar bells with scholars of European integration.9 In particular, that vision tallies well with the recent experience of the European welfare systems.10 It seems fair to observe that the inherited space of the national welfare states is indeed undergoing a dialectic process of deterritorialisation and reterritorialisation: on the one hand, certain historically entrenched assumptions associated with the post-war national welfare systems have increasingly become challenged and unsettled; on the other hand, there is greater recognition of the emergence of local and regional, as well as international and supranational, dimensions to the conception, construction, organisation and delivery of welfare goods and services. We shall explore this idea further, with reference to the relationship between the state space of the national welfare systems and the influence of EU membership, particularly since the introduction of Union citizenship and its transformation in the hands of the Court of Justice.11 3 Ibid, p 29. Ibid, p 64. 5 Ibid, p 57. 6 Ibid, p 57. 7 Ibid, pp 64-67. 8 Ibid, Ch 3, especially at p 112. 9 Indeed, consider the essays in M Berezin and M Schain (eds), Europe Without Borders: Remapping Territory, Citizenship and Identity in a Transnational Age (John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, 2003). 10 On which, see further M Ferrera, The Boundaries of Welfare: European Integration and the New Spatial Politics of Social Protection (OUP, Oxford, 2005). 11 For a broader perspective on the potential for a mutually transformative interaction between national and Union citizenships, see D Kostakopoulou, “European Union Citizenship: Writing the Future” 4 2 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) 2.2. Challenges to national welfare states and the “constitutional asymmetry” of EU welfare policies There seems widespread agreement that the European welfare states, for all their distinctive national characteristics, face certain common challenges, especially concerning the viability of traditional values such as the principle of universal coverage and the provision of relatively generous levels of support.12 The greatest pressure appears to emanate from internal factors: for example, social changes in fields such as labour market participation, population aging, divorce rates and single parent families; the recognition of a broader range of social risks and the costs of new medical treatments; a more widespread faith among political elites and the population at large in the supposed ability of market forces to play a constructive role in public services.13 Even if important structural differences remain, the flavour of reform in many countries is now familiar: promoting work rather than protecting labour; selective targeting of support rather than universal entitlement; emphasis on the social obligations of citizens rather than the social right to welfare; and expanding use of the private sector rather than purely public administration for the delivery of welfare services.14 Many scholars tend to ascribe to external factors – such as the (real or perceived) economic and budgetary pressures posed by greater global competition – a primarily aggravating role in this essentially internal process of welfare state reform (or at least one which remains mediated through and thus reshaped by domestic institutions and actors).15 However, the (quasi-exogenous) demands arising from membership of the European Union are acknowledged to exercise a much greater (or at least more tangible) influence upon national welfare policies.16 That influence derives, in particular, from the constraints imposed by economic integration within (2007) 13 ELJ 623. Consider, in particular, the discourse on “nested memberships”, e.g. T Faist, “Social Citizenship in the European Union: Nested Membership” (2001) 39 JCMS 37. For detailed studies in other contexts, e.g. O Golynker, Ubitquitous Citizens of Europe: The Pardigm of Partial Migration (Intersentia, Antwerp, 2006); J Shaw, The Transformation of Union Citizenship: Electoral Rights and the Restructuring of Political Space (CUP, Cambridge, 2007). 12 As observed by M Ferrera and M Rhodes (eds), Recasting European Welfare States (Frank Cass, London, 2000) at p 1. 13 See further, e.g. M Roche and R van Berkel (eds), European Citizenship and Social Exclusion (Ashgate, Aldershot, 1997); D Hine and H Kassim (eds), Beyond the Market: the EU and National Social Policy (Routledge, London, 1998); M Ferrera and M Rhodes (eds), Recasting European Welfare States (Frank Cass Publishers, London, 2000); S Kuhnle (ed), Survival of the European Welfare State (Routledge, London, 2000); J van Vugt and J Peet (eds), Social Security and Solidarity in the European Union (Physica-Verlag, Heidelberg, 2000); P Pierson (ed), The New Politics of the Welfare State (OUP, 2001); M Kleinman, A European Welfare State? (Palgrave, Basingstoke, 2002). 14 To borrow from the phrasing used by N Gilbert, “The Modern Welfare State: The Changing Context of Social Protection” (written version of paper presented at The Social Contract in the Modern Welfare Sate: Historical and Theoretical Perspectives (University of Oxford) 18-20 April 2007). 15 See further, e.g. F Ross, “Interests and Choice in the ‘Not Quite So New’ Politics of Welfare in M Ferrera and M Rhodes (eds), Recasting European Welfare States (Frank Cass, London, 2000); P Pierson (ed), The New Politics of the Welfare State (OUP, 2001) especially Chs 1-3; M Kleinman, A European Welfare State? (Palgrave, Basingstoke, 2002) especially Ch 3. 16 E.g. M Ferrera and M Rhodes (eds), Recasting European Welfare States (Frank Cass, London, 2000) at p 2; S Kuhnle (ed), Survival of the European Welfare State (Routledge, London, 2000) at pp 12-14. For analysis, see further the various contributions in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005) and G de Búrca (ed), EU Law and the Welfare State (OUP, Oxford, 2005). 3 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) the Single Market: whether direct, through the application of free movement and competition rules to specific domestic choices about the organisation and delivery of welfare goods and services;17 or indirect, such as the widespread assumption that more intense competition to retain and attract mobile undertakings or capital within the Single Market, or to stimulate economic performance by national economic operators obliged to compete with foreign rivals, induces Member States to reduce the labour costs and / or overall tax burdens implied by their existing levels of welfare support;18 coupled with the risk that the budgetary constraints imposed by participation in economic and monetary union may produce a negative impact upon the financing of national social protection systems.19 All of that provides the basis for the well-known critique of the EU’s alleged “constitutional asymmetry”: the pressures on national social choices exerted by European economic integration are not matched by the availability at Union level of countervailing resources for the purposes of protecting and promoting social rights in general, or welfare provision in particular.20 Save for relatively marginal activities such as the CAP and the Structural Funds, the EU is generally characterised by the performance of extremely limited direct redistributive functions, the exercise of rather weak regulatory powers in the field of welfare (as compared to other areas of social policy such as labour law) that might instead seek to compel domestic resources to be employed along particular redistributive pathways, and a default tendency to rely on soft law instruments, such as the open method of coordination within the context of the Lisbon Strategy, to achieve many of the Union’s welfare policy objectives.21 Of course, the Union’s restricted welfare competences may be interpreted as a natural reflection of its impoverished legitimacy – among Member State political elites and the general population alike – to assume any more far-reaching independent social mandate.22 Indeed, it has been argued that, when it comes to the Union’s social and welfare policy objectives, more actually means less.23 Nevertheless, the accusation of “constitutional asymmetry” has stuck and seems to cut deeply into the psyche of See further, e.g. T Hervey, ‘Social Solidarity: A Buttress Against Internal Market Law?’ in J Shaw (ed), Social Law and Policy in an Evolving European Union (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2000). That is true especially in the context of the healthcare caselaw: see further, e.g. V Hatzopoulos, “Killing National Health and Insurance Systems but Healing Patients? The European Market for Health care Services After the Judgmnets of the ECJ in Vanbraekel and Peerbooms” (2002) 39 CMLRev 683 and (more recently) “Health Law and Policy: The Impact of the EU” in G de Búrca (ed), EU Law and the Welfare State (OUP, Oxford, 2005). 18 See further, e.g. L Delsen, N van Gestel and J van Vugt, ‘European Integration: Current Problems and Future Scenarios’ in J van Vugt and J Peet (eds), Social Security and Solidarity in the European Union (Physica-Verlag, 2000). 19 See further, e.g. M Panić, “The Euro and the Welfare State” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005). 20 E.g. B Schulte, ‘The Welfare State and European Integration’ (1999) 1 EJSS 7; F Scharpf, ‘The European Social Model: Coping With the Challenges of Diversity’ (2002) 40 JCMS 645. 21 As regards which, see further, e.g. N Bernard, “Between a Rock and a Soft Place: Internal Market versus Open Coordination in EU Social Welfare Law” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005); J Zeitlin, “Social Europe and Experimentalist Governance: Towards a New Constitutional Compromise” in G de Búrca (ed), EU Law and the Welfare State (OUP, Oxford, 2005). 22 See further, e.g. G Majone, Dilemmas of European Integration: The Ambiguities and Pitfalls of Integration by Stealth (OUP, Oxford, 2005). 23 As observed by W Lamping during a presentation on “The Limits and Opportunities of Institutionalising European Social Solidarity” at the conference Seeking Solidarity in the European Union: Towards Social Citizenship and a European Welfare State? (University of Sussex, 7 May 2008). 17 4 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) many of the Union’s supporters and detractors alike: in theory, the national welfare states remain pre-eminent; in practice, that pre-eminence tends to be undermined rather than supported by the Union. 2.3. Union citizenship and domestic welfare boundaries based on nationality and territoriality The introduction of Union citizenship was seen by many commentators as an opportunity partially to redress that balance,24 and ultimately, to provide an important new source of affiliation to and legitimacy for the process of European integration.25 Even in the absence of extensive redistributive or harmonising competences in the sphere of welfare provision, the evolution of a workable “European social citizenship” could still be realised through action to promote more universal rights to free movement across the Union territory for all Community nationals, and the creation of novel expectations of social solidarity based upon the shared identity of Union citizenship, going beyond the traditional restriction of mobility and equal treatment rights under Community law to persons deemed economically active in an employed or self-employed capacity. Such a “European social citizenship” would obviously be much more modest in its ambitions than any ordinary “national social citizenship” – not least in that its benefits would be reserved primarily to that relatively small proportion of the population who do in fact exercise rights to free movement in another Member State – but it would at least be attainable within the existing constitutional constraints and limited competences available to the Union.26 It is apparent that the benefits even of any such modest “European social citizenship” – more extensive and more secure rights, both as regards residency and to social support, for economically inactive persons previously excluded from the full protection of Community law – are to be discharged vicariously by the Member States themselves. The line between creating new models of social solidarity derived from Community law, and recasting old forms of social solidarity as they exist under national law, is a fine one.27 Indeed, that prospect raises a fresh set of challenges for 24 For early analyses of Union citizenship after its introduction by the Maastricht Treaty, e.g. C Closa, “The Concept of Citizenship in the Treaty on European Union” (1992) 29 CMLRev 1137; R Kovar and D Simon, “La Citoyenneté Européenne” [1993] Cahiers de Droit Européen 285; D O’Keeffe, “Union Citizenship” in D O’Keeffe and P Twomey, (eds) Legal Issues of the Maastricht Treaty (Wiley, Chichester, 1994); H U J d’Oliveira, “European Citizenship: Its Meaning, Its Potential” in R Dehousse (ed), Europe After Maastricht: An Ever Closer Union? (Law Books in Europe, Munich, 1994); S Hall, Nationality, Migration Rights and Citizenship of the Union (Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, 1995); S O’Leary, The Evolving Concept of Community Citizenship: From the Free Movement of Persons to Union Citizenship (Kluwer Law, The Hague, 1996). 25 See further, e.g. M Everson, “The Legacy of the Market Citizen” in J Shaw and G More (eds), New Legal Dynamics of European Union (Clarendon, Oxford, 1995); U Preuß, “Problems of a Concept of European Citizenship” (1995) 1 ELJ 267; A Wiener and V and della Sala, “Constitution-Making and Citizenship Practice: Bridging the Democracy Gap in the EU?” (1997) 35 JCMS 595; J Shaw, “The Interpretation of European Union Citizenship” (1998) 61 MLR 293; M P Maduro, “Europe’s Social Self: The ‘Sickness Unto Death’” in J Shaw (ed), Social Law and Policy in an Evolving European Union (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2000). 26 Not that reverse discrimination against static Union citizens escapes serious criticism: consider, e.g. N Nic Shuibhne, “Free Movement of Persons and the Wholly Internal Rule: Time to Move on?” (2002) 39 CMLRev 731; E Spaventa, “Seeing the Wood Despite the Trees? On the Scope of Union Citizenship and Its Constitutional Effects” (2008) 45 CMLRev 13. 27 As observed by A Schrauwen in a presentation on “The Future of EU Citizenship: Corrosion of National Citizenship?” at the conference After the First 50 Years: The Future of European Law and Policy (University of Birmingham, 3-4 July 2008). 5 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) the national welfare systems or, to put it differently, another dimension to the dialectic process of deterritorialisation and reterritorialisation acting upon our inherited state welfare spaces. After all, two of the strongest spatial characteristics displayed by national welfare states in their formative post-war period were nationality and territoriality; those twin criteria have traditionally served, in principle, to distinguish eligible members of the domestic welfare community from outsiders excluded from its protection and benefits.28 The limitation of certain (particularly non-contributory) social rights to own nationals reflects the close interrelationship between the welfare state and the nation state: the community of interests derived from shared national identity provides much of the moral force required to justify the redistribution of wealth through social security and other welfare benefits; conversely, the community of interests derived from the shared assumption of responsibility for individual social well-being helps build and reinforce a shared national identity. That same sense of community underlies the traditional restriction of certain social rights to those resident within the domestic territory: citizens who chose to go abroad, and no longer share in the national community – or for that matter, pay taxes to the national exchequer, or submit themselves to supervision by the national authorities – forfeit the expectation of welfare support from their country of origin.29 As Halfmann has observed, “the concepts of equality and solidarity associated with the modern welfare state cannot be understood without the original restriction of welfare state policies to the members of the nation…. welfare policies are meant to impose a territorial criterion on the politics of inclusion in the political system [including] the attempts of the nation state to restrict the welfare state benefits to its citizens or to demand the consumption of the benefits on the state territory”.30 While the centre of gravity for comprehending welfare relations in contemporary Europe undoubtedly remains anchored (legally, politically and financially) at the domestic level, internally and externally driven processes of restructuring mean that nationality and territoriality can no longer claim an absolute monopoly in defining membership of and exclusion from the domestic solidaristic communities: the dialectic of deterritorialisation and reterritorialisation has surely already led to greater recognition for more diverse (subnational and supranational) dimensions to social and welfare provision.31 That is true not least as regards See further, e.g. G Vonk, “Migration, Social Security and the Law: Some European Dilemmas” [2002] European Journal of Social Security 315; M Dougan and E Spaventa, “Wish You Weren’t Here… New Models of Social Solidarity in the European Union” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005); M Ferrera, “Towards an ‘Open’ Social Citizenship? The New Boundaries of Welfare in the European Union” in G de Búrca (ed), EU Law and the Welfare State (OUP, Oxford, 2005); D S Martinsen, “The Europeanisation of Welfare: The Domestic Impact of Intra-European Social Security” (2005) 43 JCMS 1027; H Verschueren, “European (Internal) Migration as an Instrument for Defining the Boundaries of National Solidarity Systems” (2007) 9 European Journal of Migration and Law 307. 29 See further, e.g. M Dougan, “Expanding the Frontiers of Union Citizenship by Dismantling the Territorial Boundaries of the National Welfare States?” in C Barnard and O Odudu (eds), The Outer Limits of EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, forthcoming). 30 J Halfmann, “Welfare State and Territory” in M Bommes and A Geddes (eds), Immigration and Welfare: Challenging the Borders of the Welfare State (Routledge, London, 2000) at p 41. 31 Consider, for example, the increasingly divergent paths trodden by the discrete English, Scottish, Welsh and Northern Irish segments of the NHS within the UK. Consider also the relatively generous approaches of many Member States towards the access by immigrants to welfare provision: see further, e.g. V Guiraudon, “The Marshallian Triptych Reordered: The Role of Courts and Bureaucracies in 28 6 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) economic integration within the context of the Single Market: as hinted at above, Community law has long insisted that an economic contribution by foreign migrants to the host society must be recognised, in principle, as a valid ticket for entry into the national solidaristic community;32 similarly, the Community’s rules on the crossborder coordination of national social security systems, currently contained in Regulation 1408/7133 but shortly to be replaced for most purposes by Regulation 883/2004,34 have long sought to detach the payment of certain benefits from a purely territorial basis.35 Nevertheless, the prospect of a “European social citizenship” – premised upon greatly expanded rights to free movement, residency and equal treatment for all Community nationals, regardless of their economic status or contribution – would directly and significantly challenge the traditional links between an individual’s legitimate right to claim welfare support and her / his membership of each Member State’s solidaristic community, either according to historically accepted ties of belonging based upon nationality and residency, or on the basis of wellestablished Community principles relating to the facilitation of economic mobility.36 The remainder of this paper will explore the interface between the inherited spaces of Member State welfare systems based on the historic criteria of nationality and territoriality; and the emergent spaces of supranational identity suggested by the construction of new welfare rights and obligations for Union citizens under Community law. We shall see that EU membership and the impact of Union citizenship both contributes to the partial dismantling of the welfare state’s entrenched spatial identity and simultaneously seeks to offer new dimensions in its more complex reconstruction (section 3.1). However, this interaction between the EU and its Member States in reframing the spatial identity of welfare provision in the light of Union citizenship deserves to be interrogated critically in the light of its specific institutional and policy contexts. In the first place, there are questions about the impact of Community law on social solidarity: what benefits Community law brings to individuals, and what challenges this might pose for the national welfare states (section 3.2). In the second place, there are questions about the constitutional Furthering Migrants’ Social Rights” in M Bommes and A Geddes (eds), Immigration and Welfare: Challenging the Borders of the Welfare State (Routledge, London, 2000). 32 As regards resident migrant workers, any effective and genuine economic activity entitles the claimant to seek equal treatment in the field of social benefits: see, e.g. Case 249/83 Hoeckx [1985] ECR 973; Case C-237/94 O’Flynn [1996] ECR I-2617; cp. Case 53/81 Levin [1982] ECR 1035; Case 139/85 Kempf [1986] ECR 1741. However, as regards non-resident frontier workers, the Court seems to accept that the host state may require the claimant to demonstrate a sufficiently substantial economic activity within its territory, before granting access to certain social benefits: see Case C-213/05 Geven [2007] ECR I-6347; Case C-212/05 Hartmann [2007] ECR I-6303. On that point, see further, e.g. C O’Brien, Annotation of Geven, Hartmann and Hendrix (2008) 45 CMLRev 499; S Currie, “The Transformation of Union Citizenship” in M Dougan and S Currie (eds), 50 Years of the European Treaties: Looking Back and Thinking Forward (Hart Publishing, Oxford, forthcoming). 33 Last consolidated text published at [1997] OJ L28/1. 34 [2004] OJ L200/1. 35 See further, e.g. R Cornelissen, “The Principle of Territoriality and the Community Regulations on Social Security” (1996) 33 CMLRev 439; F Pennings, Introduction to European Social Security Law (Kluwer Law International, 2001); D S Martinsen, “Social Security Regulation in the EU: The DeTerritorialisation of Welfare?” in G de Búrca (ed), EU Law and the Welfare State (OUP, Oxford, 2005); V Paskalia, Free Movement, Social Security and Gender in the EU (Hart Publishing, 2007). 36 For present purposes, we are not concerned with the issues raised by the immigration of third country nationals for welfare policies and solidarity concepts based on traditional nationality criteria: see further, e.g. M Bommes and A Geddes (eds), Immigration and Welfare: Challenging the Borders of the Welfare State (Routledge, London, 2000); C-U Schierup, P Hansen and S Castles, Migration, Citizenship and the European Welfare State (OUP, Oxford, 2006). 7 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) implications of the recent transformation of Union citizenship for Community law itself: how that transformation affects the distribution of competences between the Union and the Member States, and the separation of powers between the ECJ and the Community legislature (section 3.3). 3. A Critical Assessment of the Welfare Rights Associated with Union Citizenship 3.1. Summary of the current legal framework At the risk of neglecting its myriad nuances, the current legal framework governing the welfare rights associated with Union citizenship – derived from the primary Treaty provisions, secondary measures adopted by the Community legislature, and of course, the extensive interpretative caselaw of the ECJ – may be summarised as follows.37 As regards relations between an economically inactive migrant and his / her host state, the inevitable compromise between (on the one hand) the desire to offer meaningful benefits to Union citizens regardless of their economic or financial status and (on the other hand) the need to respect the Member State’s limited willingness and ability to pay for the upkeep of foreign nationals who might otherwise present an unreasonable burden upon its public finances, has gradually manifested itself in the task of identifying a “real link” between migrant and host society.38 The closer the bond between the individual claimant and the Member State, the more secure will be the claimant’s right to reside within the territory, free from the fear of expulsion on economic or financial grounds;39 and the more extensive his / her right to equal treatment within the host society, as regards welfare and other social benefits.40 Union citizenship, combined with a tangible shared experience between the individual 37 For more expansive analyses, see further, e.g. A P van der Mei, Free Movement of Persons within the European Community: Cross-Border Access to Public Benefits (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2003); E Spaventa, Free Movement of Persons in the European Union (Kluwer Law International, The Hague, 2007). 38 The concept was first employed by the ECJ in Case C-224/98 D’Hoop [2002] ECR I-6191. Its potential relevance is not restricted to migrant welfare rights, or even Union citizenship: consider, e.g. the rulings in Case C-145/04 Spain v United Kingdom [2006] ECR I-7917 on voting rights to the European Parliament for certain TCNs and Case C-66/08 Kozłowski (Judgment of 17 July 2008) on grounds for non-execution of a European arrest warrant. 39 E.g. Case C-184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I-6193; Case C-413/99 Baumbast [2002] ECR I-7091; Case C-456/02 Trojani [2004] ECR I-7573. Now, contrast (at one extreme) the right to three months residency with (at the other extreme) the right to permanent residency contained in Directive 2004/38 [2004] OJ L158/77. Note that the “real link” concept is irrelevant in the case of national rules restricting residency based on an excessively restrictive interpretation of the applicable Community secondary legislation and where there is no question of claims against the public finances: consider, e.g. Case C-200/02 Zhu and Chen [2004] ECR I-9925; Case C-408/03 Commission v Belgium [2006] ECR I-2647; Case C-398/06 Commission v Netherlands (Judgment of 10 April 2008). 40 E.g. Case C-85/96 María Martínez Sala [1998] ECR I-2691; Case C-184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I-6193; Case C-224/98 D’Hoop [2002] ECR I-6191; Case C-138/02 Collins [2004] ECR I-2703; Case C-209/03 Bidar [2005] ECR I-2119; Case C-258/04 Ioannidis [2005] ECR I-8275. Indeed, the Court considered that only migrants already either in possession of a residence permit, or able to demonstrate a certain period of residence, could be considered in a comparable position to established residents and thus entitled to equal treatment within the host state at all: see, e.g. Case C-456/02 Trojani [2004] ECR I-7573 (and the discussion by M Dougan and E Spaventa, “Wish You Weren’t Here… New Models of Social Solidarity in the European Union” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005). Again, consider now the ‘sliding scale’ of equal treatment contained in Directive 2004/38 [2004] OJ L158/77. 8 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) and his / her host society, has therefore become a legitimate gateway into membership of the domestic welfare community. As regards relations between a migrant Union citizen and his / her home state, a similar approach has emerged in parallel in the caselaw.41 The tension between (on the one hand) the desire not to hinder the movement of Union citizens who may be dependent upon some form of public support and (on the other hand) the political, financial and practical constraints that favour respect for the territorially bounded nature of (particularly non-contributory) welfare provision has also been resolved through resort to a “real link” principle.42 In this context, the Court seems sensitive to whether the relevant benefit is funded by the claimant’s own contributions or instead through general taxation, and the degree to which it may be linked to the specific economic and social environment of the competent Member State: the stronger the relationship between a given welfare benefit and the domestic system of social solidarity, the weaker the force of the argument for severing the cord connecting payment of benefits to residence within the national territory.43 In addition, however, the Court will examine the degree to which the individual claimant may assert membership of his / her home state’s welfare community, even after having left the national territory, on the basis of past or present links other than continuing residence alone, which are nevertheless sufficient to warrant a right of access to the relevant benefits.44 Of course, the legal principles governing relations between a migrant citizen and his / her host state (on the one hand) and home state (on the other hand) should be seen not as discrete and mutually exclusive, but rather as cumulative and interactive. In particular, it is arguable that the Court is actively seeking to make two discrete legal tools – the barriers to movement principle as a means of challenging the territorial limitations of the home state, and the right to equal treatment as a means of overcoming the nationality limitations of the host state – work together to enhance the practical value of Union citizenship for a broader category of its potential beneficiaries than either of those legal tools could hope to achieve on its own: obliging the home state to provide welfare support in respect of its own migrant nationals helps such individuals to move closer to the point at which they can instead claim to be assimilated into the welfare system of the host state; the gradual weakening of one “real link” morphs into the gradual strengthening of another “real link” so as to help ensure for the Union citizen a smoother transition between welfare states and better continuity of social support.45 41 Either in tandem with (as in Cases C-502/01 and C-31/02 Gaumain-Cerri [2004] ECR I-6483) or even in contradiction to (in rulings such as Case C-287/05 Hendrix [2007] ECR I-6909) the coordination rules contained in Regulation 1408/71 and Regulation 883/2004: see further below. 42 See further, e.g. M Dougan, “Expanding the Frontiers of Union Citizenship by Dismantling the Territorial Boundaries of the National Welfare States?” in C Barnard and O Odudu (eds), The Outer Limits of EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, forthcoming). 43 Consider, e.g. Case 313/86 Lenoir [1988] ECR 5391; Case C-43/99 Leclere [2001] ECR I-4265; Cases C-396/05, C-419/05 and C-450/05 Habelt (Judgment of 18 December 2007); Case C-228/07 Petersen (Judgment of 11 September 2008). Cp. rulings where the Court has found that contributory benefits were wrongly categorised as special non-contributory [cash] benefits and thereby improperly excluded from the possibility of exportation under Regulation 1408/71, e.g. Case C-215/99 Jauch [2001] ECR I-1901. 44 Consider, e.g. Case C-192/05 Tas-Hagen [2006] ECR I-10451; Case C-287/05 Hendrix [2007] ECR I-6909; Cases C-11-12/06 Morgan and Bucher [2007] ECR I-9161; Case C-499/06 Nerkowska (Judgment of 22 May 2008). 45 An argument made primarily in the field of cross-border educational mobility: see, e.g. A-P van der Mei, “EU Law and Education: Promotion of Student Mobility versus Protection of Education Systems” 9 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) In any case, two further important principles, originally established by the Court in Grzelczyk and Baumbast,46 but increasingly applicable to all questions of residency, equal treatment and non-discriminatory barriers to movement, are essential to understanding the welfare relationship between migrants and their host / home states as constructed under Community law. First, Community secondary legislation which itself purports to restrict the migrant’s opportunities for free movement is nevertheless amenable to a form of “indirect judicial review” intended to guarantee that it does not unduly prejudice the existence or exercise of the Union citizen’s rights, i.e. whereby Member States are obliged to apply Community legislation which appears to limit the rights of Union citizens in accordance with the general principles of Community law, especially the principle of proportionality, so that the relevant Community rules may not be enforced against an individual where that would exceed what it necessary to protect the Member State’s legitimate interests.47 Secondly, even where it is legitimate in principle for the Member State (whether host or home) to expect a “real link” between a given claimant and the relevant welfare community, evidence to support that “real link” cannot be gathered exclusively on the basis of generalised criteria (such as past or continuing residency). The national authorities must also give due consideration to the personal circumstances of each individual claimant, even if this implies taking into account factors or circumstances not recognised as relevant or compelling under the applicable domestic legislation.48 That summary of the current legal framework governing the welfare rights and obligations associated with Union citizenship sets the scene for an analysis of the main criticisms levied, particularly against the Court’s contribution, in the academic literature. For ease of exposition, those criticisms can be divided into two main categories: concerning the implications of the caselaw for conceptions of social solidarity in Europe; and concerning the constitutional propriety of the Court’s interpretation of Union citizenship. 3.2. Concerning the implications of the caselaw for conceptions of social solidarity in Europe 3.2.1. The very principle of Community intervention in national welfare systems The evolution of national solidaristic rights and obligations has been (and continues to be) highly contested: a range of actors with different and often opposing interests must be reconciled to each other, not only through the usual medium of democratically elected assemblies and other institutions of state, but sometimes also in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, 2005); M Dougan, “Fees, Grants, Loans and Dole Cheques: Who Covers the Costs of Migrant Education within the EU?” (2005) 42 CMLRev 943 and “Cross-Border Educational Mobility and the Exportation of Student Financial Assistance” (2008) 33 ELRev 723. 46 Case C-184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I-6193; Case C-413/99 Baumbast [2002] ECR I-7091. 47 Consider the rulings in Case C-406/04 De Cuyper [2006] ECR I-6947; Case C-287/05 Hendrix [2007] ECR I-6909; Case C-228/07 Petersen (Judgment of 11 September 2008). See further, e.g. M Dougan, “The Constitutional Dimension to the Case Law on Union Citizenship (2006) 31 ELRev 613. 48 Consider the rulings in Case C-224/98 D’Hoop [2002] ECR I-6191; Case C-138/02 Collins [2004] ECR I-2703; Case C-209/03 Bidar [2005] ECR I-2119; Case C-258/04 Ioannidis [2005] ECR I-8275; Case C-287/05 Hendrix [2007] ECR I-6909; Cases C-11-12/06 Morgan and Bucher [2007] ECR I9161; Case C-499/06 Nerkowska (Judgment of 22 May 2008). See further, e.g. E Spaventa, “Seeing the Wood Despite the Trees? On the Scope of Union Citizenship and Its Constitutional Effects” (2008) 45 CMLRev 13. 10 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) by the expression of more direct forms of social confrontation such as strikes and civil disorder, and the resulting manifestations of solidarity must secure at least the tacit approval of the population at large, according to the inherited and changing social, economic, political and cultural structures and preferences of the relevant society.49 Domestic welfare relationships, as they exist at any given point in time, are therefore the product of complex and multi-faceted processes of social bargaining that pertain to the very core of national democratic contestation. Small wonder, therefore, that the definitions of belonging to and exclusion from membership of the national solidaristic community are closely associated with the fundamental expression of state (and popular) sovereignty.50 Against that background, it is possible to argue that the very principle of Community intervention in the national solidaristic communities raises certain difficulties. After all, it is highly doubtful whether the Community’s decision-making procedures – including to a degree the legislative interaction of Commission, Council and European Parliament which results in measures such as Directive 2004/38;51 but especially the adjudicative role of the Court of Justice which produces rulings such as Grzelczyk, Collins and Bidar52 – could claim to have forged their welfare choices with any comparable degree of inclusion or contestation, or to command any comparable level of popular adherence to their policy outcomes, simply by virtue of the process by which they were produced. At the very least, therefore, the welfare rights and obligations associated with Union citizenship are the product of political and legal processes which stand apart from and lack the legitimacy of their national counterparts.53 That critique could indeed be carried further. Not only are Community welfare policies largely the result of elite choices which are then superimposed onto the national solidarity systems on the basis of relatively shallow reserves of social and cultural legitimacy, but once imposed, those choices are very difficult to adjust and almost impossible to remove by any given Member State acting unilaterally.54 Regardless of the substantive merits of the rights and obligations created and promoted by the Community legislature and / or the Court, it is therefore arguable that the dimension to our solidarity relationships with the least claim to legitimacy – that associated with Union citizenship – also enjoys the most privileged and protected legal status within the domestic welfare systems. Some commentators might take issue with such an interpretation, on the grounds that it conceives of the interaction between national solidarity and Union citizenship in a relatively static and confrontational manner. A more dynamic and perhaps optimistic view would be that the complex and gradual layering of national and European identities, within the framework of the Union, offers the potential to 49 For an overview of the historical development of social solidarity, from the early 19 th century to contemporary times, see S Stjernø, Solidarity in Europe: The History of an Idea (CUP, Cambridge, 2005). 50 And that welfare rights are seen as an intrinsic element in expressing and facilitating the democratic link between citizen and state: see further, e.g. N Harris (ed), Social Security Law in Context (OUP, Oxford, 2000) especially Chs 1-2. 51 [2004] OJ L158/77. 52 Case C-184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I-6193; Case C-138/02 Collins [2004] ECR I-2703; Case C209/03 Bidar [2005] ECR I-2119. 53 Cf. K Hailbronner, “Union Citizenship and Access to Social Benefits” (2005) 42 CMLRev 1245, who seems more sympathetic towards the legitimacy of the Community legislature than that of the ECJ in manufacturing new solidarity rights for economically inactive migrant Union citizens (at pp 1265-6). 54 Especially in the case of ECJ rulings. Consider, e.g. Austria’s repeated attempts to overturn or limit the ruling in Case C-147/03 Commission v Austria [2005] ECR I-5969 concerning equal treatment for Union citizens as regards access to the national higher education system. 11 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) forge novel forms of collective consciousness and to nurture new bonds of solidarity, capable of overcoming inherited reservations about the provision of welfare support beyond the traditional (national, territoriality and contributory) boundaries of the domestic solidaristic communities.55 But assuming that thin institutional structures, weak political will and insipid popular demand render such a prospect more remote / contingent than it is imminent / assured, the question arises: will novel Community choices about belonging to and exclusion from the national solidaristic communities – imposed in a top-down fashion by the Union institutions, and thenceforth shielded from many of the ordinary processes of domestic contestation or readjustment – nevertheless prove able to embed themselves into the national welfare systems?56 Given that their input legitimacy is so precarious, it might seem that the best hope for such Community choices lies in their capacity instead to garner sufficient output legitimacy, i.e. to elicit a sympathetic and accommodating response from the Member States, or at least to tally with popular preferences emerging at the domestic level in any case. But if the rights and obligations imposed by Community law diverge from, or even directly contradict, the outcomes which would otherwise result from national political and social choices, it is possible that the welfare dimension specific to Union citizenship could be precariously exposed – and any more fundamental constitutional and / or political ambitions lying behind the promotion of a common “European social citizenship” seriously compromised.57 3.2.2. The perceived content of the welfare rights enjoyed by Union citizens If the very idea of a Community-driven reconfiguration of established national welfare spaces seems controversial, the problems continue when one turns to evaluate the perceived content of the welfare rights and obligations associated with Union citizenship. In particular, academic opinion seems divided over the substantive nature and value of the solidarity models currently being constructed under Community law. Some commentators in fact seem supportive of the Court’s caselaw, interpreting the improved but still graduated, nuanced and conditional rights of residency and equal treatment for economically inactive migrants as a valuable European dimension to social solidarity which tangibly enhances the legal and political value of Union Consider, e.g. G Davies, “‘Any Place I Hang My Hat?’ or: Residence is the New Nationality” (2005) 11 ELJ 43, who suggests that the caselaw’s emphasis on residency rather than mere nationality as the touchstone of solidarity and welfare support “is an appropriate extension of the European project; finally an assault on national and historical determinism, and its replacement by a voluntary society, open to change” (at p 56). For discussion of the inter-relationship between national and European identities, see further, e.g. K Eder and B Giesen (eds), European Citizenship Between National Legacies and Postnational Projects (OUP, Oxford, 2001); N Prentoulis, “On the Technology of Collective Identity: Normative Reconstructions of the Concept of EU Citizenship” (2001) 7 ELJ 196; N Barber, “Citizenship, Nationalism and the European Union” (2002) 27 ELRev 241; K Kumar, “The Idea of Europe: Cultural Legacies, Transnational Imaginings and the Nation State” and R Kastoryano, “Transnational Networks and Political Participation: The Place of Immigrants in the European Union” in M Berezin and M Schain (eds), Europe Without Borders: Remapping Territory, Citizenship and Identity in a Transnational Age (John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, 2003); F Mayer and J Palmowski, “European Identities and the EU: The Ties that Bind the Peoples of Europe” (2004) 42 JCMS 573. 56 Cp. S Besson and A Utzinger, “Future Challenges of European Citizenship: Facing a Wide-Open Pandora’s Box” (2007) 13 ELJ 573, who refer to the problems of “practical appropriation and conscientisation by EU citizens themselves” of judicially-led citizenship rights (at p 575). 57 Cp. P Magnette, “How Can One be European? Reflections on the Pillars of European Civic Identity” (2007) 13 ELJ 664. 55 12 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) citizenship while respecting the legitimate interests and sensitivities of the Member States.58 However, others believe that the expectations of financial solidarity now being encouraged under Community law are unduly generous. For example, Somek has argued that merely combining the formal legal status of Union citizenship with some period of residence in another territory, as the basis for expanded residency and equal treatment rights for economically inactive migrants, is no substitute for a more profound moral dimension to the welfare responsibilities any given society can be expected to demonstrate towards foreign nationals.59 Indeed, several commentators appear intuitively uncertain about whether “real links” of the sort apparently rewarded under Community law are actually capable of generating any meaningful sense of social solidarity towards economically inactive foreigners – and might not ultimately risk producing the opposite effect, i.e. of provoking a backlash among the host society against individuals who have not acquired membership of the solidaristic community according to the latter’s traditional or accepted criteria.60 In this regard, it is worth considering the potential relevance of the 2004 and 2007 enlargements of the Union. Without doubting the fundamental value of those accessions for the Union and new Member States alike, there can be little doubt that the relationship between recent enlargements and the free movement of persons has raised certain difficulties in public debate and for public policy: for example, concerning the protection of national labour markets against CEEC workers and fears about the prospect of unfair competition by CEEC undertakings,61 as well as worries that mass migration by CEEC nationals could impose serious demands upon domestic welfare benefits and services.62 On the latter point, it should be recalled that, in addition to the transitional restrictions on the free movement of persons contained in the Treaties of Accession 2003 and 2005, various Member States have responded to the Union’s enlargement by introducing additional restrictions on the availability of domestic social support for migrant Union citizens.63 As has been observed, such restrictions are often targeted primarily at the economically active migrant, challenging the assumption that Community law has succeeded in convincing Member States to automatically translate even an economic contribution into Consider, e.g. C Jacqueson, “Union Citizenship and the Court of Justice: Something New Under the Sun? Towards Social Citizenship” (2002) 27 ELRev 260; H Verschueren, “European (Internal) Migration Law as an Instrument for Defining the Boundaries of National Solidarity Systems” (2007) 9 European Journal of Migration and Law 307; S Giubboni, “Free Movement of Persons and European Solidarity” (2007) 13 ELJ 360. 59 A Somek, “Solidarity Decomposed: Being and Time in European Citizenship” (2007) 32 ELRev 787. 60 E.g. C Tomuschat, Annotation of Sala (2000) 37 CMLRev 449; C Barnard, “EU Citizenship and the Principle of Solidarity” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005). Note also: M Dougan, “Free Movement: The Workseeker as Citizen” (2001) 4 CYELS 93; K Hailbronner, “Union Citizenship and Access to Social Benefits” (2005) 42 CMLRev 1245; C Barnard, Annotation of Bidar (2005) 42 CMLRev 1465. 61 In which regard, consider disputes such as those in Case C-438/05 Viking Line (Judgment of 11 December 2007); Case C-341/05 Laval un Partneri (Judgment of 18 December 2007); Case C-346/06 Dirk Rüffert (Judgment of 3 April 2008). 62 See further, e.g. M Dougan, “A Spectre is Haunting Europe… Free Movement of Persons and the Eastern Enlargement” in C Hillion (ed), EU Enlargement: A Legal Approach (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2004); A Adinolfi, “Free Movement and Access to Work of Citizens of the New Member States: The Transitional Measures (2005) 42 CMLRev 469. 63 See further, e.g. P Larkin, “The Limits to European Social Citizenship in the United Kingdom” (2005) 68 MLR 435; S Currie, Migration, Work and Citizenship in the Enlarged European Union (Ashgate, Aldershot, forthcoming). 58 13 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) solidaristic bonds with the host society.64 More broadly, one might wonder whether the temporal coincidence of the 2004 and 2007 enlargements with the Court’s transformation of Union citizenship merely exacerbates the difficulties of securing popular acceptance for the principle of financial solidarity towards migrant Community nationals: it seems hard to imagine that such a dramatic expansion in the number and diversity of right-holders within such a short space of time, against the background of a political and public discourse which presents CEEC migration as much as a menacing threat as a shared right, could help (at least in the short term) to foster deeper as well as merely wider transnational welfare bonds based upon our common Union citizenship. Indeed, Italy’s treatment of Romanian migrants, and of the Roma community, which began after the 2007 accession under the left-wing government of Prodi and then escalated under the right-wing administration of Berlusconi, suggests that the Union’s massive eastern enlargement has not necessarily translated into an “ever closer union” between the peoples of Europe – and could even have kindled certain feelings of hostility and alienation. Another group of scholars adopt a rather different perspective on the caselaw. For example, O’Brien submits that the Court’s “real link” concept is in fact a relatively un-ambitious and un-intrusive construct: it confers upon migrant Union citizens little more than a right to be assessed according to a rational, appropriate, accurate and flexible administrative procedure; but the Court does not otherwise fundamentally interfere with the Member State’s power to determine precisely which substantive factors and relationships will be valued as legitimate entry-tickets into its own welfare society. Viewed from that perspective, the “real link” test could indeed act as a vehicle for disguising and legitimising social exclusion against economically inactive migrant Union citizens: for example, where Member States are free to recognise and reward certain forms of social integration and civic participation while marginalising and devaluing others – almost, in effect, creating a form of “integration test” for certain Community nationals.65 In any event, according to this analysis, even if Union citizenship might produce limited benefits (for example) as regards the procedural fairness and transparency of domestic systems of welfare adjudication, nevertheless the caselaw itself emerges neither as a threat to the moral depth and complexity of essentially national concepts of solidarity, nor as a panacea to the Union’s own concerns about “constitutional asymmetry”.66 That critique may be linked up to another argument, which also stresses the essentially limited impact of Union citizenship, particularly in the context of relations between migrant and host state.67 In particular, the primary “added value” of Union citizenship – so far as concerns those (as in Baumbast)68 who derive their residency status from Community law – is to cushion claimants who are essentially financially independent from the effects of an over-zealous application of Community law S Currie, “‘Free’ Movers? The Post-Accession Experience of Accession-8 Migrant Workers in the United Kingdom” (2006) 31 ELRev 207. 65 See C O’Brien, “Real links, abstract rights and false alarms: the relationship between the ECJ’s ‘real link’ case law and national solidarity” (2008) 33 ELRev 643. 66 Consider also criticism of the vagueness of the “real link” concept, and the wide leeway this affords to Member States, e.g. by S O’Leary, “Solidarity and Citizenship Rights in the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union” in G de Búrca (ed), EU Law and the Welfare State (OUP, Oxford, 2005); S Besson and A Utzinger, “Future Challenges of European Citizenship: Facing a Wide-Open Pandora’s Box” (2007) 13 ELJ 573. 67 See M Dougan, “The Court Helps Those Who Help Themselves… The Legal Status of Migrant Workseekers Under Community Law in the Light of the Collins Judgment” [2005] EJSS 7. 68 Case C-413/99 Baumbast [2002] ECR I-7091. 64 14 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) concerning the need to demonstrate sufficient resources and comprehensive medical insurance; and also to extend a helping though still limited hand to other categories of Union citizens who seem deserving of support because they are trying to better themselves in some orthodox economic sense, for example, as migrant students (as in Grzelczyk)69 or workseekers (as in Collins).70 Beyond that, however, Union citizenship holds out to more vulnerable categories of individuals (as in Trojani)71 only the promise of equal treatment as regards access to social advantages, but without the security of residence within the host territory necessary to make such equal treatment truly meaningful in practice,72 unless the claimant (as in Sala73 and Bidar,74 or now, pursuant to the permanent residency provisions of Directive 2004/38) has achieved a sufficient degree of integration into the host society as to effectively place him/herself beyond the possibility of expulsion by the national authorities.75 On that view, Union citizenship could once again claim to make only a modest contribution to the legitimisation of Community power through a “European social citizenship”; if anything, Community law appears designed to entrench and perpetuate unequal rights for individual Union citizens.76 3.2.3. The structure of judicial reasoning and the balance between individual rights and collective interests Academic opinion is therefore unsure what to make of the Court’s conception of Union solidarity and its relationship to national solidarities. To complicate matters further, the solidarity model being promoted by the Court can be criticised from another perspective, concerning the inter-relationship between (first) the balance between an individual right to welfare support and the collective aspects of social solidarity, (secondly) the very structure of judicial reasoning employed in the caselaw on Union citizenship, and (thirdly) the proper role of the judicial function in disputes about the allocation of welfare resources. Despite Marshall’s influential categorisation of social rights alongside more traditional civil and political rights in the triptych of modern citizenship, 77 other scholars have argued that social – and especially welfare rights – are marked by an important difference: they are fundamentally about the redistribution of income between social groups, and imply a claim on resources and legitimisation of the redistributive role of the state.78 Of course, welfare rights may display all the 69 Case C-184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I-6193. Case C-138/02 Collins [2004] ECR I-2703. 71 Case C-456/02 Trojani [2004] ECR I-7573. 72 See further, on the temptation for Member States to expel Union citizens rather than risk welfare liabilities towards them, e.g. S Fries and J Shaw, “Citizenship of the Union: First Steps in the European Court of Justice” (1998) 4 EPL 533; S O’Leary, “Putting Flesh on the Bones of European Union Citizenship” (1999) 24 ELRev 68. 73 Case C-85/96 María Martínez Sala [1998] ECR I-2691. 74 Case C-209/03 Bidar [2005] ECR I-2119. 75 See further, e.g. C Barnard, “EU Citizenship and the Principle of Solidarity” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005). 76 The potential for greater exportation of benefits from the home state pursuant to Article 18 EC may help alleviate some of those inequalities, but without eliminating them entirely: see further, e.g. M Dougan, “Expanding the Frontiers of Union Citizenship by Dismantling the Territorial Boundaries of the National Welfare States?” in C Barnard and O Odudu (eds), The Outer Limits of EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, forthcoming). 77 T H Marshall, Citizenship and Social Class (CUP, 1949, reprinted Pluto Press, 1991). 78 M Kleinman, A European Welfare State? (Palgrave, Basingstoke, 2002) pp 194-195. 70 15 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) characteristics of enforceable subjective legal rights: as recognised under Community law itself, the very concept of social security usually implies the conferral upon its beneficiaries of a legally defined position, with benefits granted as of right upon the occurrence of a particular contingency.79 Nevertheless, it has been argued that “[t]he language of social citizenship, in effect, enables what is fundamentally a political struggle and a philosophical argument about income redistribution and economic inequality to be dressed up in the language of legal rights”.80 Or to put it differently, one might say that questions about entitlement to welfare engage not only the individual’s personal expectation of social support, but also the relevant society’s choices about the allocation of its available resources, which in turn reflect collective moral judgments concerning the nature of its social solidarity: what risks to protect against, what levels of support to offer, and which individuals fall within the catchment area of collective responsibility.81 Yet it is arguable that Community law, and particularly the approach of the ECJ, risks neglecting that crucial collective dimension to social solidarity. 82 In that regard, one might begin with the observation that it has become so easy to trigger the application of the provisions on Union citizenship – thanks to the Court’s broad construction of the personal and material scope of the Treaty,83 and the sheer breadth of the rights of residency, equal treatment and freedom from barriers to movement enjoyed by individual citizens – that the mere existence of a prima facie infringement of the Treaty has surely lost its ability to tell us anything meaningful about the balance of policy interests at stake in any given dispute. In other words, breaching the Treaty has become so commonplace that the relevant national rules should not per se be treated with antagonism, as if it can thenceforth be taken for granted that they have offended against some higher public interest.84 That would be to elevate the simple principle of movement – and incidentally, all of the second-order rights derived from that movement, such as individual rights to welfare support from the host or home state – above all other manifestations of the general good. Yet it is arguable that that is exactly the nature and outcome of judicial reasoning in free movement cases: having triggered the application of the Treaty on the basis of an individual right connected to movement, the onus then falls upon the Member State to explain and defend its disputed national rules, in accordance with the constraints imposed by the principle of proportionality and other general principles of Community law. The very 79 See, e.g. Case 79/76 Fossi [1977] ECR 667. M Kleinman, A European Welfare State? (Palgrave, Basingstoke, 2002) p 195. 81 For a detailed analysis of the theoretical nature of social solidarity, including the relationship between individual and collective interests, see S Stjernø, Solidarity in Europe: The History of an Idea (CUP, Cambridge, 2005). 82 As noted also by S Giubboni during a presentation on “A Certain Degree of Financial Solidarity: Some Reflections on the Caselaw of the Court of Justice on Cross-Border Access to National Welfare Systems” at the conference Seeking Solidarity in the European Union: Towards Social Citizenship and a European Welfare State? (University of Sussex, 7 May 2008). Similar allegations have been raised against the “individualistic” approach to social and welfare rights in the EU’s Charter of Fundamental Rights: see, e.g. M Berezin and M Schain (eds), Europe Without Borders: Remapping Territory, Citizenship and Identity in a Transnational Age (John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, 2003) at pp 22-24. 83 On which, see E Spaventa, “Seeing the Wood Despite the Trees? On the Scope of Union Citizenship and Its Constitutional Effects” (2008) 45 CMLRev 13. Also, e.g. A Epiney, “The Scope of Article 12 EC: Some Remarks on the Influence of European Citizenship” (2007) 13 ELJ 611; Y Borgmann-Prebil, “The Rule of Reason in European Citizenship” (2008) 14 ELJ 328. 84 See, in a similar sense, N Nic Shuibhne Annotation of Schwarz, Commission v Germany and Morgan and Bucher (2008) 45 CMLRev 771. 80 16 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) structure of legal argumentation before the Court of Justice therefore emphasises from the outset the importance of the individual and endorses his / her claim of entitlement to welfare support, whereas the collective aspects of social solidarity are put on the defensive and thereby at an inherent disadvantage.85 That inherent disadvantage is aggravated by certain other features of adjudication before the Court of Justice. On one side, the Court does not allow the process of triggering the Treaty (for example, on the basis of unequal treatment by the host state or a barrier to movement by the home state) to be complicated by the need for the individual to demonstrate empirically that his / her movement has actually been deterred or impeded in any meaningful way. The Court relies on intuitive – sometimes even counter-intuitive – assessments which attribute the average citizen with both penetrating foresight and inordinate sensitivity, such that almost any inequality of treatment for migrants acts as a deterrent to their apparently boundless expectation of unimpeded mobility.86 On the other side, the Court often insists that Member States fearful of the consequences that rights to free movement and / or equal treatment for individual Union citizens might inflict upon national policy choices, even those recognised as valid imperative requirements capable in principle of justifying an infringement of the Treaty, must nevertheless produce firm evidence to substantiate those fears.87 In several cases, Member States have failed to defend their national policy choices simply because they were unable to present to the Court fully documented empirical analyses to substantiate their concerns.88 In the battle between competing suppositions, it seems that those favouring the individual will often trump those designed to protect the public interest, so that the nature as well as the burden of proof in free movement cases conspires against the collective aspects of social solidarity.89 The balance is further tipped in favour of an individual right to welfare support by another feature of the Court’s caselaw on Union citizenship and the principle of proportionality: the insistence that Member States must not determine qualification for benefits according to generalised criteria applied in an exclusive and exhaustive fashion, without taking into account the personal circumstances of each individual claimant – an assessment which may well oblige the national authorities to recognise entitlement to welfare support on the basis of additional factors not See further, e.g. M Dougan and E Spaventa, “Wish You Weren’t Here… New Models of Social Solidarity in the European Union” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005). Cf. Y Borgmann-Prebil, “The Rule of Reason in European Citizenship” (2008) 14 ELJ 328, who challenges the idea that the caselaw under Art 18 EC establishes a conceptual hierarchy between the individual’s prima facie right to free movement and the Member State’s imperative requirements of the public interest. 86 For a vivid recent example, consider Case C-212/06 Government of the French Community and Walloon Government v Flemish Government (Judgment of 1 April 2008). 87 Though not in every dispute: consider, e.g. Case C-157/99 Peerbooms [2001] ECR I-5473; Cases C11-12/06 Morgan and Bucher [2007] ECR I-9161. 88 Consider, e.g. Case C-385/99 Müller-Fauré [2003] ECR I-4509; Case C-147/03 Commission v Austria [2005] ECR I-5969. Note also Case C-228/07 Petersen (Judgment of 11 September 2008). 89 Consider also the problem for Member States of demonstrating that an individual’s recourse to social assistance renders them an “unreasonable burden”, and therefore susceptible to physical removal from the territory, having regard to the cumulative effect of similar cases: see further, e.g. M Dougan and E Spaventa, “Educating Rudy and the (Non-)English Patient: A Double Bill on Residency Rights Under Article 18 EC” (2003) 28 ELRev 699; though consider the ruling in Case C-385/99 Müller-Fauré [2003] ECR I-4509, para 74. Contrast with the views of A P van der Mei, “Residence and the Evolving Notion of European Union Citizenship” (2003) 5 European Journal of Migration and Law 419. 85 17 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) ordinarily considered valuable or even relevant under domestic law.90 The Court’s “personal circumstances” approach to the principle of proportionality deserves criticism in its own right on the grounds (first) that it risks creating serious legal uncertainty, for individuals and authorities alike, in a field generally characterised by the need for expeditious decision-making on a mass scale;91 and (secondly) that it may end up diverting valuable financial resources into the administrative procedures for assessing entitlement to benefits, with potential adverse consequences for the overall provision of welfare support.92 But in addition, it is arguable that the potentially intrusive nature of the Court’s “personal circumstances” assessment contrasts strongly with the traditional basis upon which concepts of social solidarity are adjudicated by the courts in many Member States. Domestic courts have long been conscious of the limits of judicial intervention in decisions concerning the allocation of welfare resources, having regard to their limited expertise and carefully demarcated democratic mandate, relative to that of the competent political and administrative authorities. In most cases, national judges (and administrative tribunals) are more comfortable with enforcing basic standards of procedural fairness as regards the treatment of individual claimants, rather than promoting their own vision of substantive justice in contradiction to the wide discretionary powers exercised by the primary decision-makers.93 However, the Court of Justice seems much bolder in its willingness to question the Member State’s political choices about the equitable sharing of available resources, or rather, to encourage judicial intervention for the benefit of individual claimants, on the basis that their “personal circumstances” outweigh the admittedly legitimate interests of the relevant Member State as embodied in the latter’s established, and theoretically justifiable, decisionmaking structures and criteria.94 In short: the caselaw on Union citizenship tends to elevate free movement within the EU over all other manifestations of the general interest, in particular, by privileging individual welfare rights and expectations over the collective interests and priorities normally inherent in concepts of social solidarity, and ultimately, to alter the traditional character of judicial review in cases involving difficult choices about how best to marshal scarce, or at least finite, national welfare resources. Of course, such tendencies need not be viewed in a negative light: those commentators who have 90 See above. Consider, e.g. AG Kokott in Case C-287/05 Hendrix (Judgment of 11 September 2007), especially paras 70-73 Opinion. See further, e.g. M Dougan, “The Constitutional Dimension to the Case Law on Union Citizenship (2006) 31 ELRev 613; H Verschueren, “European (Internal) Migration as an Instrument for Defining the Boundaries of National Solidarity Systems” (2007) 9 European Journal of Migration and Law 307. 92 Cp. discussion of the merits and problems of discretionary (as opposed to rule-based) decisionmaking in welfare systems in N Harris (ed), Social Security Law in Context (OUP, Oxford, 2000) at pp 35-37. 93 In English law, the two main examples are R v Cambridge District Health Authority, ex parte B [1995] 2 All ER 129 and R v Gloucestershire County Council, ex parte Barry [1997] AC 584. See further, e.g. E. Palmer, “Resource Allocation, Welfare Rights: Mapping the Boundaries of Judicial Control in Public Administrative Law” (2000) 20 OJLS 63; and since the introduction of the Human Rights Act 1998, e.g. J King, “The Justiciability of Resource Allocation” (2007) 70 MLR 197. 94 A criticism magnified by recent rulings where the claimant’s “personal circumstances” were arguably far from unique or even exceptional, and taken into account systematically could amount to the straightforward abolition of the relevant national restrictions: e.g. Cases C-11-12/06 Morgan and Bucher [2007] ECR I-9161; Case C-499/06 Nerkowska (Judgment of 22 May 2008). However, contrast with the views expressed in C O’Brien, “Real links, abstract rights and false alarms: the relationship between the ECJ’s ‘real link’ case law and national solidarity” (2008) 33 ELRev 643. 91 18 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) criticised the marked reluctance on the part of national judges to intervene on behalf of individual claimants suffering undoubted hardship as a result of disputed decisions concerning welfare allocation might welcome moves by the ECJ to encourage a more activist judicial role, not only in Community law cases, but eventually and by osmosis in purely internal situations as well, whereby the domestic courts ensure that political choices concerning welfare allocation are conducted within the same framework of public law principles as any other branch of national administration.95 But others will be dismayed by such a prospect, and might point to the healthcare caselaw – understood as a branch of the caselaw on the exportation of benefits from the home state,96 based on the reimbursement by an insured person’s own healthcare system of the costs incurred in receiving medical treatment from a healthcare provider established in another Member State – to help illustrate their concerns for both the emergent Community and the inherited national concepts of social solidarity.97 On the one hand, certain academics praise the Court’s healthcare caselaw for helping those individuals who have been “let down” by their own national healthcare system to seek medical assistance elsewhere in the Union; for putting greater pressure on the Member States to increase the resources devoted to their domestic healthcare systems in an effort to reduce clinically unjustified waiting lists; and perhaps even for pointing out to the Union the potential benefits of organising the Member States’ collective healthcare resources in a more efficient manner, which takes advantage of particular regional medical strengths and the economies of scale to be derived from greater cross-border specialisation.98 On the other hand, the Court has been accused (usually by specialists in domestic healthcare law) of placing an individual right to “queue jump” above the principle of solidarity – here understood in terms of the universal sharing of costs and opportunities – which underpins many national healthcare systems; it is further argued that that right to queue jump will, in practice, benefit only a restricted class of patient, i.e. educated, confident and articulate enough to know and exploit their rights, and wealthy enough both to pay for treatment upfront, as well as cover any ancillary costs such as travel and accommodation, including those entailed by any accompanying family or friends.99 That sort of critique might well be projected further, into the entire caselaw on the exportation of benefits: without doubting the advantages for migrating individuals of continuing to 95 Consider the arguments for greater judicial intervention in the field of social and welfare rights, e.g. by G van Bueren, “Including the Excluded: The Case for an Economic, Social and Cultural Human Rights Act” [2002] PL 456. 96 Even if the legal basis for the decided healthcare caselaw is Art 49 EC on the free movement of (economic) services, rather than Art 18 EC on the free movement of (economically inactive) Union citizens, the underlying principles remain the same. Indeed, consider Case C-208/07 ChamierGlisczinski (Opinion of 11 September 2008; Judgment pending). 97 Especially: Case C-157/99 Peerbooms [2001] ECR I-5473; Case C-385/99 Müller-Fauré [2003] ECR I-4509; Case C-372/04 Watts [2006] ECR I-4325; Case C-444/05 Stamatelaki [2007] ECR I3185. 98 See further, e.g. P van Nuffel, “Patients’ Free Movement Rights and Cross-Border Access to Healthcare” (2005) 12 MJ 253; A Kaczorowska, “A Review of the Creation by the European Court of Justice of the Right to Effective and Speedy Medical Treatment and its Outcomes” (2006) 12 ELJ 345. Consider also M Flear, “Developing Euro-Biocitizens through Migration for Healthcare Services” (2007) 14 MJ 239. 99 See further, e.g. J Montgomery, “Impact of European Union Law on English Healthcare Law” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005); C Newdick, “Citizenship, Free Movement and Health Care: Cementing Individual Rights by Corroding Social Solidarity” (2006) 43 CMLRev 1645; J McHale, “Framing a Right to Treatment in English Law? Watts in Retrospective” (2007) 14 MJ 263. 19 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) enjoy social support from their home state, the removal of territorial welfare restrictions does diminish the resources available to the public institutions to provide for the well being of their static citizens. That in turn is illustrative of an important element, and potentially an important flaw, in the ECJ’s overall approach to welfare disputes: its tendency to focus on the rights of the individual migrant, to the potential neglect of the collective interests of the relevant society. 3.3. Concerning the constitutional propriety of the Court’s interpretation of Union citizenship The second main category of criticisms levied against the Court’s caselaw concerns the constitutional propriety of its interpretation of the welfare rights associated with Union citizenship. 3.3.1. Disregarding the Community’s variegated regulatory competences? To begin with, the Court may be accused of developing the caselaw on Union citizenship in disregard of the limitations on the Community’s regulatory competences as enshrined in the Treaty. In fields such as health, education and social security, the Treaty confers upon the Community legislature only limited powers to intervene in the national legal systems, strictly circumscribed by the terms of the applicable legal bases (which, in most cases, expressly rule out the possibility of harmonising domestic law).100 Yet the Member State’s duty to respect the obligations imposed directly under the Treaty – particularly in the field of free movement, including the provisions on Union citizenship – manages to exert an increasingly profound influence on the exercise of its domestic prerogatives to determine for itself the organisation and functioning of its own systems of healthcare, education and social protection. Furthermore, each time the Court finds that a particular category of national rules infringes the primary Treaty provisions, it brings such rules within the potential ambit of the Community’s competence to adopt harmonising measures for the purposes of reducing or eradicating obstacles to the proper functioning of the internal market and / or the free movement of Union citizens. The Commission’s long-awaited proposal in July 2008 for a directive on the application of patients’ rights in cross-border healthcare – citing the Court’s caselaw under Article 49 EC as its competence trigger and Article 95 EC as its legal basis, and providing for the harmonisation of various aspects of national law relating to the cross-border provision of medical treatment – serves as an excellent example of such “competence creep”.101 The caselaw concerning the welfare rights and obligations of migrant Union citizens is therefore capable of rendering unto the Community legislature that which (according to the scheme of differentiated regulatory competences envisaged by the Treaty) was rightly assumed to belong to the Member States themselves. It is true that the Court’s caselaw pursues an admirable logic when it refuses to exclude per se such matters as health, education and social security from the impact 100 On health: Art 152 EC. On education: Arts 149-150 EC. On social security: Arts 18 and 137 EC. COM(2008) 414 Final. See further, e.g. D Wyatt, “Community Competence to Regulate Medical Services” in M Dougan and E Spaventa (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2005); G Davies, “The Community’s Internal Market-Based Competence to Regulate Healthcare: Scope, Strategies and Consequences” (2007) 14 MJ 215. 101 20 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) of the primary Treaty provisions.102 But logic can provide Community law with only so much legitimacy. After all, the social, economic, political and cultural sensitivities of interfering with national rules on health, educational or welfare policy are similar regardless of whether that interference emanates from the Community legislature or instead the judiciary. Indeed, it is arguable that judicial intervention – precisely because it lacks a clear mandate, bypasses deliberation by democratic institutions, and (especially in cases concerning the interpretation of primary Treaty provisions) is difficult to amend or reverse – raises even greater legitimacy problems in fields of marginal Community responsibility than action by the accountable political institutions. It therefore remains open for debate whether the Court should find a lighter step with which to tread across spheres characterised by only complementary Community regulatory competences – not by excluding the application of the primary Treaty provisions altogether, of course, but at least by tempering the rigour with which the objective of free movement is balanced against the Member State’s countervailing legitimate interests, particularly within the context of the proportionality assessment.103 3.3.2. Disregarding the Community legislature’s regulatory preferences? Just as serious is the accusation that the Court has developed its caselaw on Union citizenship sometimes even in disregard of the regulatory choices expressed by the Community legislature in the exercise of its competences under the Treaty. As we have seen, “indirect judicial review” of Community secondary legislation restricting the exercise of free movement rights by Union citizens first emerged in the rulings in Grzelczyk and Baumbast,104 in situations where the claimant’s actual or potential reliance on welfare benefits / services within the host state called into question his / her ability to satisfy the requirements for lawful residency contained in the Residency Directives adopted in 1990-1993.105 The Court established that Community measures regulating the exercise of the Union citizen’s right to free movement, as referred to in Article 18 EC, must nevertheless be applied by the national authorities in compliance with the general principles of Community law, especially the principle of proportionality.106 In this regard, Grzelczyk and Baumbast constituted a novel development in the caselaw: such judicial review of national acts, even though they are in full compliance with valid Community legislation, amounts (indirectly) to judicial review of that very Community legislation, and not of the “light touch” sort one would normally expect as regards exercise of the Community’s own legislative powers, but rather of a very detailed and intrusive kind which pierces right to the core – the “personal circumstances” – of each individual case.107 102 See, e.g. Case C-372/04 Watts [2006] ECR I-4325, para 92 (as regards healthcare); Case C-76/05 Schwarz (Judgment of 11 September 2007), para 70 (as regards education); Case C-499/06 Nerkowska (Judgment of 22 May 2008), paras 23-24 (as regards welfare benefits). 103 See, in a similar sense, F Jacobs, “Citizenship of the European Union: A Legal Analysis” (2007) 13 ELJ 591. 104 See above. 105 Directive 90/364 [1990] OJ L180/26; Directive 90/365 [1990] OJ L180/28; Directive 93/96 [1993] OJ L317/59. 106 See further, e.g. M Dougan and E Spaventa, “Educating Rudy and the (Non-)English Patient: A Double Bill on Residency Rights Under Article 18 EC” (2003) 28 ELRev 699. 107 M Dougan, “The Constitutional Dimension to the Case Law on Union Citizenship (2006) 31 ELRev 613. 21 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) The specific application of indirect judicial review illustrated in Grzelczyk and Baumbast has now been incorporated by the Community legislature into the text of Directive 2004/38, which expressly provides that recourse to social assistance shall not justify automatic recourse to expulsion of the claimant from the host state.108 However, the broader principle of indirect judicial review has since been extended into a broader range of situations where Community secondary legislation (implicitly or explicitly) purports to limit or condition the exercise of Union citizenship rights pursuant to Article 18 EC, yet the Court obliges the Member States to apply or enforce such legislation without prejudice to the requirements derived from the primary Treaty provisions themselves. For example, the Court in cases such as Tas-Hagen and Nerkowska, and Morgan and Bucher, found that home state territorial restrictions on the payment of civilian war benefits and student financial assistance (respectively) were in prima facie breach of Article 18 EC and had to be objectively justified – even though such benefits were deliberately excluded from the material scope of Regulation 1408/71 (and will remain so under Regulation 883/2004) and were thus intended not to be governed by the principle of exportation contained in the coordination regime.109 More controversially, it seems that even benefits which do fall within the material scope of Regulation 1408/71 (and Regulation 883/2004), but whose exportation from the home state has been positively restricted by the Community legislature, are now amenable to scrutiny under the primary Treaty provisions. In De Cuyper, the Court relied on Article 18 EC to examine the case of a Union citizen claiming that Belgium could not terminate his unemployment benefits on the sole grounds that he had changed habitual residence to France – notwithstanding the fact that the situation appeared fully congruent with the provisions of Regulation 1408/71.110 The personal circumstances of the particular claimant in De Cuyper did not appear to justify setting aside the Belgian territorial restriction on payment of unemployment benefits. However, in the subsequent case of Petersen, the Court indeed insisted upon the exportation of an unemployment benefit from Austria to Germany, in favour of a migrant (ex-)worker relying on Article 39 EC, even though the relevant claimant again fell outside the situations expressly provided for under the Community’s own coordination regime.111 The ruling in Petersen is couched in relatively narrow terms: the Court claimed not to be directly contradicting Regulation 1408/71, which contains only limited coordination provisions, such that all remaining national residency requirements can still be scrutinised under the Treaty itself;112 furthermore, the possibility of exportation as imposed under the primary Treaty provisions was explained by reference to the special nature of the disputed benefit (which was offered on a provisional basis to applicants for invalidity pension), whereas the Court hinted strongly that, when it came to objectively justifying residency restrictions on “ordinary” unemployment benefits, the primary Treaty provisions would oblige 108 Art 14(3) Directive 2004/38. Case C-192/05 Tas-Hagen [2006] ECR I-10451; Case C-499/06 Nerkowska (Judgment of 22 May 2008); Cases C-11-12/06 Morgan and Bucher [2007] ECR I-9161. Consider cases where the claimant fell outside the personal scope of Regulation 1408/71 but could nevertheless rely on the primary Treaty provisions to challenge territorial restrictions on welfare benefits: e.g. Case C-213/05 Geven [2007] ECR I-6347; Case C-212/05 Hartmann [2007] ECR I-6303. 110 Case C-406/04 De Cuyper [2006] ECR I-6947. See further, e.g. M Cousins, “Citizenship, Residence and Social Security” (2007) 32 ELRev 386. 111 Case C-228/07 Petersen (Judgment of 11 September 2008). 112 Ibid, especially at paras 38-44. 109 22 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) Member States to follow only those rules already contained in Regulation 1408/71.113 Nevertheless, such judicial modesty should be read against the background of the previous ruling in Hendrix.114 In that case, which was also based on Article 39 EC, the Court made apparent its objection to a decision by the Netherlands to terminate payment of a disability benefit for young people on the sole grounds that the claimant worker had moved his habitual residence to Belgium – even though the disputed payment was validly categorised as a special non-contributory [cash] benefit under Regulation 1408/71 and should thus have been excluded entirely from the possibility of exportation.115 It is not only in the application of Regulation 1408/71 that we might now encounter the principle of indirect judicial review over Community secondary legislation restricting the Union citizen’s free movement rights. Notwithstanding the partial codification of Grzelczyk and Baumbast in Directive 2004/38, other provisions of the new legislative regime on free movement for Union citizens may yet provoke a similar judicial response. For example, Advocate General Mazák in Förster has advised the Court effectively to ignore Article 24(2) Directive 2004/38, insofar as it purports to overrule the judgment in Bidar116 by excluding the right of equal treatment as regards educational grants and loans for migrant students who cannot qualify as either workers or permanent residents, in favour of analysing each dispute on its own merits pursuant to the primary Treaty provisions, the “real link” test and a “personal circumstances” assessment.117 Similarly, academic commentators have suggested that the Court might use the principle of indirect judicial review so as to bypass Article 24(2) Directive 2004/38, insofar as it appears to overturn the ruling in Collins118 by excluding migrant workseekers from equal treatment as regards entitlement to social assistance.119 On the one hand, some commentators have lodged serious constitutional criticisms against the Court’s principle of indirect judicial review.120 The Court’s interpretation of Union citizenship is not only immune from the Member States acting unilaterally in the exercise of their residual regulatory powers, and indeed impervious to their collective wishes as “masters of the Treaties”, whose carefully designed system of variegated competences has had little impact upon the forward integrative dynamic of the caselaw, but is also resilient even against the express will of the Community’s own legislature. In effect, it is argued, the Court is usurping the role of the Council and the European Parliament, and extending rights to Union citizens beyond (and indeed despite) the clear limits negotiated and agreed by the Union’s accountable political institutions. On the other hand, it has been argued that the Court’s caselaw on indirect judicial review is capable of plausible constitutional 113 Ibid, especially at paras 57-62. Case C-287/05 Hendrix [2007] ECR I-6909. 115 See further, e.g. C O’Brien, Annotation of Geven, Hartmann and Hendrix (2008) 45 CMLRev 499. 116 Case C-209/03 Bidar [2005] ECR I-2119. 117 Case C-158/07 Förster (Opinion of 10 July 2008; Judgment pending). Cp. M Dougan, “Fees, Grants, Loans and Dole Cheques: Who Covers the Costs of Migrant Education within the EU?” (2005) 42 CMLRev 943; O Golynker, “Student Loans: the European Concept of Social Justice According to Bidar” (2006) 31 ELRev 390. 118 Case C-138/02 Collins [2004] ECR I-2703. 119 See further, e.g. M Dougan, “The Court Helps Those Who Help Themselves… The Legal Status of Migrant Workseekers Under Community Law in the Light of the Collins Judgment” [2005] EJSS 7; O Golynker, “Jobseekers’ Rights in the European Union: Challenges of Changing the Paradigm of Social Solidarity” (2005) 30 ELRev 111. 120 In particular: K Hailbronner, “Union Citizenship and Access to Social Benefits” (2005) 42 CMLRev 1245. 114 23 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) justification.121 In effect, the assertion that Union citizenship is “destined to be the fundamental status”122 of all Member States nationals has succeeded in elevating the relevant primary Treaty provisions to a special place within the Community’s hierarchy of legal acts and justifies a more rigorous examination of the impact of Community secondary legislation upon the exercise of the individual’s fundamental freedoms. However, that constitutional justification, while it may be legally plausible, does expose a weak flank in the Court’s whole enterprise of enhancing the value and status of Union citizenship. Free movement by economically active persons has always enjoyed an express mandate in the Treaty, benefited from a reasonably clear teleology to guide its development, and been furnished with the hard legal tools required to achieve its goals. By contrast, free movement by economically inactive persons can call upon only an ambiguous mandate under the Treaty, and lacks any distinct teleology to direct its interpretation, while the legal armoury made available to the Community institutions in this field is obviously more limited. Yet despite those obstacles, the Court has succeeded in crafting a mandate, a teleology and the legal tools, all by itself. The caselaw on Union citizenship effectively relies on blind faith in a particular political vision – that Union citizenship really is destined to be the fundamental status of all Community nationals – which the Court considers powerful enough to justify a transformation in the complex web of welfare relationships between individuals and societies, host and home states, and Community institutions and judicial authorities. Indeed, in the current process of deterritorialising and reterritorialising welfare states within the EU, the Court seems to be asserting that it is the emergent supranational space, as interpreted by the judges, which truly expresses and projects the collective will of the Member State populations, and thereby commands an authority more compelling than that of either the inherited national models or any alternative understanding expressed by the Union’s political leaders. Is that vision persuasive? In particular, can it survive the painful process of constitutional reform leading up to, and now engulfing, the Treaty of Lisbon 2007? 4. The Relevance of the Treaty of Lisbon 2007 New treaties have a reputation for neglecting to address the thorny issue of the Union’s relationship to the national welfare states and its role in welfare policy more generally.123 True to form, the Treaty of Lisbon 2007 seems at first glance of little (if any) relevance to the debate about the welfare rights and obligations associated with migrant Union citizens. After all, Lisbon’s formal impact upon the existing Treaty provisions concerning Union citizenship is marginal.124 Even the introduction of an In particular: M Dougan, “The Constitutional Dimension to the Case Law on Union Citizenship (2006) 31 ELRev 613. 122 For the first time in Case C-184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I-6193, para 31. And in many other cases since, e.g. Case C-224/98 D’Hoop [2002] ECR I-6191, para 28; Case C-148/02 Garcia Avello [2003] ECR I-11613, para 22; Case C-224/02 Pusa [2004] ECR I-5763, para 16; Cases C-482 and 493/01 Orfanopoulos [2004] ECR I-5257, para 65; Case C-403/03 Schempp [2005] ECR I-6421, para 15; Case C-520/04 Turpeinen [2006] ECR I-10685, para 18; Case C-50/06 Commission v Netherlands [2007] ECR I-4383, para 32. 123 Consider, e.g. G Falkner, “The Treaty on European Union and Its Revision: Sea Change or Empty Shell for European Social Policies?” in S Kuhnle (ed), Survival of the European Welfare State (Routledge, London, 2000). 124 Save for the new power under Art 21(3) TFEU to legislate on social security and social protection for Union citizens: see below. See further on the post-Lisbon Union citizenship provisions, e.g. S 121 24 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) express reference to the idea that Union citizenship shall be additional to, and not replace, national citizenship merely clarifies the status quo.125 Nor, in this context, does the conferral of binding legal effects upon the Charter of Fundamental Rights, including the provisions concerning social solidarity, seems likely to make much practical difference.126 The constitutional reform process has therefore produced neither any direct and clear endorsement, nor any direct and clear rejection, of the status quo as it has evolved in the secondary legislation and through the ECJ’s caselaw. Yet a broader look at the Treaty of Lisbon, and at the constitutional reform process of which Lisbon now forms part, suggests that there may be more subtle lessons to be learned in this field. The revised Treaties are certainly peppered with newfound references to “solidarity” between citizens and between Member States, 127 and to the Union’s role in combating social exclusion and promoting social justice.128 However, the revised Treaties are also notable for their renewed emphasis on the principle that the Union enjoys only those powers conferred upon it by the Member States,129 and on the need to exercise those attributed competences with due consideration for the principle of subsidiarity.130 Furthermore, the revised Treaties would contain fresh indications that social welfare in general, and social security in particular, are to be considered special fields at the interface between Union and national competences. In the first place, most of the existing limits on Union power as regards the spheres related to social protection would remain in place;131 indeed, health and education would be formally categorised as examples of complementary (rather than exclusive or shared) Union competence.132 In the second place, even as regards the Union’s “hard” regulatory powers in the field of social security, the decision-making procedures prescribed under the revised Treaties would continue to highlight the sensitive nature of the relevant subject-matter. For example, the new power in Article 21(3) TFEU for the Union institutions to adopt measures concerning social security or social protection necessary to attain the free movement of Union citizens may only be exercised by default, and according to a special legislative procedure, based on unanimity in the Council of Ministers and consultation of the European Parliament. The Union’s existing power to adopt (minimum) harmonisation measures in the field of social security and social protection for workers would remain subject to the same special legislative procedure, without any possibility of the Council taking a simple decision to replace it with the ordinary legislative procedure,133 and still subject to the proviso that Union measures may neither affect the Member State’s right to define the Currie, “The Transformation of Union Citizenship” in M Dougan and S Currie (eds), 50 Years of the European Treaties: Looking Back and Thinking Forward (Hart Publishing, Oxford, forthcoming). 125 See Art 20(1) of the revised TFEU. 126 For a more detailed analysis, see J Tooze, “Social Security and Social Assistance” in T Hervey and J Kenner (eds), Economic and Social Rights Under the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights (Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2003). 127 E.g. sixth recital of the preamble, Art 2 and Art 3(3) of the revised TEU; Art 222 TFEU. 128 E.g. Art 3(3) of the revised TEU; third recital of the preamble and Art 9 TFEU. 129 E.g. Art 3(6), Art 4(1) and Art 5(2) of the revised TEU. 130 E.g. Art 4(2) and Art 5(3) of the revised TEU; Protocol on the application of the principles of subsidiarity and proportionality. 131 On education: Arts 165-166 TFEU. On health: Art 168 TFEU. On social security: Art 153 TFEU. 132 See Arts 2(5) and 6 TFEU. Moreover, although social security falls within the Union’s shared competence as regards social policy in general, according to Art 153 TFEU, harmonisation is not possible as regards combating social exclusion and modernising social protection systems. 133 Art 153(2) TFEU. Though recourse could still be made to the general “passerelle clause” contained in Art 48(7) of the revised TEU. 25 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) fundamental principles of its social security system nor significantly affect its financial equilibrium.134 Moreover, as regards the Union’s longstanding power to promote the cross-border coordination of national social security systems, the Member States were unable to agree to a wholesale conversion of the unanimity requirement currently contained in Article 42 EC, to ordinary QMV within the Council of Ministers under the revised TFEU. The IGC instead agreed to create a unique “emergency brake” procedure.135 Thus, the revised Article 48 TFEU employs the ordinary legislative procedure (i.e. co-decision), with the Council acting by QMV as normal, unless and until a Member States declares that draft legislation would affect fundamental aspects, or the financial balance, of its social security system. In that event, the ordinary legislative procedure shall be suspended and the matter referred to the European Council. Within four months, the European Council may (by consensus) refer the draft back to the Council, permitting the ordinary legislative procedure to resume; or instead kill off the draft, by either taking no action or requesting the Commission to submit a new proposal.136 In broad terms, the Treaty of Lisbon therefore affirms that welfare in Europe is undergoing a process of deterritorialisation and reterritorialisation whose anchorage is firmly located at the national level, supplemented by various new dimensions cultivated by Community law or attributable to Union membership, but where simple assertions about “supranational solidarity” lack any true legal, political or social meaning when divorced from the constitutional constraints imposed by the Treaties. In specific terms, it is arguable that the revised Treaties would complicate further the problematic constitutional dimension to the welfare rights associated with Union citizenship. After all, the Member States in their capacity as Treaty drafters continue to stress and indeed reinforce the peculiarly sensitive nature of welfare as a field of primarily national responsibility, and to impose ever more precise limits on the powers of the Community legislature to intervene therein. Does that increase pressure on the ECJ to align its caselaw concerning the interpretation of the primary Treaty provisions more sympathetically with the system of graduated Union competences enshrined in the revised Treaties; and / or to show greater deference towards the welfare choices of the Member States, in particular, when it comes to the proportionality assessment of national rules in prima facie breach of the Union citizens’ rights to free movement and equal treatment? More fundamentally, perhaps, it is arguable that the constitutional reform process leading up to and beyond the signing of the Treaty of Lisbon highlights the fragile normative basis upon which the Court has constructed its caselaw on Union citizenship. In this regard, it would be tempting to focus on the detailed reasons why the voters of France and the Netherlands, and then Ireland, rejected the Constitutional Treaty and the Treaty of Lisbon (respectively).137 After all, among the wide variety of antagonisms displayed towards the Constitutional Treaty / Treaty of Lisbon during the course of the three unsuccessful popular referenda, it would be relatively easy to find some constituency of public opinion which objected to the Union’s constitutional reform on grounds that tally – however superficially – with the sorts of academic 134 Art 153(4) TFEU. Though a variant of that “emergency brake” is also used in the field of judicial cooperation in criminal matters (under Arts 82(3) and 83(3) TFEU). See further: M Dougan, “The Treaty of Lisbon 2007: Winning Minds, Not Hearts” (2008) 24 CMLRev 617. 136 Note Declaration No 23 annexed to the Final Act. 137 See the post-referenda opinion polls conducted at the request of the Commission in France, the Netherlands and Ireland: Flash Eurobarometer Poll Nos 171, 172 and 245 (respectively). 135 26 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) concerns surrounding the welfare rights associated with Union citizenship highlighted in previous sections of this paper: for example, an objection to the feeling that the integration process is being driven forward by unresponsive political elites; the desire to protect the national social model and welfare system from outside threats or interference, whether by nebulous processes such as globalisation or by identifiable organisations like the EU; or popular responses to the Union’s enlargement into central and eastern Europe, especially fears concerning the dynamic migration patterns it has unleashed (at least for certain Member States), and indeed broader public concerns about the fragile relationship between immigration, integration and national identity. But however tempting, such an approach could only ever yield limited and potentially even misleading results. After all, any political scientist would remind us of the obvious difficulties in drawing firm or coherent conclusions about voter preferences on European integration from the negative referenda results in France, the Netherlands and Ireland: “no” votes were cast for myriad reasons, not all of them related to the Constitutional Treaty / Treaty of Lisbon itself, or even to issues concerning their country’s engagement with the EU; and many of those reasons would appear upon closer analysis to be mutually incompatible – some people wanting “less Europe” with a narrower focus on free trade, others wanting “more Europe” with an active agenda of greater social integration.138 Against that background, perhaps the main lesson to be learned from the constitutional reform process, for our purposes, is that there are genuine problems in identifying and pursuing a “shared vision of European integration” among the peoples of Europe. In fact, the post-Laeken debate on the “future of Europe” seems to have revealed the existence of powerful differences between political vision and public opinion within and between Member States. It is not without significance that, in the aftermath of both the failure of the Constitutional Treaty, and the rejection by Irish voters of the Treaty of Lisbon, there were repeated suggestions that the future of the integration process surely lay in acknowledging and accommodating greater differentiation between the 27 Member States of the enlarged European club, through either the mechanism of enhanced cooperation,139 or the division of the Union in a more formalised core and periphery.140 It might well be mere coincidence that the rulings in Grzelczyk and Baumbast were delivered in the early and essentially optimistic stages of the constitutional reform process.141 It might also be an interesting game to speculate about whether the smooth ratification and entry into force of the original Constitutional Treaty would have vindicated the Court’s trailblazing vision of Union citizenship and emboldened the judges to push further their particular conception of supranational welfare solidarity. But as events turned out, the crisis triggered by the 2005 referenda, the fresh jolts from the Irish vote in 2008, and the ongoing challenge of finding a way See further, e.g. P Taggart, “Questions of Europe: The Domestic Politics of the 2005 French and Dutch Referendums and their Challenge for the Study of European Integration” in (2006) 44 JCMS: Annual Review 7. 139 In which regard, note that the Treaty of Lisbon would further liberalise the substantive and procedural conditions for engaging in enhanced cooperation, as compared to the regime inherited from he Treaties of Amsterdam and Nice: see Art 20 of the revised TEU and Arts 326-334 TFEU. 140 See, e.g. T Konstadinides, “Now and Then: Fischer’s Core Europe in the Aftermath of the Collapse of the December 2003 Constitutional Talks” [2004] Irish Journal of European Law 113. 141 Grzelczyk was delivered between the Nice European Council of December 2000 and the Laeken European Council of December 2001; Baumbast was decided during the deliberations of the Convention of the Future of Europe. 138 27 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) forward for the EU’s constitutional reform, all leave dangerously exposed the main problems – allegations of social engineering and of judicial activism – associated with the Court’s caselaw on the welfare rights of Union citizens. Even though we can feel confident that few (if any) French, Dutch or Irish voters rejected the Constitutional Treaty or the Treaty of Lisbon because of rulings such as Grzelczyk or Baumbast, Tas-Hagen or De Cuyper, Hendrix or Morgan and Bucher, it nevertheless seems legitimate to pose the question: does the Union’s constitutional crisis suggest that the Court’s adventurous interpretative approach to Article 18 EC was in fact somewhat ahead of its time? Has the Court been too hasty in assuming that mutuality of destiny – and of solidarity – which provides the driving normative rationale behind its caselaw on Union citizenship, and purports to justify such powerful transformative effects for the welfare states, even without express sanction from the Member States or the Union’s political institutions? Conversely, should the slap in the face of our “shared vision of European integration” which the ratification crises of 2005 and 2008 surely represent, lead the Court to retreat back towards a more orthodox interpretation of the welfare rights of Union citizens, i.e. in which there is greater legal recognition for the collective aspects of social solidarity and greater judicial deference towards political choices about how best to allocate a given society’s available welfare resources? 5. Concluding Remarks In theory, the decline of the nation state’s historic monopoly over welfare provision has created the opportunity for new spatial identities and solidarities to emerge, not least through EU membership and the anticipation of closer economic, social, political and cultural integration between Member States. In practice, however, it remains far from clear that Member State citizens have actually reconciled themselves to this possibility. On the one hand, the restructuring of welfare spaces within Europe has not fundamentally altered the continued moral and financial anchoring of social solidarity at the level of each nation state. On the other hand, the EU has increasingly sought to develop a social dimension to its own activities, and a supranational dimension to European welfare spaces, within the framework of its own peculiar competences and institutions. This paper has argued that this dialectic raises various substantive and constitutional problems – and ultimately suggested that the new welfare spaces generated by processes of supranational integration might well be viewed as much as a threat as an opportunity, even by those they are intended to benefit. In particular, the general assumption that greater rights for Union citizens (including more generous rights to residency, equal treatment and unimpeded movement, linked to the provision of welfare benefits and services by the migrant’s host and home states) would be good for the EU’s social and political legitimacy has perhaps given way to a more sober assessment, based on an increasing sense that an over- or prematurely ambitious articulation of Union citizenship can actually be mismanaged, to the detriment of not only the EU’s quest for greater popular acceptance, but also the inherited networks of social solidarity that provide the cornerstone of the national welfare states. The post-Laeken constitutional reform process perhaps serves to compound those concerns – particularly through the lessons suggested by the negative popular referenda in France, the Netherlands and Ireland concerning the fragility and conditionality of our nascent European solidarity. For its part, the Treaty of Lisbon preserves the accepted but rather vague idea of a multi-level 28 To appear in: R. Nielsen, U. Neergaard and L. Roseberry (eds), Integrating Welfare Functions into EU Law: From Rome to Lisbon, (DJØF Publishing, Copenhagen, forthcoming in 2009) European welfare space, grounded in the Member States but open to a Union dimension, though without offering any clearer way forward or alternative strategy for the future. The ball, as so often, ends up back in the Court: its vision of Union citizenship initially transformed this field of Community law; will that vision survive the tumults of the constitutional reform process unaltered? 29